24.11.2012 Views

CCR Intro.fm - PULP - University of Pretoria

CCR Intro.fm - PULP - University of Pretoria

CCR Intro.fm - PULP - University of Pretoria

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The annual Constitutional Court Review is devoted to analysing the<br />

work <strong>of</strong> the South African Constitutional Court in the year preceding<br />

publication. Every volume contains two long essays, each with<br />

replies, subject-specific articles, and case comments. This inaugural<br />

2008 volume examines the major themes and currents reflected in<br />

the decisions handed down by the Court in 2007.<br />

CLoSA<br />

Constitutional Law <strong>of</strong> South Africa<br />

Konrad<br />

Adenauer<br />

Stiftung<br />

South African Institute for Advanced Constitutional,<br />

Public, Human Rights and International Law<br />

Strap ad FINAL.indd 1 5/27/09 9:57:58 AM<br />

<strong>Pretoria</strong> <strong>University</strong> Law Press<br />

<strong>PULP</strong><br />

www.pulp.up.ac.za<br />

ISSN: 2073-6215<br />

<strong>CCR</strong><br />

CONSTITUTIONAL COURT REVIEW<br />

VOLUME 1 • 2008<br />

<strong>PULP</strong><br />

<strong>CCR</strong><br />

VOLUME 1<br />

•<br />

2008<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL<br />

COURT<br />

REVIEW<br />

Lead essays/respones<br />

On the uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity: Some notes on application, avoidance, equality and<br />

objective unconstitutionality from the 2007 term <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa<br />

Frank I Michelman ...................................................................................................................................<br />

The Constitutional Court, court watchers and the Commons: A reply to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

Michelman on constitutional dialogue, ‘interpretive charity’ and the citizenry as sangomas<br />

Tshepo Madlingozi ...............................................................................................................................<br />

Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

AJ van der Walt ........................................................................................................................................<br />

Legal subsidiarity and constitutional rights: A reply to AJ van der Walt<br />

Karl Klare ............................................................................................................................................<br />

Articles<br />

‘Oh, what a tangled web we weave ...’ Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract,<br />

good faith and transformation – towards a politics <strong>of</strong> friendship in the politics <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

Jaco Barnard-Naudé .................................................................................................................................<br />

Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the Constitutional Court<br />

Cora Hoexter ............................................................................................................................................<br />

Case comments<br />

Sustainable development in practice: Fuel Retailers Association <strong>of</strong> Southern Africa v Director-<br />

General Environmental Management, Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture, Conservation and Environment,<br />

Mpumalanga Province<br />

Loretta Feris .............................................................................................................................................<br />

Fuel Retailers, sustainable development & integration: A response to Feris<br />

Dire Tladi ............................................................................................................................................<br />

Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

Patrick Lenta ............................................................................................................................................<br />

The case for religious inclusivism and the judicial recognition <strong>of</strong> religious associational<br />

rights: A response to Lenta<br />

Iain T Benson ......................................................................................................................................<br />

Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy: NM & Others v Smith & Others<br />

(Freedom <strong>of</strong> Expression Institute as amicus curiae)<br />

Glenn Penfold & Dario Milo ....................................................................................................................<br />

Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> policy considerations Steenkamp NO v<br />

Provincial Tender Board, Eastern Cape<br />

Sanele Sibanda ..........................................................................................................................................<br />

Severing the umbilical cord: A subtle jurisprudential shift regarding children and their primary<br />

caregivers<br />

Ann Skelton .............................................................................................................................................<br />

1<br />

63<br />

77<br />

129<br />

155<br />

209<br />

235<br />

255<br />

259<br />

295<br />

311<br />

335<br />

351


Editors<br />

Stu Woolman, Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong><br />

Theunis Roux, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> New South Wales<br />

Danie Brand, Senior Lecturer, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong><br />

Editorial Board<br />

Laurie Ackermann, Constitutional Court Justice Emeritus<br />

Mary Arden, Lady Justice, Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal <strong>of</strong> England & Wales<br />

Danwood Chirwa, Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Cape Town<br />

Sujit Choudhry, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Toronto<br />

Christian Courtis, Human Rights Officer, United Nations Office <strong>of</strong> the High Commissioner<br />

for Human Rights<br />

Javier Couso, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Universidad Diego Portales, Chile<br />

Charles Fombad, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Botswana<br />

Nicole Fritz, Director, Southern Africa Litigation Centre<br />

Karthy Govender, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> KwaZulu-Natal<br />

Michelo Hansungule, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong><br />

Karl Klare, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Northeastern <strong>University</strong><br />

Heinz Klug, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Wisconsin<br />

Sandy Liebenberg, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Stellenbosch <strong>University</strong><br />

Frank Michelman, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Harvard Law School<br />

John Mubangizi, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> KwaZulu-Natal<br />

Christina Murray, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Cape Town<br />

Charles Ngwena, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Free State<br />

Enyinna Nwauche, Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Rivers State <strong>University</strong><br />

Cheryl Saunders, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Melbourne<br />

Dire Tladi, Legal Counsel, South Africa, United Nations<br />

AJ van der Walt, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Stellenbosch <strong>University</strong>


CONSTITUTIONAL<br />

COURT<br />

REVIEW<br />

(2008) 1<br />

2009


Constitutional Court Review (2008) 1<br />

Published by:<br />

<strong>Pretoria</strong> <strong>University</strong> Law Press (<strong>PULP</strong>)<br />

The <strong>Pretoria</strong> <strong>University</strong> Law Press (<strong>PULP</strong>) is a publisher at the Faculty <strong>of</strong> Law,<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong>, South Africa. <strong>PULP</strong> endeavours to publish and make<br />

available innovative, high-quality scholarly texts on law in Africa that have<br />

been peer-reviewed. <strong>PULP</strong> also publishes a series <strong>of</strong> collections <strong>of</strong> legal<br />

documents related to public law in Africa, as well as text books from African<br />

countries other than South Africa.<br />

For more information on <strong>PULP</strong>, see www.pulp.up.ac.za<br />

Printed and bound by:<br />

ABC Press<br />

Cape Town<br />

To order, contact:<br />

<strong>PULP</strong><br />

Faculty <strong>of</strong> Law<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong><br />

South Africa<br />

0002<br />

Tel: +27 12 420 4948<br />

Fax: +27 12 362 5125<br />

pulp@up.ac.za<br />

www.pulp.up.ac.za<br />

Cover:<br />

Yolanda Booyzen, Centre for Human Rights<br />

ISSN: 2073-6215<br />

© 2009<br />

The Constitutional Court Review forms part <strong>of</strong> the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law in Africa<br />

Project funded by the World Bank.


CONSTITUTIONAL COURT REVIEW<br />

The Constitutional Court Review is a once-a-year journal dedicated to<br />

the analysis <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s decisions <strong>of</strong> the previous<br />

year. Its purpose is to provide a platform for high-level academic<br />

engagement with the jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> the South African<br />

Constitutional Court.<br />

To this end, each issue <strong>of</strong> the Review contains two lead essays<br />

exploring broad themes arising from a given year’s jurisprudence<br />

(each ± 20 000 words), each with its own response (± 5 000 words); a<br />

number <strong>of</strong> shorter subject-specific articles (each ± 10 000 words); and<br />

several case comments that engage more narrowly with a given<br />

decision <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court (each ± 5 000 words).<br />

Lead essays are solicited by the editors, as are some <strong>of</strong> the subjectspecific<br />

articles and case notes, but for the remainder unsolicited<br />

contributions are invited. Such contributions must be sent to the<br />

editors at danie.brand@up.ac.za in MS Word format on or before<br />

31 May <strong>of</strong> the year following that on which a contribution focuses.<br />

Contributions will only be considered if they follow the house style,<br />

available at www.pulp.up.ac.za.<br />

iii


SUBSCRIPTION<br />

Subscriptions through agents or bookshops:<br />

R380-00 (including VAT but excluding postage and packaging)<br />

Subscriptions directly through <strong>PULP</strong>:<br />

R292-00 (including VAT but excluding postage and packaging)<br />

Subscriptions by registered students directly through <strong>PULP</strong>:<br />

R220-00 (including VAT but excluding postage and packaging)<br />

Postage and packaging charges are:<br />

R45-00 per subscription<br />

Subscriptions should be directed to the publisher:<br />

<strong>PULP</strong> - <strong>Pretoria</strong> <strong>University</strong> Law Press<br />

Faculty <strong>of</strong> Law<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong><br />

<strong>Pretoria</strong><br />

0002<br />

E-mail: pulp@up.ac.za<br />

Website: http://www.pulp.up.ac.za<br />

iv


Lead essays/responses<br />

TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

On the uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity: Some notes on application, 1<br />

avoidance, equality and objective unconstitutionality from the<br />

2007 term <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa<br />

Frank I Michelman<br />

The Constitutional Court, court watchers and the Commons: 63<br />

A reply to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman on constitutional<br />

dialogue, ‘interpretive charity’ and the citizenry<br />

as sangomas<br />

Tshepo Madlingozi<br />

Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term 77<br />

AJ van der Walt<br />

Articles<br />

Legal subsidiarity and constitutional rights: A reply to 129<br />

AJ van der Walt<br />

Karl Klare<br />

‘Oh, what a tangled web we weave ...’ Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> 155<br />

contract, good faith and transformation — towards a<br />

politics <strong>of</strong> friendship in the politics <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

Jaco Barnard-Naudé<br />

Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law 209<br />

in the Constitutional Court<br />

Cora Hoexter<br />

Case comments<br />

Sustainable development in practice: Fuel Retailers Association 235<br />

<strong>of</strong> Southern Africa v Director-General Environmental<br />

Management, Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture, Conservation<br />

and Environment, Mpumalanga Province<br />

Loretta Feris<br />

Fuel Retailers, sustainable development & integration: 255<br />

A response to Feris<br />

Dire Tladi<br />

v


Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform 259<br />

regulations<br />

Patrick Lenta<br />

The case for religious inclusivism and the judicial 295<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> religious associational rights:<br />

A response to Lenta<br />

Iain T Benson<br />

Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy: NM & Others v Smith & 311<br />

Others (Freedom <strong>of</strong> Expression Institute as amicus curiae)<br />

Glenn Penfold & Dario Milo<br />

Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> policy 335<br />

considerations. Steenkamp NO v Provincial Tender Board,<br />

Eastern Cape<br />

Sanele Sibanda<br />

Severing the umbilical cord: A subtle jurisprudential shift 351<br />

regarding children and their primary caregivers<br />

Ann Skelton<br />

vi


ON THE USES OF INTERPRETIVE ‘CHARITY’: SOME<br />

NOTES ON APPLICATION, AVOIDANCE, EQUALITY<br />

AND OBJECTIVE UNCONSTITIONALITY FROM THE<br />

2007 TERM OF THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT OF<br />

SOUTH AFRICA*<br />

* I am indebted to Stu Woolman, and to two anonymous referees, for exceptionally<br />

helpful, trenchant comments. I hope that what follows shows the benefit <strong>of</strong> their<br />

efforts, even if I remain incorrigible on some points <strong>of</strong> difference.<br />

** Robert Walmsley <strong>University</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Harvard <strong>University</strong>.<br />

1<br />

D Davidson Inquiries into truth and interpretation (1984) 197 (Davidson Truth).<br />

2 S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ (2007) 123 South African Law<br />

Journal 762 (Woolman ‘Amazing’).<br />

3<br />

Barkhuizen v Napier 2007 7 BCLR 691 (CC).<br />

4 Masiya v Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions 2007 5 SA 30 (CC); 2007 8 BCLR 927 (CC)<br />

(‘Masiya’).<br />

5<br />

NM v Smith 2007 5 SA 250 (CC); 2007 7 BCLR 751 (CC) (‘NM’).<br />

6 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 762 (‘chattering classes’).<br />

1<br />

Frank I Michelman*<br />

Charity is forced on us; whether we like it or not, if we want to<br />

understand others, we must count them right in most matters. 1<br />

1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

To hear Stu Woolman tell it, disturbing lapses and weaknesses — an<br />

apparent ‘lack <strong>of</strong> analytical rigour’ suggesting what could be a<br />

‘penchant for outcome-based decision-making’ — have been showing<br />

up recently in the work <strong>of</strong> a Constitutional Court whose prior record<br />

<strong>of</strong> performance has deservedly garnered widespread applause. 2<br />

Woolman cites as evidence three decisions from the Court’s work in<br />

the year 2007: Barkhuizen, 3 Masiya, 4 and NM, 5 and suggests that his<br />

reactions to these decisions are widely shared among South Africa’s<br />

well-informed Court-followers. 6 He makes a worthy, illuminating,<br />

formidable case, one that the Court would do well to consult and<br />

ponder.


2 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

Formidable is not, however, conclusive. For reasons I shall come<br />

to shortly, I have chosen to devote this space to seeing what might be<br />

said on the other side, specifically with regard to NM and Masiya, on<br />

behalf <strong>of</strong> a Court that, I quite agree with Woolman, has left itself with<br />

a lot <strong>of</strong> explaining to do. The controlling opinions in these cases are<br />

indeed, as Woolman says, ‘thinly reasoned’, 7 if by that we mean they<br />

are in some respects insufficiently explained. It is, however, another<br />

question whether these cases have been wrongly or irresponsibly<br />

managed, as measured by reasonably discoverable, valid considerations<br />

<strong>of</strong> law and legal administration.<br />

In particular, I shall be questioning Woolman’s diagnosis from<br />

these cases <strong>of</strong> ‘a court uncomfortable with the direct application <strong>of</strong><br />

the specific substantive provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ and ‘in full<br />

flight from any meaningful engagement with Chapter 2 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution.’ 8 Whether a wider survey <strong>of</strong> the jurisprudence would<br />

warrant an over-all diagnosis <strong>of</strong> an excessive flight from substance is<br />

a question on which I hazard no judgment here. All I say here is that<br />

NM and Masiya do not, to my eye, support the diagnosis, nor is that,<br />

in my view, the best way for us to regard these cases. One feature<br />

common to both is the Constitutional Court’s seeming gravitation to<br />

its inherent power to develop the common law in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

Constitution sections 173 and 39(2) — as opposed to its judicial review<br />

power in terms <strong>of</strong> sections 8 and 172(1) — when undertaking<br />

modification <strong>of</strong> common law rules under pressure from the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. Woolman believes the Court moves too freely to the inherent<br />

power. He associates that tendency, as symptom or cause (or both),<br />

with excessive flight from substance. I aim to raise a doubt about any<br />

such connection. 9<br />

The main controversy over Masiya appears to me to turn, at<br />

bottom, more on a point <strong>of</strong> substantive disagreement between the<br />

Court and Woolman than on any notable disregard for Bill-<strong>of</strong>-Rights<br />

substance on the Court’s part. The controversy over NM is more<br />

complicated, and more centrally my concern in these pages. It<br />

certainly is true that Woolman and the Court divide over when, if<br />

ever, the Constitutional Court ought to resort to an ‘indirect’ instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> a ‘direct’ application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to a common law doctrine<br />

or rule — the Court, in Woolman’s view, making far too much use <strong>of</strong><br />

7 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 762, 790 n 51.<br />

8 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 783.<br />

9<br />

I have nothing to say about another symptom or cause <strong>of</strong> flight that some might<br />

mention, to wit, the Court’s readiness on some occasions to move to the<br />

‘justification’ phase <strong>of</strong> a Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights case either without having decided the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> a substantive infringement, see, eg, Christian Education South Africa<br />

v Minister <strong>of</strong> Education 2000 4 SA 757 (CC) para 27, or, perhaps, having found an<br />

infringement on the basis <strong>of</strong> a merely ‘notional’ reading <strong>of</strong> the right in question.<br />

See S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional<br />

law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) ch 34 16-18.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 3<br />

‘indirect’. Such a division need not, however — or so I shall contend<br />

— reflect any reduced or absent sense on the Court’s part <strong>of</strong><br />

responsibility to engage with the substance <strong>of</strong> Chapter Two and its<br />

several, rights-naming clauses. It might rather come down to a<br />

question <strong>of</strong> doctrinal good-housekeeping on which nothing <strong>of</strong><br />

substance depends. The Court and Woolman are differing, I shall<br />

suggest, over how best to understand and sort out the respective<br />

<strong>of</strong>fices <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’s two paths to judicial revision <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law under constitutional pressure: revision as a remedy for<br />

constitutional violation pursuant to sections 172(1) 10 and 8, 11 and<br />

revision in the exercise <strong>of</strong> judicial powers to develop the common<br />

law, with a view to promoting the spirit, purport, and objects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2). That filing-system question, I<br />

shall maintain, is entirely distinct from the one about when and how<br />

regularly the Court regards itself as on or <strong>of</strong>f the hook for an<br />

elucidation <strong>of</strong> one or another <strong>of</strong> the specific clauses in the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights.<br />

In developing these claims, I shall be quite openly engaged in<br />

filling in passages <strong>of</strong> exposition and explanation that are missing from<br />

the Court’s opinions in NM and Masiya, to a degree that may<br />

sometimes strike readers as excessively indulgent <strong>of</strong> the Court, if not<br />

as entirely fanciful. In construing and re-presenting the work <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court in these cases, I take myself to be following<br />

something akin to what linguists and language-philosophers have<br />

called a ‘principle <strong>of</strong> charity’. ‘Something akin,’ not the genuine<br />

article, for this is not a work <strong>of</strong> philosophy, but rather an intended<br />

contribution to a lawyers’ kibitz on the work <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional<br />

Court.<br />

The ‘principle <strong>of</strong> charity’, Wikipedia tells us,<br />

10 172.(1) When deciding a constitutional matter within its power, a court —<br />

(a) must declare that any law or conduct that is inconsistent with the<br />

Constitution is invalid to the extent <strong>of</strong> its inconsistency; and<br />

(b) may make any order that is just and equitable ...<br />

11 8.(1) The Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights applies to all law, and binds the legislature, the executive,<br />

the judiciary and all organs <strong>of</strong> state.<br />

(2) A provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights binds a natural or a juristic person if, and to<br />

the extent that, it is applicable, taking into account the nature <strong>of</strong> the right and<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> any duty imposed by the right.<br />

(3) When applying a provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to a natural or juristic person in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> subsection (2), a court —<br />

(a) in order to give effect to a right in the Bill, must apply, or if necessary<br />

develop, the common law to the extent that legislation does not give effect to<br />

that right; and<br />

(b) may develop rules <strong>of</strong> the common law to limit the right, provided that the<br />

limitation is in accordance with section 36(1) ...


4 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

is an approach to understanding a speaker’s statements by interpreting<br />

the ... statements to be rational and, in the case <strong>of</strong> any argument,<br />

rendering the best, strongest possible interpretation <strong>of</strong> an argument. 12<br />

Donald Davidson, surely one <strong>of</strong> the principle’s chief philosophical<br />

architects and expositors, also calls it ‘the principle <strong>of</strong> rational<br />

accommodation,’ and summarises as follows: ‘We make maximum<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> the words and thoughts <strong>of</strong> others when we interpret in a way<br />

that optimises agreement.’ 13 Davidson meant ‘optimise’ as between<br />

thinking that the other must be holding to beliefs (and, relatedly,<br />

aims) that differ drastically from our own (else he couldn’t have said<br />

what he did), and thinking that we must not have heard him right the<br />

first time. 14<br />

The philosophical underpinnings <strong>of</strong> the charity principle are far<br />

afield from our concerns here and need not delay us. All that matters<br />

from that department is the motivation for adherence to the<br />

principle, which the moniker ‘charity’ does not very well convey. The<br />

aim <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity is not generosity toward others, or<br />

anything like that. It is not to pay homage, deference, or respect to<br />

our interlocutors, or to avoid giving <strong>of</strong>fense. It is not to demonstrate<br />

our own good manners, or to toe some Goody Two-Shoes line against<br />

critiques that are not ‘constructive’. (I hold Stu Woolman’s pull-nopunches<br />

style <strong>of</strong> court-watching to be entirely constructive and<br />

admirable.) No, the aim <strong>of</strong> ‘charitable’ interpretation is not any <strong>of</strong><br />

those. The aim is to learn. It is aggressively to learn what there is to<br />

be learnt from puzzles the interlocutors pose to us, by assuming there<br />

is method in their madness and doing our best to ferret that out, using<br />

everything else we know or can guess (in part from their likeness and<br />

kinship to us) about where they are coming from. ‘To see too much<br />

unreason on the part <strong>of</strong> others’, Davidson says, is ‘to undermine our<br />

ability to understand what it is they are so unreasonable about.’ 15 It<br />

is to risk missing issues that might merit our consideration.<br />

There are hazards — normative pitfalls — in the way <strong>of</strong> such an<br />

approach to the construction <strong>of</strong> judicial opinions. For one: these<br />

writings enjoy among us the status <strong>of</strong> utterances <strong>of</strong> law by a socially<br />

recognised organ <strong>of</strong> authority to say what the law is. And maybe,<br />

therefore, it really does not do for us to go about pretending the<br />

writers have said things they did not mean to say (perhaps meant not<br />

to say), in our effort to make their writings accord with what we take<br />

12<br />

13<br />

14<br />

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_<strong>of</strong>_charity (accessed 21 June 2008).<br />

As above.<br />

‘[T]here is no deciding ... between the view that the Other has used words as we<br />

do but has more or less weird beliefs, and the view that we have translated him<br />

15<br />

wrong.’ Davidson Truth (n 1 above) 101.<br />

Davidson Truth (n 1 above) 153.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 5<br />

to be legal reason — it being they, after all, and not we, who are the<br />

authorised law-sayers.<br />

Lying just ahead are deep jurisprudential waters into which I do<br />

not choose to wade on this occasion. I mean only to grant up front the<br />

possible dangers from a ‘charitable’ approach, while pointing also to<br />

some possible gains. A close examination <strong>of</strong> NM and Masiya, from a<br />

methodological stance <strong>of</strong> all-but-last-ditch resistance against a<br />

conclusion <strong>of</strong> blatant error, failure <strong>of</strong> nerve, or flight from<br />

responsibility on the Court’s part, can demonstrate, I believe, some<br />

benefits <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity as a working disposition on our part —<br />

not necessarily suited, <strong>of</strong> course, to every moment in history or every<br />

judicial performance we may encounter. Such an examination can<br />

show how that posture may sometimes aid us in performing our task<br />

<strong>of</strong> getting at the truth <strong>of</strong> law or at any rate — more modestly — <strong>of</strong><br />

developing culturally credible resources for the possible guidance <strong>of</strong><br />

judicial performance in the future, with no less a view (here following<br />

Theunis Roux) to the judiciary’s ‘legal’ than to its ‘sociological’ and<br />

‘institutional’ legitimacy. 16<br />

2 ‘Direct’ and ‘indirect’ application<br />

Much <strong>of</strong> what is to follow turns on debates over when, if ever, the<br />

Constitutional Court ought to resort to an ‘indirect’ instead <strong>of</strong> a<br />

‘direct’ application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to a common law doctrine or<br />

rule. Such debates sometimes risk falling into confusion and<br />

misunderstanding, because not everyone conceives or defines the<br />

distinction in exactly the same way, and perhaps some <strong>of</strong> us do not<br />

conceive or define it uniformly at every turn or in every context. It<br />

will, therefore, behoove us to survey briefly some <strong>of</strong> the variant<br />

senses <strong>of</strong> this distinction, and, in particular, to specify what Woolman<br />

— consistently — means by it in the work <strong>of</strong> his to which what follows<br />

is something <strong>of</strong> a rejoinder.<br />

So far as I am aware, the distinction in South African legal<br />

discourse between direct and indirect application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

16 T Roux ‘Principle and pragmatism on the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa’<br />

(2008) 7 I-CON 106 (Roux ‘Pragmatism’). In Roux’s vocabulary, the ‘legal<br />

legitimacy’ <strong>of</strong> judicial review rises and falls with perceptions <strong>of</strong> a court’s capacity<br />

to decide cases according to forms <strong>of</strong> reasoning acceptable to the legal<br />

community <strong>of</strong> which it is a part. Legal legitimacy refers to ‘the plausibility (rather<br />

than correctness) <strong>of</strong> a judicial decision or body <strong>of</strong> decisions according to<br />

applicable standards <strong>of</strong> legal reasoning.’ Thus defined, Roux explains, legal<br />

legitimacy is to be distinguished from two other sociological and institutional<br />

dimensions <strong>of</strong> the judiciary’s public standing, which Roux names ‘public support’<br />

and ‘institutional security’ meaning the court’s capacity to resist political attacks<br />

on its independence. As above 109. Roux posits that a court presiding over a<br />

system <strong>of</strong> judicial constitutional review does well to act with an eye to all three<br />

dimensions <strong>of</strong> legitimacy. See as above 110-11.


6 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

first arose in regard to the question <strong>of</strong> so-called horizontal application<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights under the Interim Constitution (although, as we<br />

shall see, it has outgrown its context <strong>of</strong> origin). In terms <strong>of</strong> that<br />

debate, to apply the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights ‘horizontally’ was to bring it to bear<br />

decisively, in a case in which (a) there was no state party and (b) it<br />

appeared that the pivotal legal doctrine or rule was (or might be) a<br />

rule or doctrine <strong>of</strong> the common law, as opposed to the terms <strong>of</strong> a<br />

statute. 17 In such a case, either or both <strong>of</strong> the following would have<br />

to be true: A plaintiff bases a claim for relief on a rule or doctrine <strong>of</strong><br />

the common law, and/or a defendant bases a defense (including the<br />

defense <strong>of</strong> ‘absolution’ or ‘no cause <strong>of</strong> action’) on a rule or doctrine<br />

<strong>of</strong> the common law. One or the other (or both) <strong>of</strong> the parties might<br />

question the compatibility with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

rule or doctrine on which the other relies. If that occurs, and the court<br />

rules in that party’s favor on that basis, a horizontal application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights will have taken place, under the definition we are now<br />

considering.<br />

Consider, now, a case such as NM, in which the plaintiff charges<br />

the defendant with unauthorised disclosure <strong>of</strong> private information<br />

concerning the plaintiff, and the defendant seeks to respond by<br />

proving that she did not knowingly or intentionally publish without<br />

authorisation, but rather acted honestly (if mistakenly) in the belief<br />

that authorisation had been given. How might the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights be<br />

brought to bear on this case, specifically section 14, which guarantees<br />

a right <strong>of</strong> privacy to everyone?<br />

A court might proceed by drawing a standard <strong>of</strong> care from section<br />

14, and then measuring the defendant’s conduct by that<br />

constitutionally prescribed standard, with a view to holding the<br />

defendant liable for a delict if her conduct fails the constitutional<br />

test. Alternatively, a court might proceed by asking whether the<br />

extant common law rule — which absolves publishers <strong>of</strong> private<br />

information from tort liability where they did not intentionally or<br />

knowingly publish without authorisation — is consistent with section<br />

14, with a view to possibly revising the common law rule in such a way<br />

that the defendant will be found liable for tortious conduct under the<br />

common law as revised to make it ‘constitutional’. In the first<br />

instance, the court applies the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to conduct; in the second<br />

instance, it applies it to law.<br />

17<br />

See Du Plessis v De Klerk 1996 3 SA 850 (CC); 1996 5 BCLR 658 (CC) para 49<br />

(Kentridge AJ) (‘Du Plessis’) (in effect, defining a ‘vertical’ case as one that<br />

either involves a state party or turns on a statute); S Woolman ‘Application’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) ch<br />

31 (Woolman ‘Application’) 18 (similarly describing ‘the traditional, vertical,<br />

view’); 4 (reporting general agreement that ‘the heart <strong>of</strong> the application debate<br />

was whether the common law, when relied upon by a private party in a private<br />

dispute, was subject to constitutional review.’).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 7<br />

This distinction — between testing conduct by a Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

standard, and testing law by a Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights standard — may have been<br />

what some early deployments <strong>of</strong> the direct/indirect distinction had at<br />

least partly in mind: application <strong>of</strong> the constitutional standard to<br />

conduct is ‘direct’ application, whereas application <strong>of</strong> it to law is<br />

‘indirect’ application. If so, that usage <strong>of</strong> the distinction cannot<br />

survive today. As we shall see below, Constitution section 8(3)<br />

virtually rules out the immediate application <strong>of</strong> a Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

standard to any private person’s conduct, directing rather that all<br />

such applications be made, instead, to the legal rules and doctrines<br />

on which litigating parties rely to found their claims and defenses. 18<br />

Consider, then, another sort <strong>of</strong> choice that might confront a court<br />

in our invasion-<strong>of</strong>-privacy case, where the court is already committed<br />

to test only law, not conduct, under the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. A court<br />

disposed to rule in the plaintiff’s favor, despite the defendant’s<br />

proven defense <strong>of</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> intention to publish without<br />

authorisation, might proceed by first holding the extant, delictual law<br />

<strong>of</strong> privacy invalid by reason <strong>of</strong> inconsistency with a specific right<br />

guaranteed by some rights-granting clause in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights — here<br />

it would be section 14 (‘Everyone has the right to privacy ...’) — and<br />

then, by way <strong>of</strong> remedy for the unconstitutionality, directing a<br />

curative revision or ‘development’ <strong>of</strong> the common law. As explained<br />

further below, the court then would be acting under the aegis <strong>of</strong><br />

Constitution section 172(1), or <strong>of</strong> Constitution section 8, or (perhaps<br />

it would be best to say) <strong>of</strong> both <strong>of</strong> those sections. Alternatively, the<br />

court might take its cue from Constitution section 39(2). It might then<br />

by-pass the question <strong>of</strong> the extant law’s possible invalidity by reason<br />

<strong>of</strong> inconsistency with a specific, rights-granting clause, and simply<br />

find the extant delictual doctrine unacceptably out <strong>of</strong> sorts with the<br />

overall ‘spirit, purport, and objects’ <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. We might<br />

classify the first sort <strong>of</strong> judicial action as ‘direct’ application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, and the second sort as ‘indirect’.<br />

We then would have severed any special connection <strong>of</strong> the direct/<br />

indirect distinction to cases involving horizontal application <strong>of</strong> the Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights, because the distinction as now defined is equally applicable<br />

18<br />

But the conduct/law distinction does survive in transmogrified form to postsection<br />

8 debate. See, eg, H Cheadle ‘Application’ in H Cheadle, D Davis & N<br />

Haysom (eds) South African constitutional law: The Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights (2002) 19: ‘ ...<br />

[B]ecause generally stated rights are not appropriate vehicles for the imposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> standards <strong>of</strong> conduct, section 8 seeks to avoid application <strong>of</strong> the right to<br />

conduct <strong>of</strong> private persons by requiring either legislation or a common law rule<br />

‘to give effect to the right.’ This constitutional motif <strong>of</strong> an intermediate law<br />

between the constitutional right and the conduct <strong>of</strong> the state or <strong>of</strong> the private<br />

actor repeats itself throughout the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.’ Woolman takes Cheadle to be<br />

saying, contentiously, that ‘the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights rarely, if ever, applies directly to<br />

“conduct”. It applies to law.’ Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 155.


8 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

to cases that are incontestably vertical in nature. 19 Take, for<br />

example, a case, which surely must be classed as vertical, in which<br />

the state prosecutes a person for alleged commission <strong>of</strong> the common<br />

law crime <strong>of</strong> sodomy. When that case came before the Constitutional<br />

Court, the Court employed the form <strong>of</strong> application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

that we are now calling ‘direct’, so as to invalidate the crime <strong>of</strong><br />

sodomy and erase it from the common law <strong>of</strong> South Africa. 20 Had the<br />

Court seen fit to do so, it could have achieve the same result<br />

‘indirectly’, by holding that the common law <strong>of</strong> crime must be<br />

‘developed’ so as to omit the crime <strong>of</strong> sodomy, in order to stay in tune<br />

with the overall spirit etc <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.<br />

To be as precise as possible about where we have come, we now<br />

have before us the following three, live possibilities:<br />

(a) ‘direct’ = declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity followed by remedial development<br />

<strong>of</strong> the common law; ‘indirect’ = development <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

to keep it attuned to the spirit etc. <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, with no<br />

attendant declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity.<br />

(b) ‘direct’ = a finding <strong>of</strong> the extant common law’s inconsistency with<br />

norms or standards contained in one or another specific rights-granting<br />

clause; ‘indirect’ = no such finding, but only a finding <strong>of</strong> disharmony<br />

with the general spirit etc. <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights taken whole.<br />

(c) ‘direct’ = judicial action in terms <strong>of</strong> Constitution sections 172(1), 8;<br />

‘indirect’ = judicial action in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2).<br />

When Stu Woolman speaks <strong>of</strong> ‘direct’ versus ‘indirect’ application <strong>of</strong><br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, he tends to run these oppositions together. No doubt<br />

opposition ‘b’ must stand as his core, his <strong>of</strong>ficial definition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

distinction. 21 But Woolman sustains no effort to pry or to hold the<br />

three oppositions apart. Rather, he sometimes treats the three as a<br />

cluster, in which each opposition in some way entails, insinuates,<br />

attracts, or bleeds into both <strong>of</strong> the other two. Such a treatment flows<br />

naturally from Woolman’s strongly held, carefully argued normative<br />

view that South African jurists ought to follow a discipline <strong>of</strong> holding<br />

the oppositions in fixed alignment. Woolman’s construction is<br />

captured in the table below. 22<br />

19<br />

See Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 5 n 1 (observing that the ‘application’<br />

debate must now be framed in terms <strong>of</strong> ‘direct’/’indirect’, not ‘vertical’/<br />

’horizontal’).<br />

20<br />

See National Gay & Lesbian Coalition v Minister <strong>of</strong> Justice 1996 3 SA 850 (CC);<br />

1996 5 BCLR 658 (CC) paras 73, 90 (Sodomy Case).<br />

21 ‘Direct challenges describe instances in which the prescriptive content <strong>of</strong> at least<br />

one specific substantive provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights applies to the law or to the<br />

conduct at issue. Indirect challenges describe instances in which the prescriptive<br />

content <strong>of</strong> no specific provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights applies to the law or to<br />

conduct at issue.’ Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 5 n 1.<br />

22 See generally Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above).


form <strong>of</strong> judicial power<br />

(a)<br />

substantive test <strong>of</strong><br />

inconsistency (b)<br />

controlling section <strong>of</strong><br />

Constitution (c)<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 9<br />

‘direct’ (1) ‘indirect’ (2)<br />

judicial-review power<br />

to declare invalidity<br />

and prescribe remedy<br />

involving revision <strong>of</strong><br />

common law [1a]<br />

is common law<br />

inconsistent with<br />

requirements <strong>of</strong> a<br />

specific right in the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights? [1b]<br />

172(1) and/or 8 [1c] 39(2) [2c]<br />

inherent power to<br />

develop common law<br />

in normal course <strong>of</strong><br />

adjudication [2a]<br />

is common law<br />

inconsistent with<br />

general objects <strong>of</strong> Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights, even though<br />

not inconsistent with<br />

requirements <strong>of</strong> any<br />

specific rights? [2b]<br />

According to what Woolman urges as the best, overall, combined<br />

construction <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’s relevant texts and purposes,<br />

whenever a court chooses to proceed — or finds itself proceeding — in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> 1a, 1b, or 1c, it ought to require itself concomitantly<br />

to proceed, on that occasion, in terms <strong>of</strong> other two members <strong>of</strong> triplet<br />

1; and conversely, <strong>of</strong> course, for any court that finds itself proceeding<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> the members <strong>of</strong> triplet 2.<br />

Whether Woolman’s normative/textual arguments in favor <strong>of</strong> his<br />

preferred construction, and <strong>of</strong> a correspondingly disciplined juristic<br />

practice, entirely succeed is not our question here. My question will<br />

rather be whether the prism <strong>of</strong> Woolman’s preferred construction<br />

works to the overall advantage <strong>of</strong> clarity <strong>of</strong> analysis in approaching<br />

the work <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court. If the Constitutional Court<br />

should happen to be working with a different (and perhaps itself<br />

defensible) construction, then it may not. To be more specific:<br />

Suppose that (as I shall suggest the evidence shows) the Constitutional<br />

Court is quite comfortable combining 2a and 2c with 1b. Woolman<br />

finds that combination wrongheaded, or, at any rate suboptimal from<br />

the standpoint <strong>of</strong> assigning clear, distinct, and jurisprudentially<br />

cogent meanings to the several, relevant constitutional clauses. Call<br />

that the Court’s ‘construction error’. The construction error —<br />

2a+1b+2c — cannot be counted as contributory towards a flight from<br />

meaningful engagement with the substance <strong>of</strong> the rights-naming<br />

provisions <strong>of</strong> Chapter Two, because one <strong>of</strong> its components — 1b — is<br />

entirely congenial to what Woolman means by engagement. The<br />

construction error and the ‘flight error’ (as we may call the latter) are<br />

two different things. Woolman sometimes seems to me to be<br />

detecting the flight error where only the construction error is clearly<br />

in evidence.


10 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

3 NM v SMITH<br />

3.1 The case<br />

Charlene Smith wrote a book about the public career <strong>of</strong> Patricia De<br />

Lille, an MP and a public figure. The book recounted De Lille’s<br />

interventions on behalf <strong>of</strong> persons living with HIV/AIDS. These<br />

included an episode involving controversial drug trials at the<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong>, in which the three women who became the<br />

plaintiffs in the case <strong>of</strong> NM — ‘NM’, ‘SM’, and ‘LH’ — were among the<br />

volunteer subjects. The three plaintiffs figure significantly in the<br />

book’s account <strong>of</strong> the controversy, as persons living with HIV. They<br />

are in no way otherwise persons <strong>of</strong> the slightest public note nor would<br />

their names be recognisable by members <strong>of</strong> the public outside their<br />

own special circles <strong>of</strong> acquaintance.<br />

Smith learned the plaintiffs’ names from a copy <strong>of</strong> an in-house<br />

report <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>essor’s investigation <strong>of</strong> the medical-study controversy,<br />

conducted on behalf <strong>of</strong> the <strong>University</strong> and intended for restricted<br />

circulation. (No one complains <strong>of</strong> the means by which Smith obtained<br />

her copy.) The report refers to ‘annexures’ containing forms signed<br />

by the three plaintiffs, giving consent to the inclusion <strong>of</strong> their names<br />

in the report. The copy provided to Smith did not include the<br />

annexures. Smith’s book, when published, identified the plaintiffs by<br />

name as persons living with HIV, as the report had done. Contrary to<br />

Smith’s expectation, it emerged that the consents given by the<br />

plaintiffs to the report’s author, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Strauss, were not general<br />

releases to disclose their medical information, with names attached,<br />

to the public at large, but only authorised a limited disclosure for<br />

purposes related to the <strong>University</strong>’s investigation.<br />

The plaintiffs brought an action against Smith for damages,<br />

claiming that her book’s identification <strong>of</strong> them by name, without their<br />

consent, as persons living with HIV amounted to a violation <strong>of</strong> their<br />

common law rights to privacy, specifically in terms <strong>of</strong> the actio<br />

iniuriarum. 23 Under the common law as it then stood (and still stands,<br />

in the wake <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s decision in NM), the<br />

plaintiffs could succeed only if Smith were found to have acted<br />

toward them in a manner that was not only objectively wrongful but<br />

also intentionally so. 24 Smith contended that any wrong she might<br />

have committed toward the plaintiffs, by way <strong>of</strong> publishing their<br />

23<br />

In order to maintain clarity, I focus my examination <strong>of</strong> NM on the claims for<br />

damages against defendant Smith; I do not discuss the claims for other forms <strong>of</strong><br />

relief, or the claims for damages against defendants Patricia De Lille and New<br />

Africa Books Ltd.<br />

24 See NM (n 5 above) para 55 (Madala J); para 151 (O’Regan J).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 11<br />

private information without their consent, was unintentional. The<br />

crux <strong>of</strong> her defense was that she acted in the honest (if mistaken)<br />

belief that the plaintiffs’ consents, <strong>of</strong> which she read in the Strauss<br />

Report, covered unrestricted circulation <strong>of</strong> the information regarding<br />

them contained in the report. Apparently persuaded by Smith’s<br />

testimony to this effect, the High Court absolved Smith <strong>of</strong> liability for<br />

tortious invasion <strong>of</strong> privacy. 25 The Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal refused<br />

review, giving no reasons, and the plaintiffs took their case to the<br />

Constitutional Court. 26<br />

Three members <strong>of</strong> the Court — Langa CJ, O’Regan J, and Sachs J<br />

— concluded that the case against Smith disclosed a need to develop<br />

the common law so to remove an incompatibility with the objects <strong>of</strong><br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights in the matter <strong>of</strong> protecting privacy. These members<br />

would have developed the common law so as to impose liability, on<br />

‘media defendants’ only, for negligent (or unreasonable), wrongful<br />

disclosure <strong>of</strong> private information. 27 The Court’s majority took a<br />

different tack. They joined an opinion by Madala J, holding that<br />

Smith’s unauthorised disclosure <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs’ private information<br />

should be found intentional in terms <strong>of</strong> the extant common law<br />

standard <strong>of</strong> liability. 28 They accordingly ordered a judgment for<br />

damages against Smith 29 while declining to address any question <strong>of</strong><br />

developing the common law. 30 Of the three justices who thought the<br />

common law must be developed, Langa CJ and Sachs J concurred in<br />

the order awarding damages to the plaintiffs, on the ground that the<br />

record showed negligence on the part <strong>of</strong> Smith. 31 O’Regan J would<br />

have absolved Smith <strong>of</strong> negligence and, hence, <strong>of</strong> liability. 32<br />

3.2 A Critique<br />

Woolman’s objections to the Constitutional Court’s performance in<br />

NM are mainly directed to the decision and opinion <strong>of</strong> the majority.<br />

While the objections refer to specific, alleged deficiencies and<br />

missteps in this particular case, Woolman presents them as exemplary<br />

<strong>of</strong> broader, worrisome trends in the work <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court.<br />

These are most compendiously summed up as a ‘lack <strong>of</strong> analytical<br />

rigour’ suggestive <strong>of</strong> ‘a penchant for outcome-based decisionmaking.’<br />

33 In Woolman’s view, the decision in NM ‘appears to rest<br />

25<br />

26<br />

27<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 46 (Madala J); para 125 (O’Regan J).<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 19.<br />

See NM (n 5 above) paras 92-94 (Langa CJ); paras 170-19 (O’Regan J); paras 203-<br />

28<br />

29<br />

30<br />

31<br />

32<br />

33<br />

04 (Sachs J).<br />

See NM (n 5 above) paras 58-65.<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 90.<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 57.<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 92 (Langa CJ); para 207 (Sachs J).<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 189.<br />

Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 762.


12 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

upon a deeply-felt <strong>of</strong>fence to the majority’s moral sensibility about<br />

how vulnerable persons in our society ought to be treated.’ 34<br />

Woolman’s bill <strong>of</strong> particulars includes the following:<br />

(1) The majority ended up acting ‘as a trier <strong>of</strong> fact in a run-<strong>of</strong>-the-mill<br />

actio iniuriarum matter’ 35 — a sort <strong>of</strong> task, Woolman evidently means to<br />

say, that the Constitutional Court was not created to do.<br />

(2) The majority’s crucial factual determination regarding Smith’s<br />

intention is ‘contrary to the evidentiary record’, which ‘cannot support<br />

a factual finding that the respondents had acted intentionally to harm<br />

the privacy and the dignity interests <strong>of</strong> the applicants.’ 36<br />

(3) The majority failed to provide an adequate explanation for why,<br />

once they had determined that the case would be disposed <strong>of</strong> by<br />

applying an unmodified, long-established common law standard <strong>of</strong><br />

liability, they did not dismiss the appeal as being no proper concern <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitutional Court. 37<br />

(4) The majority diminished the Constitution by declining to take up for<br />

consideration a possible ‘challenge to the actio inuriarum grounded in a<br />

specific substantive provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ or the possible<br />

‘creation <strong>of</strong> a self-standing constitutional action grounded in the right to<br />

privacy or the right to dignity.’ 38 This objection echoes prior pleas from<br />

Woolman, for a shift <strong>of</strong> the Court’s emphasis away from ‘indirect’<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights pursuant to section 39(2) to ‘direct’<br />

application pursuant to section 8. 39 The Court’s penchant for section<br />

39(2) is deplorable, Woolman maintains, because it plays into the false<br />

seductions <strong>of</strong> a so-called minimalist approach to constitutional<br />

adjudication that is unsuited to the present, early state <strong>of</strong> development<br />

<strong>of</strong> South African constitutional jurisprudence and culture. 40 It invites the<br />

Court to issue highly contextualised decisions that may feel right to the<br />

justices and many <strong>of</strong> those looking on, thus avoiding or postponing<br />

intracurial division and public controversy, but that remain unexplained<br />

on the level <strong>of</strong> principled, clause-by-clause exposition <strong>of</strong> the meanings<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rights-guarantees in Chapter 2 and the values underlying them. 41<br />

Yet the Court’s presumed, special capacity for that more challenging —<br />

in part because potentially divisive — task <strong>of</strong> principled explication is its<br />

raison d’être par excellence. Performance <strong>of</strong> that task, Woolman<br />

perceives, is a service to the country that only the Constitutional Court<br />

34 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 787.<br />

35 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 783.<br />

36 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 781.<br />

37<br />

See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 782 & n 40; Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa, 1996 sec 167(3)(b) (The Constitutional Court ‘may decide only<br />

constitutional matters, and issues connected with decisions on constitutional<br />

matters’).<br />

38 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 783.<br />

39 See generally Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above).<br />

40 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 764-65 n 4, 784-87.<br />

41 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 784-86.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 13<br />

can provide, and that it must perform for the sake <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law in<br />

South Africa. 42<br />

(5) In sum, the majority’s narrow, non-venturesome treatment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

case shirked a sort <strong>of</strong> service to the country that the Court was created<br />

to provide, to wit: authoritative delineation and explication <strong>of</strong> the<br />

principles animating the several specific substantive rights in Chapter 2,<br />

conveyed with definition sufficient to ‘determine the actual validity <strong>of</strong><br />

the rule being challenged in the instant matter and <strong>of</strong> similar rules<br />

challenged in subsequent matters’; also to enable citizens and<br />

government <strong>of</strong>ficials to ‘ensure that their behaviour conforms to our<br />

Constitution’, and also to equip lower courts and lawyers to ‘identify the<br />

law and thereby settle, litigate and adjudicate, with some confidence,<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights cases.’ 43 NM, Woolman concludes, ‘shows a court in full<br />

flight from any meaningful engagement with Chapter 2 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution.’ 44<br />

Woolman’s observations are eminently worth pondering, and by no<br />

means without warrant in the majority opinion in NM, as written. I<br />

mean to show, however, how the complaints turn on matters <strong>of</strong><br />

interpretation that can be resolved in the Court’s favour — with, no<br />

doubt, varying degrees <strong>of</strong> effort from the reader. The opinion in NM<br />

is indeed thin and chary <strong>of</strong> explanation, in places where it could and<br />

should be thicker and more forthcoming. Contrary to Woolman’s view,<br />

however, I think the NM majority got to the right answer, by a proper<br />

path (although the path preferred by Langa CJ seems to me superior),<br />

and for essentially (and detectably) right reasons. I say so with utmost<br />

respect to the opinion in the case that most ambitiously addresses the<br />

task <strong>of</strong> substantive elucidation <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights that Woolman<br />

misses from the Court’s work, the dissenting opinion <strong>of</strong> O’Regan J.<br />

Admirable as that opinion is in many ways, in the end it decides the<br />

case wrongly, in my view. Moreover, it perhaps does so for causes not<br />

unrelated to O’Regan J’s evident commitment to (and talent for) the<br />

work <strong>of</strong> principled exposition <strong>of</strong> the contents <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights.<br />

3.3 A pleading choice<br />

In order to succeed with their case against Smith, the NM plaintiffs<br />

had to show that Smith’s conduct not only had harmed them in fact,<br />

but had done so in a way that was liability-engendering, according to<br />

the terms <strong>of</strong> some law meant to protect persons in the plaintiffs’<br />

position against the sort <strong>of</strong> harm at issue. Of course, it would be up to<br />

the plaintiffs to say what law they had in mind. Their answer was: the<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> delict, and specifically the actio iniuriarum. 45<br />

42 See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 786-87.<br />

43 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 763.<br />

44 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 783.<br />

45 See NM (n 5 above) paras 22, 27-29.


14 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

A different response was also imaginably available. The plaintiffs<br />

might have pleaded as their cause <strong>of</strong> action Constitution section 14<br />

(‘Everyone has the right to privacy’), as rendered applicable to<br />

Smith’s conduct by Constitution section 8(1) (‘The Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

applies to all law, and binds the legislature, the executive, the<br />

judiciary and all organs <strong>of</strong> state’) and (8(2) (‘A provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights binds a natural ... person if, and to the extent that, it is<br />

applicable ...’). 46 Rather than (or in addition) to claiming damages for<br />

a common-law tort, the plaintiffs might have claimed on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

a constitutional tort. They did not do so, and it will repay us to ask<br />

why they did not. The common-law path selected by the plaintiffs was<br />

not, after all, free and clear <strong>of</strong> evident obstacles. The plaintiffs (or<br />

their lawyers) would have known the list <strong>of</strong> conventionally established<br />

requirements for success in a claim for invasion <strong>of</strong> privacy based on<br />

the actio iniuriarum. 47 They would have known that among these was<br />

a showing <strong>of</strong> the defendant’s intention (‘animus iniurandi’) to<br />

commit, as against the plaintiff, the wrong consisting <strong>of</strong> a publication<br />

<strong>of</strong> private facts concerning the plaintiff, without the plaintiff’s leave<br />

or against her will — where the category <strong>of</strong> ‘private’ facts includes any<br />

and all facts, not yet publicly available, whose disclosure to the public<br />

would be expected to ‘cause mental distress and injury to anyone<br />

possessed <strong>of</strong> ordinary feelings in the same circumstances’. 48<br />

Consider, then, a defendant who publishes a plaintiff’s entire,<br />

anguished medical history (naming her), in the honest but false belief<br />

that the plaintiff has given leave for publication, or that the<br />

information has been previously (lawfully) published and hence is no<br />

longer private. Such a defendant will indeed have committed the<br />

wrong in question, ‘objectively’ described as above; her action will,<br />

in that sense, have been wrongful under the law. Missing from the<br />

case, however, will be the usual basis for an inference <strong>of</strong> the<br />

defendant’s intention to mistreat (‘wrong’) the plaintiff in that way<br />

— to wit, the defendant’s actual knowledge <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> the facts that, in<br />

combination, would render her action wrongful.<br />

To put the matter simply: Under the common law <strong>of</strong> delict as it<br />

stood when the plaintiffs filed their case against Smith, negligent but<br />

non-intentional commission <strong>of</strong> the objective wrong <strong>of</strong> unauthorised<br />

publication <strong>of</strong> private facts was not deemed legally actionable, ‘as a<br />

46 See NM (n 5 above) para 132 (O’Regan J) (confirming the applicability <strong>of</strong><br />

Constitution sec 14 to private actors).<br />

47<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 55 (Madala J); para 151 (O’Regan J).<br />

48 NM (n 5 above) para 34 (Madala J), citing National Media Ltd v Jooste 1996 3 SA<br />

262 (A); 1996 2 All SA 510 (A). O’Regan J preferred to leave open whether the<br />

Constitution might possibly require some expansion <strong>of</strong> this common-law test for<br />

the protected (‘private’) status <strong>of</strong> the facts disclosed, but she was clear that ‘the<br />

publication <strong>of</strong> otherwise confidential information about a life-threatening illness<br />

is likely to cause distress to the person concerned’, and thus falls under the<br />

common-law test for liability. NM (n 5 above) para 137.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 15<br />

rule’. 49 Plaintiffs might sometimes have succeeded on the basis <strong>of</strong> a<br />

rebuttable presumption <strong>of</strong> intention, once objectively wrongful<br />

publication was shown, 50 or by establishing a modified form <strong>of</strong><br />

intention known as dolus eventualis (or reckless disregard) on the<br />

defendant’s part, 51 but a defendant who could satisfy a judicial factfinder<br />

that her mistake was bona fide, although careless, would<br />

escape liability.<br />

In NM, the available evidence was consistent (at least) with<br />

defendant Smith’s claim <strong>of</strong> an honest belief that the plaintiffs had<br />

consented to unrestricted public naming <strong>of</strong> them as the persons (living<br />

with HIV) who had played certain, described roles in the drug-trial<br />

controversy. Whether that evidence could further support a claim <strong>of</strong><br />

absence <strong>of</strong> negligence on Smith’s part is much more doubtful, as we<br />

shall see. Thus there was, from the beginning, reason to calculate<br />

that the plaintiffs’ prospect for success might depend on whether the<br />

body <strong>of</strong> law (the ‘cause <strong>of</strong> action’) they invoked to support their claim<br />

would impose liability on a merely negligent defendant. 52 At the<br />

moment when the plaintiffs sued, the common law <strong>of</strong> delict evidently<br />

was against them on that potentially crucial point. By contrast, for<br />

aught anyone could then tell, the law <strong>of</strong> the putative constitutional<br />

tort based on section 14 <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights might have been with<br />

them. Even so, the plaintiffs chose to base their claim on the actio<br />

iniuriarum, and not on section 14 <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. That choice<br />

requires explanation.<br />

3.4 Two litigation agendas compared<br />

In the view <strong>of</strong> Madala J, the plaintiffs were forced to their pleading<br />

choice by the Constitutional Court’s 1997 decision in Fose. 53 Fose<br />

certainly does leave a doubt about when, if ever, ‘constitutional<br />

damages’ might be awarded in respect <strong>of</strong> a violation <strong>of</strong> a provision in<br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. It seems to me, however, for reasons I am about to<br />

present, that a complete explanation for the NM plaintiffs’ pleading<br />

choice would have to include the further point that a claim expressly<br />

and immediately invoking the prescriptive content <strong>of</strong> section 14 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, as a test <strong>of</strong> the legally actionable character <strong>of</strong> Smith’s<br />

conduct, would have brought the plaintiffs to very much the same<br />

49<br />

50<br />

NM (n 5 above) para 55 (Madala J).<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 65 (Madala J); para 93 (Langa CJ); paras 125, 155, 169<br />

51<br />

52<br />

(O’Regan J).<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 155 (O’Regan J).<br />

The summons issued by the plaintiffs makes clear they understood that this was<br />

53<br />

so. See NM (n 5 above) para 124 (O’Regan J) (describing the summons).<br />

Fose v Minister <strong>of</strong> Public Safety and Security 1997 3 SA 786 (CC); 1997 7 BCLR 851<br />

(CC); see NM (n 5 above) para 27.


16 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

pass, regarding the question <strong>of</strong> that conduct’s intentionality, as<br />

resulted from their common-law claim.<br />

This consequence follows inexorably from the mandate <strong>of</strong><br />

Constitution section 8(3), as construed by the Constitutional Court. 54<br />

That section provides:<br />

When applying a provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to a natural or juristic<br />

person in terms <strong>of</strong> subsection (2), a court —<br />

(a) in order to give effect to a right in the Bill, must apply, or if<br />

necessary develop, the common law to the extent that legislation does<br />

not give effect to that right; and<br />

(b) may develop rules <strong>of</strong> the common law to limit the right, provided<br />

that the limitation is in accordance with section 36(1).<br />

By this seemingly clear command <strong>of</strong> constitutional law, any court<br />

disposed to impose civil liability, in terms <strong>of</strong> standards <strong>of</strong> conduct<br />

drawn from one or another <strong>of</strong> the rights-guarantees in the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights, is required to proceed in one <strong>of</strong> three ways, and not otherwise.<br />

Either (1) the court must decide the case in terms <strong>of</strong> legislation that<br />

gives due effect to the constitutional right in question; or (2) in the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> such legislation, the court must decide the case in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> applicable common law that gives due effect to the constitutional<br />

right in question; or (3) if the court decides that the applicable<br />

common law does not currently give due effect to the right, the court<br />

must decide the case in terms <strong>of</strong> the common law as developed by the<br />

court so as to cure the deficiency. 55<br />

Accordingly, in NM, the result <strong>of</strong> a claim for a ‘direct’ application<br />

<strong>of</strong> section 14 to Smith’s conduct would have been the Court’s having<br />

to decide two principal issues in tandem: whether giving due effect to<br />

54<br />

That is to say, it follows inexorably from the Constitutional Court’s authoritative,<br />

‘black letter’ construction <strong>of</strong> the three subsecs <strong>of</strong> sec 8, as announced in Khumalo<br />

v Holomisa 2002 3 SA 401 (CC); 2002 8 BCLR 771 (CC) (‘Khumalo’) paras 29-32 and<br />

precisely summarised by Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 6, 45. It would not<br />

follow from Woolman’s ‘preferred reading’ <strong>of</strong> sec 8, summarised at Woolman<br />

‘Application’ (n 17 above) 11, 45-46. But <strong>of</strong> course the NM plaintiffs’ lawyers<br />

would have had to frame their case in the shadow <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s<br />

reading, not that <strong>of</strong> any commentator.<br />

55 This directive carries out what logic would seem to require in its absence. We can<br />

use the NM case to illustrate. Suppose a court finds that Smith’s conduct has<br />

‘limited’ (ie, violated) NM’s prima facie right to privacy under Constitution sec<br />

14. Smith will seek refuge under Constitution sec 36(1). She will claim that she<br />

has acted in terms <strong>of</strong> law <strong>of</strong> general application, namely, the extant common law<br />

<strong>of</strong> delict, which — as she will claim — insulates her from liability as long as her<br />

conduct has not been knowingly and intentionally wrongful. The court, then, will<br />

have to decide whether that rule <strong>of</strong> the common law, bestowing a legal privilege<br />

to commit negligent (although objectively wrongful) publication <strong>of</strong> private<br />

information, is reasonable and justifiable in terms <strong>of</strong> Constitution sec 36(1). If the<br />

answer is ‘no,’ the court will have no option but to develop the common law so as<br />

to cure the defect.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 17<br />

section 14 requires that Smith be held liable in this case, given the<br />

evidence and what it shows; and whether (and, if so, how) the<br />

common law as it currently stands must be ‘developed’ to encompass<br />

at least some instances <strong>of</strong> non-intentionally but objectively wrongful<br />

invasion <strong>of</strong> privacy. The first question for decision surely would have<br />

been (a) whether Smith’s conduct was both objectively wrongful and<br />

animo iniurandi according to the pre-existing common-law standard.<br />

If yes, the plaintiffs would prevail. 56 If no, the next question would<br />

have been (b) whether the plaintiffs’ case against Smith discloses a<br />

need to expand common-law liability to catch at least some instances<br />

<strong>of</strong> non-intentionally but objectively wrongful publication <strong>of</strong> private<br />

facts, in order to vindicate fully the right <strong>of</strong> privacy guaranteed by<br />

Constitution section 14. If no, the defendant would prevail. If yes, the<br />

next question would have been (c) precisely what modification <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law is required in order to give due effect to the<br />

constitutional right <strong>of</strong> privacy, in the light <strong>of</strong> possibly competing<br />

constitutional principles and values such as freedom <strong>of</strong> expression —<br />

a question that would have been decided by judges who were at the<br />

same time, inevitably, thinking about (d) whether one or another<br />

newly expanded zone <strong>of</strong> liability that the Court might approve would<br />

catch Smith’s conduct.<br />

Compare that agenda with the one that plaintiffs basing their<br />

claim on the actio iniuriarum must anticipate. Taking the common<br />

law as it stands, they can succeed by establishing that (a) Smith’s<br />

conduct was both objectively wrongful and animo iniurandi in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the extant common law standard <strong>of</strong> liability. 57 Alternatively, given<br />

the court’s inherent power to develop the common law, 58 combined<br />

with the court’s duty to develop the common law so as to promote the<br />

spirit, purport, and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, imposed by<br />

Constitution section 39(2), 59 the plaintiffs can succeed by<br />

establishing, in the light <strong>of</strong> their case against Smith, all <strong>of</strong> the<br />

following: (b) that the common law’s current, blanket prescription <strong>of</strong><br />

non-liability in all instances <strong>of</strong> non-intentionally but objectively<br />

wrongful publication <strong>of</strong> private facts is not acceptable to the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights; plus (c) and (d) that when the common law is properly<br />

56<br />

For completeness, we should note the possibility <strong>of</strong> the defendant persuading the<br />

court that the extant common law standard must undergo development in her<br />

favor, either in terms <strong>of</strong> Constitution sec 8(3) (in order to give due horizontal<br />

effect to the right <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> expression guaranteed by sec 15), or in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

sec 39(2) (in order to keep the common law in tune with the objects <strong>of</strong> the bill <strong>of</strong><br />

rights in the matter <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> expression).<br />

57<br />

And also, if necessary, successfully defending that standard against complaint<br />

that it unduly constricts constitutionally valued freedom <strong>of</strong> expression.<br />

58 ‘The Constitutional Court, Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal and High Courts have the<br />

inherent power to ... develop the common law, taking into account the interests<br />

<strong>of</strong> justice.’ Constitution sec 173.<br />

59 Carmichele v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security 2001 4 SA 938 paras 33-39, makes<br />

clear that a court is required to consider whether such development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law is required in any case where a party urges the point.


18 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

modified in order to give due effect to the constitutional right <strong>of</strong><br />

privacy, in the light <strong>of</strong> possibly competing constitutional principles<br />

and values such as freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, Smith’s conduct in this case<br />

will render her liable to the plaintiffs.<br />

The two agendas look virtually identical. 60 Therefore (the bottom<br />

line): Since Fose suggests the possibility <strong>of</strong> special obstacles facing<br />

claims for constitutional damages, the plaintiffs’ course <strong>of</strong> least<br />

resistance was to base their demand for damages on a claim <strong>of</strong> a<br />

common law violation <strong>of</strong> privacy under the actio iniurarum, with<br />

section 39(2) hovering overhead. To my mind, Madala J’s opinion<br />

adequately (if somewhat elliptically) evinces a clear appreciation <strong>of</strong><br />

the entire line <strong>of</strong> thought I have just been unpacking. 61 At the very<br />

least, Madala J’s opinion is in all respects consistent with this line <strong>of</strong><br />

thought. If, as Woolman truly says, the opinion never poses the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> ‘the [judicial] creation <strong>of</strong> a self-standing constitutional<br />

action grounded in the right <strong>of</strong> privacy’, 62 that is because the<br />

applicants, it would seem for sufficient reasons that the majority may<br />

fairly be taken to have understood, chose not to start up that<br />

particular formulation <strong>of</strong> their claim.<br />

3.5 Jurisdiction<br />

Although the plaintiffs thus chose to rely on a common law and not a<br />

constitutional cause <strong>of</strong> action, their appeal to the Constitutional<br />

Court was quite patently and undeniably one that fell within that<br />

Court’s subject-matter jurisdiction — limited though that jurisdiction<br />

surely is to ‘constitutional matters’ and issues ‘connected to’<br />

constitutional matters. 63 The overarching legal problem presented by<br />

the case is whether the common law <strong>of</strong> delict, in regard to invasion <strong>of</strong><br />

privacy, requires some modification in order to keep it in line with the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights taken as a whole. Involved, as one immediately sees, is<br />

not only a question about whether — and if so, how far — the common<br />

law must be altered so as to attach liability to at least some instances<br />

<strong>of</strong> non-intentionally wrongful disclosure <strong>of</strong> private facts, in order to<br />

keep faith with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights in regard to privacy and dignity.<br />

Equally involved is a question about whether — and if so, how far —<br />

the common law may permissibly impose such liability, having in mind<br />

the commitment <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights in regard to freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

expression. These are obviously issues <strong>of</strong> full-scale constitutional<br />

import.<br />

60 Or very closely so. Arguably, there is a difference, which I will address at the<br />

close <strong>of</strong> my discussion <strong>of</strong> the NM case (see below part 3.10) and in my discussion,<br />

to follow, <strong>of</strong> Masiya.<br />

61 See NM (n 5 above) paras 24, 27, 55-57.<br />

62 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 783.<br />

63 Constitution sec 167(3)(b).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 19<br />

Woolman sees NM as a case in which the Constitutional Court<br />

majority found no occasion to consider these constitutionally fraught<br />

issues <strong>of</strong> common-law development, because it decided the case,<br />

instead, by overturning the High Court’s factual conclusion that<br />

Smith’s objective violation <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs’ privacy was nonintentional<br />

and hence non-actionable under the extant common law<br />

standard. That might seem to invite a question about why the<br />

majority did not order the case dismissed for lack <strong>of</strong> jurisdiction, once<br />

it perceived that the case could and would be decided on standard,<br />

common-law grounds (‘run-<strong>of</strong>-the-mill’ grounds, Woolman calls<br />

them). 64 And indeed, the majority must be faulted for its own<br />

complicity in creating an impression <strong>of</strong> the irrelevance <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights to its disposition <strong>of</strong> the case. 65<br />

That impression, however, is mistaken. We shall see that it is at<br />

least an open question whether the NM majority did not, in effect,<br />

‘develop’ the common law in response to constitutional pressure. (In<br />

that regard, the majority may be faulted for misapprehending the<br />

implications and ramifications <strong>of</strong> its own decision in the case.) But<br />

suppose we say that it did not. The majority could still be right in<br />

affirming the Constitutional Court’s jurisdiction in this case, even<br />

after reaching its conclusion against any constitutionally imposed<br />

need for adjustment <strong>of</strong> the common law. Jurisdiction would hold, as<br />

long as the case presented a fairly debatable question <strong>of</strong> such a need<br />

— including <strong>of</strong> a need to weaken the actio iniuriandum in deference<br />

to freedom <strong>of</strong> expression; for surely such a question is itself a<br />

constitutional matter. (Ask yourself: Does the Constitutional Court<br />

forfeit jurisdiction by deciding, after argument, to uphold as<br />

constitutional a plausibly challenged statute?) 66<br />

The very presence <strong>of</strong> the dissents in this case would thus seem to<br />

settle in the affirmative the question <strong>of</strong> jurisdiction. At all events, the<br />

very question <strong>of</strong> how to construe and apply the extant common law to<br />

64 See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 782 n 40: ‘[T]he court <strong>of</strong>ten accepts cases<br />

prior to the meaningful application <strong>of</strong> its collective “mind” to the question <strong>of</strong><br />

whether or not the case genuinely raises a constitutional issue.’ For an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> a jurisdictional dismissal, upon its becoming apparent to the Court that no<br />

constitutionally-pressured development <strong>of</strong> the common law is in the <strong>of</strong>fing, see<br />

Phoebus Apollo Aviation CC v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security [2002] ZACC 26;<br />

2003 1 BCLR 14 paras 10-12.<br />

65 See NM (n 5 above) para 69 (excusing the Court from considering the possible<br />

impact on freedom <strong>of</strong> expression from its decision to hold Smith liable, on the<br />

ground that ‘this judgment is not extending the common law definition <strong>of</strong><br />

intention to include negligence in relation to the publication <strong>of</strong> private medical<br />

facts’).<br />

66 If, as I assert, the Constitutional Court is competent to hear any non-frivolous<br />

claim <strong>of</strong> a need (in terms <strong>of</strong> sec 39(2)) to develop a common-law rule on which a<br />

party to the case relies, the effect may be to extend the Court’s jurisdiction too<br />

broadly for your comfort. If so, the fault lies not in the Court but in the drafters<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitution. See FI Michelman ‘The supremacy <strong>of</strong> the Constitution and the<br />

rule <strong>of</strong> law’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd<br />

Edition, OS, 2005) ch 11 7-9 (Michelman ‘Supremacy’).


20 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

facts <strong>of</strong> the sort presented by the case <strong>of</strong> NM, being determinative <strong>of</strong><br />

whether the common law must undergo development in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

section 8 or 39, is itself drenched in constitutional-legal<br />

considerations. All <strong>of</strong> the common-law-framed issues in the case —<br />

whether the facts concerning the HIV status <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs were <strong>of</strong><br />

‘private’ quality and whether the private character <strong>of</strong> those facts had<br />

been fatally compromised by previous disclosure for allegedly limited<br />

purposes; 67 whether Smith’s conduct was intentionally wrongful in<br />

the relevant, legal sense; 68 whether that conduct was in any degree<br />

negligent, and, if so, in what specific respects 69 — stood to be decided<br />

in the shadow <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and <strong>of</strong> the looming possibility that<br />

the common law might, depending on how they were decided, have<br />

to be developed under the mandate <strong>of</strong> section 39(2).<br />

Madala J wrote for the majority as follows:<br />

The dispute before us is clearly worthy <strong>of</strong> constitutional adjudication<br />

and it is in the interests <strong>of</strong> justice that the matter be heard by this Court<br />

since it involves a nuanced and sensitive approach to balancing the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> the media, in advocating freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, privacy and<br />

dignity <strong>of</strong> the applicants irrespective <strong>of</strong> whether it is based on the<br />

constitutional law or the common law. This Court is in any event<br />

mandated to develop and interpret the common law if necessary. 70<br />

The last sentence is crucial. In the light <strong>of</strong> what precedes it, it states<br />

why the case does ‘genuinely raise a constitutional issue’ 71 and it<br />

shows that the NM majority in this case necessarily undertook more<br />

(and did more) than merely ‘act as a trier <strong>of</strong> fact in a run-<strong>of</strong>-the-mill<br />

actio iniuriarum matter.’ 72<br />

I shall make these matters more concrete in discussion to follow<br />

below. For now, the point simply is that no one conversant with the<br />

established commitment <strong>of</strong> South African constitutional<br />

jurisprudence to a pervasive influence for the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

throughout the length and breadth <strong>of</strong> the country’s law 73 could doubt<br />

that the knot <strong>of</strong> common-law controversies in NM deserved — if it did<br />

not demand — the attentions <strong>of</strong> at least one <strong>of</strong> South Africa’s two<br />

pinnacle courts, exercising a responsibility imposed on both <strong>of</strong> them<br />

(given how the plaintiffs chose to frame their case) by section 39(2).<br />

Had an appeal to the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal been an open<br />

possibility in this case, and the Constitutional Court nevertheless<br />

67<br />

See NM (n 5 above) paras 34-45 (Madala J); paras 135-137; paras 142-43 (O’Regan<br />

68<br />

69<br />

70<br />

71<br />

72<br />

73<br />

J).<br />

See NM (n 5 above) paras 58-65 (Madala J); paras 155-69 (O’Regan J).<br />

See NM (n 5 above) paras 100-11 (Langa CJ); paras 183-89 (O’Regan J).<br />

NM (n 5 above) para 31.<br />

Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 782 n 40.<br />

Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 783.<br />

See Michelman ‘Supremacy’ (n 66 above) 37-41.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 21<br />

accepted the case for hearing, I would have expected from the Court<br />

some careful explanation for its choice thus to allow circumvention <strong>of</strong><br />

the SCA. That, however, was not the state <strong>of</strong> affairs confronted by the<br />

Constitutional Court when NM’s application arrived at its doorstep.<br />

The SCA had already removed itself from the case by its summary<br />

refusal <strong>of</strong> leave to appeal. 74<br />

3.6 A puzzle<br />

The Constitutional Court divided sharply over assessment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

evidence concerning the intentionality <strong>of</strong> Smith’s conduct. Writing for<br />

a majority <strong>of</strong> seven justices, Madala J concluded that Smith acted<br />

intentionally, within the terms <strong>of</strong> the doctrine then and here<br />

surrounding the actio iniuriarum. 75 In the views <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ and Sachs<br />

J, Smith’s conduct, although not intentionally wrongful, was<br />

negligent or unreasonable (and thus liability-producing under the<br />

common law as they would have had it developed). 76 In the view <strong>of</strong><br />

O’Regan J, Smith’s conduct was entirely free <strong>of</strong> fault. 77 There are two<br />

divisions worth exploring here: first, the division between Madala J’s<br />

majority and the three justices — Langa CJ , Sachs J, and O’Regan J<br />

— who rejected the majority’s finding <strong>of</strong> intentionally wrongful<br />

conduct on the part <strong>of</strong> Smith; and, second, the division among those<br />

three over the question <strong>of</strong> Smith’s negligence.<br />

Smith had directed her trial testimony to explaining how she<br />

acted in the honest belief either that the plaintiffs’ names had<br />

already been disclosed to the general public or else that the plaintiffs<br />

had fully and finally waived objection to any such disclosure. The High<br />

Court had absolved Smith <strong>of</strong> any intention to act contrary to the<br />

plaintiffs’ wishes in this regard. As O’Regan J’s extensive and careful<br />

summary amply demonstrates, such an inference is, at the very least,<br />

reasonably supportable from essentially unchallenged components <strong>of</strong><br />

Smith’s testimony. 78 But then a nagging question arises: How are we<br />

to explain the majority’s apparent deviation from the established<br />

practice <strong>of</strong> deference by appellate tribunals to trial court findings on<br />

issues <strong>of</strong> fact? That looks to me like Sherlock Holmes’s dog that did<br />

not bark: a puzzle we should probe, if we — I mean we as academics<br />

— mean to leave no stone unturned in getting to the innards <strong>of</strong> the<br />

problem presented to the Constitutional Court by the NM case. The<br />

question all the more strikingly demands our attention because the<br />

74<br />

See NM (n 5 above) para 26.<br />

75 See NM (n 5 above) paras 58-65.<br />

76 See NM (n 5 above) paras 92-93 (Langa CJ); paras 205-07 (Sachs J).<br />

77<br />

See NM (n 5 above) paras 155-69 (intention); paras 183-89 (negligence).<br />

78 See NM (n 5 above) paras 157, 159-64.


22 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

majority itself declined to address it, despite its having been pressed<br />

by O’Regan J in dissent. 79<br />

Academics can speculate — sometimes pr<strong>of</strong>itably — about<br />

imaginable, realist-style explanations for such puzzling judicial<br />

silences. (Was the Court just hell-bent on imposing a result that it<br />

likes? Did some intracurial disagreement get in the way <strong>of</strong> full<br />

transparency?) In keeping with my general undertaking for this essay,<br />

I choose a different path <strong>of</strong> speculation — that <strong>of</strong> assuming (or<br />

pretending, if you like that better) that the NM majority thought the<br />

legal reasons for its action (here, overturning a lower court’s factual<br />

determination) so obvious as not to require explanation. The idea is<br />

to see what we might learn about the legal problem presented to the<br />

court by the case at hand by giving the court every benefit <strong>of</strong> the<br />

doubt, working to make their judgment, as a follower <strong>of</strong> Ronald<br />

Dworkin might say, the best that it can be.<br />

Approaching the matter in that spirit, we may discover that the<br />

majority’s finding <strong>of</strong> intentionally wrongful action on Smith’s part,<br />

disputable though it surely is, is no more flatly ‘contrary’ to the<br />

evidentiary record than an opposite finding is. 80 We may find that,<br />

pace all <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ, O’Regan J, and Stu Woolman, the record (as<br />

described by the opinion-writers in NM) can indeed ‘support a factual<br />

finding that [Smith] had acted intentionally to harm the privacy and<br />

dignitary and dignitary interests <strong>of</strong> the applicants.’ 81 Judgment on<br />

this point may depend partly on what you mean by ‘intentionally’, but<br />

that feature in the case is, as I have already pointed out and shall<br />

explain further below, a part <strong>of</strong> what makes this case indubitably one<br />

<strong>of</strong> constitutional law for the Constitutional Court to decide.<br />

3.7 ‘Incremental development’ and Smith’s ‘intention’<br />

Therefore, consider Constitution section 39(2). Remember how it<br />

goes?<br />

When interpreting any legislation, and when developing the common law<br />

or customary law, every court, tribunal or forum must promote the<br />

spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.<br />

All right, then: Where there is fair room for disagreement over the<br />

proper gloss on statutory terminology, and the choice is outcomedeterminative<br />

for the case sub iudice, courts are instructed by the<br />

Constitution to prefer the gloss that they find to be the more truly<br />

79 See NM (n 5 above) paras 125, 169.<br />

80 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 781.<br />

81 As above (invoking the opinions <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ and O’Regan J in NM).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 23<br />

promotive <strong>of</strong> the objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. How goes it, then, when<br />

a like question arises with respect to common law terminology?<br />

Please don’t stand there painting me, along with Stu Woolman,<br />

into ‘some ... benighted Hartian, positivist view’ 82 <strong>of</strong> the common<br />

law, or telling me that there is so such thing as ‘common law<br />

terminology’ to make a match with statutory terminology. I join<br />

Woolman in knowing — and you know, too — that there very obviously<br />

is such a thing, which is not to say that Woolman and I do not also fully<br />

understand the common law to be, at bottom, an assemblage <strong>of</strong><br />

always open-ended principles, not <strong>of</strong> closed-ended rule-sentences.<br />

(We can leave aside whether the latter is any the less true <strong>of</strong> statute<br />

law.) 83 Where Woolman and I both stand our ground is on the point<br />

that lawyers and the rule <strong>of</strong> law cannot make do with a common law<br />

discourse that is not densely populated by rule statements, ‘common<br />

law terminology’. We both — and so do you, Reader — ‘work within a<br />

tradition ... <strong>of</strong> which South Africa is most avowedly a part’, which<br />

‘recognises rules as a necessary feature <strong>of</strong> the legal [including the<br />

common law] landscape.’ 84 Witness:<br />

For the common law action for invasion <strong>of</strong> privacy based on the actio<br />

iniuriarum to succeed, the following must be proved:<br />

(a) Impairment <strong>of</strong> the applicants’ privacy;<br />

(b) Wrongfulness; and<br />

(c) Intention (animus iniurandi). 85<br />

The elements <strong>of</strong> the actio injuriarum are the intentional and wrongful<br />

infringement <strong>of</strong> a person’s dignitas, fama, or corpus. 86<br />

Those are two somewhat variant, but essentially identical, renditions<br />

<strong>of</strong> the same, single instance <strong>of</strong> a genus that lawyers routinely call<br />

‘rules’ <strong>of</strong> the common law. As such, they exemplify perfectly what I<br />

mean by my jurisprudentially obtuse expression, ‘common law<br />

terminology’, coined by way <strong>of</strong> analogy to ‘statutory terminology’.<br />

Now, cases arise in which statutory terminology is found<br />

unacceptably out <strong>of</strong> sorts with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, on any reading <strong>of</strong> the<br />

statute falling within the outer limits imposed by a decent respect for<br />

grammar and lexicon. 87 In those cases, by constitutional command, a<br />

judicial declaration <strong>of</strong> the statute’s ‘invalidity’ — unconstitutionality<br />

82<br />

Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 789.<br />

83 See generally, on these matters, R Dworkin Law’s Empire (1986).<br />

84 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 791.<br />

85<br />

NM (n 5 above) para 55 (Madala J).<br />

86 NM (n 5 above) para 151 (O’Regan J) (citing both Voet Commentary on the<br />

87<br />

Pandects 47 10 1 and R v Umfaan 1908 TS 62 at 66 (Innes CJ)).<br />

See, eg, National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs<br />

2000 2 SA 1 (CC), 2000 1 BCLR 39 (CC) paras 25-26 (Home Affairs).


24 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

— must ensue. 88 How goes it with cases in which common law<br />

terminology is similarly found to be irreparably out <strong>of</strong> sorts with the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights: say, because it would flatly restrict civil liability for<br />

certain sorts <strong>of</strong> wrongful harming to instances in which the wronging<br />

is intentional, when the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights would be better satisfied by<br />

lifting that flat restriction? You might answer: In such cases, the<br />

common law is to be declared invalid as it stands and then remedially<br />

‘developed’ so as to cure the defect. You might <strong>of</strong>fer as an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> such a cure (passing, for now, the absence <strong>of</strong> any declaration <strong>of</strong><br />

invalidity) the bit <strong>of</strong> terminological surgery supported by Langa CJ,<br />

O’Regan J, and Sachs J in NM, according to which the term ‘intention<br />

(animus iniurandi)’, where it appears in item (c) in Madala J’s above<br />

recital <strong>of</strong> the elements <strong>of</strong> the civil cause <strong>of</strong> action for invasion <strong>of</strong><br />

privacy, would be replaced (in some, if not all, categories <strong>of</strong> cases) by<br />

the term ‘intention (animus iniurandi) or negligence’. We have there,<br />

as it were, a remedy <strong>of</strong> ‘reading in’. (Compare it with a replacement<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘spouse’, in a statute, by ‘spouse or partner, in a permanent<br />

same-sex life partnership in which the partners have undertaken<br />

reciprocal duties <strong>of</strong> support’.) 89<br />

Have you begun to glimpse the point I am after? Section 39(2)<br />

contains an express instruction — call it a constitution-conforming<br />

instruction — to judges engaged in the interpretation <strong>of</strong> statutory<br />

terminology, according to which the judges must interpret with a view<br />

to promoting the spirit, purport, and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights,<br />

presumably before deciding whether they must declare the statute<br />

invalid and resort (perhaps) to remedial reading-in. On its face,<br />

section 39(2) entirely omits any parallel, express instruction to judges<br />

engaged in the contextualised application (as opposed to any surgical<br />

alteration by excision or insertion <strong>of</strong> words) <strong>of</strong> common law<br />

terminology. Since such an instruction does appear in the Interim<br />

Constitution, one might pause for a moment to wonder whether the<br />

omission was intentional. 90 It is difficult, however, to conceive what<br />

the drafters might have intended by it. Are there, after all, no cases<br />

in which a due regard for the objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights would, or<br />

should, crucially affect a judge’s interpretive shading and application<br />

88<br />

See Constitution sec 172(1)(a).<br />

89 Satchwell v President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa & Another 2002 6 SA 1 (CC),<br />

2002 9 BCLR 986 (CC) para 37.<br />

90<br />

Compare Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa Act 108 <strong>of</strong> 1994 (Interim<br />

Constitution) sec 35(2):<br />

No law which limits any <strong>of</strong> the rights entrenched in this Chapter, shall be<br />

constitutionally invalid solely by reason <strong>of</strong> the fact that the wording used prima<br />

facie exceeds the limits imposed in this Chapter, provided such a law is<br />

reasonably capable <strong>of</strong> a more restricted interpretation which does not exceed<br />

such limits, in which event such law shall be construed as having a meaning in<br />

accordance with the said more restricted interpretation.<br />

(The Afrikaans version has ‘reg’ where the English has ‘law’; and so, by the<br />

reasoning used by Kentridge J in Du Plessis, it presumably means to cover<br />

common law along with statute law. See Du Plessis (n 17 above) para 44.)


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 25<br />

<strong>of</strong> common law terminology as it stands to the facts <strong>of</strong> a particular<br />

case? Thus, without any declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity and concomitant<br />

surgery on the terminology as received? If so, are not the courts<br />

plainly — if implicitly — required by section 39(2) to shade and apply<br />

in favor <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights? And is it not a part <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional<br />

Court’s responsibility — and jurisdiction — to speak the last word on<br />

whether lower courts have done so properly in a given case?<br />

In a luminous opinion for the Court in K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and<br />

Security (‘NK’), 91 O’Regan J answered all <strong>of</strong> those questions with a<br />

resounding ‘yes’. In NK, the plaintiff, having been assaulted and raped<br />

by police <strong>of</strong>ficers, sued the Minister for damages on a theory <strong>of</strong><br />

respondeat superior. The plaintiff stood ready to contend for<br />

‘development’ <strong>of</strong> the common law, but only if her case would not<br />

succeed ‘on a proper application’ <strong>of</strong> the extant common law rule <strong>of</strong><br />

vicarious liability. 92 You can see why she had to argue thus in the<br />

alternative. As O’Regan J explained:<br />

the common law [normally] develops incrementally through the rules <strong>of</strong><br />

precedent ... [It sometimes happens that a court must] determine<br />

whether a new set <strong>of</strong> facts falls within or beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> an existing<br />

rule. The precise ambit <strong>of</strong> each rule is therefore clarified in relation to<br />

each new set <strong>of</strong> facts. A court faced with a new set <strong>of</strong> facts, not on all<br />

fours with any set <strong>of</strong> facts previously adjudicated, must decide whether<br />

a common-law rule applies to this new factual situation or not. If it holds<br />

that the new set <strong>of</strong> facts falls within the rule, the ambit <strong>of</strong> the rule is<br />

extended. If it holds that it does not, the ambit <strong>of</strong> the rule is restricted,<br />

not extended. 93<br />

O’Regan J had no doubt that a court facing such a decision is bound<br />

by the mandate <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) — to heed the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights when<br />

‘developing’ the common law — even though no ‘new’ or ‘changed’<br />

common law rule is in the <strong>of</strong>fing: 94<br />

The overall purpose <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) is to ensure that our common law is<br />

infused with the values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. It is not only in cases where<br />

existing rules are clearly inconsistent with the Constitution that such an<br />

infusion is required. The normative influence <strong>of</strong> the Constitution must be<br />

felt throughout the common law. Courts making decisions which involve<br />

the incremental development <strong>of</strong> the rules <strong>of</strong> the common law in cases<br />

where the values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution are relevant are therefore also<br />

bound by the terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2). The obligation imposed upon courts<br />

by section 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution is thus extensive, requiring courts to<br />

be alert to the normative framework <strong>of</strong> the Constitution not only when<br />

91 [2005] ZACC 8; 2005 6 SA 419 (CC) (NK).<br />

92 NK (n 91 above) para 14.<br />

93<br />

NK (n 91 above) para 16.<br />

94 As above.


26 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

some startling new development <strong>of</strong> the common law is in issue, but in all<br />

cases where the incremental development <strong>of</strong> the rule is in issue. 95<br />

By ‘incremental development’, O’Regan J plainly meant the process<br />

she had just previously been describing: ‘A court [facing] a new set <strong>of</strong><br />

facts, not on all fours with any set <strong>of</strong> facts previously adjudicated,<br />

[deciding] whether a [settled] common-law rule applies to this new<br />

factual situation or not.’ In NK, O’Regan J held that the judicial work<br />

in such cases should count as ‘development’ <strong>of</strong> the common law for<br />

the purposes <strong>of</strong> section 39(2). 96 It seems she felt she had to say so, in<br />

order to establish firmly the Constitutional Court’s jurisdiction in the<br />

case before her, which she saw as presenting a question about<br />

whether certain facts fell properly within the rule <strong>of</strong> respondeat<br />

superior, construing and applying that rule with due regard to the Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights.<br />

Madala J’s majority in NM found that defendant Smith’s conduct<br />

fell under the head <strong>of</strong> ‘intentionally’ wrongful privacy-invasion —<br />

insomuch as (or so the majority found from the evidence) Smith ‘at<br />

least foresaw the possibility that the consent had not been given to<br />

the disclosure’. 97 Might we not well understand them as having<br />

followed in the tracks <strong>of</strong> O’Regan J’s work in NK — deciding, under<br />

pressure from the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, ‘whether the common law rule<br />

applies to this new factual situation or not’? ‘While the claim falls to<br />

be dealt with under the actio iniuriaum,’ the majority had already<br />

reminded us, ‘the Constitution must inform the application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law’. 98 Were they just vamping there, or might we take<br />

those words as a cue to understanding that the majority’s application<br />

to Smith’s conduct <strong>of</strong> the common law category <strong>of</strong> ‘intention’ (which,<br />

we must remember, already included dolus eventualis), was shaded<br />

or tinctured with a view to bringing or keeping the common law<br />

doctrine in full conformity with the objects <strong>of</strong> Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights? 99<br />

It is not impossible to see why the majority might have chosen<br />

such a path to judgment in Smith’s case, in preference to a judicially<br />

declared, surgical replacement <strong>of</strong> the term ‘intention’ in Madala J’s<br />

item (c) by ‘intention or negligence’ — even granting that the latter<br />

95 NK (n 91 above) para 17.<br />

96 See NK (n 91 above) paras 16, 17.<br />

97<br />

NK (n 91above) para 64 (Madala J).<br />

98 NM (n 5 above) para 28; see also para 50 (‘If human dignity is regarded as<br />

foundational in our Constitution, a corollary thereto must be that it must be<br />

jealously guarded and protected.’).<br />

99 I am not alone in thus understanding Madala J’s opinion; I have Sachs J for<br />

company. See NM (n 5 above) paras 201-02 (Sachs J) (‘It is in [the] human rights<br />

context [addressed by the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights] that the competing interests at stake in<br />

the present matter must be dealt with. In a fittingly accessible manner, Madala J<br />

has indicated how in the particular circumstances <strong>of</strong> this case competing needs<br />

with respect to human dignity, on the one hand, and freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, on<br />

the other, should be reconciled.’)


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 27<br />

technique carries with it a more immediately accessible package <strong>of</strong><br />

instruction to learners <strong>of</strong> the law. 100 Terminological replacement is<br />

inevitably — to some irreducible degree — done at wholesale, and it<br />

is — to that irreducible degree — inevitably a blunter instrument than<br />

pure case-by-case steering. If — to illustrate — we follow the carefully<br />

plotted line <strong>of</strong> thought in O’Regan J’s NM opinion (agreed to by both<br />

Langa CJ and Sachs J), a due regard for the Constitution’s privacy<br />

right calls for addition <strong>of</strong> negligence liability to the actio iniuriarum<br />

for privacy invasion. 101 But hold the phone. A due regard for the<br />

Constitution’s freedom-<strong>of</strong>-expression principle calls for at-least<br />

initial or provisional restriction <strong>of</strong> the to-be-added negligence liability<br />

to a category <strong>of</strong> ‘media’ defendants, with ‘media’ defined<br />

expansively enough to include the authors and publishers <strong>of</strong> books as<br />

well as the more strictly journalistic, daily and periodical print and<br />

electronic media. 102 There is nothing in itself wrong with such a<br />

definitional-categorical approach, conducted with the sort <strong>of</strong> caution<br />

and care evinced by O’Regan J’s opinion. But neither can it be thought<br />

indefensible for a judge to decide that the process <strong>of</strong> drawing the<br />

distinctions that contextual variations will require is better pursued,<br />

at least for the time being, through the inflections <strong>of</strong> case-by-case<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the extant rule and the operations <strong>of</strong> stare decisis (as<br />

explained by O’Regan J in NK) than through process <strong>of</strong> word-andphrase-surgery-and-implant<br />

otherwise known as ‘development’ <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law, even if the choice for pure, case-by-case adjustment<br />

entails some sacrifice <strong>of</strong> transparency to rote learners.<br />

Transparency is not entirely foregone, after all, as long as stare<br />

decisis holds in measurable degree. That is why I say that Madala J<br />

spoke too hastily in saying that there was no need for him to consider<br />

any possible ‘chilling effect’ <strong>of</strong> his judgment on freedom on<br />

expression, given that (as he said) he was merely applying the<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> delict as it then stood, not ‘extending’ it to include<br />

liability for negligence. 103 As O’Regan J’s analysis in NK makes clear,<br />

the NM majority’s quite striking application <strong>of</strong> the ‘intention’<br />

standard to the facts <strong>of</strong> the NM case cannot avoid making waves as a<br />

precedent, and so the question whether those waves will have a<br />

constitutionally significant chilling effect cannot be avoided.<br />

As I am about to show, however, the right answer to that question<br />

is pretty plainly ‘no’ in Smith’s case, because the true and entirely<br />

100<br />

‘Clear and accessible norms’ in the words <strong>of</strong> Sachs J. NM (n 5 above) para 204.<br />

101 See NM (n 5 above) paras 92, 95 (Langa CJ); paras 171-82 (O’Regan J); paras 203-<br />

04 (Sachs ). Sachs J speaks <strong>of</strong> the extended standard <strong>of</strong> liability as one <strong>of</strong><br />

‘reasonableness’, but he evidently has in mind approximately what Langa CJ and<br />

O’Regan J mean by ‘negligence’.<br />

102 See NM (n 5 above) paras 92-93, 95, 98-99 (Langa CJ); paras 203-05 (Sachs J);<br />

paras 177-82 (O’Regan J).<br />

103 NM (n 5 above) para 69.


28 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

innocuous ‘rule’ <strong>of</strong> Smith’s case can easily be taken to be this: If you<br />

are publishing an account <strong>of</strong> events and transactions including private<br />

facts about real persons, and you attach the true names <strong>of</strong> those<br />

persons to those facts, without having directly in hand and before<br />

your eyes pro<strong>of</strong>-positive <strong>of</strong> their express permission to have you do so,<br />

and you cannot adduce any credible reason to think that a public that<br />

knows the names is better informed or otherwise more enriched that<br />

a public that does not, you are acting in culpable disregard (call it<br />

‘negligent’, call it ‘reckless’) <strong>of</strong> those persons’ presumptive interest<br />

in retaining control over dissemination <strong>of</strong> that private fact about<br />

themselves. Lest the bar and lower bench should be left in the<br />

slightest doubt about the lesson to be drawn, Sachs J took pains to<br />

point ‘the moral <strong>of</strong> the story’:<br />

[U]nless overwhelming public interest points the other way, publishers<br />

should refrain from circulating information identifying the HIV status <strong>of</strong><br />

named individuals, unless they have the clearest possible pro<strong>of</strong> to<br />

consent to publication having been given. 104<br />

That does not seem so hard to learn, even for ‘second-year LL.Bs’. 105<br />

I have little doubt <strong>of</strong> the message by now having found its way into<br />

every well-heeled South African publisher’s and writer’s in-box.<br />

Of course, it is very far from a full treatise on the values served<br />

by the constitutional rights <strong>of</strong> privacy and freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, by<br />

comparison, say with the entirely welcome <strong>of</strong>ferings we find in the<br />

opinion <strong>of</strong> O’Regan J — memorable passages on the values<br />

underpinning the constitutional rights to privacy and freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

expression, <strong>of</strong> which I would not wish the South African constituency<br />

(or the world constituency, for that matter) to be deprived. 106 For<br />

those passages, or anything remotely comparable, the NM majority<br />

opinion can claim no credit. And yet it does not necessarily follow that<br />

the majority opinion fails to give ‘identifiable content’ to provisions<br />

in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, or that it leaves the bar and lower bench without<br />

worthwhile new instruction about ‘how the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights might<br />

operate’ in an important class <strong>of</strong> relevantly similar, future<br />

matters. 107 NM might still be treated as one <strong>of</strong> those occasions,<br />

mentioned by Woolman, <strong>of</strong> an ‘opportunity’ thrown up by the stream<br />

<strong>of</strong> cases with varying fact-patterns, to ‘expand our understanding <strong>of</strong><br />

how given rights function in given environments.’ 108<br />

104 NM (n 5 above) para 209.<br />

105 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 787 n 47.<br />

106 See NM (n 5 above) paras 126-34 (on the values underpinning the constitutional<br />

right to privacy); paras 144-46 (on the values underpinning the constitutional<br />

right to freedom <strong>of</strong> expression).<br />

107 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 763.<br />

108 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 765.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 29<br />

My proposed account <strong>of</strong> the NM majority’s finding <strong>of</strong> liabilityproducing<br />

‘intention’ on the part <strong>of</strong> defendant Smith has the further<br />

merit <strong>of</strong> providing an honorable explanation for the majority’s refusal<br />

<strong>of</strong> deference to the High Court’s contrary finding. When extant<br />

common law appears to require development in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2)<br />

or section 8(3), the Constitutional Court follows — and for good reason<br />

— a general practice <strong>of</strong> giving the High Courts and the Supreme Court<br />

<strong>of</strong> Appeal a first crack at the work. 109 No one, however, would suggest<br />

that the Constitutional Court should defer when it comes to deciding<br />

— as the Court had to decide, for example, in Khumalo — whether a<br />

common law solution reached by the common law judiciary (so to call<br />

them) is sufficiently in synch with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights as not to call for<br />

further correction. Nor, by the same token, should we expect the<br />

Constitutional Court to defer when it judges whether a lower court’s<br />

in-context application <strong>of</strong> a common law rule has been carried out with<br />

due regard for the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights — see NK — any more than when the<br />

Constitutional Court judges whether a lower court’s in-context<br />

application <strong>of</strong> a statute has complied adequately with the command<br />

<strong>of</strong> section 39(2). 110<br />

3.8 Smith’s negligence (or ‘intention’?)<br />

I turn now to the division among the three judges who thought the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> Smith’s negligence should properly be decisive <strong>of</strong> the<br />

case. I do so with the expectation that our examination <strong>of</strong> this division<br />

will cast some further light on the majority’s finding <strong>of</strong> Smith’s<br />

tortious ‘intention’.<br />

Having found an absence <strong>of</strong> intentional wrongdoing by Smith,<br />

Langa CJ, Sachs J, and O’Regan J all had to confront the question <strong>of</strong><br />

possibly developing the common law so as to impose liability for at<br />

least some instances <strong>of</strong> negligently wrongful invasion <strong>of</strong> privacy. All<br />

three agreed, at least tentatively, on the introduction <strong>of</strong> a negligence<br />

standard for ‘media’ defendants only, roughly on the model <strong>of</strong> the<br />

109 See, eg, Masiya (n 4 above) para 17 (‘Ordinarily, constitutional matters involving<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> the common law should first be taken to the Supreme Court<br />

<strong>of</strong> Appeal before they reach this Court because <strong>of</strong> the breadth <strong>of</strong> its jurisdiction<br />

and its expertise in the common law.’); Carmichele (n 59 above) paras 55-56:<br />

The proper development <strong>of</strong> the common law under section 39(2) requires close<br />

and sensitive interaction between, on the one hand, the High Courts and the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal which have particular expertise and experience in this<br />

area <strong>of</strong> the law and, on the other hand, this Court. Not only must the common<br />

law be developed in a way which meets the section 39(2) objectives, but it must<br />

be done in a way most appropriate for the development <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

within its own paradigm. There are notionally different ways to develop the<br />

common-law under section 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, all <strong>of</strong> which might be<br />

consistent with its provisions. Not all would necessarily be equally beneficial for<br />

the common law.<br />

110 See, eg, Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v Minister <strong>of</strong> Environmental Affairs & Tourism<br />

[2005] ZACC 8; 2005 6 SA 419 (CC) paras 72-98.


30 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

SCA’s introduction in Bogoshi 111 <strong>of</strong> a ‘reasonable-to-publish-even-iffalse-in-fact’<br />

standard <strong>of</strong> defamation liability for such defendants, 112<br />

approved by the Constitutional Court in Khumalo as an acceptable<br />

reconciliation <strong>of</strong> the potentially conflicting demands <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights regarding the rights to human dignity and to freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

expression. 113 Where the three came apart was over the application<br />

<strong>of</strong> a negligence standard to the evidence in the NM case.<br />

Of the three, O’Regan J was by far the most outspoken on the<br />

point — which seems surely correct — that all such applications must<br />

be sensitive to all <strong>of</strong> the affected objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, which<br />

in this case very saliently included freedom <strong>of</strong> expression. 114 In order<br />

to avoid imposing too great a burden on freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, said<br />

O’Regan J, the law must leave journalists free to ‘to publish<br />

information provided to them by reliable [published] sources without<br />

rechecking in each case whether the publication was lawful,’ at least<br />

where ‘there are no grounds for ... suspicion [<strong>of</strong>] a risk that the<br />

original publication was not lawful.’ 115 In the view <strong>of</strong> O’Regan J,<br />

grounds for suspicion were lacking in Smith’s case. Therefore, to hold<br />

her liable,<br />

one would ... have to find that wherever a reputable source has<br />

published [names <strong>of</strong> persons about whom private facts are disclosed],<br />

secondary publication may not take place without the existence <strong>of</strong><br />

informed consent having been independently verified, so that in each<br />

case, the subsequent publisher would have to re-ascertain the facts. 116<br />

And such a rule, O’Regan J concluded, would impose an<br />

‘unacceptable burden on the dissemination <strong>of</strong> information.’ 117<br />

There is an apparent flaw in this reasoning, and it lies in the word<br />

‘wherever’ (as in ‘wherever a reputable source has published ... ’).<br />

Let us grant O’Regan J her premise (strenuously disputed by all the<br />

other justices) that grounds for suspicion <strong>of</strong> a lack <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs’<br />

consent to unlimited public identification by name were entirely<br />

absent from the totality <strong>of</strong> the circumstances that Smith confronted.<br />

111 National Media Ltd v Bogoshi 1998 4 SA 1196 (SCA); [1998] 4 All SA 347 (SCA).<br />

112 See NM (n 5 above) paras 172-77 (O’Regan J).<br />

113 See Khumalo (n 54 above) paras 43-45. It is interesting to note how Khumalo and<br />

the NM minority approach the ‘reasonableness’/‘negligence’ standard from<br />

opposite directions. Khumalo approved a shift <strong>of</strong> the balance in favor <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> expression (and thus against dignitas) by moving away from a prior rule <strong>of</strong><br />

strict liability for false-in-fact, defamatory publications, whereas as the NM<br />

minority would have shifted the balance in favor <strong>of</strong> dignitas (and thus against<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> expression) by introducing negligence liability in respect <strong>of</strong> what had<br />

previously been treated as a strictly intentional tort.<br />

114 See Khumalo (n 54 above) paras 1444-48.<br />

115 NM (n 5 above) paras 185, 187.<br />

116 NM (n 5 above) para 186.<br />

117 As above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 31<br />

(More on this below.) It still does not follow that holding Smith liable<br />

for negligence in this case would signal liability ‘wherever’ a<br />

journalist or book-writer follows reputable sources in publishing<br />

private facts about named persons, and consent from those persons<br />

unexpectedly turns out to have been lacking. It only follows that<br />

liability will attach to the conduct <strong>of</strong> the second publisher when she<br />

has no sufficient reason for taking the slightest risk <strong>of</strong> invading<br />

privacy by including the names. That is a far cry from ‘wherever’, and<br />

moreover it is exactly what is required by a general norm — we call it<br />

‘negligence’ — <strong>of</strong> acting with due regard for other peoples’ interests<br />

at risk, very saliently including (in the South African legal order), their<br />

constitutionally recognised interests both in freedom <strong>of</strong> expression<br />

and in privacy.<br />

O’Regan J was prepared to find from Smith’s testimony that Smith<br />

‘simply did not entertain the possibility that either the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Pretoria</strong> or Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Strauss would have sent a report to a Member <strong>of</strong><br />

Parliament in circumstances where the consent given was only <strong>of</strong> a<br />

limited variety in a publication that did not draw attention to that<br />

fact.’ 118 I take that to signify an ultimate finding by O’Regan J that,<br />

on a preponderance <strong>of</strong> the evidence, Smith was just sucked in<br />

unthinkingly by deceptive appearances that would have prevented<br />

the question <strong>of</strong> the scope <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs’ consent from even arising<br />

in her mind or anyone’s. 119<br />

Yet the evidence on that point, as described by O’Regan J, seems<br />

to me quite open to an opposite construction. I have in mind a passage<br />

in Smith’s book, flagged by O’Regan J, that appears to say that Smith,<br />

while writing the book, decided to include the names after reflecting<br />

consciously on a series <strong>of</strong> events that led her to infer that the<br />

‘consent’ referred to in the Strauss Report must have been ‘a general<br />

consent on which she could rely’. 120 By what seems to me a quite<br />

permissible reading, the passage in question shows Smith consciously<br />

deciding that she has a sufficient basis for inferring that a general<br />

consent had been given, and the names, therefore, can safely be<br />

included. I notice also Smith’s testimony ‘point[ing] to three facts<br />

118 NM (n 5 above) para 184.<br />

119 ‘On a preponderance <strong>of</strong> the evidence’ because O’Regan J allows that Smith<br />

carries the onus <strong>of</strong> establishing absence <strong>of</strong> negligence, given pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the<br />

objective fact <strong>of</strong> her having publishing private facts without consent. See NM (n 5<br />

above) para 179.<br />

120 ‘In the chapter concerned, Ms Smith recounts the story <strong>of</strong> the clinical trial. She<br />

then points to the fact that details <strong>of</strong> the applicants’ complaints were originally<br />

published in the New York Review <strong>of</strong> Books, though under pseudonyms. She then<br />

points to the fact that pseudonyms were not subsequently used in the Strauss<br />

Report but that the real names were given and she uses the real names. The<br />

chapter itself therefore suggests that she thought that after the New York Review<br />

<strong>of</strong> Books article had been published, the applicants had consented to the<br />

publication <strong>of</strong> their names by Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Strauss and that that consent was a<br />

general consent on which she could rely.’ NM (n 5 above) para 166.


32 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

which grounded her belief that Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Strauss had obtained general<br />

consent from the applicants for the publication <strong>of</strong> their names.’ 121 If<br />

we take this testimony to mean that Smith adverted consciously to<br />

these facts in forming her belief, at a time when she was still writing<br />

her book, then the testimony amounts to Smith’s admission that she<br />

knew then that she was choosing on the basis <strong>of</strong> something less than<br />

full and direct knowledge <strong>of</strong> consent to publication by her. To put the<br />

matter in language lawyers will understand, Smith was (her own<br />

testimony suggests) consciously choosing on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

circumstantial and not ‘real’ evidence.<br />

The testimony as a whole (I mean as described by O’Regan J; I<br />

have not read the trial transcript) looks to me quite consistent with —<br />

I do not say it compels, but Smith has the onus — a finding that Smith,<br />

while writing, adverted consciously to the question <strong>of</strong> the scope <strong>of</strong><br />

consent, attempted a judgment about that matter on the evidence<br />

she had, and judged erroneously. I do not say she judged that<br />

particular question irrationally, or with the slightest bad faith, or<br />

even without the very heavy odds in her favor. I do say she<br />

nevertheless acted irresponsibly, in an important sense that the legal<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> negligence precisely nails. I say that, under a negligence<br />

standard properly understood, Smith’s mistake <strong>of</strong> judgment cannot be<br />

excusable, no matter how unlikely the error, when there was literally<br />

nothing worthwhile to be gained by taken any chance at all.<br />

But was there really nothing to be gained? ‘Freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

expression,’ states O’Regan J,<br />

is important because it is an indispensable element <strong>of</strong> a democratic<br />

society. But it is indispensable not only because it makes democracy<br />

possible, but also because <strong>of</strong> its importance to the development <strong>of</strong><br />

individuals, for it enables them to form and share opinions and thus<br />

enhances human dignity and autonomy. Recognising the role <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> expression in asserting the moral autonomy <strong>of</strong> individuals<br />

demonstrates the close links between freedom <strong>of</strong> expression and other<br />

constitutional rights such as human dignity, privacy and freedom.<br />

Underlying all these constitutional rights is the constitutional<br />

celebration <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> morally autonomous human beings<br />

independently able to form opinions and act on them. 122<br />

One concurs wholeheartedly, or at any rate I do. The question that<br />

stares one in the face, though, is how any <strong>of</strong> these interests in<br />

democracy, autonomy, or opinion-formation is compromised in the<br />

slightest (or ‘chilled’, if you like) by holding Smith liable for her<br />

borderline-inexplicable choice to publish the real names <strong>of</strong> three<br />

otherwise non-notable women who figured as persons living with HIV<br />

121 NM (n 5 above) para 163 (O’Regan J).<br />

122 NM (n 5 above) para 145 (O’Regan J).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 33<br />

in Smith’s no-doubt highly informative account <strong>of</strong> Patricia De Lille’s<br />

public career. What is the value-added by inclusion <strong>of</strong> these women’s<br />

names? Smith’s own explanation <strong>of</strong> the choice is that she included the<br />

names in order to give her book ‘authenticity’. 123 Please! Would the<br />

book have been one whit the less authentic, the less informative, the<br />

less democracy- or autonomy-supportive, if Smith had fictionalised<br />

the names, explaining in a preface or a footnote that she had done<br />

so? 124 Surely a person acts negligently when she chooses a course <strong>of</strong><br />

action that anyone can see has the capacity to injure others, and a<br />

reasonable member <strong>of</strong> society would perceive an obvious way to avoid<br />

the risk <strong>of</strong> injury, which is clearly <strong>of</strong> lesser cost to anyone than the<br />

injury might be to any who would suffer it. 125<br />

In Smith’s case, avoidance was available at the negligible cost <strong>of</strong><br />

forbearing to include the names. The cost <strong>of</strong> avoidance thus would not<br />

have been that <strong>of</strong> the onerous detective work posited by O’Regan J,<br />

or <strong>of</strong> the delays in publishing publicly valuable content that such work<br />

might occasion; it would only have been the loss <strong>of</strong> the smidgin <strong>of</strong><br />

novelistic coloration that Smith added to her book by inserting the<br />

publicly meaningless real names <strong>of</strong> three women who were otherwise<br />

living their lives entirely out <strong>of</strong> the public eye — a cost bordering on<br />

zero, it would seem, in a public perspective.<br />

And now the circle closes. Consider that the effrontery <strong>of</strong> seeking<br />

to excuse the decision to name the plaintiffs by the appeal to<br />

‘authenticity’ may have been instrumental in leading Madala J’s<br />

majority to its conclusion that Smith’s choice was ‘intentional’ in the<br />

pertinent, legal sense. 126 Sachs J, supporting a finding <strong>of</strong> negligence,<br />

remarked that ‘if the slightest doubt existed, there was no need to<br />

publish the actual names <strong>of</strong> the defendants.’ 127 I so not see why one<br />

123 See NM (n 5 above) paras 24, 61.<br />

124 If ‘authenticity’ really means scooping the competition, or showing what a<br />

superior gumshoe you are, it cannot, in the Constitution’s scales, weigh tellingly<br />

against a risk to other people’s privacy and dignity. If ‘authenticity’ means<br />

providing your readership with persuasive indication that you really have had<br />

access to authoritative sources, or to the sources you say you have accessed, it<br />

does weigh tellingly in principle, but not in application to this case. Smith had<br />

plenty <strong>of</strong> other concrete particulars to carry that burden, not to mention Patricia<br />

De Lille’s endorsement <strong>of</strong> her book as an ‘authorised’ biography.<br />

125 ‘The traditional test for negligence is axiomatic ... : negligence is established if a<br />

reasonable person in the position <strong>of</strong> the defendant would have foreseen the<br />

harm, the reasonable person would have taken steps to prevent it and the<br />

defendant did not take those steps.’ NM (n 5 above) para 100 (Langa CJ), citing<br />

Krueger v Coetzee 1966 2 SA 428 (A) at 430E. It would seem that Langa CJ meant<br />

‘would have foreseen some risk [not the certainty or near-certainty] <strong>of</strong> harm’.<br />

Later on in his opinion, he wrote that the crucial question in the case was<br />

‘whether the reasonable journalist [in Smith’s position] would have foreseen the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> consent.’ NM (n 5 above) para 105. I have suggested that<br />

the evidence is compatible with a finding that Smith did in fact foresee that<br />

possibility — granted that she, with good reason, regarded it as very slight.<br />

126 See NM (n 5 above) paras 54, 61, 65.<br />

127 NM (n 5 above) para 205.


34 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

should not go a bit further and say: Since there was nothing <strong>of</strong> value<br />

to be gained by publishing the true names (recall the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

openly fictionalising them), it was negligent to publish them without<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> positive <strong>of</strong> consent, expressly directed to the would-be<br />

publisher in question.<br />

For this reason, I am led to quibble with the statement <strong>of</strong> Langa<br />

CJ that ‘the’ crucial question to be decided in Smith’s case was<br />

‘whether the reasonable journalist [in Smith’s position] would have<br />

foreseen the possibility <strong>of</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> consent’. 128 That is, <strong>of</strong> course,<br />

a highly pertinent question for any judge approaching this case. To my<br />

mind, though, an equally crucial question is whether a responsible<br />

author, aware that she lacked pro<strong>of</strong>-positive <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs’ consent<br />

to the inclusion <strong>of</strong> their names in her book (as distinguished from<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Strauss’s report), would have included the names. One can<br />

agree with O’Regan J that the reasonable author would not have<br />

‘foreseen’ the possibility <strong>of</strong> a restricted consent, if by that we mean<br />

that the reasonable author would have rated that possibility<br />

extremely unlikely, and still find plainly negligent — plainly fraught<br />

with an unjustifiable risk <strong>of</strong> harm to others — the publication <strong>of</strong><br />

private facts about named persons whom you do not know and with<br />

whom you have never met, whose full and clear consents you do not<br />

have in hand, and who might just as well have gone nameless in your<br />

publication, so far any anyone’s legitimate interests are concerned.<br />

Are we perhaps verging here on ‘reckless disregard’? Gaining, then,<br />

some further insight into the majority’s finding <strong>of</strong> ‘intentionally’<br />

wrongful conduct by Smith? 129<br />

3.9 A ‘minimalist’ moment?<br />

O’Regan J’s opinion does not address at all this matter <strong>of</strong> the<br />

vanishingly low value for Smith’s book <strong>of</strong> naming the plaintiffs, even<br />

though other justices raised it quite vividly in their opinions, and even<br />

though the omission leaves in limbo both O’Regan J’s conclusion that<br />

Smith was not negligent and her complaint about the costs to freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> expression <strong>of</strong> imposing liability in cases such as Smith’s. If my<br />

analysis is sound, those costs are virtually nil. A flat rule <strong>of</strong> liability<br />

for publishing the names <strong>of</strong> persons attached to private facts, where<br />

the names are publicly meaningless and add nothing to the opinionforming<br />

and autonomy- or democracy-supporting value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

published content, could easily be derived as a contextual<br />

specification <strong>of</strong> the negligence principle for cases to which it applies.<br />

Such a rule would seemingly be something <strong>of</strong> a gain for dignitas and<br />

128 NM (n 5 above) para 105.<br />

129 NM (n 5 above) para 125. O’Regan J construes the majority’s finding <strong>of</strong><br />

intentionality in terms <strong>of</strong> reckless disregard.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 35<br />

an utterly negligible loss for freedom <strong>of</strong> expression. It would thus<br />

seem to be a rule upon which all members <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court<br />

could agree: a triumph, one might say, <strong>of</strong> ‘minimalism’. 130<br />

I am thinking here <strong>of</strong> the dimension <strong>of</strong> ‘width’, not ‘depth’, 131 for<br />

(as I hope I have sufficiently shown) there is substantial depth in the<br />

solution I described for the NM case. In the list <strong>of</strong> possible benefits <strong>of</strong><br />

a minimalist sensibility marshaled by Iain Currie (following Cass<br />

Sunstein), 132 there is one that does not appear: Minimalism can be<br />

conducive to getting the answer right! I mean right in principle,<br />

getting a principle right. Judges whose habit it is to scan for possible<br />

narrow grounds <strong>of</strong> decision, in cases where their court or their<br />

country’s legal culture is evidently divided over broader-gauged terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> debate, may sometimes be the likelier to detect some set <strong>of</strong><br />

relatively contextualised terms <strong>of</strong> decision that perhaps will not only<br />

induce a voting consensus, but also may help to clarify for everyone<br />

concerned the true (or at any rate an agreed) meaning for the<br />

broader terms <strong>of</strong> contention (here, ‘intention’ and ‘negligence’) that<br />

have been leading their debate into trouble.<br />

Thus, a focus on a relatively contextual point in NM — the point<br />

that the inclusion <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs’ names was sheerly gratuitous from<br />

the standpoint <strong>of</strong> the public informational and autonomy-supportive<br />

value <strong>of</strong> Smith’s account <strong>of</strong> Patricia De Lille’s career — might have<br />

helped clarify for everyone what the negligence principle really<br />

means and is all about. If your lines <strong>of</strong> reasoning get fixed at too<br />

wholesale a level — say, something like ‘negligence liability for<br />

publishing and freedom <strong>of</strong> expression do not mix’ — you not only may<br />

overlook a possibly consensus-forming resolution <strong>of</strong> the case before<br />

you, you may fail to see how your generalisations are leading you to a<br />

conclusion that traduces the true point and meaning <strong>of</strong> negligence as<br />

a legal concept, and <strong>of</strong> negligence liability’s value as an instrument<br />

for the advancement <strong>of</strong> the objective normative value system for<br />

which the Constitution <strong>of</strong> South Africa is supposed to speak.<br />

3.10 A case <strong>of</strong> ‘direct’ or ‘indirect’ application?<br />

A loose end still flaps in the breeze. In part 3.4 above, I compared the<br />

litigation agendas respectively implied by a constitution-based and a<br />

common law cause <strong>of</strong> action in NM. The Constitution-based action<br />

succeeds (if it does) by way <strong>of</strong> an exercise <strong>of</strong> the court’s power <strong>of</strong><br />

130 See I Currie ‘Judicious avoidance’ (1999) 15 South African Journal on Human<br />

Rights 139 147-50.<br />

131 A judicial decision is ‘narrow’ (as opposed to ‘wide’) when it is ‘minimal in<br />

impact on future decisions’. It is ‘shallow’ (as opposed to ‘deep’) when it is<br />

‘minimally theorised’. See Currie (n 130 above) 147.<br />

132 See Currie (n 130 above) 146-50.


36 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

judicial review: declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity and ensuing, remedial<br />

modification <strong>of</strong> the common law. 133 The common law action succeeds<br />

(if it does) by way <strong>of</strong> a court’s exercise <strong>of</strong> its inherent power to<br />

develop the common law in the ordinary course <strong>of</strong> adjudication, under<br />

pressure to conform the common law to the norms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution. Granting this notional difference in the respective<br />

judicial powers to be put into play, I concluded that the resulting<br />

litigation agendas would be virtually identical, whichever source <strong>of</strong><br />

power would be chosen. I warned, however, <strong>of</strong> an arguable difference<br />

to be taken up later. Later is now; the arguer for the difference is Stu<br />

Woolman, and the difference argued for is this: Arriving at a<br />

declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity, required for the plaintiffs’ success in a<br />

constitution-based action, involves a court in a distinctly more<br />

rigorous and exacting mode <strong>of</strong> constitutional analysis and exposition<br />

than does arrival at a decision to exercise the inherent power to<br />

develop the common law.<br />

Here it is in a nutshell:<br />

... [T]he drafters intended for there to be two different processes. The<br />

first process — direct application — takes the [specifically named] rights<br />

and freedoms, and the general rules derived from them, as our point <strong>of</strong><br />

departure for determining whether [some challenged parcel <strong>of</strong> common<br />

law doctrine] is invalid. The second process — indirect application —<br />

allows for a mode <strong>of</strong> analysis that neither specifies whether a particular<br />

right demands vindication nor permits a finding <strong>of</strong> invalidity. Instead, ...<br />

the courts operate under a general injunction to bring all law into line<br />

with the ‘spirit, purport and objects’ <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and the<br />

‘objective, normative value system’ made manifest in the text <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution as a whole. 134<br />

The framers, Woolman says, had a particular reason for their<br />

provision <strong>of</strong> these two, distinct processes — direct and indirect<br />

application — for measuring the constitutional acceptability <strong>of</strong> a<br />

challenged common law doctrine or rule. As he explains:<br />

Section 8 does not mean that the prescriptive content <strong>of</strong> the substantive<br />

provisions in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights covers each and every legal dispute ...<br />

[W]hile the specific provisions in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights cover a large domain<br />

<strong>of</strong> law and conduct, they do not engage all law and conduct. The<br />

133 That is, owing to the command <strong>of</strong> sec 8(3), it does not succeed by way <strong>of</strong><br />

damages imposed on Smith for a constitutional tort.<br />

134 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 769.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 37<br />

independent purpose <strong>of</strong> s 39(2) is to engage law and conduct not<br />

engaged by any <strong>of</strong> the specific provisions set out in Chapter 2. 135<br />

This reason for providing the two, distinct processes <strong>of</strong> direct and<br />

indirect application implies, as Woolman further points out, a definite<br />

order <strong>of</strong> march for courts called upon to consider the constitutional<br />

acceptability <strong>of</strong> one or another rule or doctrine <strong>of</strong> the common law:<br />

... [O]ne must first ascertain what the ambit is <strong>of</strong> the allegedly<br />

applicable constitutional provisions [he means the several rightsgranting<br />

clauses in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights]. Only when one has determined<br />

that ambit, and found that it does not speak to the issues raised by a<br />

[questioned] rule <strong>of</strong> [the common] law, can one turn to the more<br />

open-ended invitation <strong>of</strong> s 39(2). Analysis <strong>of</strong> the specific provisions <strong>of</strong><br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, and the consistency <strong>of</strong> law or conduct with those<br />

provisions, logically must be prior to the analysis <strong>of</strong> the common law in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> the general spirit, purpose and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 136<br />

In other words, the marching order, logically implied by the<br />

Constitution’s principle <strong>of</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor between direct and<br />

indirect application is: direct application first, then indirect, but only<br />

if direct fails to engage the common law rule or doctrine in<br />

question. 137<br />

But <strong>of</strong> course Woolman’s point is not merely that the Constitution<br />

implies a particular order <strong>of</strong> priority <strong>of</strong> resort to direct and indirect<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. It is that the obedience <strong>of</strong> courts to<br />

this order <strong>of</strong> march — direct before indirect — is <strong>of</strong> crucial importance<br />

to the long-run interest in the proper elucidation <strong>of</strong> South African<br />

constitutional law. And that is because <strong>of</strong> a difference in the sorts and<br />

levels <strong>of</strong> explanatory rigour respectively exacted from courts by<br />

direct and indirect application. When applying the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

directly in terms <strong>of</strong> section 8, the Court ‘engages the content <strong>of</strong> the<br />

substantive provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ and ‘articulates<br />

135 As above.<br />

136 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 777. Woolman elaborates:<br />

If we reverse the spin, and we first use sec 39(2) to bring the law into line with<br />

the general spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, there is simply<br />

nothing left to be done in terms <strong>of</strong> direct application. The reason is obvious. If<br />

the general spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> Chapter 2, which embraces (at a<br />

minimum) the entire value domain reflected by the specific substantive<br />

provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, does not require a change in the law (or a change<br />

in conduct brought about by a change in the law), then no narrower set <strong>of</strong><br />

purposes reflected in a single substantive provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights could be<br />

expected to do so.<br />

137 See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 83 (‘The logic ... is one that should require<br />

the courts to ... develop the common law in light <strong>of</strong> the general objects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights only where no specific right can be relied on by a party challenging a<br />

given rule <strong>of</strong> common law ... ’) (emphasis in original).


38 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

constitutional rules that amplify that content.’ 138 When applying the<br />

Bill indirectly in term <strong>of</strong> section 39(2), it does not.<br />

Appropriately does not? Obediently does not? Well, Woolman<br />

wants us to read sections 8 and 39 as setting up two cleanly ‘distinct<br />

modes <strong>of</strong> analysis’. 139 The suggestion would seem to be that a court,<br />

by choosing to frame its inquiry in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2), thereby<br />

limits itself to the detection <strong>of</strong> inconsistencies between the parcel <strong>of</strong><br />

common law in question and what we might call the normative<br />

residue <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, meaning whatever normative intimations<br />

a court can draw from the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights as a whole but cannot trace<br />

or ascribe to any <strong>of</strong> the specific rights-naming clauses. If analysis <strong>of</strong> a<br />

rule’s consistency with the specific provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

‘logically must be prior’ to analysis <strong>of</strong> its consistency with the<br />

normative residue, then the latter process — indirect application —<br />

must be reserved for cases in which the former cuts no ice. And<br />

conversely, then, if a court, in a private-on-private case turning on<br />

common law doctrine, is going to find a ‘direct’ inconsistency —<br />

meaning an inconsistency with something contained in one or another<br />

the rights-naming clauses — then that court really ought not, on, that<br />

occasion, speak the name <strong>of</strong> 39(2). 140<br />

But how, after all, can it be so important that this particular<br />

discipline be observed? I do not mean the discipline <strong>of</strong> searching for<br />

clause-based inconsistencies before turning to the question <strong>of</strong><br />

residual inconsistencies, about which I raise no question here. 141<br />

I mean — and mean only — the discipline <strong>of</strong> not saying ‘39(2)’<br />

when a clause-based inconsistency is what you are after. For this<br />

specific practice rule, I can find no reason in Woolman’s magisterial<br />

work on application (which is generally rich in jurisprudential and<br />

even philosophical reflection) beyond doctrinal tidiness and<br />

symmetry. The point is to avoid ‘redundancy’, ‘surplusage’, ‘elision’<br />

in the constitutional text — or, in other words, overlap between the<br />

sorts <strong>of</strong> judicial performances respectively authorised by sections 8<br />

138 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 768.<br />

139 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 776; see Part II above.<br />

140 According to Woolman’s preferred construction <strong>of</strong> secs 8 and 39(2) as a package,<br />

sec 39(2) should be understood to stand for the following proposition: Where no<br />

specific right can be relied upon by the party challenging a given rule or law or<br />

the extant construction <strong>of</strong> a rule <strong>of</strong> law the courts are obliged to interpret<br />

legislation or to develop the law in light <strong>of</strong> the general objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 12. See also at 80 (indicating that, on<br />

the preferred construction, ‘s 39(2) is not the intended engine for changes in the<br />

common law that flow from the direct application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’).<br />

141 A question could, however, be raised about it. See FI Michelman ‘Unenumerated<br />

rights under popular constitutionalism’ (2006) <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Pennsylvania Journal<br />

<strong>of</strong> Constitutional Law 121, 135-36, 152-53 (discussing views <strong>of</strong> Ronald Dworkin<br />

and John Rawls).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 39<br />

and 172(1), on the one hand, and 39(2), on the other. 142 We would not<br />

want two constitutional clauses sharing any <strong>of</strong> the same work. 143<br />

Some might wonder whether Woolman’s interpretive construction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the framers’ design — his strict correlation <strong>of</strong> clause-bound<br />

inspection to sections 8 and 172(1), and residual inspection to section<br />

39(2) — perhaps proceeds from an unrealistically high expectation <strong>of</strong><br />

formal tidiness and tightness in constitutional drafting. On that score,<br />

NK may give a hint. In NK, O’Regan J’s flexing <strong>of</strong> the respondeat<br />

superior standard plainly was driven, not by some normative residue<br />

detected in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, but by attention to the prescriptive<br />

contents <strong>of</strong> several, specific clauses, including those ensuring rights<br />

to ‘freedom and security <strong>of</strong> the person, and in particular, the right to<br />

be free from all forms <strong>of</strong> violence from either public or private<br />

sources as well as [the] right to dignity, right to privacy and right to<br />

substantive equality.’ 144 O’Regan J plainly was engaged in the first <strong>of</strong><br />

the two ‘instances’ <strong>of</strong> need for common-law development in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

section 39(2), recalled by her from Thebus: the kind that arises when<br />

‘a rule <strong>of</strong> the common law is inconsistent with a constitutional<br />

provision’. 145 Was she, therefore, wrong to file the decision under the<br />

head <strong>of</strong> 39(2) rather than 8?<br />

Might that depend on whether O’Regan J considered herself, after<br />

all, to be engaged in ‘development’ <strong>of</strong> the common law, as<br />

contemplated by section 8(3)? Does ‘develop’, there, encompass only<br />

an express, terminological re-writing, or does it also take in a court’s<br />

choice about how to apply an established standard to an arguably<br />

‘new’ set <strong>of</strong> facts, as in NK? Section 39(2) speaks to a court’s<br />

142 See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 771, 777; Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above)<br />

10, 11, 12, 55. The ‘two instances’ reading <strong>of</strong> sec 39(2) in S v Thebus 2003 6 SA<br />

505 (CC); 2003 10 BCLR 1100 (CC) para 28 (‘Thebus’) (where one <strong>of</strong> the instances<br />

is ‘when a rule <strong>of</strong> the common law is inconsistent with a constitutional provision’)<br />

is objectionable to Woolman because it ‘<strong>of</strong>fends the “no surplusage” canon <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional interpretation by making parts <strong>of</strong> FC sec 8 redundant.’ Woolman<br />

‘Application’ (n 17 above) 79.<br />

143<br />

Woolman adduces an incisive and entirely persuasive reason for not allowing sec<br />

39(2) to suck up, exclusively or preemptively, the whole field <strong>of</strong> constitutionally<br />

propelled re-examination <strong>of</strong> the common law. That reason has to do with the<br />

currently imposed, substantial exclusion <strong>of</strong> the High Courts from such reexamination<br />

when conducted under the aegis <strong>of</strong> sec 39(2). See Afrox Health Care<br />

v Strydom 2002 6 SA 21 (SCA); Ex parte Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security v Walters<br />

2002 4 SA 643 (CC), 2002 2 SACR 105 (CC), 2002 7 BCLR 663 (CC). A like restriction<br />

cannot be, and has not been, imposed on High Court re-examination where ‘a<br />

party has a colourable claim grounded in the direct application <strong>of</strong> a substantive<br />

provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights in terms <strong>of</strong> section 8'. It is, therefore, <strong>of</strong> crucial<br />

importance, Woolman argues, to resist an ‘elision’ in which sec 39(2) would, in<br />

effect, swallow up sec 8. Woolman ‘Application’ 10, 55-56, 64. This argument is,<br />

to me, entirely compelling. It does not, however, explain why courts should be<br />

barred from ever resorting to sec 39(2) when the detected inconsistency is with a<br />

specific provision, which is the issue that my text, above, addresses.<br />

144<br />

NK (n 91 above) para 14.<br />

145 NK (n 91 above) para 16, citing Thebus (n 142 above) para 28.


40 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

‘interpreting’ law, whereas section 8(3) speaks to a choice between<br />

‘applying’ and ‘developing’ law. Does that difference, perhaps, make<br />

section 39(2) more apt to the sort <strong>of</strong> work accomplished by the Court<br />

in NK?<br />

It might seem so, to some; it certainly wouldn’t have to, to all <strong>of</strong><br />

us. But I do not mean my string <strong>of</strong> questions to constrain very strongly<br />

— much less lead ineluctably — toward a conclusion either way. I only<br />

mean it to confirm a truth that Woolman, more than anyone, has<br />

recognised and exposed through his meticulous, sterling, searching<br />

work on the application conundrum: When the question is that <strong>of</strong><br />

parsing the exact relations and connections among this Constitution’s<br />

several clauses on application and remedies, no fully neat and<br />

satisfying answer is to be had. ‘Some surplusage seems inevitable.’ 146<br />

There are not shells to cover all the peas, and so it is a choice among<br />

imperfections — in that sense, a matter, as Woolman says, <strong>of</strong><br />

‘interpretation’. 147<br />

3.11 The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the pudding<br />

But, as Woolman also rightly insists in the same place, it does not<br />

follow that grounds are lacking for preferring one interpretation —<br />

one construction — over another. One ground <strong>of</strong> preference might<br />

well be the differing ways in which the respective constructions cue<br />

and guide, concentrate and dissipate, the judiciary’s deployments <strong>of</strong><br />

its efforts and energies. Woolman notes that a ‘muscular’ use <strong>of</strong><br />

section 39(2) ‘could’, in theory, produce the sorts <strong>of</strong> rights-based,<br />

rights-expounding work he finds the Court retreating from. 148 But he<br />

fears that, in practice, a Court that is allowed to give up too easily on<br />

section 8, or to slide too easily to section 39, will be (has been) a<br />

Court that too <strong>of</strong>ten fails to decide in terms <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> the specific,<br />

rights-naming clauses in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, and accordingly fails too<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten to engage in the principled elucidation <strong>of</strong> those clauses that<br />

decision in such terms entails. That states a legitimate concern, on its<br />

face by no means implausible. Still, the claim is an empirical one,<br />

subject to testing as such. NK, I have just suggested, <strong>of</strong>fers a bit <strong>of</strong><br />

evidence against it. (So, for that matter, does Thebus, where the<br />

Constitutional Court, under the sign <strong>of</strong> section 39(2), considered in<br />

great detail whether a prosecutor’s reliance on the common-purpose<br />

doctrine ‘trenches on’ or ‘denies’ the constitutional rights <strong>of</strong> a<br />

criminal accused not to be deprived <strong>of</strong> freedom without just cause<br />

and to be presumed innocent.) 149<br />

146 Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 71.<br />

147 See Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 13 n 1.<br />

148 Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 766 n 6.<br />

149 Thebus (n 142 above) paras 36, 42.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 41<br />

To what extent, we might ask, does the Constitutional Court’s<br />

work in NM tend to bear out Woolman’s empirical concern? Start with<br />

O’Regan J. Her NM opinion certainly exemplifies the sort <strong>of</strong><br />

elucidation that Woolman associates with direct application pursuant<br />

to section 8. 150 If O’Regan J had given clear indication that she was<br />

proceeding in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2), as distinct from section 8, that<br />

would have told against Woolman’s empirical claim. However, she did<br />

not. What might be a bit worrisome from Woolman’s corner, though,<br />

is the further fact that O’Regan J did not ever bother to say under<br />

which set <strong>of</strong> constitutional auspices — 8 or 39(2) — she was<br />

undertaking to develop the common law. (But Langa CJ, concurring<br />

with O’Regan J’s proposed development, did make clear that he<br />

understood himself to be proceeding in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2).) 151<br />

Neither did O’Regan J ever pause to declare invalid the extant<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> privacy invasion. All this perhaps does tell a bit against<br />

Woolman, insomuch as it might suggest that O’Regan J believes it<br />

does not matter which auspices she invokes, which would contradict<br />

Woolman’s insistence that it does matter, not just because an order<br />

<strong>of</strong> march has been prescribed, but because marching under section<br />

39(2) has an effect on the justices <strong>of</strong> releasing them from the very<br />

work <strong>of</strong> clause-by-clause exposition that O’Regan J’s NM opinion so<br />

clearly exemplifies.<br />

What about the NM majority? Madala J, denying that he was<br />

engaged in any sort <strong>of</strong> modification <strong>of</strong> the common law, had no<br />

occasion to claim any set <strong>of</strong> constitutional auspices for modifying it.<br />

But suppose he had said directly that his finding <strong>of</strong> ‘intention’, on<br />

Smith’s part, to disclose private facts without authorisation to do so<br />

from the persons concerned, resulted from a shading <strong>of</strong> the common<br />

law category <strong>of</strong> ‘intention’ under pressure <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights,<br />

specifically in the matter <strong>of</strong> privacy protection. What more could<br />

Madala J then have said by way <strong>of</strong> explaining his action, than that the<br />

disclosure went to the ‘inviolable core’ <strong>of</strong> privacy as previously<br />

defined in Bernstein, 152 and that the privacy-protection principle <strong>of</strong><br />

section 14 requires exposure to civil liability <strong>of</strong> anyone who publishes<br />

core-private facts when the publisher ‘at least foresaw the possibility<br />

that the consent had not been given to the disclosure’? 153<br />

Madala J did not say those things in that way, nor could he have,<br />

because he did not purport to be judging this case in terms <strong>of</strong> the Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights, à la NK. But can we not fairly guess from his opinion that he<br />

150 See NM (n 5 above) paras 126-35 (constitutional right to privacy); paras 144-46<br />

(constitutional right to freedom <strong>of</strong> expression).<br />

151 See NM (n 5 above) para 120.<br />

152 Bernstein v Bester NO 1996 2 SA 751 (CC); 1996 4 BCLR 449 (CC) para 77. Compare<br />

NM (n 5 above) paras 33, 41-42.<br />

153 Compare NM (n 5 above) para 64.


42 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

would have said them, if he had undertaken to explain himself in such<br />

terms? If so, then NM is, to that very modest extent, a sign that<br />

section 39(2) does not necessarily, and does not always, function as a<br />

lure to a form <strong>of</strong> judicial decision-making that ignores and by-passes<br />

the regulative content <strong>of</strong> the rights-naming clauses <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. Masiya, as we are about to see, provides some further<br />

evidence to like effect.<br />

4 MASIYA<br />

4.1 The case and a critique<br />

The state charged Masiya with the common law crime <strong>of</strong> rape. Under<br />

the law as it then stood, rape was defined in terms <strong>of</strong> non-consensual,<br />

vaginal penetration (and thus could involve female victims only). The<br />

evidence in Masiya’s case showed forcible, anal penetration <strong>of</strong> a nineyear<br />

old girl. 154 Anal penetration <strong>of</strong> a female or a male could support<br />

a conviction <strong>of</strong> indecent assault, but not <strong>of</strong> rape. Indecent assault is<br />

classified as the lesser crime, and it carries a lesser penalty than<br />

rape. 155<br />

In the course <strong>of</strong> the state’s prosecution <strong>of</strong> Masiya, questions arose<br />

as to whether the extant common law definition <strong>of</strong> rape fell to be<br />

declared invalid as inconsistent with the Constitution, and whether<br />

that law ought to be developed so as to cover Masiya’s proven act <strong>of</strong><br />

anal penetration. 156 The two questions are not unrelated, but neither<br />

are they necessarily coupled. In the event <strong>of</strong> an adjudicative<br />

154 See Masiya (n 4 above) paras 6, 13.<br />

155 See Masiya (n 4 above) para 15 (indicating that ‘indecent assault attracts more<br />

lenient sentences than rape’).<br />

156 There was, <strong>of</strong> course, a further question about retrospective application to<br />

Masiya’s case <strong>of</strong> any extended definition the Constitutional Court might direct.<br />

The Court answered ‘no’ to that question, see Masiya (n 4 above) para 56, even as<br />

it also answered ‘yes’ to the question <strong>of</strong> whether the advent <strong>of</strong> Masiya’s case<br />

before the courts <strong>of</strong>fered an apt occasion for developing the definition. See<br />

Masiya (n 4 above) para 51:<br />

If the definition <strong>of</strong> rape were to be developed retrospectively it would <strong>of</strong>fend the<br />

constitutional principle <strong>of</strong> legality. However, if it was to be accepted that the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> legality was a bar to the development <strong>of</strong> the common law, the courts<br />

could never develop the common law <strong>of</strong> crimes at all. Such a conclusion would<br />

undermine the principles <strong>of</strong> the Constitution which required the courts to ensure<br />

that the common law was infused with the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution.<br />

From a US constitutional lawyer’s perspective, major worries remain, not only<br />

about prospective-only application <strong>of</strong> a common law ruling, but also, and<br />

relatedly, about South African constitutionalism’s evident relaxation <strong>of</strong> what we<br />

would call a ‘case or controversy’ prerequisite to judicial jurisdiction. See<br />

generally R Fallon et al Hart & Wechsler’s the federal courts and the federal<br />

system 5 ed (2003) 73-85. Woolman’s critique <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s Masiya<br />

decision being in no way directed to such worries, I say nothing more about them<br />

here.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 43<br />

declaration <strong>of</strong> the current definition’s constitutional invalidity,<br />

corrective development <strong>of</strong> the common law might well follow on as a<br />

part <strong>of</strong> a just and equitable remedial order, in terms <strong>of</strong> Constitution<br />

s 172(1). 157 But even in the absence <strong>of</strong> such a declaration, a court<br />

might arguably still find itself bound by Constitution section 39(2) to<br />

develop the definition so as cover Masiya’s case. 158<br />

On what grounds, then, might the Constitutional Court, sitting in<br />

Masiya’s case, have held constitutionally incompatible the extant<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> rape ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it fails to cover cases <strong>of</strong> anal<br />

penetration? Not, in the first place, on any theory <strong>of</strong> the law’s<br />

infringement <strong>of</strong> Masiya’s constitutional rights or those <strong>of</strong> other<br />

putative <strong>of</strong>fenders covered by the definition. For, obviously,<br />

the current definition <strong>of</strong> rape criminalises unacceptable social conduct<br />

that is in violation <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights. It ensures that the<br />

constitutional right to be free from all forms <strong>of</strong> violence, whether public<br />

or private, as well as the right to dignity and equality are protected. 159<br />

In other words, any limiting effect <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> rape on the liberty <strong>of</strong><br />

putative rapists is obviously and amply justified in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

Constitution section 36(1). 160 It easily follows that any declaration <strong>of</strong><br />

the current definition’s unconstitutionality would have to issue in<br />

contemplation <strong>of</strong> constitutionally protected interests, not <strong>of</strong> those<br />

who might find themselves charged with assaultive crime, but <strong>of</strong> the<br />

class consisting <strong>of</strong> all who might suffer sexual assault — the general<br />

public, more or less. Thus, it was with a view to ‘afford[ing] society<br />

the full protection <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’ that the trial court in Masiya’s<br />

157<br />

It seems that, in Masiya’s case, Constitution sec 8 can also serve as the ground <strong>of</strong><br />

an order to develop the common law, inasmuch as an antecedent declaration <strong>of</strong><br />

the invalidity <strong>of</strong> the common law definition <strong>of</strong> rape might be said to result (in the<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> sec 8(2)) from an application <strong>of</strong> certain provisions in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to<br />

the conduct (or to common law regulating the conduct) <strong>of</strong> Fanuel Sitakeni Masiya,<br />

a natural person. Since Woolman generally argues in terms <strong>of</strong> a choice between ss<br />

8 and 39(2), as the constitutional authorisation to be invoked by the Court for<br />

some ensuing directive for common law modification, and since nothing seems to<br />

depend on whether a remedial order would issue in terms <strong>of</strong> sec 172(1)(b) or in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> sec 8, I shall, in what follows, refer to the one or the other as the<br />

context most naturally suggests.<br />

158 See Masiya (n 4 above) para 33 (quoting from Carmichele (n 59 above) para 36,<br />

and also citing Thebus (n 152 above) paras 28-31):<br />

... ‘[C]ourts must remain vigilant and should not hesitate to ensure that the<br />

common law is developed to reflect the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights ... whether or not the parties in any particular case request the Court to<br />

develop the common law under section 39(2).’ Where there is deviation from the<br />

spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, courts are obliged to develop the<br />

common law by removing the deviation.<br />

159 Masiya (n 4 above) para 27.<br />

160 See also Constitution sec 12(1)(a): ‘Everyone has the right to freedom and<br />

security <strong>of</strong> the person, which includes the right — (a) not to be deprived <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom arbitrarily or without just cause’.


44 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

case took up sua sponte the question <strong>of</strong> extending the common law <strong>of</strong><br />

rape to acts <strong>of</strong> anal penetration. 161<br />

For convenience, we might imagine that it would be the Director<br />

<strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions who presses the claim for some development <strong>of</strong><br />

the common law that would result in Masiya’s conduct being<br />

punishable as rape. 162 The DPP, pointing to the state’s constitutionally<br />

imposed duty to protect and fulfil the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights, 163 might charge the received definition <strong>of</strong> rape with a<br />

constitutional sin <strong>of</strong> omission, to wit, its omission to make acts <strong>of</strong> anal<br />

penetration punishable as rape. Impermissibly under-protected as a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> that omission, the DPP might say, are the right to freedom<br />

from private violence, conferred by section 12(1)(c), 164 and the right<br />

to have one’s dignity respected and protected, conferred by section<br />

10. 165 Alternatively or additionally, the DPP might urge a declaration<br />

<strong>of</strong> invalidity based on a sin <strong>of</strong> commission by the current law, to wit,<br />

commission <strong>of</strong> an unfair discrimination prohibited by Constitution<br />

section 9(3). 166 It is unconstitutionally unfair, the DPP might urge, for<br />

the state, through its common law, to <strong>of</strong>fer lesser levels <strong>of</strong><br />

recognition, and <strong>of</strong> protection-by-deterrence, to male than to female<br />

sufferers <strong>of</strong> forced, sexualised, bodily penetration, or (within the<br />

class <strong>of</strong> female victims) to sufferers <strong>of</strong> anal than to sufferers <strong>of</strong><br />

vaginal penetration.<br />

A judicial modification <strong>of</strong> the common law definition <strong>of</strong> rape,<br />

presented as a remedy for a constitutional violation declared on any<br />

<strong>of</strong> the grounds aforesaid, would be an instance <strong>of</strong> what Woolman<br />

classifies as ‘direct’ application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. But a court<br />

sitting in Masiya’s case might also arguably be authorised and required<br />

to undertake an extension <strong>of</strong> the common law definition <strong>of</strong> rape to<br />

reach cases <strong>of</strong> anal penetration, even in the absence <strong>of</strong> any finding <strong>of</strong><br />

the classical definition’s inconsistency with any clause in the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. Start by setting aside the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights entirely. Perhaps a<br />

court might simply decide that considerations <strong>of</strong> policy and justice<br />

call, under present social conditions, for extension <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> rape so as to take in cases <strong>of</strong> anal penetration, either <strong>of</strong><br />

161 Masiya (n 4 above) paras 8-9.<br />

162 In point <strong>of</strong> fact the DPP did not urge any modification <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> rape but rather sought conviction for indecent assault. See Masiya (n<br />

4 above) para 7. I make the opposite assumption for the sake <strong>of</strong> expository<br />

convenience.<br />

163 See Constitution sec 7(2): ‘The state must respect, protect, promote and fulfil<br />

the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.’<br />

164 ‘Everyone has the right to freedom and security <strong>of</strong> the person, which includes the<br />

right — ... to be free from all forms <strong>of</strong> violence from either public or private<br />

sources’.<br />

165 ‘Everyone has inherent dignity and the right to have their dignity respected and<br />

166<br />

protected.’<br />

‘The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on<br />

one or more grounds, including race, gender, sex ...’.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 45<br />

females only or <strong>of</strong> males as well. The court might then invoke its<br />

ordinary, inherent power to develop the common law as and when<br />

occasioned by the interests <strong>of</strong> justice. 167 In doing so, the court might<br />

or might not refer, beyond its general authority to keep the common<br />

law attuned to the times and to the interests <strong>of</strong> justice, to its more<br />

specific obligation, under section 39(2), to see to the conformation <strong>of</strong><br />

the common law with the spirit, purport, and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights.<br />

In Masiya, the Constitutional Court, in an opinion by Nkabinde J,<br />

concluded by issuing an order directing a revision <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> rape to include acts <strong>of</strong> anal penetration <strong>of</strong> females. 168 It<br />

did so while (a) expressly declining to issue a declaration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

invalidity (unconstitutionality) <strong>of</strong> the non-extended definition, and<br />

(b) declining to decide whether acts <strong>of</strong> anal penetration <strong>of</strong> males<br />

would be covered in the extended definition <strong>of</strong> rape resulting from<br />

the adjudication in Masiya’s case — thus, in effect, retaining for the<br />

present a definition <strong>of</strong> rape in which only females can be victims.<br />

Those two features <strong>of</strong> the Court’s Masiya decision, (a) and (b), are<br />

the targets <strong>of</strong> vigorous complaint from Woolman. Both stand, in his<br />

view, as further documentation <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s<br />

unaccountable habit — and that habit’s doctrinally debilitating<br />

consequences — <strong>of</strong> refusal to engage in direct application <strong>of</strong> the Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights or to undertake the rule-like expositions <strong>of</strong> the contents <strong>of</strong><br />

the several rights-protecting clauses that direct application is<br />

expected to induce.<br />

As with Woolman’s objections to the Court’s performance in NM,<br />

these objections to Masiya seem to me in some part answerable. The<br />

main idea continues to be this: We want to see what happens if we<br />

strain to turn these very features in the judgment — the ones that we<br />

may initially find puzzling or disturbing — into keys to discovery <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Court’s own understanding <strong>of</strong> the legal problem presented by the<br />

case; and perhaps, through that, to notice something true — I do not<br />

mean necessarily welcome — about the meaning and structure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law. When we train that sort <strong>of</strong> effort on the Constitutional Court’s<br />

work in Masiya, we may find that Woolman’s objections lose some –<br />

though it will not be all — <strong>of</strong> their sting.<br />

167 See Constitution sec 173 (‘The Constitutional Court, Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal and<br />

High Courts have the inherent power to protect and regulate their own process,<br />

and to develop the common law, taking into account the interests <strong>of</strong> justice.’).<br />

168 See Masiya (n 4 above) para 74(5).


46 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

4.2 The decision’s gravamen: Under-protection<br />

In Masiya, the Constitutional Court concluded that the extant<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> rape, although not prone to a finding <strong>of</strong> invalidity,<br />

nevertheless fell to be developed under pressure from the spirit,<br />

purport, and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. By my reading — and this<br />

point is central to my examination <strong>of</strong> Woolman’s critique — the<br />

decisive pressure came (in the Court’s view) not from the Bill’s<br />

prohibition against unfair discrimination, but rather from its positive<br />

commitments to protection <strong>of</strong> persons against violence and indignity.<br />

The Court does mention section 9 — ‘flirts with’ it, if you like 169 — but<br />

does not finally rest its action on considerations sounding in equality.<br />

As I have understood the Court’s opinion, the decisive fault it finds in<br />

the common law lies not in any unfair discrimination committed by<br />

the law but rather in protection omitted from it: not in the law’s<br />

perpetration <strong>of</strong> inequality, but in its under-protection <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutionally guaranteed dignity and freedom from violence. A<br />

complaint <strong>of</strong> under-protection is, <strong>of</strong> course, a matter distinct in<br />

principle from a complaint <strong>of</strong> unequal treatment. By what I presume<br />

to <strong>of</strong>fer as the ‘charitable’ reading <strong>of</strong> Nkabinde J’s opinion, it is the<br />

under-protection complaint that carries the day in Masiya.<br />

Oh, yes, to be sure, the ‘issues raised’ in the case included<br />

‘equality’ — specifically citing section 9(1)’s guarantee to everyone <strong>of</strong><br />

‘equality before the law’ and ‘equal protection and benefit <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law’. 170 And, yes, Nkabinde J made the comparative observation that<br />

the trauma associated with anal penetration is ‘just as humiliating,<br />

degrading, and physically hurtful’ as that associated with vaginal<br />

penetration. 171 She said, as well, that inclusion <strong>of</strong> anal penetration in<br />

the definition <strong>of</strong> rape ‘will increase the extent to which the<br />

traditionally vulnerable and disadvantaged group will be protected by<br />

and benefit from the law’. 172 But all <strong>of</strong> those remarks are perfectly<br />

consistent with the view that the current law is constitutionally<br />

deficient in the specific respect that it under-protects the rights to<br />

dignity and freedom from violence. They could all easily have been<br />

written by a judge applying a bill <strong>of</strong> rights that contains no equality<br />

clause.<br />

As Nkabinde J’s opinion proceeds, we read the following: It is the<br />

<strong>of</strong>fice <strong>of</strong> the crime <strong>of</strong> rape to ‘ensure[] that the constitutional right<br />

to be free from all forms <strong>of</strong> violence, whether public or private, as<br />

well as the right to dignity and equality are protected.’ 173 It is<br />

169 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 768 n 10.<br />

170 Masiya (n 4 above) para 18 & n 32.<br />

171 Masiya (n 4 above) para 39.<br />

172 As above.<br />

173 Masiya (n 4 above) para 27.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 47<br />

specifically with regard to these objectives that the current definition<br />

is fatally ‘under-inclusive’. 174 ‘Non-consensual anal penetration <strong>of</strong><br />

women and young girls such as the complainant in this case<br />

constitutes a form <strong>of</strong> violence against them equal in intensity and<br />

impact to that <strong>of</strong> non-consensual vaginal penetration.’ 175 Extending<br />

the definition to include anal penetration will ‘protect the dignity <strong>of</strong><br />

survivors’. 176 It will ‘increase the extent to which [a] traditionally<br />

vulnerable and disadvantaged group will be protected’ against<br />

‘humiliating, degrading and physically hurtful’ treatment, and<br />

‘therefore’ — meaning, in that particular respect — it will ‘harmonise<br />

the common law with the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights.’ 177<br />

In sum, it is all about a constitutionally required level <strong>of</strong><br />

protection, not about the distinct injury to the self or to dignity that<br />

flows from being subjected to second-class treatment. The Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights sections in the foreground here are 10 and 12, not 9. The Court<br />

convicts the current law <strong>of</strong> a constitutional sin <strong>of</strong> omission <strong>of</strong> due<br />

protection; it does not convict it <strong>of</strong> a constitutional sin <strong>of</strong> commission<br />

<strong>of</strong> unfair discrimination.<br />

4.3 A case <strong>of</strong> judicious avoidance?<br />

In Woolman’s view, this short-changing <strong>of</strong> section 9 counts as<br />

unimitigated vice in the decision. In mine, it can claim some support<br />

in ordinary judicial prudence. What, after all, is the context — the<br />

field — <strong>of</strong> the differential treatment that troubles Woolman? 178 It is<br />

the grading <strong>of</strong> crimes within nests <strong>of</strong> including and lesser-included<br />

<strong>of</strong>fenses. (It is not as if Mr Masiya escapes conviction <strong>of</strong> crime —<br />

serious crime — if he is convicted <strong>of</strong> indecent assault and not rape.)<br />

What is involved is the schedule <strong>of</strong> penalties devised by the lawmaker<br />

for more and less aggravated variations on the same core <strong>of</strong>fense.<br />

Plainly, it is not against the grain <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, or contrary to<br />

any clause contained therein, for lawmakers to draw such lines. To<br />

the contrary, we should think it monstrous if they did not.<br />

From an equality-clause standpoint, then, an important question<br />

presented to the Constitutional Court by the Masiya appeal was one<br />

<strong>of</strong> best judicial practice: whether it would be generally in the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> justice, and conducive to long-term optimal performance<br />

174 As above.<br />

175 Masiya (n 4 above) para 37.<br />

176 Masiya (n 4 above) para 38.<br />

177 Masiya (n 4 above) para 39.<br />

178 Note that I am not yet dealing with the issue raised by the Court’s postponement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the question <strong>of</strong> the new rape definition’s application to cases involving male<br />

victims.


48 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

by the judiciary <strong>of</strong> its role in the over-all governmental order <strong>of</strong> a<br />

democratic South Africa, for the Constitutional Court to swing open<br />

its doors to complaints <strong>of</strong> unconstitutionally unfair discrimination,<br />

assertedly wrought by the lawmaker’s choices <strong>of</strong> where and how to<br />

draw the lines required by the gradations <strong>of</strong> penalties (for more and<br />

less aggravated incidents <strong>of</strong> the same class <strong>of</strong> crime) that the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights and the rule <strong>of</strong> law almost certainly demand. 179 If you think<br />

that is an easy question, it must be because you feel sure that answer<br />

is ‘no’. If you feel the answer might well be ‘yes’, you must<br />

nonetheless grant that answer is not immediately self-evident. The<br />

Constitutional Court, I accordingly conclude, had respectable reason<br />

for hesitating to tackle the question in a case where the need for a<br />

challenged law’s correction was sufficiently clear on constitutionally<br />

resonant grounds <strong>of</strong> substantive under-protection, equality<br />

considerations being held at bay.<br />

4.4 A case <strong>of</strong> direct application?<br />

In her Masiya judgment, Nkabinde J concludes that the extant<br />

common law definition <strong>of</strong> rape ‘is not inconsistent with the<br />

Constitution’. 180 Accordingly, no declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity is to issue,<br />

and no development <strong>of</strong> the common law definition <strong>of</strong> rape is to ensue<br />

in the guise <strong>of</strong> a remedy for constitutional invalidity. 181 Rather, ‘the<br />

definition is to be extended ... so as to promote the spirit, purport<br />

and objects <strong>of</strong> the bill <strong>of</strong> rights.’ 182 Evidently in play, then, is an<br />

exercise <strong>of</strong> the Court’s inherent authority, in terms <strong>of</strong> sections 173<br />

and 39(2), to develop the common law, as opposed to its judicialreview<br />

power, conferred by section 172(1), to declare invalidity and<br />

craft just and equitable remedial orders. 183 Just as Woolman says.<br />

Let us next notice what stands immediately behind Nkabinde J’s<br />

refusal to declare the extant rape law unconstitutional and hence<br />

invalid. Here is the crucial passage:<br />

The current definition <strong>of</strong> rape criminalises unacceptable social conduct<br />

that is in violation <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights. It ensures that the<br />

constitutional right to be free from all forms <strong>of</strong> violence, whether public<br />

or private, as well as the right to dignity and equality are protected.<br />

179 I have in mind here a general standard <strong>of</strong> appraisal <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s<br />

performance closely aligned to the one projected by Roux ‘Pragmatism’ (n 16<br />

above).<br />

180 Masiya (n 4 above) para 27.<br />

181 Masiya (n 4 above) para 51.<br />

182 Masiya (n 4 above) para 27.<br />

183 See Masiya (n 4 above) para 45 (‘[T]he extension <strong>of</strong> the common-law definition <strong>of</strong><br />

rape to include non-consensual anal penetration <strong>of</strong> females will be in the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> justice and will have, as its aim, the proper realisation by the public<br />

<strong>of</strong> the principles, ideals and values underlying the Constitution.’).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 49<br />

Invalidating the definition because it is under-inclusive is to throw the<br />

baby out with the bath water. What is required then is for the definition<br />

to be extended instead <strong>of</strong> being eliminated so as to promote the spirit,<br />

purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 184<br />

We can all see the conceptual problem to which Nkabinde J is calling<br />

attention there. Woolman sees it and chalks it up to ‘fuzzy logic’, a<br />

point to which we shall return. 185<br />

Nkabinde J suggests a comparison <strong>of</strong> the rape crime at issue in<br />

Masiya with the erstwhile common law crime <strong>of</strong> sodomy, at issue in<br />

the ‘Sodomy’ case. 186 Let us follow her lead. Decidedly not by way <strong>of</strong><br />

‘a process <strong>of</strong> developing the common law’, but by way <strong>of</strong> ‘a direct<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to a common-law criminal <strong>of</strong>fence’,<br />

the sodomy crime was simply wiped <strong>of</strong>f the books, declared<br />

‘constitutionally invalid in its entirety’. 187 If there, why not here?<br />

Because it is not true in Masiya’s case, as it was in the Sodomy<br />

case, that the parcel <strong>of</strong> common law at issue ‘subjected people to<br />

criminal penalties for conduct which could not constitute a crime in<br />

our constitutional order’, 188 and therefore could and should be<br />

declared null and void by reason <strong>of</strong> inconsistency with provisions in<br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. Rather, the opposite is true. The rape crime, as<br />

historically defined, ‘criminalises unacceptable social conduct that is<br />

in violation <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights’. 189 Nullification <strong>of</strong> the sodomy<br />

crime as defined by the common law leaves all as it should be,<br />

constitutionally speaking. Nullification <strong>of</strong> the rape crime as defined<br />

by the common law leaves ... what?<br />

Of course, legal insiders know how to spin out an acceptable<br />

answer: It leaves, we would say, the common law in need <strong>of</strong> remedial<br />

modification – say, by a remedy <strong>of</strong> ‘reading in’ — as a cure for its<br />

constitutional sin <strong>of</strong> omission, its defect <strong>of</strong> inconsistency with sections<br />

10 and 12(1) <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. That is the gist <strong>of</strong> Woolman’s<br />

complaint against Nkabinde J’s logic. 190 The complaint is entirely<br />

valid. And yet something also feels right about Nkabinde J’s detection<br />

<strong>of</strong> the insult to ordinary reason that lies in condemning, as<br />

inconsistent with the Constitution, a legal prohibition whose presence<br />

on the books the Constitution positively demands. A remedial<br />

authority that would subtend on such a strange-sounding declaration,<br />

184 Masiya (n 4 above) para 27 (citations omitted).<br />

185 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 768 n 10.<br />

186 See Masiya (n 4 above) para 27.<br />

187 ‘Sodomy’ Case (n 20 above) para 90.<br />

188 Masiya (n 4 above) para 27.<br />

189 As above.<br />

190 See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 768 n 10 (‘The court appears to conclude that<br />

a finding <strong>of</strong> invalidity <strong>of</strong> a rule <strong>of</strong> common law can result only in a simple<br />

declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity.’).


50 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

she quite clearly conveys, ought not to be the first resort <strong>of</strong> the Court<br />

when some other resort is available, some other path <strong>of</strong> reasoning to<br />

a Constitution-satisfying outcome. And indeed another path is<br />

available, providentially supplied by the framers. The ram in the<br />

thicket (block that metaphor!) is section 39(2).<br />

The choice for section 39(2) is understandable in those terms, if<br />

not fully defensible. My reason for drawing that distinction will soon<br />

be on the table, but first we should confirm why Woolman is right to<br />

criticise the choice. To work the question through, we can start by<br />

imagining that the Constitution had been so written as to foreclose<br />

recourse in this case to section 39(2); say, it flatly prohibited the<br />

courts from performing terminological surgery on the common law,<br />

except as a remedy for constitutional invalidity declared. With such a<br />

prohibition in place, should the Constitutional Court have been willing<br />

to declare invalid the extant common law rape crime, that being the<br />

only path left open to them to a judicial cure for what they see as a<br />

constitutionally unendurable sin <strong>of</strong> omission in the law, that is, its<br />

failure to impose appropriately severe condemnation and penalty on<br />

forcible acts <strong>of</strong> anal penetration? If you ask me, a Court sitting in a<br />

transformative constitutional order would have no choice but to do<br />

just that, awkward as the declaration <strong>of</strong> invalidity might feel to the<br />

Court.<br />

The Constitutional Court, it seems, took the view that it did not<br />

have to perpetrate that awkwardness in Masiya’s case. They had<br />

access to the omission-fixing cure in question via section 39(2), so why<br />

should they have engaged in the seeming doubletalk <strong>of</strong> declaring<br />

constitutionally invalid a constitutionally required parcel <strong>of</strong> the<br />

extant law — only in the next breath to restore what they have just<br />

condemned as unconstitutional, in the guise <strong>of</strong> an instantaneously<br />

ensuing ‘remedy’? Why mangle straight-line, ordinary reason in that<br />

way, when the drafters have provided a fit alternative?<br />

A conclusive answer to that question is prefigured by my imagined<br />

case <strong>of</strong> the constitutional prohibition on judicial rewriting <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law, except as a remedy for declared constitutional<br />

invalidity. Notice that, with respect to statutes, such a constitutional<br />

prohibition is not imagined, it is actual! In terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2),<br />

statutes are open to judicial interpretation but not to judicial<br />

‘development’. By its holding that the old rape definition’s omission<br />

<strong>of</strong> anal penetration is ‘not inconsistent with the Constitution’, the<br />

Court has, in principle, disabled itself from curing an identically<br />

flawed act <strong>of</strong> Parliament should one ever happen to issue. And that,<br />

surely, is an unacceptable implication. 191<br />

191 I am indebted for this point, which I had failed to see, to an anonymous referee.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 51<br />

The Masiya Court thus erred in withholding a declaration <strong>of</strong><br />

invalidity <strong>of</strong> the old common law <strong>of</strong> rape. Its error, however, consists<br />

only <strong>of</strong> resort to section 39(2) where section 172(1) seemed to the<br />

Court not to fit the case while section 39(2) seemed fully serviceable.<br />

The error is not at all symptomatic <strong>of</strong> a flight from the burdens <strong>of</strong><br />

clause-by-clause exposition <strong>of</strong> constitutional content that attend<br />

upon direct application.<br />

The focus <strong>of</strong> the crime <strong>of</strong> rape, writes Nkabinde J, ‘ is on the<br />

breach <strong>of</strong> “a more specific right such as the right to bodily integrity”<br />

and security <strong>of</strong> the person and the right to be protected from<br />

degradation and abuse.’ 192 Presumably, there was something, some<br />

line <strong>of</strong> thought, that Nkabinde meant to convey by that direct allusion<br />

to O’Regan J’s opinion for the Court in Dawood. What, then? Well,<br />

that is the passage in Dawood where O’Regan J exactly differentiates<br />

between dignity as ‘a value that informs the interpretation <strong>of</strong> many,<br />

possibly all, other rights’ (or, in other words, dignity acting as a<br />

condiment in the spirit-brew <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights) and dignity as ‘a<br />

justiciable and enforceable right that must be respected and<br />

protected’. Dignity, then, as a target <strong>of</strong> ‘direct’, not ‘indirect’,<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, as Woolman understands those terms.<br />

There, and in other passages I have quoted above, Nkabinde J’s<br />

opinion makes sufficiently clear that the Masiya Court’s modification<br />

<strong>of</strong> the common law is designed to respond, not to some spirit<br />

summoned from the vasty deeps <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, but rather to<br />

certain, specifically identified, distinctly articulated demands <strong>of</strong><br />

sections 10 and 12(1)(c) <strong>of</strong> the Bill — most particularly, the<br />

Constitution’s mandate to protect people against private violence. As<br />

used (however mistakenly) in the Masiya case, section 39(2) is not<br />

serving as an escape-hatch from the Court’s responsibility for clauseby-clause<br />

elucidation <strong>of</strong> the contents <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. It is rather<br />

serving as a handy authorisation for a moderately drastic bit <strong>of</strong><br />

judicial surgery on the common law, in circumstances where the<br />

Court finds inapposite section 172(1)(b)’s license to operate qua<br />

remedy for invalidity.<br />

In making this use <strong>of</strong> section 39(2), Nkabinde J followed precedent<br />

set by the Constitutional Court in Carmichele. Just as the Court there<br />

chose not to condemn, as constitutionally out <strong>of</strong> line, whatever<br />

affirmative, protective duties were already imposed on the police by<br />

the extant common law <strong>of</strong> delict, so the Court in Masiya chose not to<br />

condemn, as constitutionally out <strong>of</strong> line, whatever liabilities to<br />

criminal conviction were already imposed on perpetrators <strong>of</strong> sexual<br />

192 Masiya (n 4 above) para 25, quoting from Dawood v Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs 2000<br />

3 SA 936 (CC); 2000 8 BCLR 837 (CC) para 35.


52 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

violence by the extant common law <strong>of</strong> crimes. In both cases, the<br />

extant impositions <strong>of</strong> duty and liability were in order as far as they<br />

went. In both, the issue was one <strong>of</strong> broadening those impositions;<br />

there was no question <strong>of</strong> contracting, much less deleting them. Just<br />

as the Constitutional Court in Carmichele found that development <strong>of</strong><br />

the common law under the aegis <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) was the apt course<br />

to take in those circumstances, so did the Court in Masiya. In both<br />

cases, moreover, the Court made sufficiently clear its view that a<br />

duty- and liability-extending modification <strong>of</strong> the common law was<br />

required not just by some immanent, residual, order <strong>of</strong> values to be<br />

distilled from the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights as a whole, but also by an application<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitution’s specific guarantees respecting dignity and<br />

freedom and security <strong>of</strong> the person. 193<br />

It seems we might extract from the Carmichele/Masiya pair a<br />

general guideline <strong>of</strong> South African constitutional law, as follows:<br />

When the constitutional fault detected in some duty- and liabilityimposing<br />

parcel <strong>of</strong> the common law lies not at all in the imposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> duty and liability, but only in the failure to define the type <strong>of</strong><br />

duty- and liability-raising conduct in question with sufficient<br />

protective effect, then the authorisation for judicial surgery on the<br />

common law is to be found not in the court’s judicial-review/<br />

remedial power granted by section 172(1), but rather in its inherent<br />

power to develop the common law in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2). The<br />

reason for this result is not any thought that under-protection in dutydefining<br />

laws can only <strong>of</strong>fend against some residual ‘spirit’ <strong>of</strong> the Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights as a whole, but not against any clear, core, animating<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> any particular rights-naming clause. The reason for the<br />

result simply is that the section 172(1)(b) remedial power is expressly<br />

conditioned on an antecedent declaration <strong>of</strong> inconsistency <strong>of</strong> some<br />

law with the Constitution, and, in this class <strong>of</strong> cases — so thinks the<br />

Court — there is nothing to declare inconsistent.<br />

In sum: At stake here is a notional distribution <strong>of</strong> the source <strong>of</strong><br />

judicial authority and obligation to develop the common law, as<br />

between two clauses in the Constitution. Not at stake is a flight from<br />

direct application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, as Woolman defines ‘direct’.<br />

Rather, the Carmichele/Masiya pair (and let us also recall NK and<br />

Thebus) shows the Constitutional Court rejecting Woolman’s<br />

preferred construction <strong>of</strong> the relations among sections 8, 39(2), and<br />

172(1), as outlined in Part 2 <strong>of</strong> this article.<br />

193 See Carmichele (n 59 above) para 44 (‘[T]here is a duty imposed on the state and<br />

all <strong>of</strong> its organs not to perform any act that infringes these rights. In some<br />

circumstances there would also be a positive component which obliges the state<br />

and its organs to provide appropriate protection to everyone through laws and<br />

structures designed to afford such protection.’); Masiya (n 4 above) paras 25, 27,<br />

37, 38, 39, reviewed above, text accompanying notes 169-177.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 53<br />

Woolman, <strong>of</strong> course, is fully aware <strong>of</strong> this gap between his own<br />

preferred construction and the Court’s ‘black letter’ construction. He<br />

is nevertheless careful not to suggest that the gap must necessarily<br />

make a world <strong>of</strong> difference in practice. 194 To the contrary, he<br />

explicitly points out that the Constitutional Court, using its own<br />

construction, could make a ‘muscular’ use <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) that ‘could<br />

generate the kinds <strong>of</strong> decisions and constitutional rules’ he is looking<br />

for. 195 But he sees this possibility as ‘entirely hypothetical’, asserting<br />

that the Constitutional Court has not, in fact, ‘deployed s 39(2) in the<br />

muscular fashion that would be necessary to rebut my primary<br />

arguments.’ 196 One can assume, though, that were the Court, acting<br />

under the aegis <strong>of</strong> section 39(2), to search specifically for<br />

incompatibility between some challenged law and particular<br />

provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, that should count for Woolman as<br />

direct application. 197 I believe that Masiya — like Carmichele and NK<br />

— is most naturally read as just such a case, as opposed to a case <strong>of</strong> a<br />

non-differentiated appeal by the Court to some vaguely conjured<br />

‘spirit’ <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights entire. If Woolman does not see the cases<br />

that way, that might possibly be because his normative commitments<br />

are getting in the way, by which I mean his insistence that section 8<br />

and 39(2) must, on pain <strong>of</strong> redundancy, have mutually ‘independent’<br />

purposes, 198 entailing distinct tests for the common law’s liability to<br />

revision: incompatibility with ‘the specific provisions <strong>of</strong> Chapter 2’<br />

under section 8, incompatibility with the normative residue under<br />

section 39(2). 199<br />

4.5 The sex-discrimination issue: Easy or hard?<br />

For several pages, now, I have been reflecting on the Constitutional<br />

Court’s designation, in Masiya, <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) — and not section 8 or<br />

172(1) — as the source <strong>of</strong> its authority to review the High Court’s order<br />

in respect <strong>of</strong> developing the common law <strong>of</strong> rape. I turn now to<br />

another feature <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s Masiya decision that has<br />

excited Woolman’s concern, namely, the Court’s postponement <strong>of</strong><br />

the question whether the definition <strong>of</strong> rape, once extended to cover<br />

anal as well as vaginal penetration, must also be extended to cover<br />

penetration <strong>of</strong> males as well as females. My first suggestion (but then<br />

things will grow more complicated) will be that Woolman’s difference<br />

with the Court in this regard depends on a substantive disagreement<br />

concerning the merits <strong>of</strong> a particular constitutional claim. More<br />

precisely, it has to do with a conflict between Woolman’s and the<br />

194 See generally Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above).<br />

195 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 766 n 6.<br />

196 As above.<br />

197 See as above.<br />

198 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 769.<br />

199 See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 769, 771.


54 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

Court’s respective preliminary judgments regarding the merits <strong>of</strong> a<br />

claim against the rape definition’s consistency with Constitution<br />

sections 9(1) and 9(3), if that definition, once extended to cover anal<br />

penetration <strong>of</strong> females, is not immediately extended again to cover<br />

anal penetration <strong>of</strong> males.<br />

Of course, Masiya’s case does not squarely present that question;<br />

only a prosecution for rape in a case <strong>of</strong> anal penetration <strong>of</strong> a male<br />

could do that. Woolman does not — and I doubt he ever would — raise<br />

a blanket objection to judicial hesitancy to reach for hard<br />

constitutional questions whose resolution is not necessary to a<br />

complete disposition <strong>of</strong> the case sub iudice. What he does clearly<br />

think is that the constitutional violation is, in this instance, so<br />

exceptionally and blatantly clear that the Constitutional Court could<br />

appropriately have resolved it on the spot. 200 The hangup is that the<br />

Court apparently does not share Woolman’s perception <strong>of</strong> the<br />

obviousness <strong>of</strong> the answer to the equality clause question thus posed.<br />

If the question really is debatable in light <strong>of</strong> the applicable<br />

precedents, then the Court’s forbearance to decide on the spot will<br />

seem (to an American constitutional lawyer, at any rate) to be<br />

routinely predictable for any court in a constitutional democracy,<br />

disposing over an assigned power <strong>of</strong> judicial review; the forbearance<br />

simply cannot then qualify as probative for a general complaint about<br />

a judicial addiction to excessive minimalism. And the Court, I am<br />

about to suggest, had detectible reason to assess the equality clause<br />

question as debatable under its own precedents.<br />

In the view <strong>of</strong> the trial court in Masiya’s case — as well as in the<br />

apparent view <strong>of</strong> Woolman 201 — restricting the newly extended rape<br />

law’s protection to women is ‘irrational and totally senseless’, an<br />

‘arbitrary discrimination’ 202 — and thus, it would seem, a direct<br />

violation not only <strong>of</strong> section 9(3) but also section 9(1), according to<br />

the ‘tabulation’ for a section 9 inquiry laid down by Goldstone J in<br />

Harksen. 203 In the view <strong>of</strong> the High Court, the restriction results in<br />

‘discriminatory sentencing’, an apparent invocation <strong>of</strong> section 9(3)’s<br />

prohibition <strong>of</strong> unfair discrimination. 204 What is more, the<br />

Constitutional Court agrees that ‘non-consensual anal penetration ...<br />

200 Having noted his agreement with Langa CJ’s ‘unassailable’ view that ‘it makes no<br />

sense to distinguish between men and women’ with respect to the gravity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

crime <strong>of</strong> anal rape, Woolman goes on to say that ‘in these circumstances’ the<br />

Court was wrong to refrain from addressing the sex-specificity issue in a case<br />

whose facts did not require its resolution. Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 767.<br />

201 As above.<br />

202 Masiya (n 4 above) para 9.<br />

203 See Harksen v Lane NO [1997] ZACC 12; 1997 11 BCLR 1489; 1998 1 SA 300 para 53<br />

(item ‘(a)’ in the tabulation).<br />

204 Masiya (n 4 above) paras 2, 15.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 55<br />

is [no] less degrading, humiliating and traumatic’ for males than for<br />

females. 205 But, again, the hangup is that the Constitutional Court<br />

does not allow that it automatically follow from this equivalence that<br />

a gender-specific definition <strong>of</strong> rape must be unconstitutional. 206<br />

How could it not? The Court does not spell out its answer, but<br />

those conversant with the Court’s equality jurisprudence can see one<br />

sitting there. Section 9(3) prohibits unfair discriminations on grounds<br />

<strong>of</strong> sex, but not all sex-based differentiations are unfair (and much less<br />

are all <strong>of</strong> them arbitrary and thus in violation <strong>of</strong> section 9(1)). 207<br />

According to the Court’s carefully developed and precisely articulated<br />

doctrine, discrimination is ‘unfair’ when and ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it has the<br />

effect <strong>of</strong> impairing dignity or inflicting some comparably serious<br />

harm. 208 That may not be uncontroversial doctrine or (for aught I<br />

know) the doctrine favored by Woolman, but substantive doctrine it<br />

surely is, quite carefully and elaborately wrought by the<br />

Constitutional Court.<br />

So consider: In the view <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court,<br />

it is ... widely accepted that sexual violence and rape not only <strong>of</strong>fends<br />

the privacy and dignity <strong>of</strong> women but also reflects the unequal power<br />

relations between men and women in our society. 209<br />

Rape, said the Court, is understood in South Africa as being ‘not<br />

simply an act <strong>of</strong> sexual gratification, but one <strong>of</strong> physical domination’<br />

— ‘an extreme and flagrant form <strong>of</strong> manifesting male supremacy over<br />

females.’ 210 Historically, said the Court, ‘rape has been and continues<br />

to be a crime <strong>of</strong> which females are its systematic target.’ 211 In the<br />

prevailing societal view as reported by the Court, not only do females<br />

thus bear the major brunt <strong>of</strong> the degradation and brutality inflicted<br />

by sexual violence, but where such violence is consciously or<br />

unconsciously directed to the subordination <strong>of</strong> some sex or gender —<br />

as it somewhat systematically is, according to what the Court takes to<br />

be the dominant understanding — that sex or gender is the female or<br />

feminine, not the male or masculine.<br />

Perhaps that all adds up to a controversial batch <strong>of</strong> observations<br />

about prevailing South African understandings. (I do not know and<br />

shall not try to say.) But let us ask: Accepting the observations as<br />

correct, do they really provide a grader <strong>of</strong> penalties for crimes with a<br />

205 Masiya (n 4 above) para 30.<br />

206 As above. (‘That this is so does not mean that it is unconstitutional to have a<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> rape which is gender-specific.’).<br />

207 See Harksen (n 203 above) para 53.<br />

208 See Harksen (n 203 above) paras 46, 50, 51(c).<br />

209 Masiya (n 4 above) para 28.<br />

210 Masiya (n 4 above) para 36.<br />

211 As above.


56 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

decisive reason to tilt the balance more favorably to liberty and<br />

mercy, as against prevention and condemnation, when sexual<br />

violence is directed against males? On first look, I find it far from<br />

obvious that they do. I cannot, however, deny that the question is a<br />

hard one that requires careful thought. The Court’s observations do,<br />

then, point to a possible reason, not inherently injurious to the dignity<br />

<strong>of</strong> men or <strong>of</strong> women — any more than, in Hugo, President Mandela’s<br />

reasons for restricting his commutation order to mothers were found<br />

injurious to the dignity <strong>of</strong> men or <strong>of</strong> women 212 — why a lawmaker<br />

might decide to treat sexual violence toward women as a more<br />

seriously graded crime than sexual violence toward men. If not unfair<br />

in Hugo, why unfair here? One can so inquire in good faith, without for<br />

a moment doubting that that anal rape is a monstrous affront to the<br />

dignity and security <strong>of</strong> male as well as female victims — any more than<br />

any justice sitting in Hugo could have doubted that imprisonment is<br />

hard for men as it is for women. 213<br />

Granted, ‘strong arguments’ could be made — and were, to the<br />

Constitutional Court in Masiya’s case — ‘to the effect that genderspecificity<br />

in relation to rape’ must be deemed constitutionally unfair<br />

ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it undoubtedly reflects ‘patriarchal stereotypes<br />

inconsistent with the Constitution.’ 214 Exactly parallel arguments<br />

were made in Hugo, including by justices who found, contrary to the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court, that the President’s genderspecific<br />

deployment <strong>of</strong> his pardon power was indeed an act <strong>of</strong> unfair,<br />

sex-based discrimination. 215 In Hugo, the claims <strong>of</strong> constitutionally<br />

unacceptable stereotyping met up with both respectful consideration<br />

and formidable rebuttal from the majority side. 216 In Masiya, the<br />

Court did not reject the parallel arguments, it rather left them for<br />

another day. 217 Perhaps there are members <strong>of</strong> the Court engaged in,<br />

or open to, reconsideration <strong>of</strong> the position taken in Hugo. The matter<br />

at issue is obviously difficult, deep, and <strong>of</strong> major import for South<br />

African sex-equality jurisprudence. It may well currently divide the<br />

justices, just as it divided them in Hugo. If they wait, views might<br />

undergo maturation and moderation. Parliament may speak, and that<br />

could make a difference. In Hugo, the sex-discrimination question<br />

could not wait; if the discrimination were to be found unfair and<br />

unjustified, a remedial question would then arise that conceivably<br />

could have issued in Mr Hugo obtaining release from prison. In Hugo,<br />

the sex-discrimination question could not wait; Mr Hugo's claimed<br />

right against unfair, sex-based discrimination was directly and<br />

212 See The President <strong>of</strong> South Africa v Hugo 1997 4 SA 1 (CC); 1997 6 BCLR 708 (CC).<br />

213 See Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 767.<br />

214 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) para 29.<br />

215 See Hugo (n 212 above) para 80 (Kriegler J); paras 93-94 (Mokgoro J).<br />

216 See Hugo (n 212 above) paras 37-39 (Goldstone J); para 113 (O’Regan J).<br />

217 See Masiya (n 4 above) paras 29, 36.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 57<br />

immediately at stake. In Masiya, by contrast, the question can wait;<br />

the prisoner at bar has nothing at stake in the resolution.<br />

4.6 Objective unconstitutionality<br />

But Woolman maintains that the question cannot wait, owing to the<br />

Constitutional Court’s adherence to the doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective<br />

unconstitutionality. 218 Woolman puts the matter thus: ‘[I]f one<br />

cannot imagine the court’s refusing [on some future occasion] to<br />

extend the ‘new’ rule to embrace coerced anal intercourse <strong>of</strong> men,<br />

then the new rule is objectively unconstitutional as <strong>of</strong> the moment it<br />

was announced.’ 219 From this, Woolman apparently deduces that the<br />

Court is obliged to decide now (Woolman thinks in the affirmative)<br />

whether extension <strong>of</strong> the new rule to the protection <strong>of</strong> men is<br />

constitutionally required. But how, exactly, would that follow?<br />

Consider this possible response: Under the doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective<br />

unconstitutionality, a court is not free to postpone to some future<br />

case a decision on the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> any law whose application<br />

to a pending case would be decisive, even if the putative<br />

constitutional defect in that law pertains strictly to rights <strong>of</strong> persons<br />

other than the parties to the pending case. (‘The right to challenge<br />

the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> a statute which affects you directly cannot be<br />

made dependent on the finding <strong>of</strong> some other constitutional right on<br />

which to base the challenge. What if there is no such right?’) 220 Since<br />

the Court could never justify convicting Masiya in terms <strong>of</strong> an<br />

objectively unconstitutional law, it is obliged to face the question <strong>of</strong><br />

the new rule’s complete constitutionality as a part <strong>of</strong> its disposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> Masiya’s case.<br />

That cannot be Woolman’s argument, for the simple and obvious<br />

reason that the Constitutional Court is not, as matters turn out,<br />

proposing to apply the new definition <strong>of</strong> rape to the pending<br />

prosecution <strong>of</strong> Masiya. 221 The only law the Court proposes to apply to<br />

him is the old, constitutionally unassailable law defining the crime <strong>of</strong><br />

indecent assault, and so there is no way that an on-the-spot<br />

assessment <strong>of</strong> the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> the new rule can affect the<br />

prosecution’s outcome. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as the doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective<br />

unconstitutionality means to allow parties to pending cases to claim<br />

218 See, eg, Home Affairs (n 87 above) para 29:<br />

On the objective theory <strong>of</strong> unconstitutionality adopted by this Court a litigant<br />

who has standing may properly rely on the objective unconstitutionality <strong>of</strong> a<br />

statute for the relief sought, even though the right unconstitutionally infringed is<br />

not that <strong>of</strong> the litigant in question but <strong>of</strong> some other person.<br />

219 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 2 above) 167 n 7.<br />

220 Ferreira v Levin NO 1996 1 SA 984 (CC), 1996 1 BCLR 1 (CC) para 163 (Chaskalson<br />

P) (‘Ferreira’).<br />

221 See Masiya (n 4 above) paras 56-57 (deciding against retrospective application).


58 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

the benefit <strong>of</strong> the unconstitutionality (on whatever grounds) <strong>of</strong> rules<br />

and doctrines being then and there invoked against them, it can have<br />

no purchase in the pending prosecution <strong>of</strong> Masiya (nor in any<br />

imaginable future prosecution <strong>of</strong> him, unless in respect <strong>of</strong> some<br />

utterly hypothetical, future criminal act). 222<br />

Thus, on what we might call a precise or strict reading <strong>of</strong> the<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective unconstitutionality, it cannot have the effect <strong>of</strong><br />

requiring a decision <strong>of</strong> the putative section 9(3) claim against the new<br />

rule, as a part <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s disposition <strong>of</strong> the case <strong>of</strong><br />

Masiya v DPP CCT 54/06. But is there, perhaps, some looser version <strong>of</strong><br />

objective unconstitutionality that might have such an effect? I do not<br />

see what it would be. The doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective unconstitutionality<br />

cannot reasonably be taken to commit the Constitutional Court to onthe-spot<br />

adjudication <strong>of</strong> every conceivable claim <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

defect that might arguably afflict any <strong>of</strong> the rules and doctrines that<br />

in any way crop up in a case sub iudice. That way surely lies madness.<br />

We can use a variation on NM to illustrate. Suppose the Court<br />

decides to take the case up for review, in the expectation that it<br />

cleanly presents a question about the consistency <strong>of</strong> the extant<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> privacy-invasion with Constitution section 14,<br />

insomuch as the extant law flatly excludes liability for nonintentional,<br />

but negligent, unauthorised disclosures <strong>of</strong> private<br />

information. Upon study <strong>of</strong> the record, the Court discovers that it<br />

contains a binding stipulation from all sides, to the effect that the<br />

book-writer was not negligent or in any way at fault for her action —<br />

so all that could remain for the Constitutional Court to do would be to<br />

affirm the decision below on that ground. It seems Woolman would be<br />

among the first to insist (and I would agree) that the Court ought now<br />

to dismiss the appeal for want <strong>of</strong> jurisdiction. But why should that<br />

follow, after all? Why should not the Court rather say: ‘There is still a<br />

question in the air about whether the extant common law <strong>of</strong> privacyinvasion<br />

is constitutional, insomuch as it flatly excludes liability for<br />

negligence, so we really owe it to the country to decide that now, per<br />

the doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective unconstitutionality’. Is that how we want<br />

the Court to be conducting its affairs?<br />

222 Thus, this is not a case in which refusal to decide a constitutional question on the<br />

spot could possibly involve the Court in ‘recognis[ing] the validity <strong>of</strong> a [law] in<br />

respect <strong>of</strong> one litigant, only to deny it to another.’ Ferreira (n 220 above) para 26<br />

(Ackermann J). Neither — owing to the non-retrospectivity ruling in Masiya — is it<br />

a case in which the postponement compromises ‘legal certainty’ to the<br />

disadvantage <strong>of</strong> any individual contemplating some or other course <strong>of</strong> action (as<br />

above). Of course, the objective-unconstitutionality argument would have bite in<br />

Masiya’s case, if the Court had decided in favor <strong>of</strong> retrospective application <strong>of</strong><br />

the new rule. But I do not take Woolman to be suggesting that the Court’s ruling<br />

against retrospective application is itself symptomatic <strong>of</strong> a flight from substantive<br />

decisionmaking responsibility.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 59<br />

Nothing that I know <strong>of</strong> in the Constitutional Court’s oeuvre<br />

suggests that the Court itself has ever thought so. The Court has<br />

rejected a ‘narrow’ approach to standing in constitutional cases. 223<br />

Accordingly, the Court will address constitutional challenges by or on<br />

behalf <strong>of</strong> any litigant — whether or not his or her own constitutional<br />

rights are at stake — who can show that ‘he or she is directly affected<br />

by’ the law in question, and in that sense has an ‘interest in’ the<br />

challenge. 224 The Court has furthermore indicated that it will be<br />

generous in deciding whether such an interest has been shown. 225 The<br />

Court has also, however, expressly recognised the factors militating<br />

against allowance <strong>of</strong> constitutional challenges by persons claiming<br />

only a ‘hypothetical’ or ‘academic’ interest:<br />

The principal reasons for this objection are that in an adversarial system<br />

decisions are best made when there is a genuine dispute in which each<br />

party has an interest to protect. There is moreover the need to conserve<br />

scarce judicial resources and to apply them to real and not hypothetical<br />

disputes. The United States courts also have regard to ‘the proper role<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Courts in a democratic society’ which is to settle concrete<br />

disputes, and to the need to prevent courts from being drawn into<br />

unnecessary conflict with coordinate branches <strong>of</strong> government. 226<br />

These would seem to be reasons why ‘few, if any, countries have at<br />

all times allowed all persons to invoke the jurisdiction <strong>of</strong> Courts to<br />

solve all legal problems.’ 227 South Africa does not draw the line nearly<br />

as strictly as some countries do (mine, for example), 228 but a line<br />

there surely must be, and drawing it at the point where the litigant<br />

raising the challenge has something at stake in its resolution — that<br />

is, qua litigant, not just qua citizen — seems not a bad place to draw<br />

it. That, at any rate, is what I understand the doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective<br />

unconstitutionality to do. Woolman fears the doctrine may be falling<br />

into some degree <strong>of</strong> ‘desuetude’. 229 I respond only that Masiya cannot<br />

stand as evidence for that proposition.<br />

4.7 The court’s responsibility as lawmaker<br />

Suppose you are persuaded that the doctrine <strong>of</strong> objective<br />

constitutionality, as currently propounded by the Constitutional<br />

Court, does not oblige the Court to address a section 9(3) claim<br />

223 Ferreira (n 220 above) para 162 (Chaskalson P).<br />

224 Ferreira (n 220 above) paras 165-66 (Chaskalson P).<br />

225 ‘It is for this Court to decide what is a sufficient interest in the circumstances.’<br />

Ferreira (n 220 above) para 168 (Chaskalson P, rejecting Ackermann J’s view that<br />

the Applicants lacked standing to raise a particular constitutional challenge).<br />

226 Ferreira (n 220 above) para 164 (citation omitted).<br />

227 Ferreira (n 220 above) para 31 (Ackermann J).<br />

228 See, eg, n 154 above.<br />

229 Woolman ‘Application’ (n 17 above) 50.


60 Uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’<br />

against the new rule, as part <strong>of</strong> its disposition <strong>of</strong> Masiya’s case. That<br />

is certainly not yet to say that nothing so obliges it. What most likely<br />

would so oblige it, if anything does, is the simple fact that the Court<br />

is the author <strong>of</strong> the new rule, and we can rightly demand <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court that it — above all other agents in the South<br />

African constitutional order — take care, when it gets into the<br />

business <strong>of</strong> writing laws, to write only laws that are fully consistent<br />

with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. I mean, just imagine that Cabinet, having<br />

decided to preempt completely the common law <strong>of</strong> sexually<br />

assaultive crimes with a new statutory code, tables before Parliament<br />

a draft that defines rape as the vaginal or anal penetration <strong>of</strong><br />

females. It will most definitely be in order for objectors to demand<br />

that Parliament must now, before acting, decide whether, in its<br />

advised view, such a statute could pass constitutional muster under<br />

section 9(3). If that is so for Parliament, must it not be even more<br />

clearly so for the Constitutional Court?<br />

Maybe not. To say so with perfect confidence is to lose sight<br />

momentarily <strong>of</strong> some differences between a court and a parliament in<br />

a constitutional democracy. When Parliament passes a bill, it, by<br />

necessary implication, clears that bill <strong>of</strong> constitutional defect so far<br />

as it can tell (no doubt subject to possible judicial correction). When<br />

the Constitutional Court declines to decide the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> a<br />

parliamentary enactment, in a case where nothing can possibly turn<br />

on that decision, it does not do that; it rather says ‘I am a court, I am<br />

moderately self-restrained by habit that you [meaning the country]<br />

would not really wish me to shake <strong>of</strong>f, and the time for that is not yet<br />

ripe.’<br />

‘But’, you will justly reply, ‘the new rule we are concerned with<br />

here is not a parliamentary enactment; it is the Court’s own, direct<br />

creation; that is just the point! There is no inter-branch dialogue in<br />

progress here, no consideration <strong>of</strong> deference to democratic<br />

accountability, no ball in Parliament’s court, to motivate or warrant<br />

postponement; there is only the Court refusing to confront itself!’ I<br />

am on shaky ground here, owing to deficient understanding <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exact interplay between common law and statute law in the South<br />

African law <strong>of</strong> crimes. (The very idea <strong>of</strong> common law crime poses a<br />

major challenge to the American-trained constitutional-legal<br />

temperament!) My impression, though, from the Masiya case itself, is<br />

that Parliament has indeed, though the Criminal Procedure Act and its<br />

various schedules, quite concretely bought into the judiciary’s<br />

historic definitions <strong>of</strong> the various crimes and, in a quite real sense,


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 61<br />

made those definitions its own — including, specifically, the sexdifferentiating<br />

aspect in the historic definition <strong>of</strong> the crime <strong>of</strong><br />

rape. 230 If that is correct, then the full <strong>of</strong> set <strong>of</strong> normal, inter-branch<br />

considerations affecting the degree to which the Court reaches out for<br />

constitutional questions is operative here.<br />

It is, to be sure, a set <strong>of</strong> considerations that can be cashed only<br />

through exercises <strong>of</strong> judgment in particular cases. The cost <strong>of</strong> waiting<br />

always must be among the factors to be considered. That there is such<br />

a cost involved in the choice that concerns us here cannot be doubted.<br />

If (as Woolman believes) the Court must eventually decide to extend<br />

the rape definition to cover cases <strong>of</strong> male victims, the next rape-like<br />

assault on a man still won’t be prosecutable as rape. That is for sure,<br />

given the anti-retrospectivity ruling in Masiya; and that could make<br />

all the difference. But the odds don’t seem overwhelmingly that way,<br />

indecent assault is still a serious crime; and the Court’s public fidelity<br />

to its anti-imperialist habit is not in itself a negligible value. Had the<br />

Court grasped the nettle in Masiya that would not, in my view, have<br />

been over the line (given that there are common law crimes that the<br />

courts are responsible to define). But neither, in my view on present<br />

information, was the decision to wait an improper one.<br />

How we judge that question may depend on how obviously and<br />

inevitably right we judge the section 9(3) claim against the new rule<br />

to be. Someone who sees the claim as irresistible is much likelier to<br />

fault the Constitutional Court for declining to decide it on the spot,<br />

than is someone, like me, who sees the claim as debatable under the<br />

precedents as they stand. In presenting the claim in that light, I have<br />

gone well beyond anything written in the Constitutional Court’s<br />

opinion; no reference to Hugo or to Harksen, for example, appears<br />

there. But I have <strong>of</strong>fered nothing that is not entirely consistent with<br />

what the Court did write, and perhaps nothing that is not more or less<br />

clearly indicated by what the Court did write, at least to those<br />

conversant with the body <strong>of</strong> the Court’s other work. In other words, I<br />

have followed the course <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity. Whether with<br />

resulting net pr<strong>of</strong>it or loss to the project <strong>of</strong> the advancement <strong>of</strong> the<br />

benign rule <strong>of</strong> constitutional law in South Africa must be for the<br />

reader to judge.<br />

230 See Masiya (n 4 above) paras 2, 7, 12.


THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT, COURT<br />

WATCHERS AND THE COMMONS:<br />

A REPLY TO PROFESSOR MICHELMAN ON<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL DIALOGUE, ‘INTERPRETIVE<br />

CHARITY’ AND THE CITIZENRY AS SANGOMAS<br />

1 Background<br />

* I would like to thank the editors for inviting me to write this reply. In particular I<br />

would like to thank Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Stu Woolman for regular conversation and extensive<br />

comments on the form and the substance <strong>of</strong> this reply. The paper also benefited<br />

from comments made by the participants at the Constitutional Court Review<br />

Conference (6-7 August 2008 Somerset West). Needless to say all errors are mine.<br />

63<br />

Tshepo Madlingozi*<br />

When I think back on the Constitutional Court’s 2007 term, one event<br />

stands out for me. On 20 August 2007, the Court was hearing Merafong<br />

Demarcation Forum v President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa. 1<br />

After a long period <strong>of</strong> struggle in which they had employed both<br />

institutional and extra-institutional mechanisms <strong>of</strong> democracy, the<br />

people <strong>of</strong> Khutsong decided to take their case to the Constitutional<br />

Court. Why? ‘The government does not want to listen.’ 2 On that day<br />

more than a 1 000 protesters gathered outside the court room toyi<br />

toying and singing liberation songs. During the course <strong>of</strong> the day,<br />

things turned nasty when protesters started burning tyres,<br />

brandishing dangerous weapons and allegedly pelting the police with<br />

stones. 3 For me, this episode vividly demonstrates the fragile state <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa’s constitutional culture.<br />

1 Merafong Demarcation Forum & Others v President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South<br />

Africa & Others 2008 5 SA 171 (CC).<br />

2 I Lekota ‘Flames in Khutsong’ Sowetan 25 May 2007 http://www.sowetan.co.za/<br />

3<br />

Columnists/IdoLekota/Article.aspx?id=473030.<br />

See ‘Khutsong battle reaches Constitutional Court’ Mail & Guardian On-line 20<br />

August 2007 http://www.mg.co.za/article/2007-09-20-khutsong-battle-reachesconstitutional-court<br />

(accessed 23 October 2008). For dramatic photos capturing<br />

these events, visit http://photos.mg.co.za/view_photo.php?pid=2036&gid=124<br />

(accessed 23 October 2008).


64 Reply to Michelman<br />

In their opposition to the incorporation <strong>of</strong> Merafong municipality<br />

into the North West province, the people <strong>of</strong> Khutsong had done<br />

everything conceivably possible within the law: They had participated<br />

in public consultation forums where they voiced their opposition<br />

against the proposal; they sent memoranda to state organs at all three<br />

levels <strong>of</strong> government; they had lobbied political parties and other<br />

stakeholders; they had engaged in peaceful marches and protests.<br />

Indeed before resorting to the litigation, the people <strong>of</strong> Khutsong had<br />

exhausted all institutional mechanisms available to them in a direct,<br />

participatory and representative democracy. In a phrase, they had<br />

done all that could be expected <strong>of</strong> an active citizenry in a<br />

constitutional democracy. Khutsong — ‘the place <strong>of</strong> peace’ — will long<br />

be remembered for the violence and mayhem that have gripped the<br />

township since December 2005. In scenes very much reminiscent <strong>of</strong><br />

the 1980s township revolts against the apartheid regime, television<br />

cameras captured daily images <strong>of</strong> young people blockading the streets<br />

with burning tyres and stones, preparing ‘molotov cocktails’, torching<br />

shops, libraries, schools, government buildings and local councillors’<br />

homes. Between December 2005 and April 2006, violent protests<br />

caused damage to private and public property estimated at<br />

R70 million. 4 The community’s deep level <strong>of</strong> discontent is further<br />

reflected by the successful boycott <strong>of</strong> the municipal elections in<br />

March 2006. Of almost 30 000 registered voters, only 232 cast their<br />

ballots. 5 From December 2005 until the end <strong>of</strong> 2007, the township was<br />

rendered ‘ungovernable’.<br />

It took a very long time before the people <strong>of</strong> Khutsong decided to<br />

take their struggle to Court. It was not an easy decision. The leaders<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Khutsong struggle were convinced that their struggle could ‘be<br />

won in the street’: 6<br />

4<br />

Centre for Development and Enterprise ‘Voices <strong>of</strong> Anger’ 10 CDE Focus (April<br />

2007) 10.<br />

5 As above.<br />

6<br />

N Kolisile ‘The crying <strong>of</strong> Khutsong’ Amandla Publishers 1 October 2008 http://<br />

www.amandlapublishers.co.za/content/view/71/32/ (accessed 2 November<br />

2008). Similarly, after the Court delivered its judgment, the Young Communist<br />

League noted in a press statement that even though it had not yet studied the<br />

Court’s decision, it was their ‘contention that matters related to forceful and<br />

illegitimate demarcations cannot be mitigated or resolved through the organs <strong>of</strong><br />

class rule — the courts.’ See ‘YCL Statement on Khutsong’s ruling by the<br />

ConCourt’ 13 June 2008 http://groups.google.com/group/yclsa-press/browse_<br />

thread/thread/67c0616a73a6f791 (accessed 20 June 2008). It is also important to<br />

note that — with the 2009 election firmly in their sight — the ruling party has<br />

recently decided that the Merafong Municipality will be incorporated back into<br />

Gauteng province. See ‘Khutsong to be returned to Gauteng’ The Mercury 22<br />

October 2008 http://www.iol.co.za index.php?set_id=1&click_id=13&art_id=<br />

vn20081022054258319C323057 (accessed 2 November 2008).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 65<br />

It would be very dangerous to put our faith in legal processes. Courts are<br />

seldom neutral and <strong>of</strong>ten tend to serve the interests <strong>of</strong> the ruling class.<br />

That is the reason we have delayed taking this matter to the<br />

Constitutional Court. For more than a year we have relied on our own<br />

mass strength and we still do. In the coming period we will utilise the socalled<br />

democratic space provided by the new constitution as well as<br />

working class resistance. Key strategies include intensifying mobilisation,<br />

building consciousness and continuing with mass struggle in the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> marches and rallies. This struggle will be won in the street!<br />

Khutsong — during this period <strong>of</strong> struggle — is both a reminder <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fragility <strong>of</strong> South Africa’s new political order and an indictment <strong>of</strong> its<br />

ability to respond effectively to those persons and communities in the<br />

greatest need. As one <strong>of</strong> the leaders <strong>of</strong> the Khutsong anti-demarcation<br />

movement wrote: ‘The struggle <strong>of</strong> the people <strong>of</strong> Greater Merafong is<br />

not just about forceful incorporation into North West, but about<br />

fighting for truth from government, people’s rights and democracy.’ 7<br />

Khutsong is not a singular, if continuous, event in a long but<br />

peaceful transition from a fascist apartheid state to a democratic<br />

constitutional order. Every week some poor community engages in<br />

illegal and <strong>of</strong>ten violent actions to back up demands for a more<br />

responsive government. Patrick Bond reports that ‘the pace <strong>of</strong> social<br />

protest intensified dramatically during the mid-2000s, soaring from<br />

5,813 recorded protests in 2004-05 to more than 10,000/year’. 8 Dale<br />

McKinley, one <strong>of</strong> the leaders <strong>of</strong> the Anti-Privatisation Forum, has<br />

argued that the increased violence employed by these community<br />

movements reflects the absence <strong>of</strong> ‘more inclusive and meaningful<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> direct and participatory democracy, that have little to do<br />

with the institutional forms <strong>of</strong> representation within bourgeois<br />

‘democratic’ society.’ 9 McKinley claims convincingly that ‘these<br />

movements have arisen out <strong>of</strong> the very failures and betrayals <strong>of</strong> the<br />

“main currents” and the institutional framework that gives them<br />

contemporary legitimacy.’ 10<br />

The biggest threat to the consolidation <strong>of</strong> South Africa’s<br />

constitutional culture is not the unprincipled and crass accusations<br />

7 Kolisile (note 6 above).<br />

8 P Bond ‘Rejoinder: Collaborations, co-optation & contestation in praxis-based<br />

knowledge production’ (2008) 35 Review <strong>of</strong> African Political Economy 271 272.<br />

9 D McKinley ‘Democracy and social movements in SA’ (2004) 28 Labour Bulletin 39<br />

40.<br />

10 McKinley (note 9 above) 40. For more in-depth analyses and case studies <strong>of</strong> these<br />

post-apartheid social movements and community organisations, see R Ballard et<br />

al (eds) Voices <strong>of</strong> protest: Social Movements in Post-Apartheid South Africa<br />

(2006); N Gibson (ed) Challenging hegemony: Social movements and the quest for<br />

a new humanism in South Africa (2006); D McKinley & P Naidoo (eds)<br />

Development Update 5 (2004); and T Madlingozi ‘Post-Apartheid social movements<br />

and the quest for the elusive “new” South Africa’ (2007) 34 Journal <strong>of</strong> Law<br />

and Society 77.


66 Reply to Michelman<br />

lodged by political elites within the African National Congress against<br />

South Africa’s ‘independent’ judiciary. The time bomb ticking away<br />

inside our polity is the disillusionment <strong>of</strong> the overwhelming majority<br />

<strong>of</strong> South Africans with the politics and the policies <strong>of</strong> our postapartheid<br />

democracy. Constitutional culture thrives when mobilised<br />

groups feel that they can appeal to constitutional norms and<br />

procedures in order to have their dispute resolved. It withers when<br />

such appeals go unheard. To be sure, the state’s response to these<br />

community movements has been at best to marginalise and vilify<br />

these movements by labelling them as ‘ultra-leftists’, ‘counterrevolutionaries’<br />

organised by white ‘racists’, ‘enemies <strong>of</strong> the new<br />

democracy’; 11 and at worst to criminalise and to suppress their<br />

struggles. 12<br />

If one <strong>of</strong> the objectives <strong>of</strong> the judiciary in a constitutional<br />

democracy is to facilitate ‘constitutional dialogue’, has the Court<br />

done enough to facilitate a dialogue between itself and the citizenry?<br />

The answer is no. More pointedly, I would caution against the<br />

judiciary’s and the academy’s acceptance <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman’s<br />

proposal that ‘the principle <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity’ will have a<br />

meaningful effect on closing the gap between the Constitutional<br />

Court and the people.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman is indeed a giant. 13 His breadth <strong>of</strong> scholarship<br />

and his ongoing commitment to South Africa have made him one<br />

11 See, as an example, the response by ANC strategist Michael Sachs to the rise <strong>of</strong><br />

these movements: M Sachs ‘“We don’t want the fucking vote”: Social movements<br />

and demagogues in South Africa’s young democracy’ (2004) 28 Labour Bulletin 23-<br />

12<br />

13<br />

27.<br />

For extensive reports on the criminalisation <strong>of</strong> poor people’s struggle as well as<br />

its violent repression, see D McKinley & A Veriava Arresting dissent: State<br />

repression and post-Apartheid social movements (2005) and M Memeza ‘A critical<br />

review <strong>of</strong> the implementation <strong>of</strong> the Regulation <strong>of</strong> Gatherings Act 205 <strong>of</strong> 1993 — A<br />

local government and civil society perspective’ (2006) available at<br />

www.fxi.org.za (accessed 14 June 2007).<br />

It is a singular honour for me to be afforded this opportunity to engage with<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Frank Michelman’s excellent foreword to this first issue <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court Review (FI Michelman ‘On the uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’:<br />

Some notes on application, avoidance, equality, and objective unconstitutionality<br />

from the 2007 term <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa’ (2008) 1<br />

Constitutional Court Review 1 (Michelman ‘Charity’)). Of those non-South African<br />

scholars who engage with the work <strong>of</strong> the South African Constitutional Court and<br />

South African Constitutional law theory in general, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman is<br />

undoubtedly one <strong>of</strong> the most dedicated and influential. Indeed, as Pr<strong>of</strong>essors<br />

Botha, Andre Van der Walt and Johan Van Der Walt have noted in a preface to a<br />

South African book dedicated to the scholarship <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong> Michelman, ‘Frank’s ideas<br />

have been — and continue to be — a source <strong>of</strong> inspiration for many <strong>of</strong> us who are<br />

interested in the possibility — and limits — <strong>of</strong> ‘transformative constitutionalism’.<br />

His writings on the judicial function and the capacity <strong>of</strong> rights discourse to<br />

facilitate and deepen democratic dialogue are among the most original and<br />

thoughtful on the topic — as are his reflections on constitutionalism as a tool for<br />

protecting a plurality <strong>of</strong> cultures, thoughtways and lifestyles; redressing<br />

inequality; and promoting social justice. It is therefore hardly surprising that<br />

South African legal academics and judges would have turned to his ideas in an


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 67<br />

<strong>of</strong> our most important allies in re-thinking the meaning <strong>of</strong> a truly postapartheid<br />

constitutional democracy. It is therefore most fitting that<br />

he should write one <strong>of</strong> the forewords to the first issue <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court Review. My mandate here, however, is not to<br />

pay homage to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman. It is, rather, to somehow engage<br />

with his response to the equally impressive commentary on the<br />

Court’s jurisprudence by Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Woolman. 14 The two interlocutors<br />

need to be read together.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman’s piece is a rejoinder to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Woolman’s<br />

critical analysis <strong>of</strong> what he describes as the Constitutional Court’s<br />

‘penchant for outcome-based decision-making and a concomitant lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> analytical rigour’. 15 This absence <strong>of</strong> analytical rigour — and its<br />

deleterious consequences — are exemplified by, though not limited<br />

to, the Court’s tendency, as Woolman sees it, to ‘refuse’ to engage in<br />

the direct application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights: ‘The persistent refusal to<br />

give rights identifiable content, by avoiding direct application results<br />

in a Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights increasingly denuded <strong>of</strong> meaning.’ 16 Woolman<br />

further contends that this refusal amounts to a ‘paradigmatic<br />

violation <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law’. This reticence makes it difficult, if not<br />

impossible<br />

for lower court judges, lawyers, government <strong>of</strong>ficials and citizens to<br />

discern, with some degree <strong>of</strong> certainty, how basic law is going to be<br />

applied, and to know, with some degree <strong>of</strong> certainty, that the basic law<br />

is going to be applied equally ... 17<br />

Michelman disagrees with Woolman’s conclusion that the thinly<br />

reasoned judgments in NM 18 and Masiya 19 show that the Court is in<br />

‘full flight from any meaningful engagement with Chapter 2 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution’ 20 and thus an abdication <strong>of</strong> the Court’s institutional<br />

13 attempt to break with the formalism and authoritarianism characterising our<br />

legal past, and to make sense <strong>of</strong> the democratic and egalitarian aspirations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution.’ H Botha et al (eds) Rights and democracy in a transformative<br />

constitution (2003) vii. In a paper presented in 2003 at a symposium dedicated to<br />

the scholarship <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Frank Michelman — Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Levinson had this to say:<br />

‘There are many reasons to honour Frank Michelman, not least because there are<br />

so many different topics — central to the enterprise <strong>of</strong> thinking about law — about<br />

which he has been remarkably illuminating. He is truly a giant on whose shoulders<br />

many <strong>of</strong> us are proud to stand as we try to think our way through the dilemmas<br />

presented by trying to take the enterprise <strong>of</strong> American constitutionalism<br />

seriously’. S Levinson ‘Perpetual union, “free love”, and secession: On the limits<br />

to the “consent <strong>of</strong> the governed”’ (2003) 39 Tulsa Law Review 457 457.<br />

14 S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law<br />

Journal 762 (Woolman ‘Amazing’); S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al<br />

(eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) ch 31.<br />

15 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 762.<br />

16 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 763.<br />

17 As above.<br />

18 NM v Smith 2007 5 SA 250 (CC) (NM).<br />

19 Masiya v Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions 2007 5 SA 30 (CC) (Masiya).<br />

20 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 783.


68 Reply to Michelman<br />

responsibility. Michelman agrees entirely with Woolman’s contention<br />

that the majority opinions in NM and Masiya are ‘thinly reasoned’. He<br />

demurs from the thesis that these cases ‘have been wrongly or<br />

irresponsibly managed, as measured by reasonably discoverable, valid<br />

considerations <strong>of</strong> law and legal administration.’ 21<br />

The move Michelman then makes may be one <strong>of</strong> the most powerful<br />

rhetorical ploys in analytic philosophy: the use <strong>of</strong> the Donald<br />

Davidson’s principle <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity. That principle in short<br />

requires that if we are genuinely interested in understanding another<br />

person or culture, then we must count them ‘right’ in most <strong>of</strong> what<br />

they say and do. To refuse to do so would consign them to the<br />

madhouse. Michelman describes the principle <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity<br />

as ‘an approach to understanding a speaker’s statements by<br />

interpreting the ... statements to be rational and, in the case <strong>of</strong> any<br />

argument rendering the best, strongest possible interpretation <strong>of</strong> an<br />

argument.’ 22 The aim <strong>of</strong> this principle, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman tells us 23<br />

is to learn. It is aggressively to learn what there is to learn from puzzles<br />

the interlocutors pose to us, by assuming there is method in their<br />

madness and doing our best to ferret that out, using everything else we<br />

know or can guess ... about where they are coming from.<br />

Michelman deploys the technique <strong>of</strong> ‘interpretive charity’ in order to<br />

fill in the gaps in the majority’s opinions in NM and Masiya. After an<br />

extensive and careful examination <strong>of</strong> the majority opinions in NM and<br />

Masiya, through a charitable lens, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman concludes<br />

that the fact that the Constitutional Court seems to be gravitating<br />

towards its inherent power to develop common law in terms <strong>of</strong> section<br />

173 and 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution — as opposed to its judicial review<br />

power in terms <strong>of</strong> section 8 and 172(1) when undertaking a<br />

modification <strong>of</strong> common law rules under pressure from the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights — does not mean that the court is uncomfortable with engaging<br />

with the substance <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.<br />

Woolman sees the refusal to undertake the direct application <strong>of</strong><br />

specific substantive provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights as evidence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

court that does not respect its own precedents; as evidence <strong>of</strong> a court<br />

unaccountable to the community <strong>of</strong> constitutional interpreters and<br />

incapable <strong>of</strong> telling its citizens how to conform their behaviour to the<br />

dictates <strong>of</strong> the basic law; and as evidence that the Court — at the end<br />

<strong>of</strong> it all — is responsible for ‘the amazing, vanishing <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

21 Michelman ‘Charity’ (n 13 above) 2.<br />

22 Wikipedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Principle_<strong>of</strong>_charity as cited by<br />

Michelman ‘Charity’ (note 13 above) 4.<br />

23 Michelman ‘Charity’ (n 13 above) 4.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 69<br />

Rights’. 24 Michelman sees the choice to go the route <strong>of</strong> indirect<br />

application made possible by section 39(2) — rather than direct<br />

application under section 8 — as no more than a matter <strong>of</strong> ‘doctrinal<br />

housekeeping’; 25 a ‘filing system’-question 26 over which nothing <strong>of</strong><br />

substance turns. Woolman maintains that form is substance: Direct<br />

application ultimately leads to a proper elucidation <strong>of</strong> South African<br />

constitutional law. Michelman remains unmoved. Woolman’s<br />

construction — magisterial as it is — proceeds, as Michelman notes,<br />

from an ‘unrealistic high expectation <strong>of</strong> formal tidiness and tightness<br />

in constitutional drafting.’ 27 In Michelman’s opinion, the application<br />

conundrum — as brilliantly set out by Woolman — can not be resolved.<br />

Both authors agree that some surplusage is inevitable.<br />

2 Engendering ‘constitutional dialogue’ with the<br />

Commons<br />

I am not a constitutional lawyer. The main direction <strong>of</strong> my arguments<br />

can, without apology, be said to be political. However, what I will<br />

focus on still remains a bone <strong>of</strong> contention between Woolman and<br />

Michelman: the Court’s accountability and responsibility to ensure<br />

principled constitutional dialogue and its alleged failure to do so. I am<br />

interested in seeing who, beyond Woolman’s ‘chattering classes’, 28<br />

influences the Constitutional Court. I am interested in asking whether<br />

the Court truly engages in a dialogue with ordinary persons. I would<br />

argue — consistent with the positions staked out by Woolman — that<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the ways that the Court can make itself accountable to the<br />

public, and thus facilitate constitutional dialogue, is when its<br />

judgments are sufficiently reasoned, fully justified and widely<br />

published. ‘Thinly reasoned’ judgments that require the reader to<br />

enter into a highly sophisticated and technical reconstruction <strong>of</strong> a<br />

judgment — some would say a sangoma-like exercise — do not advance<br />

the cause <strong>of</strong> ensuring that ordinary people are part <strong>of</strong> the ‘principled’<br />

— or at least transparent — constitutional dialogue to which the Court<br />

is ostensibly committed. I must therefore conclude that the principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘interpretive charity’ has limited value in bridging the gap between<br />

the Court and the vast majority <strong>of</strong> its constituents.<br />

24 Woolman argues that the Court’s failure to get application jurisprudence right<br />

and that it ‘continues to err in such quite obvious ways reflects, at a minimum<br />

three possibilities: (1) the court simply ignores academic interventions; (2) the<br />

court believes the academic criticism to be incorrect; and (3) the court ignores<br />

obvious doctrinal errors because it holds itself largely unaccountable to the<br />

existing community <strong>of</strong> academic and pr<strong>of</strong>essional interpreters’ (Woolman<br />

‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 783).<br />

25 Michelman ‘Charity’ (n 13 above) 3.<br />

26 As above.<br />

27 Michelman ‘Charity’ (n 13 above) 39.<br />

28 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 762.


70 Reply to Michelman<br />

How did I arrive at this conclusion regarding the limits <strong>of</strong> the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> interpretive charity in contemporary South Africa? Again,<br />

not on the basis <strong>of</strong> a nuanced assessment <strong>of</strong> the highly technical<br />

debate between Michelman and Woolman. I have read the exchange<br />

between Woolman and Michelman to ultimately be about how the<br />

Constitutional Court should conduct itself in relation to various<br />

stakeholders. Woolman argues, convincingly, that ‘a principled<br />

judicial dialogue’ that the Court claims to stimulate, 29 is not possible<br />

if the Court, in his opinion, ‘refuses to say more than is necessary to<br />

decide a case on its facts.’ 30 Michelman demands that we try harder,<br />

and that if we take the principle <strong>of</strong> ‘interpretive charity’ seriously<br />

then we might just be able also to enter into a ‘principled dialogue’<br />

with the Court.<br />

Woolman does not deny the gravitational pull <strong>of</strong> Michelman’s<br />

charitable approach. Instead, he contends ‘that a court that cannot<br />

be held accountable to its own precedent, to the text <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution, or to the community <strong>of</strong> constitutional interpreters, and<br />

that grounds its decisions by mere genuflection in the direction <strong>of</strong> s<br />

39(2), more closely approximates a “kryptocracy” than a<br />

“logocracy”.’ 31 Whether we agree with this characterisation or not,<br />

all <strong>of</strong> us should be in agreement that trenchant and sustained critique<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Court’s jurisprudence from academics should be encouraged.<br />

What should we read into the Court’s sense <strong>of</strong> imperviousness to being<br />

influenced or at least being accountable to a community <strong>of</strong><br />

‘constitutional interpreters’? If we agree that the court fails to create<br />

the conditions for a ‘principled dialogue’ between itself and what<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Woolman refers to as ‘a cohort <strong>of</strong> educated Constitutional<br />

Court watchers’; 32 through its ‘murky, if not tendentious, lines <strong>of</strong><br />

reasoning’ then what hope is there for the Commons, the masses <strong>of</strong><br />

the people that are directly affected by its decisions? 33<br />

Writing in 1992, Donald Nicolson noted that although the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

judicial independence is important in a democratic society,<br />

‘democracy is also threatened by an unaccountable judiciary.’ 34 I do<br />

not wish to enter into debates about the nature and the form that<br />

29 As called for by the Court in S v Mhlungu 1995 3 SA 867 (CC) para 129.<br />

30 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 785.<br />

31 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 784.<br />

32 Woolman ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) 762.<br />

33 Woolman is at pains to point out, however, that he is not simply — or even<br />

primarily — interested in what he rather glibly calls the chattering classes.<br />

Indeed, he argues in ‘Amazing’ (n 14 above) and elsewhere that a constitutional<br />

democracy cannot function as a constitutional democracy when no more than a<br />

few hundred people can read and decipher the meaning <strong>of</strong> the Court’s decisions.<br />

See also S Woolman & M Bishop ‘Law’s Autonomy’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds)<br />

34<br />

Constitutional conversations (2008) 1.<br />

D Nicolson ‘Ideology and the South African judicial process — Lessons from the<br />

past’ (1992) 8 South African Journal on Human Rights 50 70.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 71<br />

judicial accountability should take. Nor do I desire to revisit the<br />

arguments around how various techniques <strong>of</strong> judicial accountability<br />

can ensure a way out <strong>of</strong> the ‘counter-majoritarian’ dilemma. I am<br />

solely interested in how ‘public accountability’ can contribute to the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> constitutional dialogue between the Court and the<br />

Commons. It is also important to note that I use ‘accountability’ in the<br />

very narrow sense proposed by Louis Seidman: 35<br />

Sometimes we say that persons are accountable when they are required<br />

to give an account <strong>of</strong> themselves — that is, to give reasons or<br />

justifications for conduct and to demonstrate that such conduct is not<br />

the product <strong>of</strong> mere whim or caprice.<br />

Seidman argues that opinion writing exposes the judge’s thought<br />

process to those who read it, permits criticism <strong>of</strong> the justifications<br />

that the court <strong>of</strong>fers and thereby allows judges to be held<br />

accountable.<br />

To state that the ‘culture <strong>of</strong> justification’ 36 that flows from the<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law is just as applicable to the judiciary as it is<br />

to the executive and to the legislature, is to state the obvious. In<br />

cases where the Court’s decisions run counter to public opinion —<br />

assuming that such opinion can be accurately determined — it is<br />

vitally important that the Court fully justifies its decisions if it is not<br />

to lose public legitimacy. 37 Chief Justice Pius Langa has rightly<br />

observed that<br />

[T]he relationship which [the judiciary] has with rest <strong>of</strong> the community<br />

is ... important. It should be regarded as an integral part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

community it serves, and it can only function properly if it enjoys the<br />

complete trust and confidence <strong>of</strong> that community. 38<br />

Judging from various public statements and op-ed pieces written by<br />

members <strong>of</strong> the judiciary, it would seem that recent public criticism<br />

<strong>of</strong> the judiciary has caught members <strong>of</strong> the bench by surprise. The<br />

judges appear to have assumed that their public legitimacy was<br />

secure. However, one simply needs to look at the results <strong>of</strong> various<br />

empirical surveys to see that, for the majority <strong>of</strong> this country, the<br />

35 LM Seidman ‘Ambivalence and accountability’ (1988) 61 Southern California Law<br />

Review 1571 1574.<br />

36<br />

E Mureinik’s term. See E Mureinik ‘A bridge to where? <strong>Intro</strong>ducing the interim Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights’ 1994 (10) South African Journal on Human Rights 31.<br />

37 See T Roux ‘Principle and pragmatism on the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa’<br />

(2009) 7 International Journal <strong>of</strong> Constitutional Law 106. See also E van<br />

Huyssteen ‘The South African Constitutional Court and the death penalty: Whose<br />

values’ (1996) 24 International Journal <strong>of</strong> Sociology <strong>of</strong> Law 291.<br />

38<br />

See T Mbeki ANC Today 5(23) http://www.anc.org.za/ancdocs/anctoday/2005/<br />

text/at23.txt (accessed 22 October 2008).


72 Reply to Michelman<br />

Constitutional Court does not enjoy high public support. 39 Indeed,<br />

recent comments by Anthony Butler are spot on: ‘The idea that the<br />

courts are suddenly under siege is a fantasy. Their legitimacy has long<br />

been fragile ...’. 40<br />

Amongst community movements, activists and ordinary people —<br />

as opposed to educated Constitutional Court watchers and members<br />

<strong>of</strong> the chattering class — the judiciary has not been able to shake <strong>of</strong>f<br />

the impression that it is an instrument <strong>of</strong> the elites. 41 Take this<br />

exchange between the Treatment Action Campaign’s Mark Heywood<br />

and another activist. Mark Heywood — an unabashedly activist<br />

Constitutional Court watcher — wrote 42<br />

The Constitution is at the heart <strong>of</strong> our democracy. It prescribes<br />

accountable and ethical government, openness and a culture <strong>of</strong> justification<br />

by politicians for their actions. But more than this, it should be<br />

the touchstone for all public policy, an instrument that can be used to<br />

insist on public policy that places equality and social improvement at the<br />

heart <strong>of</strong> all government action.<br />

Now, to a ‘sober-minded’ and indeed ‘educated’ Constitutional<br />

Court watcher, this plea might seem quite reasonable. But that was<br />

not how it was read by one Commons activist: 43<br />

This near spiritual, nay, pathological worship <strong>of</strong> the handwork <strong>of</strong> neoliberals<br />

is how the masses and their struggle for full independence, selfreliance<br />

and liberation got substituted for ‘the constitution’! All political<br />

power and authority somehow got squeezed into the Constitution, and<br />

what all need do is learn it, and enforce its provisions, and instantly, all<br />

will be solved. What is concealed is that the real social and economic<br />

power in this marginal act <strong>of</strong> giving themselves a liberal constitution<br />

automatically moved, and conformed, into the capitalist class. And true,<br />

to the extent reasonably possible, the people’s real problems will be<br />

attended to!<br />

What is also never frequently spoken about are ... the massive racial<br />

fears <strong>of</strong> the white supremacists, who, upon being born again as capitalist<br />

class rights fighters through a liberal constitution, abandoned their<br />

‘minority racial rights’, and fought to have the constitution invested<br />

with ‘supreme power’ over all else.<br />

39 On such public opinion surveys, see Roux (n 37 above) 107 n 4. (Roux reports that<br />

27.9 per cent ‘attentive’ public support for the CCSA in 1997, ie among citizens<br />

who had heard about the Court, and ‘34 per cent public support for the CCSA in<br />

40<br />

2004’).<br />

A Butler ‘Emotional responses overlook good points Mantashe makes’ Business Day<br />

41<br />

14 July 2008.<br />

See T Madlingozi ‘The limits <strong>of</strong> transformative constitutionalism in the struggle<br />

42<br />

against poverty and marginalisation’ (2009, forthcoming) copy on file with author.<br />

M Heywood ‘Political climate dangerous for poor most <strong>of</strong> all’ Business Day 28 July<br />

43<br />

2008.<br />

A Banda Debate Listserve (28 July 2008) debate-bounces@debate.kabissa.org<br />

(accessed 28 July 2008).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 73<br />

The point here is that criticism <strong>of</strong> the judiciary does not only come<br />

from those who engage in scurrilous attacks on the judiciary in order<br />

to advance their narrow political agenda. Criticism <strong>of</strong> the judiciary<br />

also comes from those who are genuinely concerned about the gap<br />

between constitutional promises and the lived, impoverished, reality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the majority <strong>of</strong> South Africans.<br />

The common reaction by judges and legal analysts to criticism <strong>of</strong><br />

certain court judgments is to argue that the people do not understand<br />

the law or that they have not acquainted themselves sufficiently with<br />

the facts <strong>of</strong> the case. The former President <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong><br />

Appeal, Justice CT Howie has argued that not enough trouble has been<br />

taken ‘to tell our public, and our media, something <strong>of</strong> what judicial<br />

independence is all about’ and that public criticism is <strong>of</strong>ten made in<br />

the absence <strong>of</strong> getting to know the ‘vital facts’. 44 But as a member <strong>of</strong><br />

the Commons, I must ask: Whose responsibility is it to make sure that<br />

the public not only knows the ‘vital facts’ but also understands the<br />

working <strong>of</strong> the courts? Further, and more significantly, what if the<br />

public tries to acquaint itself with the reasons for a particular<br />

decision, only to be confronted with a ‘thinly reasoned’ judgment?<br />

How reasonable is it to expect members <strong>of</strong> the public to adopt the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> ‘interpretive charity’ and engage in the laborious exercise<br />

<strong>of</strong> filling in meanings and passages in the courts’ decisions as<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelman urges us to do?<br />

3 Conclusion<br />

During the Court’s 2007 term (and well into its 2008 docket),<br />

incidences referred to as ‘threats to the judiciary’ reached a fever<br />

pitch. In the weeks and months preceding the appearance <strong>of</strong> the then<br />

deputy president <strong>of</strong> the African National Congress (ANC) in court to<br />

face charges <strong>of</strong> corruption, robust criticism, emanating largely from<br />

members <strong>of</strong> the tripartite alliance — the ANC, the South African<br />

Communist Party and the Congress <strong>of</strong> South African Trade Unions —<br />

became common place. The slogan ‘We will kill for Zuma’ if the Court<br />

did not find in his favour became a disturbingly regular part <strong>of</strong> public<br />

discourse in some quarters.<br />

More than ever, the Court needs to court public support in order<br />

to protect itself against escalating ‘attacks on the judiciary’<br />

emanating from various political quarters. Theunis Roux has shown<br />

that in the past the Court has not needed public support in order to<br />

safeguard its institutional security because the ‘ANC political elite has<br />

shielded the Court from the political repercussions <strong>of</strong> its most<br />

44<br />

Justice CT Howie ‘Judicial independence’ (2003) 120 South African Law Journal<br />

679 679 & 682 (emphasis added).


74 Reply to Michelman<br />

unpopular decision ...’. 45 In light <strong>of</strong> recent events this protection can<br />

no longer be taken for granted. Indeed, these events dictate that the<br />

Court change its strategy and work to consolidate its public<br />

legitimacy. That is no small task. The Court has not yet engaged in any<br />

meaningful outreach programs. 46<br />

The Constitutional Court might be based near Hillbrow. It might<br />

be located in a non-intimidating, inviting building and it might be<br />

geographically accessible. The judges might be very friendly and well<br />

meaning people. But the members <strong>of</strong> the Court continue to operate<br />

and to move within the circles <strong>of</strong> ‘educated Constitutional Court<br />

watchers’. I have seen and enjoyed the presence <strong>of</strong> Constitutional<br />

Court judges at various academic conferences. But I am yet to see any<br />

<strong>of</strong> them at various workshops and rallies hosted by social movements.<br />

I have seen members <strong>of</strong> the Court give frank and engaging public<br />

lectures at various universities. But I am yet to see any <strong>of</strong> them<br />

address members <strong>of</strong> social movements. 47 I have heard members <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court give interviews on English radio stations. I have<br />

never heard any <strong>of</strong> them <strong>of</strong>fer an interview on an African language<br />

radio station.<br />

An ‘educated Constitutional Court watcher’ might tell me that the<br />

Court does not need to undertake such a public role. After all, their<br />

communications are a matter <strong>of</strong> public record. But where are the<br />

Sesotho or TshiVenda translations <strong>of</strong> the Court’s judgments? 48 And<br />

even if they did appear on the Court’s website, I fail to see how that<br />

would make any difference at all to the majority <strong>of</strong> South Africans<br />

who remain quaintly removed from the internet and other forms <strong>of</strong><br />

new media.<br />

As we launch this Review, we need to pause and think <strong>of</strong> ways that<br />

ordinary people, the Commons, can become part <strong>of</strong> the ‘principled<br />

dialogue’ to which the Court and academics such as Woolman and<br />

Michelman have committed themselves. Finally, as South Africa<br />

enters what has been aptly described as the ‘second transition’ —<br />

characterised by, amongst other things, robust engagement with<br />

45 Roux (note 37 above) 138.<br />

46 In its annual strategic/business plan, under a section entitled ‘Outreach<br />

programs’ the Director <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court only manages to mention<br />

initiatives such as the law researchers program and the setting up <strong>of</strong> the Court’s<br />

choir and soccer team. See ‘Annual Strategic/Business Plan 2008/2009’ http://<br />

www.constitutionalcourt.org.za/site/Admin/ANNUAL%20STRATEGIC%20BUSINESS%<br />

20PLAN%202008-2009.pdf (accessed 21 October 2008).<br />

47 Justice Dennis Davis is a notable exception in this regard. Justice Davis regularly<br />

gives key note addresses to social movement conferences and other events.<br />

48 During his interview for position <strong>of</strong> the Deputy Justice, Justice Dikgang Moseneke<br />

noted the practical and cost implications in handing down judgments in other<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficial languages. See http://www.constitutionalcourt.org.za/site/judges/<br />

transcripts/dikgangmoseneke1.html (accessed 1 November 2008).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 75<br />

institutions supporting democracy and the settling <strong>of</strong> major political<br />

disputes in courts 49 — the Court’s opinions will more than ever before<br />

play a significant role in public discourse and democratic politics. It<br />

is, therefore, vitally important that the Court holds itself<br />

accountable, not only to ‘educated constitutional court watchers’,<br />

but also to the Commons — some 46 million ordinary South Africans.<br />

Fully reasoned and sufficiently justified opinions that do not require<br />

the public to engage in highly complex exercises in ‘interpretive<br />

charity’ would be a first step in that direction. Maybe, just maybe,<br />

the events <strong>of</strong> 20 August 2007 might not be repeated in the future.<br />

49 See S Ndlangisa ‘Political ball is in our courts’ City Press 24 August 2008 24.


NORMATIVE PLURALISM AND ANARCHY:<br />

REFLECTIONS ON THE 2007 TERM<br />

77<br />

AJ van der Walt *<br />

1 The decline <strong>of</strong> foundation and the allure <strong>of</strong><br />

anarchy<br />

Waren die klaren Bedeutungen aus dem Haus, tanzte die Sprache auf<br />

dem Tisch. 1<br />

As a schoolboy, Robin Davies 2 was intrigued to hear that, according to<br />

the likes <strong>of</strong> DH Lawrence, if one really wanted something one ‘should<br />

have it, ought to have it, must do it or take it if you can’. However,<br />

Robin soon learnt that social norms <strong>of</strong>ten prevent you from taking<br />

what you want and they cause all kinds <strong>of</strong> trouble when you do. ‘You<br />

can have [me and the children], or you can have everyone else. Not<br />

both’, his wife Nancy told him, years later, laying down the law about<br />

his philandering. 3 ‘You can’t do both’, his father ruled when, aged 15<br />

or so, Robin wanted to visit a friend on an afternoon when his parents<br />

had already arranged something for that evening.<br />

* B Jur et Art Honns (BA) LLB LLD (Potchefstroom) LLM (Witwatersrand), South<br />

African Research Chair in Property Law, Faculty <strong>of</strong> Law, Stellenbosch <strong>University</strong><br />

(hosted by Stellenbosch <strong>University</strong>, funded by the Department <strong>of</strong> Science and<br />

Technology and administered by the National Research Foundation). Thanks to<br />

Gustav Muller, Elmien du Plessis, Mikhalien Kellermann and Janke Strydom for<br />

research assistance, and to Karl Klare, the participants in the <strong>CCR</strong> workshop and<br />

Geo Quinot, Philip Sutherland, Henk Botha, Irma Kroeze and Wessel le Roux for<br />

discussions and comments, to Philip Sutherland for access to a draft <strong>of</strong> ‘Insuring<br />

contractual fairness in consumer contracts’ (Stellenbosch Law Review<br />

1<br />

forthcoming), and to Halton Cheadle for an instructive exchange on application in<br />

the context <strong>of</strong> labour disputes. Remaining shortcomings are my own. My apologies<br />

to the reader for indulging a 30-year obsession.<br />

T Dorn ‘Ultima ratio’ in D Schwanitz et al Amoklauf im Audimax: Stories (1998) 7-<br />

2<br />

3<br />

46 18.<br />

In Kingsley Amis’s novel You can’t do both (2004).<br />

Patrick Standish received a similar ultimatum in Difficulties with girls (1988), as<br />

did Amis in real life.


78 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

Kingsley Amis, ‘the most clubbable <strong>of</strong> men’ and a womaniser <strong>of</strong><br />

note, 4 was frustrated by restrictions on his freedom to have things his<br />

way, but he was familiar with the power <strong>of</strong> bourgeois morality —<br />

‘taking it if you can’ wrought havoc when he decided that he should<br />

have what one <strong>of</strong> his characters called ‘marriage, 1960s style’, openly<br />

taking his mistress on holiday. 5 Like his characters, Amis found that<br />

he could have the wife and the children or the girlfriend; not both.<br />

Several Amis characters given to ‘take it if they can’ are forced to<br />

abandon some <strong>of</strong> what they wanted or lose everything, including their<br />

dignity. 6 It is easy to sc<strong>of</strong>f at silly ‘rules’ about not having two social<br />

engagements on the same day, but not all social norms are so easily<br />

dismissed, even if they appear arbitrary.<br />

The framing discourse for these Amis novels (and my purpose in<br />

recalling them) is not about accepting or rejecting social norms —<br />

despite his scorn for conventional morality, Amis did not subscribe to<br />

moral anarchy 7 (and in the 2007 term the Constitutional Court said<br />

little about morality). 8 Characters in the novels who made a life out<br />

<strong>of</strong> taking it if they could were not very nice persons and, despite<br />

flashes <strong>of</strong> defiance, Amis was not justifying their behaviour. 9 In fact,<br />

Amis was commenting on what could be described — not in his words<br />

— as the complexity <strong>of</strong> human relationships in a time when social<br />

fundamentalism was being replaced by pluralism 10 and, consequently,<br />

relativism and uncertainty. World War II liberated men and<br />

women from their traditional sexual and gendered social roles and<br />

4 On the autobiographical nature <strong>of</strong> You can’t do both see Z Leader The life <strong>of</strong><br />

Kingsley Amis (2006) 3 7-9. Martin Amis confirmed that finding parallels between<br />

his father’s life and novels is not ‘making the elementary mistake <strong>of</strong> conflating<br />

the man with the work’, since ‘all writers know that the truth is in the fiction’:<br />

Experience (2000) 28.<br />

5 Jenny, in Difficulties with girls (1988); the girlfriend was Elizabeth Jane Howard,<br />

Amis’s second wife.<br />

6 ‘Better be a bastard than a fool’, Roger Micheldene told himself, without much<br />

conviction, towards the end <strong>of</strong> One fat Englishman (1963).<br />

7<br />

In the Memoirs (1991) Amis remembered that his father put his, Kingsley’s,<br />

shortcomings down to his complete lack <strong>of</strong> religion. ‘And’, he says, ‘I should not<br />

be truly his son if I had never felt that he had something there.’ Amis concluded<br />

the Memoirs with a poem, entitled ‘Instead <strong>of</strong> an Epilogue’ and dedicated ‘To H’.<br />

In the final verse Amis lists the admirable characteristics <strong>of</strong> ‘someone’ he met<br />

when twenty-four, then proceeds: ‘Well, that was much as women were meant to<br />

be, / I thought, and set about looking further. / How can we tell, with nothing to<br />

compare?’<br />

8 But see Schaik v S 2008 2 SA 208 (CC) par 76.<br />

9<br />

Leader (n 4 above) 468: ‘Roger [Micheldene], like Patrick [Standish], knows how<br />

horrible he is.’<br />

10 Like J Dewar ‘The normal chaos <strong>of</strong> family law’ (1998) 61 Modern Law Review 467-<br />

485 I use the term to indicate a diversity <strong>of</strong> conflicting norms. See LL M<strong>of</strong>okeng<br />

‘The right to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion: An apparently misunderstood aspect <strong>of</strong> legal<br />

diversity in South Africa’ (2007) 11 Law, Democracy & Development 121-131; S<br />

Louw ‘Mysterium inequitatis: Truth, elections, autonomy in the Southern African<br />

politic’ (2006) 33 Politikon 221–238 (relying on C Lefort’s notion <strong>of</strong> ‘the political’<br />

to argue that democracy relies on diversity and pluralism). See further M Koenig<br />

& P de Guchteneire (eds) Democracy and human rights in multicultural societies<br />

(2007).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 79<br />

from the remnants <strong>of</strong> Victorian and Christian morality, opening up<br />

room for experimentation and free choice, 11 but liberation coincided<br />

with uncertainty and disruption. 12 Freedom from tradition comes at a<br />

price: once we give up the certainty <strong>of</strong> transcendent truth, choices<br />

become contingent and dangerous. Abandoning the certainty <strong>of</strong><br />

tradition created a normative vacuum and raised the spectre <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

anarchy and turpitude. As Amis framed it much later, reflecting on<br />

bad choices he had made: ‘how can we tell, with nothing to<br />

compare?’ 13 The problem with postwar pluralism was that, once the<br />

certainty <strong>of</strong> immutable rules is abandoned, there is nothing to<br />

compare. When tradition is traded in for pluralism, everything is open<br />

for questioning, which could create the impression that everything is<br />

up for grabs; that everything goes. In an effort to avoid anarchy, the<br />

temptation is to fall back on the formalism <strong>of</strong> empty rules.<br />

Amis’s depiction <strong>of</strong> postwar English society illustrates the slippery<br />

slope in post-traumatic society from normative pluralism to anarchy<br />

or, more accurately, to a facile choice between anarchy and<br />

reactionary formalism. The modernist rejection <strong>of</strong> foundation and<br />

acknowledgement <strong>of</strong> normative pluralism was inevitable, but the<br />

resulting uncertainty proved harder than expected. A similar process<br />

took place in law: ever since Realist and Critical Legal Studies scholars<br />

destroyed the theoretical credibility <strong>of</strong> fundamentalism and pointed<br />

out the indeterminacy and contingency implied by pluralism, lawyers<br />

— who usually deny that normative choice plays any role in law — had<br />

to account for their normative choices. In the face <strong>of</strong> nihilism and<br />

anarchy a reversion to formalism seems like a small price to pay for<br />

clarity and certainty.<br />

11 Social liberalisation after World War II can be traced to the aftermath <strong>of</strong> World<br />

War I, just like the Critical Legal Studies Movement continued a trend initiated by<br />

the Legal Realists. M Tushnet ‘Critical legal studies: An introduction to its origins<br />

and underpinnings’ (1986) 36 Journal <strong>of</strong> Legal Education 505-517 argues that the<br />

question whether Critical Legal Studies continued Legal Realism is uninteresting; I<br />

take continuation between the two world wars for granted. During the wars,<br />

women were forced to take men’s places in factories, liberating them from their<br />

home-maker role. Similarly, people fighting in the wars realised that the<br />

subservient social roles they were used to before the war (because <strong>of</strong> age, social<br />

status or race) no longer suited them. In both cases, liberation from tradition<br />

undermined the authority <strong>of</strong> social hierarchy.<br />

12 The street protests <strong>of</strong> 1968 that shocked mainstream society from Prague to Paris<br />

and from Berkeley to Berlin originated in the same context: the civil rights<br />

movement, women’s lib, the hippie movement, anti-war protests and student<br />

uprisings during the 1960s were founded upon rejection <strong>of</strong> traditional authority<br />

13<br />

and mainstream morality.<br />

See n 7 above. See IJ Kroeze ‘When worlds collide: An essay on morality’ (2007)<br />

22 SA Public Law 323-335, especially 331-332 333-335.


80 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

John Dewar 14 argues that normative pluralism, which he describes<br />

as a plurality <strong>of</strong> rules and values that are chaotic, incoherent and even<br />

antinomic in that the contradictions between them cannot be<br />

resolved in the long run, is normal in so far as contradictions at the<br />

level <strong>of</strong> rules are held at bay by practices not completely determined<br />

by text. In Dewar’s view, normative pluralism changes into anarchy<br />

when it combines with uncertainty about purposes; as soon as<br />

pluralism extends beyond the level <strong>of</strong> rules, normative anarchy<br />

ensues. Dewar identifies normative anarchy in situations where rights<br />

are mixed with discretion in a way that defies balancing and where<br />

regulatory legislation moves from rules to utility and back without<br />

suitable systemic adaptations.<br />

In a way, the early Amis novels described just such a shift from<br />

rules to utility and back — like Robin Davies, Amis and thousands <strong>of</strong><br />

others rebelled against the inflexible and arbitrary post-war<br />

dictatorship <strong>of</strong> surviving pre-war morality and craved the greater<br />

freedom and flexibility they experienced during the war. Of course,<br />

with flexibility comes the burden <strong>of</strong> discretion but, according to<br />

Dewar and Amis, abandoning foundation does not necessarily end in<br />

nihilism: normative anarchy can be avoided as long as contradictions<br />

are restricted by common purpose. In the less utilitarian language <strong>of</strong><br />

Joseph William Singer, the Critical Legal Studies movement ‘brought<br />

nihilism to centre stage’ by denying the possibility <strong>of</strong> determinacy,<br />

objectivity and neutrality in legal reasoning, but the absence <strong>of</strong><br />

foundation ‘does not condemn us to indifference or arbitrariness, nor<br />

make it ridiculous to ask, or impossible to answer, the question <strong>of</strong><br />

what we should do or how we should live’. 15 In Singer’s view legal<br />

theory, as a form <strong>of</strong> political activity, opens everything up for<br />

questioning without putting everything up for grabs — critical legal<br />

theory acknowledges moral and political goals that give direction to<br />

‘what we must do and how we should live’. 16<br />

Of course, on one level Dewar and Singer are vulnerable to<br />

accusations <strong>of</strong> fundamentalism — how does shared purpose or political<br />

goal that saves pluralism from anarchy differ from Victorian or<br />

Christian (or legal Formalist) sources <strong>of</strong> foundation? 17 How is any<br />

14 n 10 above, 468-473. See further J Dewar ‘Reducing discretion in family law’<br />

(1997) 11 Australian Journal <strong>of</strong> Family Law 309-326; S Parker ‘Rights and utility in<br />

Anglo-Australian family law’ (1992) 55 Modern Law Review 311-330; M Maclean<br />

Making law for families (2000).<br />

15<br />

‘The player and the cards: Nihilism and legal theory’ (1984) 94 Yale Law Journal<br />

1-70 8: asking ‘what shall we do and how shall we live?’ opens up dissent rather<br />

than consensus. See Tushnet (n 11 above) 509; A Hunt ‘The theory <strong>of</strong> Critical<br />

Legal Studies’ (1986) 6 Oxford Journal <strong>of</strong> Legal Studies 1-45.<br />

16 Singer (n 15 above) 66-70 identifies cruelty, misery, hierarchy and loneliness as<br />

the greatest problems that legal theory faces.<br />

17<br />

On foundation in law see P Fitzpatrick Modernism and the grounds <strong>of</strong> law (2001)<br />

1-7.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 81<br />

political purpose less arbitrary than Mr Davies senior’s decree that<br />

Robin cannot ‘do both’? Once the foundation <strong>of</strong> traditional rules is<br />

rejected, how do we justify the new rules we place in their stead to<br />

avoid anarchy?<br />

Developing a satisfactory answer to this challenge, if it can be<br />

done at all, will take my analysis too far <strong>of</strong>f course, but a starting<br />

point is to accept the argument <strong>of</strong> Johan van der Walt and Henk Botha<br />

that ‘the counter-majoritarian problem and the problem <strong>of</strong> significant<br />

social dissent [both sources <strong>of</strong> normative pluralism in constitutional<br />

discourse] are not technical hiccups’ but aporias that ‘open up the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> social deliberation that would exceed technical<br />

procedure’ and technical ethics to ‘give politics a chance’. 18 If there<br />

were a purpose that could avoid both anarchy and fundamentalism in<br />

the face <strong>of</strong> normative pluralism, it could be nothing else than the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> open social deliberation and dissent that defies<br />

foundation and closure to give politics a chance. 19 In the ‘community<br />

without community’ that Van der Walt and Botha have in mind, a<br />

society <strong>of</strong> diverse communities, cultures and conflicting normative<br />

values, without any justificatory or unifying common will, social<br />

deliberation and politics can be possible without anarchy. 20<br />

In the ‘community without community’, recognition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sacrificial nature <strong>of</strong> decision reveals the essence <strong>of</strong> law as its very<br />

failure to resolve social conflict with reference to a common will or<br />

purpose. In other words, politics is not to be found in a foundational,<br />

unifying common will that overcomes or mediates plurality; instead,<br />

politics is possible only in the presence <strong>of</strong> unmediated and unresolved<br />

diversity, plurality and dissent. Consequently, a purely dialogic or<br />

republican politics 21 cannot solve conflict or bring closure by<br />

18 J van der Walt & H Botha ‘Democracy and rights in South Africa: Beyond a<br />

constitutional culture <strong>of</strong> justification’ (2000) 7 Constellations 341-362 350. See H<br />

Botha ‘Democracy and rights: Constitutional interpretation in a postrealist world’<br />

(2000) 63 Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins Hollandse Reg 561-581 572-574 581;<br />

K van Marle ‘Lives <strong>of</strong> action, thinking and revolt — A feminist call for politics and<br />

becoming in post-apartheid South Africa’ (2004) 19 SA Public Law 605-628 621-<br />

624; F Michelman ‘Property as a constitutional right’ (1981) 38 Washington & Lee<br />

Law Review 1097-1114 1110: ‘it is the possibility <strong>of</strong> partial resolutions that allows<br />

us to experience the contradiction [between democracy and rights] as generative<br />

tension rather than as dead end.’<br />

19 Van der Walt & Botha (n 18 above) 350. See Van Marle (n 18 above) 621, citing B<br />

Honig (ed) Feminist interpretations <strong>of</strong> Hannah Arendt (1995) 135. See further W<br />

le Roux ‘Bridges, clearings and labyrinths: The architectural framing <strong>of</strong> postapartheid<br />

constitutionalism’ (2004) 19 SA Public Law 629-665.<br />

20<br />

n 18 above, 350-352.<br />

21 See le Roux (n 19 above) 646-660 on constitutionalism as a dialogic ‘clearing’.


82 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

mediating dissent or pluralism; 22 nor can politics be guaranteed by<br />

constitutionalism, rights or law. 23 Robert Cover pointed out that an<br />

important function <strong>of</strong> law is to ‘kill’ or suppress plurality, dissent and<br />

meaning; not to open it up. 24 However, to the extent that law is<br />

inevitable, law, rights and constitutionalism are justifiable in so far as<br />

it gives politics a chance. A major issue in this article is to ask whether<br />

the interpretive and adjudicative approach that the Constitutional<br />

Court has apparently elected to follow in deciding cases where the<br />

common law tradition and legislation have to be measured against<br />

constitutional directives is justifiable in the sense that it gives politics<br />

a chance, instead <strong>of</strong> just closing up gaps and entrenching certainty.<br />

2 Pluralism in post-apartheid constitutional<br />

theory<br />

Our Constitution does not sanction a state <strong>of</strong> normative anarchy which<br />

may arise where potentially conflicting principles are juxtaposed. 25<br />

South Africans in the post-1994 era understand the anxiety caused by<br />

abandoning normative fundamentalism. Having faced up to the<br />

wickedness <strong>of</strong> apartheid and the bankruptcy <strong>of</strong> its underlying values,<br />

the point <strong>of</strong> constitutional transformation was to replace the<br />

exclusivism <strong>of</strong> segregation with an inclusive democracy that<br />

recognises diverse communities, cultures and traditions as well as<br />

diverse social, cultural and religious values. The 1996 Constitution’s<br />

commitment to diversity is apparent from its emphasis on human<br />

dignity, equality, and freedom 26 and its recognition <strong>of</strong> the values <strong>of</strong><br />

different social, cultural and religious groups, 27 but recognition <strong>of</strong><br />

diversity as a positive value surpasses mere tolerance — social,<br />

cultural and religious pluralism (‘more-than-one’) creates and<br />

supports the very possibility <strong>of</strong> politics and democracy.<br />

22<br />

Van der Walt & Botha (n 18 above) 352 argue that judicial decisions do not solve<br />

the conflicts that arise from social complexity but suppress them at the cost <strong>of</strong><br />

one party for the sake <strong>of</strong> a social goal. R Cover ‘Violence and the word’ (1986) 95<br />

Yale Law Journal 1601-1629 1607: ‘the relationship between legal interpretation<br />

and the infliction <strong>of</strong> pain remains operative even in the most routine <strong>of</strong> legal<br />

acts’.<br />

23<br />

Van Marle (n 18 above) 625-628 warns against ‘constitutional optimism’ based on<br />

the pervasiveness <strong>of</strong> law, constitution and rights, referring to E Christodoulidis<br />

‘Constitutional irresolution: Law and the framing <strong>of</strong> civil society’ (2003) 9<br />

European Law Journal 401-432. Compare le Roux (n 19 above) 660-665.<br />

24 R Cover ‘The Supreme Court 1982 term. Foreword: Nomos and narrative’ (1983)<br />

97 Harvard Law Review 4-68 41-44.<br />

25<br />

Ngcobo J, Fuel Retailers Association <strong>of</strong> Southern Africa v Director-General:<br />

Environmental Management, Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture, Conservation and<br />

Environment, Mpumalanga Province, 2007 6 SA 4 (CC) par 93.<br />

26<br />

Compare s 1 <strong>of</strong> the 1996 Constitution.<br />

27 See ss 9(3) and 9(4), 15, 30, 31; compare ss 39(3), 211-212.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 83<br />

Since 1994 the courts had many opportunities to confirm the<br />

Constitution’s commitment to accommodation <strong>of</strong> diversity and<br />

pluralism. 28 Such an opportunity again arose in 2007 in Pillay, 29 the<br />

first equality case to be considered by the Constitutional Court in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Equality and Prevention <strong>of</strong> Unfair<br />

Discrimination Act 4 <strong>of</strong> 2000 (PEPUDA). 30 The Court reiterated the<br />

confirmation, in the Act, <strong>of</strong> ‘the Constitution’s commitment to affirm<br />

diversity’ 31 and decided that reasonable accommodation in matters<br />

<strong>of</strong> religion means that<br />

sometimes the community, whether it is the State, an employer or a<br />

school, must take positive measures and possibly incur additional<br />

hardship or expense in order to allow all people to participate and enjoy<br />

all their rights equally. It ensures that we do not relegate people to the<br />

margins <strong>of</strong> society because they do not or cannot conform to certain<br />

social norms. 32<br />

Accordingly, a school disciplinary code that inflexibly denied an<br />

exemption from normal dress code for pupils who wish to wear a nose<br />

stud as part <strong>of</strong> their religious or cultural practice discriminated<br />

against them unfairly, in conflict with the Act.<br />

Pillay demonstrates that conflict about normative pluralism in the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> diversity requires more opportunities for politics and<br />

difference, not greater consensus. There is no reason why we should<br />

agree about the wearing <strong>of</strong> nose studs, headscarves, yarmulkes or<br />

dreadlocks or why one view about any <strong>of</strong> these cultural and religious<br />

symbols should be enforced on everybody, but open deliberation and<br />

dissent about the underlying social customs and values and about<br />

tolerance is good for the democratic order. However, difference is<br />

not tolerated when it contradicts central values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution or<br />

undermines democracy 33 — normative anarchy is not permitted. What<br />

prevents pluralism from sliding into anarchy in the context <strong>of</strong> diversity<br />

28 Mostly relating to race, gender, religion and sexual orientation: Amod v<br />

Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund 1999 4 1319 (SCA) (Islamic marriage); S<br />

v Lawrence; S v Negal; S v Solberg 1997 4 SA 1176 (CC) (Christian public holidays);<br />

National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister <strong>of</strong> Justice 1999 1 SA 6<br />

(CC) (sexual orientation); Du Toit v Minister for Welfare and Population<br />

Development 2003 2 SA 198 (CC) (married status); Satchwell v President <strong>of</strong><br />

Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa 2002 6 SA 1 (CC) (sexual orientation); J v Director-<br />

General, Department <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs 2003 5 SA 621 (CC) (sexual orientation);<br />

Gory v Kolver NO 2007 4 SA 97 (CC) (sexual orientation).<br />

29 MEC for Education: KwaZulu-Natal v Pillay 2008 1 SA 474 (CC).<br />

30 n 29 above, par 39. See I Currie & J de Waal The bill <strong>of</strong> rights handbook 5 ed<br />

(2005) 267.<br />

31 Pillay (n 29 above) par 65.<br />

32 Pillay (n 29 above) par 73.<br />

33<br />

Courts refused to enforce diversity in Bhe v Magistrate, Khayelitsha 2005 1 SA 580<br />

(CC) (customary law rules <strong>of</strong> succession); Prince v President, Cape Law Society &<br />

others 2001 2 SA 388 (CC) (smoking <strong>of</strong> cannabis as part <strong>of</strong> religious observance);<br />

Christian Education in South Africa v Minister <strong>of</strong> Education 1999 2 SA 83 (CC)<br />

(corporal punishment as part <strong>of</strong> Christian education).


84 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

as a positive value is exactly what gave Amis and formalist opponents<br />

<strong>of</strong> critical legal theory headaches, namely recognising that values are<br />

contingent and that everything is open for dissent and discussion,<br />

without implying that everything goes.<br />

The new constitutional order brought about a second kind <strong>of</strong><br />

normative pluralism, where contradiction results not from different<br />

values but from the project <strong>of</strong> constitutional transformation itself. In<br />

this arena, the issue for debate is the direction, scope and pace <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional reform and, particularly, the effect <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

on existing law. The effect <strong>of</strong> the Constitution on existing law is a<br />

logical locus for deliberation (politics) about social and legal reform,<br />

but the notion that a significant part <strong>of</strong> existing law — the common<br />

law — can survive or must be insulated against some or all direct or<br />

indirect constitutional influence contradicts constitutional values and<br />

threatens constitutional politics. In a word, the preservative impulse<br />

in the application debate misrepresents the democratic principle that<br />

everything is open for debate and threatens to push the normative<br />

pluralism <strong>of</strong> transformative politics into the anarchy <strong>of</strong> fractional<br />

conflict.<br />

An important premise <strong>of</strong> my argument is that the Constitution’s<br />

commitment to diversity as a positive value is premised upon the<br />

reduced authority <strong>of</strong> the common law. 34 The Constitution is founded<br />

on a set <strong>of</strong> values and normative commitments related to democracy,<br />

human dignity, equality and freedom and on the replacement <strong>of</strong> an<br />

immoral and discredited social and political system by a new,<br />

constitutional and democratic system. The shift from exclusivity to<br />

inclusivity that it presupposes is possible only if the existing legal<br />

order can be both purified <strong>of</strong> its exclusivist and authoritarian legacy<br />

and adapted to accommodate the normative diversity <strong>of</strong> its reformist<br />

purposes. In a largely uncodified legal system that relies on judicial<br />

finding, interpretation and application <strong>of</strong> old authorities and case<br />

law, remnants <strong>of</strong> the old legal system (characterised by exclusivity<br />

and authoritarianism) will survive political change and the<br />

establishment <strong>of</strong> the new constitutional order, for the time being,<br />

34<br />

See s 39(3), read with ss 8(3), 39(3) and 173 <strong>of</strong> the 1996 Constitution, recognising<br />

the continued existence <strong>of</strong> the common law, to the extent that it is consistent<br />

with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and subject to the power <strong>of</strong> the higher courts to develop it<br />

to promote the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. Johan van der<br />

Walt has argued that (direct or indirect) horizontal application <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

would promote plurality: JWG van der Walt ‘Perspectives on horizontal<br />

application: Du Plessis v De Klerk revisited’ (1997) 12 SA Public Law 1-31;<br />

‘Progressive indirect horizontal application <strong>of</strong> the bill <strong>of</strong> rights: Towards a cooperative<br />

relation between common-law and constitutional jurisprudence’ (2001)<br />

17 South African Journal on Human Rights 341-363; Van der Walt & Botha (n 18<br />

above) 350-352.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 85<br />

dragging unwanted survivals from the past behind us. 35 Every<br />

legislative, executive and judicial decision embodies a choice<br />

between upholding remnants <strong>of</strong> the old order and enforcing change<br />

brought about by the new; every decision to uphold the existing law<br />

implies a sacrifice <strong>of</strong> constitutional reform, even when it is<br />

indubitably correct or unavoidable. Even more importantly, every<br />

decision in favour <strong>of</strong> stability and certainty or vested and acquired<br />

rights inevitably comes at the price <strong>of</strong> suppressing plurality, dissent<br />

and change.<br />

To complicate matters the role <strong>of</strong> the Constitution is ambiguous.<br />

On the one hand, any Constitution (with a Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights) is part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legal machinery that ensures stability and the protection <strong>of</strong> rights,<br />

particularly against state interference. In this perspective the<br />

Constitution is an agent for the protection <strong>of</strong> established privilege and<br />

power. On the other hand, though, the South African Constitution is<br />

clearly also an agent for change, including large-scale social,<br />

economic and political change that can affect established privilege<br />

and power negatively. It could be said that the danger <strong>of</strong> anarchy is<br />

reduced because the Constitution embodies a direction-giving<br />

purpose: different value systems are recognised, but we are all<br />

working towards an open society built on democracy, social justice<br />

and fundamental rights to human dignity, equality and freedom. Even<br />

in the face <strong>of</strong> diversity and pluralism, the Constitution directs us<br />

towards certain choices and away from others. Frank Michelman 36<br />

argues that the constitutional supremacy principle in s 1 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution, as interpreted in Pharmaceutical Manufacturers, 37<br />

establishes<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> legal-systemic harmony in the service <strong>of</strong> the vision <strong>of</strong> the<br />

good society staked out by the entire list <strong>of</strong> founding values set forth in<br />

FC s 1 and instinct in the rest <strong>of</strong> the Final Constitution. We deal here<br />

with the value <strong>of</strong> the unity <strong>of</strong> the legal system — meaning the system’s<br />

35 In the lyrics <strong>of</strong> Roger Waters: ‘they flutter behind you, your possible pasts / some<br />

bright eyed and crazy, some frightened and lost / a warning for anyone still in<br />

command / <strong>of</strong> their possible future to take care’: Pink Floyd ‘Your possible pasts’,<br />

from The final cut, subtitled A requiem for the post war dream (1983 © Pink<br />

36<br />

37<br />

Floyd Music Publishers Ltd).<br />

FI Michelman ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law, legality and the supremacy <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’ in<br />

S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005)<br />

34-44.<br />

Ex Parte President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa: In re Pharmaceutical<br />

Manufacturers Association <strong>of</strong> South Africa 2000 2 SA 674 (CC) par 44.


86 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

normative unity or, as one might say more poetically, its visionary<br />

unity. 38<br />

The notion <strong>of</strong> such a normative unity in the goal <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

transformation is certainly attractive. For administrative justice,<br />

Michelman’s analysis <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law, legality and constitutional<br />

supremacy provisions provides a starting point based on the normative<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. Similar arguments can be developed for<br />

equality and non-discrimination, where transformation also amounts<br />

to wholesale replacing <strong>of</strong> apartheid law with a fundamentally new set<br />

<strong>of</strong> rules, indicating normative unity in reform. However, some<br />

constitutional provisions look less like wholesale, unidirectional<br />

transformations and more like contradictory products <strong>of</strong> difficult and<br />

inchoate compromises. In the compromise provisions, Michelman’s<br />

‘visionary unity’ <strong>of</strong> the Constitution is less obvious or more contested<br />

than in abolition and replacement provisions like s 9.<br />

A striking example is the sections relating to the national flag and<br />

the national anthem. The national flag described in s 5 (and Schedule<br />

1) is neither based on the apartheid flag, itself the patchwork product<br />

<strong>of</strong> South Africa’s colonial and postcolonial past, nor on the ANC flag,<br />

nor is it a patchwork amalgam <strong>of</strong> the two. The Constitution simply<br />

replaced the apartheid flag with a new flag, signalling the clean break<br />

style <strong>of</strong> transformation that illustrates Michelman’s direction-giving<br />

‘visionary unity’ <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. However, the national anthem<br />

illustrates a different approach: under apartheid, Die Stem van Suid-<br />

Afrika (The Call <strong>of</strong> South Africa) was the <strong>of</strong>ficial national anthem,<br />

although Nkosi Sikelel' iAfrika was favoured by political activists and<br />

refugees. Under the 1993 Constitution the Republic had two national<br />

anthems: Nkosi Sikelel' iAfrika and Die Stem van Suid-Afrika / The<br />

Call <strong>of</strong> South Africa; 39 under the 1996 Constitution the single national<br />

anthem consists <strong>of</strong> one verse each from Nkosi Sikelel' iAfrika, Die<br />

38 Michelman (n 36 above) 37, referring to Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various<br />

Occupiers 2005 1 SA 217 (CC) par 35 (emphasis added). Michelman (n 36 above)<br />

38, meets the objection that the promise <strong>of</strong> a shared transformative purpose is<br />

another kind <strong>of</strong> fundamentalism (see nn 18-20 above and accompanying text) by<br />

describing legal-systemic unity as a contingent, relative value, arguing that<br />

contingency is brought about by the linkage <strong>of</strong> constitutional supremacy in s 1<br />

with rule <strong>of</strong> law: the value is contingent on ‘the direction <strong>of</strong> the pull’. When the<br />

direction <strong>of</strong> the pull is towards rule <strong>of</strong> justice rather than rule <strong>of</strong> law, the two<br />

values signify the unity <strong>of</strong> the legal system in the service <strong>of</strong> transformation by,<br />

under, and according to law’. This concern with the ‘pull towards the rule <strong>of</strong><br />

justice’ points in the same direction as the ‘giving politics a chance’ argument <strong>of</strong><br />

Van der Walt & Botha (n 18 above and accompanying text).<br />

39 Die Stem van Suid-Afrika (translated as The Call <strong>of</strong> South Africa) was written by<br />

Afrikaans author CJ Langenhoven in 1918; the music was composed by the<br />

Reverend ML de Villiers in 1921. The first stanza <strong>of</strong> Nkosi Sikelel' iAfrika was<br />

written in Xhosa and the music composed by Enoch Sontonga in 1897; seven<br />

stanzas in Xhoza were added by the poet Samuel Mqhayi. A Sesotho version by<br />

Moses Mphahlele was published in 1942. Information: http://www.info.gov.za/<br />

aboutgovt/symbols/anthem.htm (accessed 8 May 2008).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 87<br />

Stem van Suid-Afrika and The Call <strong>of</strong> South Africa. 40 Nothing<br />

illustrates the accommodation <strong>of</strong> post-apartheid pluralism by way <strong>of</strong><br />

a makeshift, patchwork compromise between opposing value systems<br />

better.<br />

However, patchwork compromises are not fatal. Like the national<br />

anthem, s 25 embodies a patchwork compromise between constitutional<br />

protection <strong>of</strong> existing property interests (s 25(1)-(3)) and<br />

constitutionally sanctioned land reform (s 25(4)-(9)). 41 Although it is<br />

difficult to imagine how the land-reform goals in s 25(5)-(9) could be<br />

promoted without infringing upon existing property interests in<br />

conflict with s 25(1)-(3), Michelman’s argument suggests a solution:<br />

the ‘legal-systemic unity’ <strong>of</strong> ‘every site <strong>of</strong> law’ (including both parts<br />

<strong>of</strong> s 25) is to be found in the constitutional purpose <strong>of</strong> ‘pulling in the<br />

justice direction’, ‘in the service <strong>of</strong> transformation by, under, and<br />

according to law.’ 42 Reading s 25 in this way suggests that protection<br />

<strong>of</strong> existing property interests and promotion <strong>of</strong> equitable access to<br />

property are guaranteed in so far as those purposes conform to the<br />

constitutional purpose <strong>of</strong> transformation by, under, and according to<br />

law (including legislation, common law and customary law). What<br />

renders Michelman’s reading compelling is not that it makes the<br />

conflict between two seemingly contradictory provisions or normative<br />

purposes disappear, nor that it identifies an overarching purpose in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> which they can be reconciled or balanced, but that it shows<br />

that what appears like a contradiction is in fact a tension, 43 a locus <strong>of</strong><br />

significant dissent, that makes social deliberation both inevitable and<br />

possible and that therefore ‘gives politics a chance’. The very<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> politics is founded on the significant dissent embodied in<br />

the tension between the two parts <strong>of</strong> s 25. Constitutional application<br />

gives politics a chance in so far as it views this tension as part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

contingent ‘legal-systemic unity’ <strong>of</strong> ‘pulling in the justice direction <strong>of</strong><br />

transformation by, under, and according to law’; not in order to deny<br />

or resolve the tension, but to explore it in the context <strong>of</strong> the equally<br />

contingent and contradictory justice goals <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

transformation itself. The constitutional purpose <strong>of</strong> transformation<br />

by, under and in accordance with law is not uncontested; it is a site<br />

for dissent and social deliberation; for politics. Again, in as far as law<br />

is inevitable in the process <strong>of</strong> social and political transformation, its<br />

40 Ss 2, 248(1) <strong>of</strong> the 1993 Constitution; s 4, Schedule 1 <strong>of</strong> the 1996 Constitution.<br />

The 1997 proclamation was published in Government Gazette 18341.<br />

41<br />

AJ van der Walt Constitutional property law (2005) 12-18.<br />

42 Michelman’s reading finds support in Port Elizabeth Municipality (n 38 above),<br />

specifically regarding s 25.<br />

43<br />

Van der Walt & Botha call this an aporia (n 18 above and accompanying text).<br />

Michelman explored something like the ‘legal-systemic unity’ (n 36 above) earlier<br />

(see n 18 above, 1112): ‘My suggestion is to seek a rapprochement <strong>of</strong> property<br />

and popular sovereignty in the idea that rights under a political constitution,<br />

including property rights, are first <strong>of</strong> all to be regarded as political rights.’


88 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

legitimacy must depend on the extent to which it ‘gives politics a<br />

chance’ by acknowledging the sacrifice and upholding the dissent<br />

inherent in this tension.<br />

My goal here is to consider the Constitutional Court’s response,<br />

during the 2007 term, to the compromise-based, patchwork<br />

relationship between existing law (particularly the common law) and<br />

the Constitution. In earlier constitutional discourse this has mostly<br />

been debated on the basis <strong>of</strong> the so-called application issue, referring<br />

to the question how the Constitution should find application in<br />

existing law. On the one hand, based on the constitutional aspiration<br />

to rectify the injustices and heal the divisions <strong>of</strong> the past and<br />

establish a society based on democratic values, social justice and<br />

fundamental human rights, the intention is clearly that the<br />

Constitution is the supreme law and that all law should be subject to<br />

it 44 — in this respect, the Constitution embodies a strong imperative<br />

for change in the general direction indicated by the transformation<br />

goals set out in the Constitution, as explained by Michelman. On the<br />

other hand, the desire for stability and certainty inherent in the rule<br />

<strong>of</strong> law principle implies a constitutional obligation not to disturb<br />

settled bodies <strong>of</strong> existing law 45 — and the vested rights protected by<br />

them — unnecessarily. 46 As I have argued above, this desire for<br />

stability and certainty will have a stronger effect in areas where the<br />

relevant constitutional provisions do not reveal the ‘visionary unity’<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitution — in the compromise cases, we can expect that<br />

tradition and stability will <strong>of</strong>fer stronger resistance against change.<br />

What Karl Klare described as ‘pr<strong>of</strong>essional legal sensibilities’ will also<br />

tend to favour the stability <strong>of</strong> tradition and settled law, preferring to<br />

restrict change and uncertainty to instances where it is clearly<br />

required or mandated by unambiguous constitutional or statutory<br />

prescriptions. 47<br />

That brings me to my central premise: tension between the push<br />

for constitutional reform and the pull <strong>of</strong> traditional stability<br />

constitutes more than just a minor difference about the pace or the<br />

direction <strong>of</strong> change. Underlying this tension is a larger conflict<br />

44 Ss 1, 2, 7, 8(1) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution; with regard to ss 1, 2 compare Michelman (n<br />

36 above) 34-44.<br />

45<br />

The phraseology is from S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al (eds)<br />

Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) 10.<br />

46 S 1 (rule <strong>of</strong> law); s 39(3): the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights does not deny the existence <strong>of</strong> other<br />

rights or freedoms recognised or conferred by common law, customary law or<br />

legislation, to the extent that they are consistent with the Bill. Compare ss 173,<br />

8(3), 39(2) on the higher courts’ power to develop the common law to promote<br />

the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill. Compare T Roux ‘Continuity and change<br />

in a transforming legal order: The impact <strong>of</strong> section 26(3) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution on<br />

South African law’ (2004) 121 South African Law Journal 466-492 466 467.<br />

47<br />

K Klare ‘Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 146-188 166-167.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 89<br />

between two opposing normative values or ideologies, one favouring<br />

the stability <strong>of</strong> existing law, based on the presence and the presumed<br />

political neutrality <strong>of</strong> the status quo; the other relying on the political<br />

justifiability <strong>of</strong> fundamental change indicated by the presumed social<br />

construction and injustice <strong>of</strong> the status quo. Those who think that the<br />

existing distribution <strong>of</strong> wealth, privilege and power and the law that<br />

helped create and uphold it are politically neutral and therefore not<br />

in need <strong>of</strong> political reconsideration favour a regime <strong>of</strong> rights in which<br />

the direct effect <strong>of</strong> the Constitution is preservation <strong>of</strong> the status quo;<br />

those who think that the existing regime and its laws are inherently<br />

politically constructed and hence in need <strong>of</strong> political reconsideration<br />

favour the view that neither law nor rights are immune from<br />

constitutional effect or democratic redefinition. In this perspective,<br />

the relationship between existing law and Constitution is an instance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the tension between two conflicting sets <strong>of</strong> normative values,<br />

respectively favouring stability and change, certainty and justice,<br />

rights and democracy, tradition and constitution. In the absence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

‘visionary unity’ <strong>of</strong> purpose, conflict between them could precipitate<br />

a slide into normative anarchy. Simply ignoring or subjugating one in<br />

favour <strong>of</strong> the other could, however, undermine the diversity and<br />

pluralism that is a prerequisite for significant social dissent, politics<br />

and democracy. In the terminology <strong>of</strong> Van der Walt and Botha, the<br />

legitimacy <strong>of</strong> constitutional review depends upon the extent to which<br />

constitutional law can ‘give politics a chance’ by acknowledging the<br />

aporia inherent in the tension between stability and change, and by<br />

recognising the sacrificial inevitability <strong>of</strong> upholding, in a concrete<br />

case, the one at the cost <strong>of</strong> the other, without the comfort or the<br />

certainty <strong>of</strong> an appeal to foundation.<br />

Michelman recognises the contingency <strong>of</strong> accepting diversity, but<br />

insists that constitutional transformation is possible to the extent that<br />

the direction <strong>of</strong> the pull between conflicting values favours justice<br />

rather than law. The constitutional tension between legality, rule <strong>of</strong><br />

law and constitutional supremacy involves an aporia; so does the<br />

tension between stabilising the old and promoting the new, in the<br />

sense that rule <strong>of</strong> law safeguards stability via the back door <strong>of</strong> legal<br />

certainty while constitutional supremacy demands transformation.<br />

Consequently, Michelman’s notion <strong>of</strong> visionary unity under the<br />

Constitution applies very usefully to the problem <strong>of</strong> existing law vs<br />

reform, but we should be careful not to read his analysis as superficial<br />

pragmatism. The unifying vision he identifies does not indicate an<br />

inflexible preference for change and against stability: the visionary<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> the Constitution identifies justice as a normative guideline for<br />

making hard decisions in concrete cases, but it does not pre-empt<br />

decisions in favour <strong>of</strong> change and against stability. In the language <strong>of</strong><br />

Van der Walt and Botha, Michelman’s argument recognises that every<br />

choice for or against stability or reform is a sacrificial one: the choice<br />

cannot be justified, but making an unavoidable decision is justified in


90 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

so far as it accommodates social dissent and open democratic<br />

deliberation. In every case, the question is whether the direction <strong>of</strong><br />

the pull favours justice.<br />

Relying on the theoretical groundwork <strong>of</strong> Van der Walt and Botha<br />

and Michelman, my hypothesis is that normative pluralism in the<br />

contradictions between constitutional reform and stability could<br />

easily result in either normative anarchy or reactionary formalism,<br />

unless the normative unity, the general direction <strong>of</strong> the pull, between<br />

these opposing forces favours transformative justice, by which I mean<br />

the justice that is implied by renunciation <strong>of</strong> everything the apartheid<br />

legal order represented and espousal <strong>of</strong> the central transformative<br />

values <strong>of</strong> human dignity, equality and freedom in an open and<br />

democratic society. This normative unity does not imply an inflexible<br />

preference for change and against stability, but it indicates the<br />

direction <strong>of</strong> the normative pull against which a decision for either<br />

change or stability must be justified. The questions that I will pose are<br />

whether the Constitutional Court is in the process <strong>of</strong> developing a<br />

direction-giving approach in deciding cases involving the contradiction<br />

between constitutional reform and stability and, if it is;<br />

whether this approach is justifiable in that it does not simply entrench<br />

a new formalism but, instead, opens up space for politics.<br />

3 One legal system<br />

There is only one system <strong>of</strong> law. It is shaped by the Constitution which is<br />

the supreme law, and all law, including the common law, derives its<br />

force from the Constitution and is subject to constitutional control. 48<br />

The tension between preservation <strong>of</strong> the common law tradition and<br />

constitutional transformation initially emerged in debates about the<br />

direct or indirect horizontal application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.<br />

Commentators and policy makers concerned that private-law<br />

enclaves should not be allowed to escape the reach <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

reform or to continue ‘privatised’ injustice proposed that constitutional<br />

rights should apply directly; others queried the wisdom and<br />

the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> ‘importing’ constitutional values into private law.<br />

Clothed as concern about the unnecessary abolition <strong>of</strong> a welldeveloped<br />

and supposedly politically neutral legal tradition, the<br />

latter <strong>of</strong>ten concealed anxiety about the continued existence <strong>of</strong><br />

established privilege and wealth. Conflicting decisions in which the<br />

new constitutional order was sometimes welcomed, sometimes<br />

accepted with a measure <strong>of</strong> suspicion, sometimes rejected outright,<br />

demonstrated uncertainty about the normative scheme that informs<br />

post-1994 legal reasoning.<br />

48 Chaskalson P, Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 37 above) par 44.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 91<br />

The constitutional text makes it clear that the Constitution is the<br />

supreme law <strong>of</strong> the land; 49 that the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights is the cornerstone <strong>of</strong><br />

democracy and that it enshrines the values <strong>of</strong> human dignity, equality<br />

and freedom; 50 that it applies to all law and that it binds all three<br />

arms <strong>of</strong> government and all organs <strong>of</strong> state; 51 that the state must<br />

respect, protect, promote, and fulfil the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights; 52<br />

that the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights binds natural and juristic persons if and to the<br />

extent that it is applicable, taking into account the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

right; 53 that the courts, in order to give effect to a right in the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights, must apply or, where necessary, develop the common law to<br />

the extent that legislation does not give effect to that right and may<br />

develop rules <strong>of</strong> the common law to limit the right, 54 and that courts,<br />

tribunals and other forums must, when interpreting legislation and<br />

when developing the common law and customary law, promote the<br />

spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 55 However, it was not<br />

clear how this should work out in practice — when should the<br />

Constitution or new legislation trump the common law; when should<br />

the common law be developed to promote the spirit, purport and<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Constitution; how much should be changed in the<br />

process? Even more importantly, what should the effect <strong>of</strong> established<br />

common law norms and values be when it is unclear whether the<br />

Constitution or new legislation trumps the common law?<br />

Some authors and judges share Michelman’s view that<br />

transformation and stability can exist together and that an<br />

application theory and practice that uphold the tension is obligatory<br />

— the very idea <strong>of</strong> transformative constitutionalism 56 is founded upon<br />

the notion <strong>of</strong> a constitutional order that guarantees stability while<br />

49 S 2.<br />

50<br />

S 7(1).<br />

51 S 8(1).<br />

52 S 7(2).<br />

53<br />

S 8(2).<br />

54 S 8(3).<br />

55 S 39(2).<br />

56<br />

The concept, coined by Klare (n 47 above) 146-188, inspired a cottage industry in<br />

constitutional theory; see H Botha ‘Metaphoric reasoning and transformative<br />

constitutionalism’ 2002 Tydskrif vir Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 612-627; 2003 Tydskrif<br />

vir Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 20-36; D Moseneke ‘The fourth Bram Fischer memorial<br />

lecture: Transformative adjudication’ (2002) 18 South African Journal on Human<br />

Rights 309-319; H Botha ‘Freedom and constraint in constitutional adjudication’<br />

(2004) 20 South African Journal on Human Rights 249-283; le Roux (n 19 above)<br />

629-675; Roux (n 46 above); AJ van der Walt ‘Transformative constitutionalism<br />

and the development <strong>of</strong> South African property law’ 2005 Tydskrif vir Suid-<br />

Afrikaanse Reg 655-689; 2006 Tydskrif vir Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 1-31; M Pieterse<br />

‘What do we mean when we talk about transformative constitutionalism?’ (2005)<br />

20 SA Public Law 155-166; S Liebenberg ‘Needs, rights and transformation:<br />

Adjudicating social rights’ (2006) 1 Stellenbosch Law Review 5-36; P Langa<br />

‘Transformative constitutionalism’ (2006) 17 Stellenbosch Law Review 351-360.<br />

See further the contributions <strong>of</strong> H Botha, D Davis, J Froneman, J van der Walt and<br />

K van Marle in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & JWG van der Walt (eds) Rights and<br />

democracy in a transformative constitution (2003).


92 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

simultaneously requiring (and authorising or even driving) social,<br />

economic or political transformation. 57<br />

The problem is that the debate about the place and role <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law in the new dispensation 58 has been dominated by the<br />

largely undeclared assumption that the common law should be<br />

insulated, in some measure, against constitutional amendment,<br />

presupposing that a substantial part <strong>of</strong> the common law might remain<br />

unaffected by the Constitution and that development <strong>of</strong> the rest can<br />

take place on its own terms, without raising constitutional issues. The<br />

jurisdictional format that this turf war adopted under the 1993<br />

Constitution 59 ended in Pharmaceutical Manufacturers when the<br />

Constitutional Court rejected the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal’s view<br />

that the common law grounds for review continued to exist as a body<br />

<strong>of</strong> norms ‘separate and distinct from the Constitution’: 60<br />

There are not two systems <strong>of</strong> law, ... each operating in its own field with<br />

its own highest court. There is only one system <strong>of</strong> law. It is shaped by the<br />

Constitution which is the supreme law, and all law, including the<br />

common law, derives its force from the Constitution and is subject to<br />

constitutional control. 61<br />

57 Michelman and Van der Walt & Botha argue that the tension in the Constitution is<br />

central to the possibility <strong>of</strong> politics; see nn 18-20, 36-38 above. See further Roux<br />

(n 46 above) 487.<br />

58 The problem <strong>of</strong> balancing constitutional supremacy and common law is not unique<br />

to South African law. A similar problem exists in German constitutional law and<br />

early commentaries on the South African Constitution found inspiration in German<br />

theory: D Davis, M Chaskalson & J de Waal ‘Democracy and constitutionalism: The<br />

role <strong>of</strong> constitutional interpretation’ in D van Wyk, J Dugard, B de Villiers & D<br />

Davis (eds) Rights and constitutionalism: The new South African legal order<br />

(1994) 1-130 89-97. In Carmichele v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security (Centre for<br />

Applied Legal Studies Intervening) 2001 4 SA 938 (CC) par 54 Ackermann &<br />

Goldstone JJ referred to German constitutional law. Michelman (n 36) 40 relies on<br />

this passage in Carmichele to show the Constitutional Court’s support for the view<br />

that a ‘comprehensive (if doubtless somewhat inchoate) vision <strong>of</strong> the good<br />

society’ is inherent in the Constitution. Since the European Convention was<br />

incorporated into English law by the Human Rights Act 1998, English courts have<br />

struggled to reconcile common law with human rights standards, eg eviction vs<br />

home interest in art 8 European Convention <strong>of</strong> Human Rights: Harrow London<br />

Borough Council v Qazi [2004] 1 AC 983; Kay v London Borough <strong>of</strong> Lambeth; Leeds<br />

City Council v Price [2006] UKHL 10 (HL); Connors v United Kingdom [2004] ECHR<br />

223.<br />

59 Michelman (n 36 above) 22.<br />

60<br />

The SCA decision was Commissioner for Customs and Excise v Container Logistics<br />

(Pty) Ltd; Commissioner for Customs and Excise v Rennies Group Ltd t/a<br />

Renfreight 1999 3 SA 771 (SCA); the CC decision was Pharmaceutical<br />

Manufacturers (n 37 above). Michelman (n 36 above) 15-33 explains Amod v<br />

Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund 1999 4 1319 (SCA) as a model for<br />

judges who want to keep a judgment out <strong>of</strong> the constitutional arena to reserve<br />

for the SCA final control over a category <strong>of</strong> future cases (18), although Amod<br />

might simply have avoided ‘thorny issues’; its cause <strong>of</strong> action preceded<br />

61<br />

commencement <strong>of</strong> the 1993 Constitution.<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 37 above) par 44. See Michelman (n 36 above)<br />

21-22.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 93<br />

In Pharmaceutical Manufacturers the Constitutional Court<br />

‘established, once and for all, that the SCA cannot insulate a decision<br />

on legality from CC review by dressing it as a merely common law (and<br />

hence not a constitutional) decision.’ 62 As far as review <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative action is concerned, this decision established a unitary<br />

vision <strong>of</strong> the relationship between common law and Constitution: the<br />

common law continues to exist in as far as it does not directly conflict<br />

with the Constitution. However, it does not exist as an independent<br />

body <strong>of</strong> law — there is just one system <strong>of</strong> law, shaped by the<br />

Constitution as the supreme law. The common law derives its force<br />

from the Constitution and it is subject to constitutional control and<br />

the tension between the Constitution and the common law is to be<br />

understood in terms <strong>of</strong> the transformative goal, the unitary normative<br />

vision, <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. The application, interpretation and<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law must take place in line with this<br />

vision. The essence, in the words <strong>of</strong> Michelman, is that application <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitution should promote the shared vision <strong>of</strong> an open society<br />

built on democracy, social justice and fundamental human rights and<br />

on human dignity, equality and freedom.<br />

Unfortunately, Pharmaceutical Manufacturers did not bring<br />

clarity about the effect <strong>of</strong> the Constitution on existing law (including<br />

the common law) as a whole; 63 outside <strong>of</strong> administrative law, the idea<br />

that the common law might escape constitutional influence and that<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law can develop on its own terms,<br />

without raising constitutional issues, retains some traction. Private<br />

law specialists tended simply to establish absence <strong>of</strong> direct conflict<br />

between common law principles and constitutional rights, instead <strong>of</strong><br />

seeking for normative or visionary unity. This approach presupposes<br />

that the common law could coexist alongside the Constitution, more<br />

or less unchanged, as long as it is free from the pernicious influence<br />

<strong>of</strong> apartheid. The strong version <strong>of</strong> this argument, that the law in<br />

general is politically neutral and that the abolition <strong>of</strong> apartheid laws<br />

62 Michelman (n 36 above) 18. This is what L du Plessis ‘“Subsidiarity”: What’s in the<br />

name for constitutional interpretation and adjudication?’ (2006) 17 Stellenbosch<br />

Law Review 207-231 211 refers to as jurisdictional subsidiarity.<br />

63 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 37 above) was decided prior to commencement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Administrative Justice Act 3 <strong>of</strong> 2000 (PAJA). Like Fedsure Life<br />

Assurance Ltd v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan Council 1999 1<br />

SA 374 (CC), Pharmaceutical Manufacturers dealt with the broader notion <strong>of</strong><br />

legality, which includes executive and legislative action outside <strong>of</strong> the range <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative action regulated by PAJA. With regard to the relationship between<br />

the common law, PAJA and the Constitution see Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Environmental Affairs 2004 4 SA 490 (CC) par 25: the provisions <strong>of</strong> s 6<br />

PAJA ‘divulge a clear purpose to codify the grounds <strong>of</strong> judicial review <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative action as defined in PAJA. The cause <strong>of</strong> action for the judicial<br />

review <strong>of</strong> administrative action now ordinarily arises from PAJA, not from the<br />

common law as in the past. And the authority <strong>of</strong> PAJA to ground such causes <strong>of</strong><br />

action rests squarely on the Constitution ... As PAJA gives effect to s 33 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution, matters relating to the interpretation and application <strong>of</strong> PAJA will<br />

<strong>of</strong> course be constitutional matters.’


94 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

properly eradicated politics from law, thereby restoring the common<br />

law to its former glory, no longer enjoys theoretical credibility 64<br />

outside <strong>of</strong> doctrinally conservative circles. 65 The weak version, that<br />

the common law is flexible and capable <strong>of</strong> adaptation that would<br />

bring it into line with new demands and requirements in the new<br />

constitutional democracy, is shared by many lawyers, including highranking<br />

judges in the new legal order. 66<br />

In the application debate, this argument supported the view that<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law, although referred to in the<br />

Constitution, 67 is something the civil courts are familiar with and that<br />

they should be left to do the work as they have always done it. 68 This<br />

view enjoyed wide support and strengthened the division <strong>of</strong> work<br />

between the Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal<br />

under the 1993 Constitution. 69 The High Courts, the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong><br />

Appeal and the Constitutional Court now have concurrent jurisdiction<br />

to decide on the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> legislation, but the notion<br />

persists that the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal is the specialist court on<br />

64 Botha (n 18 above) 561-581.<br />

65<br />

See J Potgieter ‘The role <strong>of</strong> the law in a period <strong>of</strong> political transition: The need<br />

for objectivity’ (1991) 54 Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 800-<br />

807 802: ‘It must be stressed that the basic assumption that the South African<br />

legal system as a whole has become illegitimate, is unfounded. The crisis in South<br />

Africa lies primarily in the socio-political rather than the legal sphere’; J<br />

Neethling ‘’n Toekomsblik op die Suid-Afrikaanse privaatreg — volwaardige<br />

naasbestaan <strong>of</strong> versoenende sintese?’ (‘A future perspective on South African<br />

private law — full coexistence or reconciliatory synthesis?) in A van Aswegen (ed)<br />

The future <strong>of</strong> South African private law (1994) 1-9 at 3: ‘In the first instance, the<br />

apartheid era cannot be attributed to Roman-Dutch law — the blame must be<br />

placed squarely on the shoulders <strong>of</strong> the ruling minority who introduced the<br />

system <strong>of</strong> apartheid by way <strong>of</strong> legislation, and they were primarily enabled to this<br />

end by the doctrine <strong>of</strong> parliamentary sovereignty which derives from English<br />

constitutional law.’ See further TJ Scott ‘The future <strong>of</strong> our Roman-Dutch law:<br />

Reflections and a suggestion’ (1993) 26 De Jure 394-400 399.<br />

66 MM Corbett ‘Trust law in the 90s: Challenges and change’ (1993) 56 Tydskrif vir<br />

Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 262-270 264. See also I Mahomed ‘The<br />

future <strong>of</strong> Roman-Dutch law in Southern Africa, particularly in Lesotho’ 1985<br />

Lesotho Law Journal 357-365 360; A Sachs ‘The future <strong>of</strong> Roman-Dutch law’ (chap<br />

8) in A Sachs Protecting human rights in a new South Africa (1990) 90-103 (‘we<br />

know it more or less, we have the books and the rules and the procedures<br />

available, we might as well use it’). See AJ van der Walt ‘Tradition on trial: A<br />

critical analysis <strong>of</strong> the civil-law tradition in South African property law’ (1995) 11<br />

South Africa Journal on Human Rights 169-206 169-171.<br />

67 Particularly ss 8(3), 39(2) and 173.<br />

68 See Brisley v Drotsky 2002 4 SA 1 (SCA); Afrox Health Care Bpk v Strydom 2002 6<br />

SA 21 (SCA). A Cockrell ‘Private law and the bill <strong>of</strong> rights: A threshold issue <strong>of</strong><br />

“horizontality”’ in Bill <strong>of</strong> rights compendium (1998) paras 3A8, 3A7 argues that<br />

‘the direct application <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights against private agencies must be<br />

mediated by the operation <strong>of</strong> the common law’.<br />

69 In the 1996 Constitution, as in the 1993 Constitution, the Constitutional Court is a<br />

specialist court and not a court <strong>of</strong> general jurisdiction. In terms <strong>of</strong> s 167 it is the<br />

court <strong>of</strong> final instance in constitutional matters only. The Constitutional Court<br />

must confirm any order <strong>of</strong> a High Court or the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal to the<br />

effect that an Act <strong>of</strong> Parliament, a provincial Act or conduct <strong>of</strong> the President is<br />

unconstitutional before that order can have effect: s 167(5). See Currie & de Waal<br />

(n 30 above) 108-109.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 95<br />

common law matters. 70 In Zantsi 71 the Constitutional Court stated<br />

that, because <strong>of</strong> the far-reaching implications <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

decisions, it would be better if lower courts first heard cases where<br />

constitutional issues are raised, because that would allow the law to<br />

develop incrementally. 72 Incremental development is said to be in<br />

line with the inherent logic <strong>of</strong> the common law and Zantsi therefore<br />

reinforced the idea that development <strong>of</strong> the common law under the<br />

Constitution could continue largely as before. 73<br />

The notion that the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal is a specialist court<br />

in common law matters is not the only reason why cases involving<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law are left to the civil courts. The<br />

Constitutional Court prefers not to sit as court <strong>of</strong> first and last<br />

instance on any matter and it prefers that the High Court or the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal decide on common law issues before it<br />

considers the matter on appeal. 74 The outcome in Carmichele 75 could<br />

be seen as pro<strong>of</strong> that the division <strong>of</strong> labour between the<br />

70 Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund 1998 4 SA 753 (CC) par 33: the<br />

SCA’s view on whether the common law should be developed is important because<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘the breadth <strong>of</strong> its jurisdiction and its expertise in the common law’.<br />

71 Zantsi v Council <strong>of</strong> State, Ciskei 1995 4 SA 615 (CC) par 5. This echoed the<br />

decision in S v Mhlungu 1995 3 SA 867 (CC) par 59 that, where it is possible to<br />

decide any case without reaching a constitutional issue, that is the course that<br />

should be followed (dissenting, Kentridge J). This principle was subsequently<br />

confirmed in Zantsi (above) par 3 and followed in Amod (CC) (n 70 above) par 33.<br />

Du Plessis (n 62 above) 207-231 calls it the subsidiarity principle.<br />

72 The notion <strong>of</strong> ‘interstitial’, incremental development that fills up small gaps in<br />

received doctrine, case by case, originated in HLA Hart The concept <strong>of</strong> law (1961)<br />

37-38. The argument is that larger changes in the common law that affect<br />

acquired rights should be introduced by legislation. However, judges are wellplaced<br />

and qualified to make smaller, reasoned ‘elaborations’ or incremental<br />

changes to the common law on doctrinal reasoning. The argument that the courts<br />

are neither democratically legitimated to bring about major changes nor qualified<br />

to judge the wisdom <strong>of</strong> policy changes is based on the deference approach <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legal process school that responded to Realism by resorting to either deference or<br />

craft: A Bickel ‘The Supreme Court 1960 term: The passive virtues’ (1961) 75 Harv<br />

LR 40-79; H Wechsler ‘Toward neutral principles <strong>of</strong> constitutional law’ (1959) 73<br />

Harv LR 1-35.<br />

73 Khumalo v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 (CC) par 45 (not shown that the common law<br />

‘as currently developed was inconsistent with the provisions <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’)<br />

can be traced to this argument. The defence <strong>of</strong> reasonable publication was<br />

developed by the SCA in National Media Ltd v Bogoshi 1998 4 SA 1196 (SCA),<br />

contradicting earlier case law where publishers were held strictly liable for<br />

defamation. Bogoshi argued that this was inspired by the dynamic logic <strong>of</strong> the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> delict and not by constitutional developments, despite confirmation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

established authority (Pakendorf v De Flamingh 1982 3 SA 146 (A)) in Neethling v<br />

Du Preez; Neethling v The Weekly Mail 1994 1 SA 708 (A), the (then still)<br />

Appellate Division <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court holding that a newspaper could only<br />

escape a claim for defamation if it could establish truth.<br />

74 Carmichele (n 58 above) paras 56-59.<br />

75 In Carmichele (n 58 above) par 45 the Constitutional Court referred the matter<br />

back to the trial court (paras 81-83), where it was decided that the common law<br />

would not have placed a duty upon the state; that the Constitution would place a<br />

duty upon the state; that the common law therefore had to be developed to place<br />

a duty upon the state; and damages was granted: Carmichele v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety<br />

and Security 2003 2 SA 656 (C).


96 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

Constitutional Court and the civil courts functions well. Given its<br />

declared preference for developing the common law incrementally<br />

the fact that the Constitutional Court referred the final order back to<br />

the High Court could be seen as an effort not to intrude too far into<br />

the sphere <strong>of</strong> the legislature, who should be given maximum scope to<br />

amend the common law by legislation. 76 At the same time, referring<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law to the high courts need not be seen<br />

as a sign <strong>of</strong> deference; the Constitutional Court has indicated that it<br />

will not compromise the supremacy <strong>of</strong> the Constitution and that it will<br />

develop the common law if that is what the interests <strong>of</strong> justice<br />

require. 77 As Du Plessis points out, the Pharmaceutical Manufacturers<br />

decision 78 was<br />

the Constitutional Court’s response to a tendency <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court<br />

<strong>of</strong> Appeal (at the time) to pretend that constitution-related issues can<br />

be disposed <strong>of</strong> in an ‘enlightened’, rights-friendly manner without<br />

reference to (let alone reliance on) the Constitution. 79<br />

In some cases the tendency to regard the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal as<br />

the specialist court in matters concerning the common law did result<br />

in outcomes that restricted the influence <strong>of</strong> the Constitution on<br />

private law. In Brisley 80 and Afrox 81 it was accepted that public policy<br />

(<strong>of</strong> which open-ended norms such as good faith form part) is informed<br />

by fundamental values in the Constitution 82 and that the Constitution<br />

might ‘spur on the development <strong>of</strong> new substantive rules <strong>of</strong> law’, 83<br />

but neither good faith nor constitutional values ‘were sufficient to<br />

outweigh the traditional bias in favour <strong>of</strong> the strict enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

agreements’ 84 and the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal was not willing to<br />

undertake development <strong>of</strong> the common law that would amount to<br />

judicial interference with agreements willingly entered into by<br />

private parties. 85<br />

76 Zantsi (n 71 above) par 5.<br />

77 Zantsi (n 71 above) par 4; Harksen v Lane NO 1998 1 SA 300 (CC) par 26.<br />

78<br />

n 37 above.<br />

79 Du Plessis (n 62 above) 217, referring to Bogoshi (n 73 above). Woolman (n 45<br />

above) 10 refers to the same tendency.<br />

80<br />

n 68 above. Roux (n 46 above) 485 argues that the majority in Brisley made a<br />

policy choice in favour <strong>of</strong> legal continuity.<br />

81 n 68 above.<br />

82<br />

In view <strong>of</strong> Carmichele (n 58 above); see Brisley (n 68 above) par 91; Afrox (n 68<br />

above) par 18.<br />

83 GF Lubbe ‘Taking fundamental rights seriously: The bill <strong>of</strong> rights and its<br />

implications for the development <strong>of</strong> contract law’ (2004) 121 South African Law<br />

Journal 395-423 401.<br />

84 Lubbe (n 83 above) 401 414.<br />

85<br />

Du Plessis (n 62 above) 218-221, referring to Afrox (n 68 above). See Woolman (n<br />

45 above) 95; T Naudé & G Lubbe ‘Exemption clauses — A rethink occasioned by<br />

Afrox Healthcare Bpk v Strydom’ (2005) 122 South African Law Journal 441-463; S<br />

Woolman & D Brand ‘Is there a constitution in this courtroom? Constitutional<br />

jurisdiction after Walters and Afrox’ (2003) 18 SA Public Law 37-82.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 97<br />

During the 2007 term the Constitutional Court decided three cases<br />

in which the effect <strong>of</strong> the Constitution on the common law was in<br />

issue: Barkhuizen, 86 NM 87 and Masiya. 88 Stu Woolman concluded that<br />

these decisions prove that ‘a penchant for outcome-based decisionmaking,<br />

and a concomitant lack <strong>of</strong> analytical rigour, has finally caught<br />

up with the Constitutional Court’; that ‘the court’s current process <strong>of</strong><br />

(public) reasoning — its preferred mode <strong>of</strong> analysis — has genuinely<br />

deleterious consequences.’ 89 In coming to this rather damning<br />

conclusion, Woolman attaches particular importance to ‘the court’s<br />

persistent refusal to engage in the direct application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights’ and its insistence upon replacing direct application analysis<br />

with what he describes as ‘flaccid analysis in terms <strong>of</strong> three vaguely<br />

defined values’, namely dignity, equality and freedom. 90 This<br />

strategy <strong>of</strong> overemphasising the constitutional values and development<br />

<strong>of</strong> the common law (or indirect application) in terms <strong>of</strong> s 39(2)<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> direct application <strong>of</strong> the rights provisions in the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights, so Woolman argues, ‘has freed the court almost entirely from<br />

the text, and thereby grants the court the licence to decide each case<br />

as it pleases’, thereby also unwittingly undermining the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

and the rule <strong>of</strong> law. 91<br />

These are strong words. If the decisions criticised by Woolman<br />

indeed indicate a tendency to free the Constitutional Court from the<br />

text <strong>of</strong> the Constitution so that it can decide each case as it pleases,<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> ‘value-speak’, and if that tendency does undermine<br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and the rule <strong>of</strong> law, then we are perhaps indeed<br />

seeing the fruits <strong>of</strong> normative anarchy. What Woolman is suggesting is<br />

that the decisions in Barkhuizen, NM and Masiya represent decision<br />

making at more or less the same level as Mr Davies senior’s ruling that<br />

Robin could not arrange a visit with a friend in the afternoon when he<br />

already had another social engagement for that evening, with his<br />

parents — the decision is arbitrary because it is based on unilateral<br />

pronouncement <strong>of</strong> vaguely defined values that are neither<br />

substantiated by foundation nor open to debate. In the absence <strong>of</strong><br />

foundation, normative pluralism calls for deliberation and politics,<br />

not flaccid but arbitrary and inflexible rules.<br />

86<br />

Barkhuizen v Napier 2007 5 SA 323 (CC) (time-limitation clauses in an insurance<br />

87<br />

contract).<br />

NM v Smith (Freedom <strong>of</strong> Expression Institute as Amicus Curiae) 2007 5 SA 250 (CC)<br />

88<br />

(publication that revealed HIV status <strong>of</strong> the applicants without consent).<br />

Masiya v Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions, <strong>Pretoria</strong> (Centre for Applied Legal<br />

Studies and Another, Amici Curiae) 2007 5 SA 30 (CC) (common law definition <strong>of</strong><br />

89<br />

rape).<br />

S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing bill <strong>of</strong> rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law<br />

90<br />

91<br />

Journal 762-794 762.<br />

Woolman (n 89 above) 763.<br />

As above.


98 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

In the early stages <strong>of</strong> the constitutional debate much emphasis<br />

was placed on direct horizontal application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. In two<br />

landmark decisions on direct horizontal application, the<br />

Constitutional Court first held that s 7(1) and 7(2) <strong>of</strong> the 1993<br />

Constitution had to be interpreted restrictively so that direct<br />

horizontal application on the law <strong>of</strong> defamation would be excluded; 92<br />

then subsequently decided that direct horizontal application was<br />

possible under s 8(2) <strong>of</strong> the 1996 Constitution. 93 In terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

application debate as it has crystallised in the case law and literature,<br />

this does not take the matter much further and we are still wavering<br />

between the preservative impulse to uphold the common law<br />

tradition unless the Constitution or new legislation explicitly requires<br />

us to depart from it and the transformative desire to change the legal<br />

infrastructure that inhibits speedy and effective social and economic<br />

reform. Most commentators who were initially enthusiastic about<br />

direct application have given up on the debate or shifted their<br />

focus, 94 but Woolman insists that the Constitutional Court’s<br />

persistent evasion <strong>of</strong> direct application ‘has genuinely deleterious<br />

effects’. 95 In the next two sections I evaluate decisions from the 2007<br />

term, arguing that they hold the key to a different perspective on the<br />

application issue. In the following two sections I identify, from the<br />

case law <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court, indications <strong>of</strong> what I describe as<br />

a subsidiarity approach that enables the courts to simultaneously<br />

promote constitutional reforms and uphold constitutional stability,<br />

choosing between the two impulses (and justifying the choice in each<br />

case) with reference to constitutional principles <strong>of</strong> justice and<br />

democracy. In the final section <strong>of</strong> the article I argue that this<br />

approach can be justified, even in so far as it creates law that<br />

resembles fixed doctrine, in so far as it is not aimed at entrenching<br />

shallow formalism but rather at upholding and enabling a<br />

constitutionally authorised and required balance between<br />

constitution and law, rights and democracy, or stability and change,<br />

within the particular historical and constitutional context <strong>of</strong> the South<br />

African Constitution. My underlying assumption, based upon the<br />

theoretical analysis in the first two sections <strong>of</strong> the article above, is<br />

that such a balance is justified in so far as it opens up space to give<br />

politics a chance, in the sense that it recognises diversity and<br />

pluralism and creates room for real social contestation and dissent.<br />

92 Du Plessis (n 62 above) 220, referring to Du Plessis v De Klerk 1996 3 SA 850 (CC).<br />

93 Du Plessis (n 62 above) 221, referring to Khumalo (n 73 above).<br />

94<br />

Eg Van der Walt (n 34 above) 341-363; Roux (n 46 above).<br />

95 n 89 above.


4 Rights and democracy<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 99<br />

Legislation enacted by Parliament to give effect to a constitutional right ought<br />

not to be ignored. 96<br />

4.1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

Decisions from the 2007 term indicate the emergence <strong>of</strong> an ‘angle <strong>of</strong><br />

approach’ 97 — an analytic rhythm — according to which courts could<br />

decide upon the tension between rights and democracy, while<br />

acknowledging what Van der Walt and Botha 98 called the irresoluble<br />

dissent embedded in the countermajoritarian dilemma. Lourens du<br />

Plessis described this kind <strong>of</strong> thought process as ‘subsidiarity’,<br />

defining it as a reading strategy whereby a court refrains from taking<br />

a decision that can be taken by a lower court or avoids a constitutional<br />

decision if the matter can be decided on a nonconstitutional basis. 99<br />

Generally speaking, the notion <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity poses conceptual and<br />

analytical problems for the politics-enhancing approach to the<br />

fundamental contradiction set out in the first two sections <strong>of</strong> the<br />

article above. This is particularly true <strong>of</strong> the way in which the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity has been enunciated in earlier South African<br />

case law. In 1995 the Constitutional Court enunciated a subsidiarity<br />

principle in Mhlungu, holding that courts should, whenever possible,<br />

decide cases without reaching a constitutional issue; 100 in 1998 it<br />

formulated another one in Amod, 101 stating that the development <strong>of</strong><br />

the common law should (in terms <strong>of</strong> the 1993 Constitution) preferably<br />

be undertaken by the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal. The latter principle<br />

was confirmed (under the 1996 Constitution) in Carmichele. 102 Stated<br />

this blandly, the principle <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity looks like a formalist escape<br />

96 Minister <strong>of</strong> Health NO v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd (Treatment Action<br />

Campaign and Another as Amici Curiae) 2006 2 SA 311 (CC) par 437 (Chaskalson<br />

CJ).<br />

97 I am indebted to Henk Botha, who first used this phrase at a workshop in 2007,<br />

explaining that it pointedly avoids the pretence <strong>of</strong> a technique that produces<br />

ready or final answers. The phrase originates from NS Ndebele’s novel The cry <strong>of</strong><br />

Winnie Mandela (2003).<br />

98 See n 19 above and accompanying text.<br />

99<br />

I do not set out or enter into the general subsidiarity debate or literature, where<br />

this notion has attracted various understandings and where it remains contested;<br />

see Du Plessis (n 62 above) 207-231. Currie & de Waal (n 30 above) 75-78 call this<br />

the ‘avoidance principle’, although their interpretation is narrower and more<br />

mechanistic. See further L du Plessis ‘The South African constitution as memory<br />

and promise’ (2000) 11 Stellenbosch Law Review 385-394 388-389; W le Roux ‘War<br />

memorials, the architecture <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court building and countermonumental<br />

constitutionalism’ in W le Roux & K van Marle (eds) Law, memory and<br />

the legacy <strong>of</strong> apartheid. Ten years after Azapo v President <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2007)<br />

65-90 87.<br />

100 n 71 above, par 59 (dissenting, Kentridge J); confirmed in Zantsi (n 71 above) par<br />

3.<br />

101 n 70 above, par 14.<br />

102 n 58 above, paras 50-55.


100 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

from politics, but in the historical and constitutional context <strong>of</strong> the<br />

South African Constitution it could also be seen as a politicsconfirming<br />

and –enhancing device that ensures interplay between<br />

constitutional principles and democratic laws, reformist initiatives<br />

and vested rights, change and stability. In the former sense,<br />

subsidiarity would serve a formalist evasion <strong>of</strong> politics; in the latter<br />

sense it could promote normative pluralism and constitutional change<br />

without succumbing to either normative anarchy or reactionary<br />

formalism.<br />

In the next two sections I discuss decisions from the 2007 term<br />

that could indicate that the Constitutional Court is developing a more<br />

general subsidiarity approach. 103 In the final section I consider the<br />

implications <strong>of</strong> this approach for the application debate and evaluate<br />

the role that subsidiarity could play in promoting normative pluralism<br />

and avoiding anarchy.<br />

4.2 The SANDU principle<br />

In SANDU, 104 the Court confirmed 105 that, once legislation has been<br />

enacted to give effect to a right in the Constitution, litigants must<br />

rely on the legislation — and may not rely directly on the<br />

constitutional provision — when bringing action to protect that right<br />

against infringement. The principle establishes a subsidiarity rule<br />

because it excludes direct application <strong>of</strong> the constitutional provision<br />

once legislation has been enacted to give effect to that right.<br />

Legislation in this category include the Labour Relations Act 66 <strong>of</strong><br />

1995 (LRA) (s 23), the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Administrative Justice Act 3 <strong>of</strong><br />

2000 (PAJA) (s 33), the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Access to Information Act 2 <strong>of</strong><br />

103 Aspects <strong>of</strong> this approach have been decided earlier. In New Clicks (n 96 above) par<br />

97 fn 81 Chaskalson CJ cites with approval a paper in which Cora Hoexter set out<br />

the logic <strong>of</strong> both SANDU and Bato Star. The paper was published as C Hoexter<br />

‘“Administrative action” in the courts’ 2006 Acta Juridica 303-324 (also published<br />

as H Corder (ed) Comparing administrative justice across the Commonwealth<br />

(2008)). See to the same effect Currie & de Waal (n 30 above) 649.<br />

104 South African National Defence Union v Minister <strong>of</strong> Defence 2007 5 SA 400 (CC)<br />

paras 51-52. See further Pillay (n 29 above) paras 39-40; Chirwa v Transnet Ltd<br />

2008 2 SA 24 (CC) paras 59 (Skweyiya J), 69 (Ngcobo J). In Sidumo v Rustenburg<br />

Platinum Mines Ltd 2008 2 SA 24 (CC) par 248 Ngcobo J confirmed the principle;<br />

the majority (paras 55-56) did not mention it. In MEC: Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture,<br />

Conservation and Environment v HTF Developers (Pty) Ltd 2008 2 SA 319 (CC) the<br />

majority (par 24) confirmed that the National Environment Management Act 107<br />

<strong>of</strong> 1998 (NEMA) is legislation contemplated by s 24(b) without mentioning SANDU<br />

(but see Ngcobo J par 62).<br />

105 Formulated in NAPTOSA v Minister <strong>of</strong> Education, Western Cape 2001 2 SA 112 (C)<br />

123B, I-J; mooted in New Clicks (n 96 above) paras 95-96, 434-437 (Chaskalson CJ,<br />

Ngcobo J); left undecided in National Education Health and Allied Workers Union<br />

v <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Cape Town 2003 3 SA 1 (CC) par 17; Ingledew v Financial Services<br />

Board: In re Financial Services Board v Van der Merwe 2003 4 SA 584 (CC) paras<br />

23-24 (Ngcobo J). See IM Rautenbach ‘Overview <strong>of</strong> Constitutional Court decisions<br />

on the bill <strong>of</strong> rights — 2007’ 2008 Tydskrif vir Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 330-348 330.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 101<br />

2000 (PAIA) (s 32) and the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Equality and Prevention <strong>of</strong><br />

Unfair Discrimination Act 4 <strong>of</strong> 2000 (PEPUDA) (s 9). 106 Application <strong>of</strong><br />

the SANDU principle to PAJA and PEPUDA indicates that the<br />

distinction between vertical and horizontal application becomes<br />

irrelevant in the context <strong>of</strong> this principle.<br />

In line with s 39(2), SANDU requires that where ‘the Legislature<br />

enacts legislation in the effort to meet its constitutional obligations,<br />

and does so within constitutional limits, courts must give full effect<br />

to the legislative purpose’. 107 In Goedgelegen Tropical Fruits 108 the<br />

Constitutional Court applied the implications, emphasising that the<br />

Restitution <strong>of</strong> Land Rights Act 22 <strong>of</strong> 1994 is remedial legislation under<br />

the Constitution and that courts, to promote the spirit, purport and<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, must acknowledge the historical<br />

background under which labour tenancies were cancelled. The cause<br />

<strong>of</strong> a historical dispossession will <strong>of</strong>ten not lie in an isolated moment<br />

in time or a single act but in the context and, as the contextual<br />

features <strong>of</strong> this case ‘constituted a grid <strong>of</strong> integrated repressive laws<br />

that were aimed at furthering the government’s policy <strong>of</strong> racial<br />

discrimination’ which ‘materially affected and favoured the ability <strong>of</strong><br />

the [landowners] to dispossess the applicants <strong>of</strong> their labour tenancy<br />

rights’, 109 the former labour tenants could claim restitution.<br />

The SANDU principle indicates that, once legislation has been<br />

enacted to give effect to a constitutional right, direct application <strong>of</strong><br />

the constitutional provision is precluded. However, this applies only<br />

when litigants seek to protect rights; when the constitutional validity<br />

<strong>of</strong> legislation is challenged, the constitutional provision applies<br />

directly. 110 In Islamic Unity 111 the Court expanded the qualification:<br />

when challenging the constitutional validity <strong>of</strong> any statute that<br />

106 In NAPTOSA (n 105 above), NEHAWU (n 105 above) and SANDU (n 104 above) the<br />

provision was s 23(5); the legislation the LRA. In Sidumo (n 104) and Chirwa (n<br />

104) two provisions (ss 23, 33) and statutes (LRA and PAJA) were in dispute. In<br />

Pillay (n 29) the provision was s 9, the legislation PEPUDA. In New Clicks (n 96)<br />

the provision was s 33, the legislation PAJA; in Ingledew (n 105) the provision was<br />

s 32, the legislation PAIA. In HTF Developers (n 104) the provision was s 24, the<br />

legislation NEMA.<br />

107 Sidumo (n 104 above) par 249, citing NEHAWU (n 105 above) par 14. Although<br />

Ngcobo J concurred in the outcome in Sidumo, he wrote a separate judgment:<br />

see n 104 above.<br />

108 Department <strong>of</strong> Land Affairs v Goedgelegen Tropical Fruits (Pty) Ltd 2007 6 SA 199<br />

(CC).<br />

109 Goedgelegen Tropical Fruits (n 108 above) paras 53, 66, 69, 71.<br />

110 New Clicks (n 96 above) par 437; SANDU (n 104 above) par 52; Sidumo (n 104<br />

above) par 249; Engelbrecht v Road Accident Fund 2007 6 SA 96 (CC) par 15<br />

111<br />

(constitutional challenge against legislation involves direct application <strong>of</strong> s 34).<br />

Islamic Unity Convention v Minister <strong>of</strong> Telecommunications 2008 3 SA 383 (CC)<br />

par 59.


102 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

conflicts with the constitutional principle <strong>of</strong> administrative justice, s<br />

33 is the review measure. 112<br />

SANDU, with its qualification, was originally justified in New<br />

Clicks: allowing litigants to rely on s 23 directly instead <strong>of</strong> on the LRA<br />

‘would encourage the development <strong>of</strong> two parallel streams <strong>of</strong> labour<br />

law jurisprudence, one under the LRA and the other under s 23(1)’;<br />

such a practice would be ‘singularly inappropriate’ 113 and would<br />

contradict the principle <strong>of</strong> ‘one system <strong>of</strong> law grounded in the<br />

Constitution’. 114<br />

Where, as here, the Constitution requires Parliament to enact legislation<br />

to give effect to the constitutional rights guaranteed in the Constitution,<br />

and Parliament enacts such legislation, it will ordinarily be<br />

impermissible for a litigant to found a cause <strong>of</strong> action directly on the<br />

Constitution without alleging that the statute in question is deficient in<br />

the remedies that it provides. Legislation enacted by Parliament to give<br />

effect to a constitutional right ought not to be ignored. And where a<br />

litigant founds a cause <strong>of</strong> action on such legislation, it is equally<br />

impermissible for a court to bypass the legislation and to decide the<br />

matter on the basis <strong>of</strong> the constitutional provision that is being given<br />

effect to by the legislation in question. 115<br />

The principle expounded by the Court is grounded in the norm that ‘to<br />

permit the litigant to ignore the legislation and rely directly on the<br />

constitutional provision would be to fail to recognise the important<br />

task conferred upon the Legislature by the Constitution to respect,<br />

protect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.’ 116 The<br />

qualification, by contrast, is justified by the norm that the majority<br />

is accountable to and can be tested against constitutional limits.<br />

SANDU therefore reflects the tension <strong>of</strong> the countermajoritarian<br />

dilemma, with the principle emphasising democracy and the<br />

qualification emphasising rights: when the democratically elected<br />

legislature meets its constitutional obligations to enact legislation<br />

that gives effect to the rights in the Constitution, within<br />

constitutional limits, the courts should respect and give full effect to<br />

that legislation. To that extent, rights are subject to democracy.<br />

However, the courts can review the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> legislation<br />

with a direct appeal to the Constitution. To that extent, democracy<br />

is subject to rights. In so far as the SANDU principle promotes this<br />

112 Zondi v MEC for Traditional and Local Government Affairs 2005 3 SA 589 (CC): If a<br />

constitutional challenge is brought against legislation for being inconsistent with s<br />

33, the proper approach is to consider whether it can be consistent with s 33: s<br />

39(2) (par 102). The next question is whether it contemplates administrative<br />

action for purposes <strong>of</strong> s 33 (par 103), whether it limits the rights in s 33 (par 106)<br />

and whether the limitation is justifiable (s 36(1)).<br />

113 New Clicks (par 96 above) paras 434, 436; NAPTOSA (n 105 above) par 123B, J.<br />

114 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 37 above) par 44.<br />

115 New Clicks (n 96 above) par 437 (Chaskalson CJ). Footnote omitted.<br />

116 SANDU (n 104 above) par 52; Pillay (n 29 above) par 40.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 103<br />

balance between democracy and rights one could say that it could be<br />

employed to promote normative pluralism without falling into the<br />

trap <strong>of</strong> either normative anarchy (anything goes) or reactionary<br />

formalism (escaping real social contestation and dissent through<br />

formalist reasoning). To that extent, the principle could also be said<br />

to give politics a chance in that it promotes and enables real social<br />

contestation and dissent between the democratic push <strong>of</strong> the<br />

majority and the stabilising pull <strong>of</strong> constitutional stability.<br />

4.3 The Bato Star principle<br />

In Chirwa 117 the Court confirmed a second principle: 118 once<br />

legislation has been enacted to give effect to a right in the<br />

Constitution, and in so far as the legislation was intended to codify<br />

the common law, litigants may not rely directly on the common law<br />

when seeking to protect that right against infringement. The<br />

principle also establishes a subsidiarity rule in that it precludes<br />

application or development <strong>of</strong> the common law; 119 once legislation<br />

has been enacted to give effect to a right, that right is protected<br />

through constitution-conforming interpretation and application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legislation in accordance with s 39(2). 120<br />

Bato Star does not render the common law irrelevant — the<br />

common law informs interpretation <strong>of</strong> the legislation. 121 The<br />

stabilising role <strong>of</strong> the common law should be treated with care,<br />

though — the common law should inform interpretation <strong>of</strong> legislation<br />

only in so far as it is consistent with the Constitution, consistent with<br />

the legislation and able to augment interpretation <strong>of</strong> the legislation<br />

as foreseen in s 39(2), namely to promote the spirit, purport and<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. Du Plessis 122 and de Ville 123 explain that<br />

the relationship between the common law (favouring stability by<br />

upholding the status quo) and legislation (favouring change through<br />

policy-driven intervention) has to be inverted in view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

centripetal interpretive force <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.<br />

The areas <strong>of</strong> existing law identified as affected by this principle<br />

are labour disputes (the LRA) 124 and just administrative action<br />

117 n 104 above, par 23; see further Fuel Retailers (n 25 above) par 37.<br />

118 Stated earlier in Bato Star (n 63 above) par 25 New Clicks (n 96 above) par 96.<br />

119 In terms <strong>of</strong> ss 173, 8(3) or 39(2). See to the same effect Currie & de Waal (n 30<br />

above) 650.<br />

120 S 39(2).<br />

121 n 63 above, par 22.<br />

122 L du Plessis Re-interpretation <strong>of</strong> statutes (2002) 179-181.<br />

123 JR de Ville Constitutional and statutory interpretation (2000) 172 66.<br />

124 Chirwa (n 104 above) par 23.


104 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

(PAJA), 125 but the Restitution <strong>of</strong> Land Rights Act 22 <strong>of</strong> 1994, 126 the<br />

National Environment Management Act 107 <strong>of</strong> 1998 (NEMA), 127 the<br />

Water Services Act 108 <strong>of</strong> 1997, the Mineral and Petroleum Resources<br />

Development Act 28 <strong>of</strong> 2002 128 and the Prevention <strong>of</strong> Illegal Eviction<br />

from and Unlawful Occupation <strong>of</strong> Land Rights Act 19 <strong>of</strong> 1998 (PIE) 129<br />

could also fit into this category.<br />

Like SANDU, Bato Star is founded on the principle <strong>of</strong> ‘one system<br />

<strong>of</strong> law grounded in the Constitution’ 130 and intended to prevent the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> parallel systems <strong>of</strong> law and jurisprudence, one based<br />

on legislation and the other on the common law. Again like SANDU,<br />

Bato Star acknowledges the countermajoritarian dilemma in that it<br />

prevents the courts from circumventing democratically enacted<br />

legislation by reverting to a parallel, alternative system <strong>of</strong> rules, 131<br />

although it leaves room for constitutional review <strong>of</strong> democratic<br />

legislation. Like SANDU, the Bato Star principle enforces normative<br />

pluralism by preventing either democratic legislation or constitutional<br />

rights from usurping all adjudicative space — by forcefully holding the<br />

balance between the two, the principle gives politics a chance in so<br />

far as it enables decision-making based on consideration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

contestation between both impulses.<br />

SANDU, Bato Star and the constitutional review qualification,<br />

considered together, are signs <strong>of</strong> a subsidiarity approach: once<br />

legislation is enacted to give effect to a constitutional right, litigants<br />

must rely on the legislation when bringing action to protect that right;<br />

they may not rely directly on the constitutional provision or on the<br />

common law. Direct application <strong>of</strong> the constitutional provision<br />

remains possible to attack the constitutional validity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legislation. Neither constitutional principle nor legislative inter-<br />

125 Fuel Retailers (n 25 above) par 37.<br />

126 Promulgated to give effect to s 121 <strong>of</strong> the 1993 Constitution, now authorised by s<br />

25(7). See Goedgelegen Tropical Fruits (n 108 above).<br />

127 Enacted to give effect to s 24(b): HTF Developers (n 104 above) par 24. Ss 31A<br />

and 32 <strong>of</strong> the Environment Conservation Act 73 <strong>of</strong> 1989 must also be interpreted<br />

to give effect to s 24: HTF Developers par 19.<br />

128 Arguably promulgated to give effect to s 24(b)(iii) and s 25(5), read with s<br />

25(4)(a).<br />

129 Enacted to give effect to s 26(3): Port Elizabeth Municipality (n 38 above) paras<br />

11-23; Occupiers <strong>of</strong> 51 Olivia Road, Berea Township, and 197 Main Street,<br />

Johannesburg v City <strong>of</strong> Johannesburg 2008 3 SA 208 (CC) par 16. S 4(1) <strong>of</strong> PIE<br />

explicitly overrides the common law. The CC declined in City <strong>of</strong> Johannesburg to<br />

decide whether PIE applied and what the relationship between PIE and s 26 is,<br />

but held that a local authority that evicts residents without meaningfully<br />

engaging with them acts at odds with the spirit and purpose <strong>of</strong> s 26(3).<br />

130 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 37 above) par 44.<br />

131 JW Singer & JM Beermann ‘The social origins <strong>of</strong> property’ (1003) 6 Canadian<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Law & Jurisprudence 217-248 238 point out that the US Supreme Court<br />

majority in Lucas v South Carolina Coastal Council 505 US 1003 (1992)<br />

characterised ‘traditional common law [property] rules as somehow more worthy<br />

than politics advanced through contemporary legislative action’, threatening to<br />

derail public policies.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 105<br />

vention or common law tradition is allowed to decide cases<br />

automatically by its own force; each case is decided only when and on<br />

the strength <strong>of</strong> contestation between the conflicting impulses <strong>of</strong><br />

stability and change; rights and constitution; tradition and reform.<br />

In so far as the cases discussed so far reach, these subsidiarity<br />

principles are attractive and relatively unproblematic. It is also<br />

reasonably simple to justify their application and outcome in the<br />

straightforward cases foreseen in these decisions. However, the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> cases will not be nearly as simple, in that they will not fall<br />

within the rather narrow ambit foreseen in the decisions discussed so<br />

far. The difficulty is to decide how far the subsidiarity approach<br />

reaches; particularly, whether the subsidiarity principles apply only<br />

where legislation was enacted specifically to give effect to a<br />

constitutional right and intended to codify existing law; whether they<br />

also to apply to other legislation; and how they affect the common<br />

law.<br />

In the sections that follow I embroider upon the logic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

subsidiarity principles that I have identified in the SANDU and Bato<br />

Star decisions, without thereby pretending either that the<br />

embroidered or expanded subsidiarity principles reflect the view (or<br />

would meet with the approval) <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court or that<br />

they constitute doctrinal necessity. The line <strong>of</strong> argument in what<br />

follows is simply to trace what the extent and outlines <strong>of</strong> the SANDU<br />

and Bato Star subsidiarity principles could be if their logic is<br />

developed further, into areas not so far foreseen or discussed by the<br />

Constitutional Court. I do not present this analysis as a proposal <strong>of</strong><br />

some kind <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity or deference principle either — in the final<br />

sections <strong>of</strong> the article, I still want to subject the outcome <strong>of</strong> this<br />

logical exploration to critical scrutiny in view <strong>of</strong> the normative<br />

framework set out earlier: if the logic <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity is embroidered<br />

upon to present a fuller picture than can at present be gleaned from<br />

case law, and should this logic be adopted and followed by the courts,<br />

and in so far as it might eventually establish legal or doctrinal<br />

principles, are or would they be justified? In asking this question, my<br />

point <strong>of</strong> departure will once again be that law (including subsidiarity<br />

principles), in so far as it is inevitable, will only be justified to the<br />

extent that it promotes normative pluralism but does not descend into<br />

either anarchy or reactionary formalism. In allowing room for<br />

normative pluralism but simultaneously avoiding anarchy, it must give<br />

politics a chance by allowing for real social contention and dissent.<br />

In this spirit, I rely on the perceived logic <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity in SANDU<br />

and Bato Star to determine whether, and how, the subsidiarity<br />

principles could apply with regard to other legislation (that it, pre-<br />

1994 legislation and partial or competing legislation) or to cases<br />

where there is no applicable legislation at all.


106 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

4.4 Application to other legislation<br />

SANDU was formulated for legislation particularly enacted to give<br />

effect to a right in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights; Bato Star was aimed at legislation<br />

that ‘covers the field’. 132 This raises the question whether these<br />

principles also apply to legislation that protects the right in question<br />

but that was neither enacted specifically with the constitutional<br />

provision in mind nor intended to codify existing law. 133<br />

The first indication that these principles could apply more widely<br />

is the justification for the subsidiarity principles: if the underlying<br />

norm is that legislation should not be sidelined in protecting a<br />

constitutional right out <strong>of</strong> respect for the transformative role <strong>of</strong> the<br />

democratic legislature, the principles should apply as widely as<br />

possible to legislation that gives effect to a right, including legislation<br />

not specifically promulgated with the constitutional provision in mind<br />

or not intended to codify existing law on the protection <strong>of</strong> that<br />

right. 134<br />

The second reason why flexible application <strong>of</strong> Bato Star makes<br />

sense is that it is <strong>of</strong>ten difficult to decide when legislation was<br />

intended to codify existing law. 135 On the one hand, some gaps are<br />

left on purpose: constitutional review <strong>of</strong> legislative, executive and<br />

judicial action is covered by neither s 33 nor PAJA and was made<br />

possible by a direct appeal to the constitutional legality principle. 136<br />

On the other hand, even legislation intended to ‘cover the field’<br />

might leave gaps on purpose or by mistake: PAJA, to which SANDU and<br />

Bato Star clearly apply, covers the grounds for review <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative action only imperfectly and the common law probably<br />

132 Stated in New Clicks (n 96 above) par 95 with reference to PAJA; see Sidumo (n<br />

104 above) par 90. See I Currie ‘What difference does the Promotion <strong>of</strong><br />

Administrative Justice Act make to administrative law?’ 2006 Acta Juridica 325-<br />

351 328-334 (whether PAJA is codifying legislation).<br />

133 The Rental Housing Act 50 <strong>of</strong> 1999 gives effect to s 25(6) (insecure tenure), but is<br />

not intended to codify landlord-tenant law.<br />

134 Currie (n 132 above) 328 critiques the tendency to treat the notion that PAJA<br />

codified the law on administrative review as if it meant that PAJA ‘made no<br />

difference to the existing law’; in other words, we can apply existing law as if it<br />

was legitimised by PAJA. Extending Bato Star to partial legislation could force<br />

interpreters to acknowledge that the common law survives only in so far as it is<br />

consistent with and augment legislation.<br />

135 It is normally easier to identify legislation specifically intended to give effect to a<br />

provision, but even there some cases might be difficult.<br />

136 See C Hoexter Administrative law in South Africa (2007) 169-175. Review <strong>of</strong> these<br />

actions is possible on the basis <strong>of</strong> the legality principle in the Constitution:<br />

Fedsure (n 63 above) paras 33-45 (legislative action); President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union 2000 1 SA 1 (CC) par 142<br />

(executive action); Nel v Le Roux NO 1996 3 SA 562 (CC) par 24 (judicial action).<br />

See C Hoexter ‘The principle <strong>of</strong> legality in South African administrative law’<br />

(2004) 4 Macquarie Law Journal 165-185.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 107<br />

still applies in the gaps. 137 The subsidiarity principles should<br />

therefore not be restricted to implementing or codifying legislation<br />

and it should be accepted that gaps will occur in legislation. Judging<br />

on the justification argument, a gap in the field covered by legislation<br />

should mean that the subsidiarity principles do not apply in that<br />

specific area, allowing direct reference, on that specific point, to<br />

either the constitutional provision (SANDU) or the common law (Bato<br />

Star). I return to this point later.<br />

The third argument that supports wider application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

subsidiarity principles is the common law presumption that legislation<br />

does not amend the common law more than is necessary; 138<br />

legislation does amend the common law in so far as the intention to<br />

amend is either stated explicitly or implied clearly. 139 Considering<br />

that pre-constitutional law survives only to the extent that it is<br />

consistent with the Constitution 140 and that all legislation must be<br />

interpreted to promote the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights, 141 it must now be the case that all legislation, whether<br />

specifically intended to codify existing law or not, either gives effect<br />

to the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and promotes the spirit, purport and<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights or is unconstitutional. 142 It thus becomes<br />

axiomatic that all legislation must give effect to the rights in and<br />

promote the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to a<br />

certain extent; the intention to amend the common law must<br />

therefore be implicit in all legislation and SANDU and Bato Star should<br />

apply to it. Lourens du Plessis 143 and Jacques de Ville 144 argue in the<br />

same direction when they state that the common law presumption<br />

either cannot apply or should be inverted in the context <strong>of</strong> the new<br />

Constitution. 145 Existing law must be interpreted to fit in with<br />

constitutional rights and therefore all legislation must be assumed to<br />

amend the common law in so far as is necessary to give effect to the<br />

Constitution, which is why the common law no longer exists as a<br />

137 Prior to PAJA the courts reviewed decisions taken by private bodies: Theron v Ring<br />

van Wellington van die NG Sendingkerk in Suid-Afrika 1976 2 SA 1 (A); Dawnlaan<br />

Beleggings (Edms) Bpk v Johannesburg Stock Exchange 1983 3 SA 344 (W);<br />

Johannesburg Stock Exchange v Witwatersrand Nigel Ltd 1988 3 SA 132 (A). It has<br />

been argued that the common law still applies in this situation: Hoexter<br />

Administrative law (n 136 above) 180-18; Currie & de Waal (n 30 above) 645.<br />

Other gaps are left by excluding grounds for review from s 6 PAJA, e g the<br />

common law rule against vagueness.<br />

138 Du Plessis (n 122 above) 177-181; de Ville (n 123 above) 170-176.<br />

139 Hoexter (n 103 above) 308: the principle that PAJA cannot be sidestepped by<br />

resorting directly to the common law is logical, ‘since statutes inevitably displace<br />

the common law’ (emphasis in original). Compare Rautenbach (n 105 above) 330.<br />

140 S 39(3).<br />

141 S 39(2).<br />

142 S 172.<br />

143 n 122 above, 179-181.<br />

144 n 123 above, 172, 66.<br />

145 Compare Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 37 above) par 45.


108 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

parallel, alternative system <strong>of</strong> rules and cannot be reverted to<br />

directly (Bato Star).<br />

To put it simply, direct application <strong>of</strong> the Constitution and the<br />

application and development <strong>of</strong> the common law should only come up<br />

in the absence <strong>of</strong> legislation. Some legislation will give effect to rights<br />

in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights more directly and some will affect existing law<br />

more explicitly and extensively, but in line with SANDU and Bato Star<br />

all legislation either fails constitutional scrutiny or triggers a<br />

subsidiarity principle according to which the right must primarily be<br />

protected via the legislation and not via direct application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional provision or the common law. In litigation aimed at<br />

protection <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right, the subsidiarity principles in<br />

SANDU and Bato Star postpone direct application <strong>of</strong> the constitutional<br />

provision and application or development <strong>of</strong> the common law until it<br />

is clear that legislation does not cover the case.<br />

Once a flexible reading <strong>of</strong> the subsidiarity principles is accepted,<br />

the next question is how these principles should apply to partial<br />

legislation; in other words, legislation that gives partial effect to a<br />

constitutional right but does not attempt or manage to ‘cover the<br />

field’ as far as protection <strong>of</strong> the right is concerned. This category is<br />

difficult to define because it is impossible to say how partial<br />

legislation must be to disqualify it from being comprehensive, as the<br />

example <strong>of</strong> PAJA in the previous section proves. If the subsidiarity<br />

principles must apply to legislation that ‘covers the field’ as<br />

imperfectly as PAJA does they should arguably apply to all partial<br />

legislation when and in so far as the legislation gives effect to a<br />

constitutional right. An example illustrates the point.<br />

In Magudu Game Co 146 the KwaZulu-Natal High Court argued that<br />

the common law principles regarding ownership <strong>of</strong> wild game should<br />

be developed, in line with s 39(2), to provide for the exigencies <strong>of</strong><br />

commercial game farming. However, the state had already enacted<br />

the Game Theft Act 105 <strong>of</strong> 1991 to protect the rights <strong>of</strong> commercial<br />

game farmers. The Act does not codify the law on wild game — outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> commercial game farming the common law remains unchanged.<br />

However, the Act does regulate commercial game farming, and the<br />

game farmer in this case could not rely on it purely because he failed<br />

to comply with registration requirements. According to the expanded<br />

version <strong>of</strong> Bato Star, development <strong>of</strong> the common law should not be<br />

an option in litigation to protect the right in so far as the legislature<br />

has enacted legislation to give effect to it, which in this case it had.<br />

146 Magudu Game Co (Pty) Ltd v Mathenjwa and others NNO 2008 2 All SA 338 (N).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 109<br />

SANDU and Bato Star must therefore be applied flexibly; even<br />

supposedly codifying legislation will leave gaps and, if the<br />

Constitution or the common law provides for such a gap, the next step<br />

could be to turn to the Constitution or the common law to fill that gap<br />

rather than challenge the legislation. Shifting the problem up to the<br />

Constitution or down to the common law before reverting to a<br />

constitutional challenge makes sense if a gap in the legislation means<br />

that the specific aspect is not covered by the legislative scheme,<br />

which means that the subsidiarity principles do not apply and the gap<br />

can be filled by application <strong>of</strong> constitutional provisions or the common<br />

law, as illustrated by constitutional review <strong>of</strong> legislative, executive or<br />

judicial acts 147 and by judicial review <strong>of</strong> administrative action in<br />

cases where private bodies exercise public power. 148<br />

It should have become clear by now that application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

subsidiarity principles in SANDU and in Bato Star respectively to<br />

partial legislation would work out differently. Applying SANDU to<br />

partial legislation involves the question whether litigants should be<br />

allowed to appeal directly to the constitutional provision to protect a<br />

right if legislation that does provide for its protection but was not<br />

made specifically to give effect to the right does not provide the<br />

required remedy in a particular case. The extension would probably<br />

work better with pre-constitutional than with new legislation, but<br />

generally there is no reason why such a relaxation <strong>of</strong> SANDU should be<br />

impossible in principle. Two qualifications should probably apply,<br />

though. Firstly, the actual purpose and scope <strong>of</strong> partial legislation<br />

should be decisive in deciding whether a direct appeal to the<br />

constitutional provision would be justified if the legislation fails to<br />

provide a remedy. Secondly, to prevent the development <strong>of</strong> parallel<br />

systems <strong>of</strong> law, this relaxation <strong>of</strong> SANDU should arguably only be<br />

possible if the gap cannot be filled by applying or developing the<br />

common law. In other words, as long as a gap in legislation can be<br />

filled by application <strong>of</strong> the common law, a direct appeal to the<br />

Constitution should not be possible in an action to protect the right<br />

— this is why the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal’s decision in Tswelopele 149<br />

to leave the common law ‘untouched’ and to create a new<br />

constitutional remedy was arguably a mistake. The result <strong>of</strong><br />

Tswelopele is two parallel remedies for ante omnia restoration <strong>of</strong><br />

spoliated possession, based on the Constitution and the common law,<br />

the only difference being that the constitutional remedy permits a<br />

restoration order that includes the use <strong>of</strong> replacement materials.<br />

Developing the common law, for a clearly circumscribed range <strong>of</strong><br />

cases, would have vindicated and celebrated judicial victories over<br />

147 n 136 above.<br />

148 n 137 above.<br />

149 Tswelopele Non-Pr<strong>of</strong>it Organisation v City <strong>of</strong> Tshwane Metropolitan Municipality<br />

2007 6 SA 511 (SCA).


110 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

apartheid injustice in decisions such as Fredericks 150 and could have<br />

made a contribution to the rehabilitation <strong>of</strong> the common law <strong>of</strong><br />

property, which did not cover itself in glory during apartheid, by<br />

demonstrating how it can support social justice. 151<br />

Since Bato Star purely prevents direct appeals to the common law<br />

by circumventing legislation, it is easier to argue that the principle<br />

should be qualified so that the common law still applies (and can be<br />

developed) in cases where partial legislation does not in fact give<br />

complete, covering effect to a constitutional right. However, a<br />

qualification is once again necessary in line with s 39: the common law<br />

can only fill gaps in legislation if and to the extent that it is not only<br />

consistent with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and with the legislative scheme but,<br />

in so far as the legislation leaves a gap, <strong>of</strong>fers the possibility (where<br />

necessary through development) <strong>of</strong> augmenting the legislation,<br />

keeping in mind the constitution-enhancing interpretive rule in s<br />

39(2). The governing principle should not be that the common law<br />

survives where it remains unaffected by constitutional or legislative<br />

provisions, but rather that the common law survives only if and in so<br />

far as it is consistent with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, consistent with existing<br />

legislation, and capable <strong>of</strong> complementing the legislation in giving<br />

effect to constitutional rights, either as it stands or through being<br />

developed for the purpose.<br />

The Magudu Game Co 152 example suggests that SANDU and Bato<br />

Star could also apply to pre-constitutional legislation. According to s<br />

39, pre-constitutional law only survives in so far as it does not conflict<br />

with constitutional provisions and can be interpreted in conformity<br />

with constitutional rights and values. Accordingly, the 1991 Act<br />

protects ownership <strong>of</strong> game to give effect to the property clause (s<br />

25) in a specific area, namely commercial game farming. A similar<br />

argument applies to all pre-constitutional legislation that can survive<br />

the new Constitution and therefore SANDU and Bato Star should apply<br />

to it. However, although it has to be interpreted in line with the<br />

Constitution, pre-constitutional legislation cannot be assumed to<br />

reflect the legislature’s effort to comply with constitutional<br />

obligations. The Expropriation Act 63 <strong>of</strong> 1975, being the only general<br />

expropriation legislation currently in force, predates the Constitution<br />

and must therefore be interpreted in line with s 25(2) and (3). 153<br />

Legislation is required to give effect to the expropriation and<br />

compensation provisions in s 25 and since there is nothing else, the<br />

150 Fredericks v Stellenbosch Divisional Council 1977 3 SA 113 (C).<br />

151 See AJ van der Walt ‘Developing the law on unlawful spoliation and squatting’<br />

(2008) 125 South African Law Journal 24-36.<br />

152 n 146 above.<br />

153 A Draft Expropriation Bill 2008 was tabled in the Portfolio Committee on Public<br />

Works on 26 March 2008: Parliamentary Monitoring Group’s website at<br />

www.pmg.org.za. This Bill was recalled for further consideration in August 2008.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 111<br />

1975 Act applies to all expropriation, but it was drafted in another era<br />

and not intended for application in the remedial and transformative<br />

context <strong>of</strong> s 25, and therefore the Act must be read through the<br />

corrective lens <strong>of</strong> s 39(2). SANDU and Bato Star should apply to the<br />

1975 Act, but in applying it the courts must keep in mind that it<br />

embodies the policies <strong>of</strong> another time and a different government and<br />

therefore it requires conscious and comprehensive re-interpretation<br />

to ensure that it gives effect to current constitutional rights and<br />

values. The majoritarian consideration that justifies SANDU, namely<br />

that the legislature’s role in the transformation process must be<br />

respected and that it must be given full effect, applies only indirectly<br />

to pre-constitutional legislation: it can only be assumed to embody<br />

the legislature’s effort to give effect to constitutional rights in so far<br />

as it allows constitution-promoting interpretation according to<br />

s 39(2), but there is always the possibility that parts <strong>of</strong> the old<br />

legislation still reflect the policies <strong>of</strong> a disgraced pre-constitutional<br />

legislature and then a constitutional challenge might be required. Up<br />

to that point, the subsidiarity principles apply in the form <strong>of</strong> the<br />

obligation to read the legislation in conformity with the Constitution,<br />

as s 39(2) requires.<br />

4.5 Competing and complementary legislation<br />

A further problem created by flexible application <strong>of</strong> SANDU and Bato<br />

Star is that several pieces <strong>of</strong> legislation, including supposedly<br />

codifying legislation like PAJA and the LRA and partial, even preconstitutional<br />

legislation, sometimes apply to the same dispute<br />

simultaneously. 154 If more than one statute compete with or<br />

complement each other, the subsidiarity principle should be that<br />

competing or complementary legislation must be applied to optimally<br />

give effect to the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and to promote the spirit, purport and<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill. 155 As a starting point this will require purposive<br />

interpretation that aligns all the applicable laws with the<br />

154 Eg SANDU (n 104 above); Sidumo (n 104 above); Chirwa (n 104 above); Fuel<br />

Retailers (n 25 above).<br />

155 In Nakin v MEC, Department <strong>of</strong> Education, Eastern Cape Province 2008 2 All SA<br />

599 (EC) paras 49-51 Froneman J argues that courts should not be forced to<br />

‘compartmentalise’, by conceptual exclusion, the possibilities for adjudicating<br />

labour disputes, namely common law <strong>of</strong> contract, labour relations and<br />

administrative justice, since a conceptual selection between the alternatives<br />

could rob the applicant <strong>of</strong> an effective remedy because the route selected (e g<br />

PAJA) might not <strong>of</strong>fer the remedy (e g payment <strong>of</strong> money) the applicant asks for.<br />

If this suggests that SANDU / Bato Star should not apply and that litigants (or the<br />

courts) should have a free choice, it conflicts with normative arguments in favour<br />

<strong>of</strong> subsidiarity. However, in so far as it points out that a meaningful remedy is<br />

important the problem could be overcome by applying subsidiarity (e g PAJA<br />

applies) but then, if PAJA does not <strong>of</strong>fer a remedy, cascade the issue on remedy<br />

down the subsidiarity hierarchy, ie by either reverting to the common law, if that<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers a suitable remedy, or to constitutional review, possibly opening up space<br />

for reading in a remedy.


112 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

constitutional scheme. Some remaining problems could be solved by<br />

focusing on the separate fields <strong>of</strong> application <strong>of</strong> each law 156 or by<br />

identifying their position in a subsidiarity grid. It has, for example,<br />

been proposed that PAJA embodies general administrative law while<br />

other statutes grant particular administrative powers, thus indicating<br />

their relative status: the LRA is particular legislation with regard to<br />

labour disputes and therefore its provisions with regard to<br />

administrative action supersede but are ‘suffused’ by the general<br />

reasonableness principles <strong>of</strong> PAJA, which is general legislation. 157 A<br />

similar hierarchical relationship was construed between NEMA and the<br />

Environment Conservation Act 73 <strong>of</strong> 1989. 158<br />

When legislation limits one right in the process <strong>of</strong> giving effect to<br />

another, the affected person can protect her right with a direct<br />

attack on the constitutional validity <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>fending legislation;<br />

SANDU allows a direct appeal to the constitutional provision. When<br />

constitutional rights provisions come into conflict, the Constitutional<br />

Court supports an optimising interpretation strategy. 159 In other cases<br />

s 39(2) requires the courts to select the interpretation that avoids the<br />

conflict or promotes the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. In these cases there does not seem to be a reason to depart<br />

from the subsidiarity principle that protection <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right<br />

should primarily be based on legislation giving effect to that right and<br />

not on the constitutional right itself or on the common law, except in<br />

so far as the constitutional validity <strong>of</strong> the legislation or the common<br />

law is attacked (in which case the constitutional provision applies<br />

directly) or in so far as the legislation does not cover the field (in<br />

which case a direct appeal to the Constitution or the common law<br />

could be possible).<br />

Several decisions from the 2007 term concerned regulatory<br />

legislation that limits a constitutional right, without the legislation<br />

being intended to give effect to that or any other right. Mohunram 160<br />

is the latest decision 161 in which the proportionality <strong>of</strong> civil forfeiture<br />

<strong>of</strong> instrumentalities <strong>of</strong> crime in terms <strong>of</strong> the Prevention <strong>of</strong> Organised<br />

Crime Act 121 <strong>of</strong> 1998 (POCA) was contested, without attacking the<br />

156 Land reform laws enacted under s 25(6) to improve security <strong>of</strong> tenure, e g the<br />

Land Reform (Labour Tenants) Act 3 <strong>of</strong> 1996, the Extension <strong>of</strong> Security <strong>of</strong> Tenure<br />

Act 62 <strong>of</strong> 1997 and the Rental Housing Act 50 <strong>of</strong> 1999, each has its own field <strong>of</strong><br />

application.<br />

157 Chirwa (n 104 above) par 23 confirmed Bato Star (n 63 above) paras 59, 149; I<br />

Currie & J Klaaren The Promotion <strong>of</strong> Administrative Justice Act benchbook (2001)<br />

par 1.24; Currie & de Waal (n 30 above) 643 fn 4. Sidumo (n 104 above) paras 104,<br />

110 states that the LRA is suffused by the constitutional reasonableness principle<br />

but in fact reads it via PAJA.<br />

158 HTF Developers (n 104) par 24; Fuel Retailers (n 25).<br />

159 See eg Christian Education (n 33 above) par 42.<br />

160 Mohunram v National Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions (Law Review Project as<br />

Amicus Curiae) 2007 4 SA 222 (CC).<br />

161 See Prophet v National Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions 2007 6 SA 169 (CC).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 113<br />

constitutional validity <strong>of</strong> the Act. It has been accepted that civil<br />

forfeiture (particularly beyond the ambit <strong>of</strong> organised crime) could<br />

result in disproportionate and arbitrary deprivation <strong>of</strong> property;<br />

hence the Constitutional Court devised a definition <strong>of</strong> instrumentalities<br />

<strong>of</strong> crime 162 and a proportionality test to determine whether<br />

forfeiture is justified. 163 Both tests are aligned with the nonarbitrariness<br />

test in FNB 164 to ensure that civil forfeiture orders under<br />

POCA would not <strong>of</strong>fend the protection <strong>of</strong> property against arbitrary<br />

deprivation in s 25(1). The proportionality test employed in these<br />

cases to interpret the legislation in a constitution-complying way<br />

confirms SANDU.<br />

In two other forfeiture cases, Armbruster 165 and Van der<br />

Merwe, 166 the facts were similar — the affected persons had large<br />

sums <strong>of</strong> foreign currency in their possession when boarding an<br />

international flight; the currency was seized by customs <strong>of</strong>ficials and<br />

declared forfeit; the affected persons attempted to reclaim the<br />

money. In Armbruster the applicant launched a constitutional attack<br />

against the regulations with an appeal to s 34; in Van der Merwe he<br />

appealed to the common law. SANDU allows a direct appeal to a<br />

constitutional provision in an attack on the validity <strong>of</strong> legislation, but<br />

according to Bato Star a direct appeal to a common law remedy<br />

should only be available if legislation does not ‘cover’ that particular<br />

aspect and the common law is capable <strong>of</strong> interpretation that conforms<br />

with the Constitution and complements the legislation.<br />

In Armbruster the Constitutional Court held that the connection<br />

between the purpose <strong>of</strong> the forfeiture, the property and the person<br />

deprived ‘could hardly be closer’; that there is sufficient reason for<br />

the deprivation and that forfeiture would not be arbitrary. 167<br />

Forfeiture could produce ‘arbitrarily harsh consequences’ but the<br />

162 Prophet (n 161 above) was applied in Mohunram (n 160 above) par 44:<br />

instrumentalities had to be given a wide meaning, but the property must play a<br />

reasonably direct role in commission <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>fence. This test is based on the nonarbitrariness<br />

standard in First National Bank <strong>of</strong> SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v<br />

Commissioner, South African Revenue Service; First National Bank <strong>of</strong> SA Ltd t/a<br />

Wesbank v Minister <strong>of</strong> Finance 2002 4 SA 768 (CC) paras 51, 100.<br />

163 Prophet (n 161 above) par 65; Mohunram (n 160 above) paras 64, 145-147. In<br />

Mohunram the majority decided that the forfeiture would be disproportionate<br />

because part <strong>of</strong> the immovable property was used for legal purposes and because<br />

the owner had already been prosecuted, convicted and fined.<br />

164 The non-arbitrariness standard was set out in First National Bank (n 162 above)<br />

paras 51, 100.<br />

165 Armbruster v Minister <strong>of</strong> Finance 2007 6 SA 550 (CC). The Treasury declared the<br />

foreign currency forfeit in terms <strong>of</strong> the Exchange Control Regulations under s 9 <strong>of</strong><br />

the Currency and Exchanges Act 9 <strong>of</strong> 1933.<br />

166 Van der Merwe v Inspector Taylor 2008 1 SA 1 (CC). Various grounds were raised,<br />

ranging from the Criminal Procedure Act 51 <strong>of</strong> 1977 to the Income Tax Act 58 <strong>of</strong><br />

1962; before the CC consensus was that the seizure was authorised by s 20 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Criminal Procedure Act.<br />

167 Armbruster (n 165 above) par 71. The nexus remarks are inspired by First<br />

National Bank (n 162 above) paras 51, 100.


114 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

regulations grant an opportunity for representations and a discretion<br />

to return the currency ‘to ameliorate undue hardship or injustice that<br />

might be perpetrated on the person affected’; therefore the<br />

regulations do not allow for arbitrary deprivation. 168 The Court also<br />

rejected the attack based on s 34, pointing out that the reasons why<br />

legislation was struck down in Zondi and Chief Lesapo, namely a<br />

particular historical and social context and complete lack <strong>of</strong> judicial<br />

control, were absent in this case. 169<br />

In Van der Merwe, the applicant elected to claim the money on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the common law rei vindicatio, arguing that foreign<br />

currency bought with funds from his banking account was his<br />

property. The High Court decided that some <strong>of</strong> the currency did not<br />

belong to him because he held it for someone else. The Constitutional<br />

Court was divided; the majority held that he proved ownership <strong>of</strong> the<br />

amount bought and held for himself, but O’Regan J would have<br />

dismissed leave to appeal because the issues have not been properly<br />

ventilated. 170 One has to agree that the Court had not seen enough<br />

evidence or heard enough argument on whether the rei vindicatio is<br />

at all feasible when cash is reclaimed; 171 when ownership vests in<br />

cash withdrawn from a bank; and whether the applicant’s state <strong>of</strong><br />

mind with regard to ownership <strong>of</strong> currency could have had any effect.<br />

In terms <strong>of</strong> Bato Star the primary question in Van der Merwe should<br />

have been whether reclamation <strong>of</strong> the money was regulated by the<br />

authorising legislation — if it was, a direct appeal to the common law<br />

remedy should have been precluded.<br />

When there is no legislation to trigger SANDU or Bato Star, the tug<br />

<strong>of</strong> war between the Constitution and the common law is most intense.<br />

The question is then whether the civil courts should be allowed to<br />

withdraw into the comfort zone <strong>of</strong> the common law, where the reach<br />

<strong>of</strong> democratic reform is weak and where the influence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution could be reduced to that <strong>of</strong> an ally in entrenching vested<br />

rights, privilege and power against democratic interference. The most<br />

difficult issues <strong>of</strong> application feature in this area, with the focus<br />

ultimately on the question whether (and how far) the independence<br />

<strong>of</strong> private law is affected by the supremacy <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.<br />

168 Armbruster (n 165 above) par 80, relying on Dawood v Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs;<br />

Shalabi v Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs 2000 3 SA<br />

936 (CC) para 53.<br />

169 Armbruster (n 165 above) paras 59-60, referring to Chief Lesapo v North West<br />

Agricultural Bank 2000 1 SA 409 (CC), Zondi (n 112 above), Metcash Trading Ltd v<br />

Commissioner, South African Revenue Service 2001 1 SA 1109 (CC).<br />

170 Van der Merwe (n 166 above) par 103.<br />

171 Woodhead Plant & Co v Gunn (1894) 11 SC 4: the currency status <strong>of</strong> money is<br />

incompatible with the right <strong>of</strong> anyone to follow stolen money into the hands <strong>of</strong> an<br />

honest receiver for value, whether it had been mixed up with other money or not.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 115<br />

5 Constitutional supremacy vs independence <strong>of</strong><br />

private law 172<br />

Mir scheint es sich [bei der Konzeption einer ‘Grundrechtsfreiheit des<br />

Privatrechts’] um eine Art Münchhausentheorem zu handeln, das den<br />

Privatrechtlern die Möglichkeit verschaffen soll, sich am eigenen Schopf<br />

aus dem Sumpf des Verfassungsrechts herauszuziehen. 173<br />

5.1 SANDU and Bato Star in the absence <strong>of</strong> legislation<br />

When no legislation applies to the protection <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right,<br />

the logic <strong>of</strong> the SANDU subsidiarity principle would imply that a<br />

litigant who wants to protect that right must rely on the common law<br />

and may not rely directly on the constitutional right, unless she<br />

challenges the constitutional validity <strong>of</strong> the common law. Mhlungu<br />

and Zantsi were no doubt intended to justify exactly such a<br />

subsidiarity principle to prevent every private quarrel being blown up<br />

into a constitutional issue when it could be dealt with in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

common law. In terms <strong>of</strong> s 39(2), the obligation to have first resort to<br />

the common law includes development <strong>of</strong> the common law to align it<br />

with the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. However,<br />

once it is clear that the constitutional right cannot be given effect to,<br />

according to the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, by<br />

either application or development <strong>of</strong> the common law a litigant can<br />

resort directly to the constitutional provision, 174 either to launch a<br />

constitutional attack against a rule or institution <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

that limits or is in conflict with the constitutional right 175 or to craft<br />

a special constitutional remedy. 176<br />

It can be argued that the legislature, in so far as it leaves the<br />

common law unamended by legislation, accepts that the common<br />

law, for the moment being, sufficiently gives effect (or can be<br />

developed to give effect) to the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights — if the<br />

legislature is dissatisfied with the common law it can change it. Out<br />

<strong>of</strong> respect for the legislature’s democratic role, protection <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional rights should, therefore, in the absence <strong>of</strong> legislation<br />

begin with the common law — a direct appeal to the Constitution<br />

should be reserved for cases where it is impossible to interpret the<br />

common law in a constitution-compliant way. This is possibly what<br />

172 Based on the title <strong>of</strong> M Ruffert Vorrang der Verfassung und Eigenständigkeit des<br />

Privatrechts (2001). I am indebted to Friedrich Schoch for bringing it to my<br />

attention and to him and Michael Sachs for explaining German theory to me.<br />

173 CW Canaris Grundrechte und Privatrecht (1999) 18.<br />

174 Masiya (n 88 above) par 27.<br />

175 The CC declared the common law crime <strong>of</strong> sodomy unconstitutional: Gay and<br />

Lesbian (n 28 above).<br />

176 In line with s 172.


116 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

inspired the unfortunately phrased remark that the common law<br />

should be allowed to develop incrementally so as not to interfere with<br />

legislative authority. 177<br />

The justification for this residuarity principle is similar to that <strong>of</strong><br />

SANDU: if litigants are allowed to choose freely between<br />

constitutional provisions and common law remedies as if they were<br />

independent, parallel systems <strong>of</strong> law, the common law will never be<br />

‘brought into’ the new constitutional dispensation. This is what<br />

happened in Tswelopele: 178 crafting a constitutional remedy and<br />

leaving the common law ‘untouched’ created two parallel remedies<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> developing the common law in line with constitutional<br />

values. The goal <strong>of</strong> ensuring one system <strong>of</strong> law under the guidance <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitution is promoted not only by preventing the common law<br />

to develop as a parallel system (Bato Star), but also by preventing<br />

development <strong>of</strong> a parallel system <strong>of</strong> unnecessary constitutional<br />

remedies. Leaving some aspect <strong>of</strong> the common law intact and crafting<br />

a new constitutional remedy should be justifiable only on<br />

constitutional grounds.<br />

In was argued in the previous section that SANDU and Bato Star<br />

apply to legislation regardless <strong>of</strong> horizontality; 179 the same should<br />

hold in the absence <strong>of</strong> legislation. Direct application and development<br />

<strong>of</strong> the common law are broader than and should not be confused with<br />

or collapsed into horizontal application; the former two will come up<br />

in vertical and horizontal relationships. 180<br />

5.2 Direct vs indirect application<br />

The most intractable question when no legislation exists is whether<br />

the constitutional provisions apply directly or whether they should be<br />

mediated through the common law. This issue came up in three 2007<br />

decisions.<br />

177 Zantsi (n 71 above) par 5; Masiya (n 88 above) par 31. Roux (n 46 above) 487<br />

notes, with reference to RG Teitel Transitional justice (2000) 24, that judges may<br />

have to do more work in transitional or transforming societies and leave less for<br />

the legislature.<br />

178 Tswelopele (n 149 above).<br />

179 The principle finds support in s 8(3)(a), which applies particularly to horizontal<br />

relationships: in applying the provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to natural and juristic<br />

persons in terms <strong>of</strong> subs 8(2) a court, ‘in order to give effect to a right in the Bill,<br />

must apply, or where necessary, develop, the common law to the extent that<br />

legislation does not give effect to that rights’ (emphasis added). I pay no direct<br />

attention to development <strong>of</strong> the customary law because none <strong>of</strong> the 2007<br />

decisions dealt with it.<br />

180 Tswelopele (n 149 above); Masiya (n 88 above).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 117<br />

In Masiya 181 the question was whether the common law definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> rape should be developed to include anal penetration. 182 The<br />

Constitutional Court decided that the common law definition was not<br />

unconstitutional because it criminalised morally and socially<br />

unacceptable behaviour. However, the definition fell short <strong>of</strong> the<br />

spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and had to be<br />

expanded. 183 The Court distinguished between its roles in testing<br />

whether legislation is consistent with the Constitution and developing<br />

the common law, adding that the courts should not ‘appropriate the<br />

Legislature’s role in law reform’ by developing the common law in a<br />

way ‘closer to codification than incremental, fact-driven<br />

development’. 184 This supports the subsidiarity principle that direct<br />

application (validity challenge) should only follow once it is clear that<br />

the common law cannot be developed appropriately. Accordingly, the<br />

case was decided as an opportunity to develop the common law rather<br />

than a constitutional validity challenge. The majority decided to<br />

develop the common law only as required by the facts <strong>of</strong> this case, to<br />

include non-consensual anal penetration <strong>of</strong> a female, 185 but in a<br />

dissenting judgment Langa CJ opined that the development should<br />

have included anal rape <strong>of</strong> men. 186<br />

Woolman 187 criticises Masiya because it ‘never truly considers the<br />

direct application <strong>of</strong> the substantive provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to<br />

the challenged common-law definition <strong>of</strong> rape’; instead, the ‘entire<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> the common-law rule takes place within the rubric <strong>of</strong> s<br />

39(2) and in terms <strong>of</strong> indirect application.’ Woolman argues that, in<br />

181 n 88 above.<br />

182 The regional court decided that the common law definition was underinclusive<br />

and extended it to non-consensual anal penetration <strong>of</strong> any person, but it did not<br />

have the power to develop the common law: Masiya (n 88 above) par 66.<br />

Magistrates’ courts are prevented from pronouncing on the validity <strong>of</strong> any law: s<br />

110 <strong>of</strong> the Magistrates’ Courts Act 32 <strong>of</strong> 1944. The High Court endorsed the a quo<br />

decision and it came before the CC for confirmation under s 172(2)(a).<br />

183 Masiya (n 88 above) paras 27, 32, 70. Masiya paras 66, 69 underlines the point<br />

that s 39(2) has a restricted purpose: the power to develop the common law is<br />

granted to the CC, the SCA and the High Courts by s 173 and not in s 39(2), which<br />

merely instructs the courts, when developing the common law or customary law,<br />

to do it so as to promote the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights — the<br />

section concerns the how <strong>of</strong> constitutional development <strong>of</strong> the common law but<br />

not the when. For similar reasons, s 8(3) should not be seen as the authorising<br />

provision for a general obligation or power to develop the common law either;<br />

the subsection pertains to cases <strong>of</strong> horizontal application, as is evident from the<br />

introductory phrase ‘[i]n applying the provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights to natural<br />

and juristic persons in terms <strong>of</strong> subsection (2), ...’ (emphasis added). In spelling<br />

out the direction <strong>of</strong> development s 39(2) indicates when the common law might<br />

require development, but it is not the authorising provision.<br />

184 Masiya (n 88) par 31.<br />

185 Masiya (n 88) par 45.<br />

186 Masiya (n 88) par 75. Sachs J concurred in the dissenting judgment.<br />

187 n 89 above, 768.


118 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

view <strong>of</strong> the language <strong>of</strong> ss 8(1) 188 and the decision in Khumalo, 189 the<br />

substantive provisions in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights should have been applied<br />

directly instead <strong>of</strong> via the development <strong>of</strong> the common law. The point<br />

in which Woolman differs from Masiya is not easily identifiable; his<br />

statement that direct application ‘takes the rights and freedoms, and<br />

the general rules derived from them, as our point <strong>of</strong> departure for<br />

determining whether law or conduct is invalid’ echoes the SANDU<br />

principle almost exactly, 190 as does his view that indirect application<br />

(protection <strong>of</strong> the right) does not permit a finding <strong>of</strong> invalidity. 191 The<br />

problem is that he describes indirect application as ‘a mode <strong>of</strong><br />

analysis that neither specifies whether a particular right demands<br />

vindication nor permits a finding <strong>of</strong> invalidity.’ 192 Woolman’s view<br />

that indirect application does not tell us whether the right requires<br />

vindication is based on the narrow assumption that vindication <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional rights primarily takes place via direct application. In<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> SANDU logic, constitutional rights can also be vindicated<br />

indirectly, via constitution-compliant interpretation <strong>of</strong> the common<br />

law. According to Masiya, indirect protection should precede direct<br />

constitutional challenges as a matter <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity, out <strong>of</strong> respect<br />

for democratic processes, while SANDU declares direct appeals to the<br />

constitutional provisions impermissible when protection <strong>of</strong> the right is<br />

in issue. 193<br />

Woolman therefore differs from the principle laid down in SANDU<br />

in that he claims the major part <strong>of</strong> constitutional litigation for direct<br />

application and assigns indirect application to a vague and apparently<br />

insignificant area <strong>of</strong> ‘law and conduct not engaged by any <strong>of</strong> the<br />

specific provisions set out in Chapter 2’, ensuring that this part <strong>of</strong> all<br />

law is also brought ‘into line with the “spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong><br />

188<br />

Although s 8(1) provides that the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights applies to all law and that it binds<br />

the legislature, the executive, the judiciary and all organs <strong>of</strong> state, it does not<br />

say that the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights applies directly or horizontally to all law. See to much<br />

the same effect Khumalo (n 73 above) paras 31-33. Woolman (n 45 above) 44<br />

disagrees, arguing that s 8(1) alone makes all law subject to the direct<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.<br />

189<br />

In Khumalo (n 73 above) the CC indicated that direct application was possible<br />

under the 1996 Constitution.<br />

190 Woolman (n 89 above) 769. As far as legislative, executive and judicial conduct is<br />

concerned Woolman reflects the approach <strong>of</strong> the courts: these forms <strong>of</strong> conduct<br />

are excluded from PAJA by the definition <strong>of</strong> ‘administrative action’ but review is<br />

possible on the basis <strong>of</strong> legality: n 136 above. However, as far as conduct by<br />

organs <strong>of</strong> state generally is concerned, at least some <strong>of</strong> it is administrative action<br />

covered by PAJA, in which case Woolman’s formulation does not reflect SANDU in<br />

that review <strong>of</strong> this conduct takes place via PAJA and not directly.<br />

191<br />

All law, including legislation and the common law, should only be declared<br />

unconstitutional once it has been established that it is impossible to find a<br />

constitutionally consistent interpretation: Masiya (n 88 above) par 27. However,<br />

rules <strong>of</strong> the common law can be declared unconstitutional when it is impossible to<br />

interpret or develop it according to values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution: Gay and Lesbian (n<br />

28 above).<br />

192<br />

Woolman (n 89 above) 769 (emphasis added).<br />

193 The legality principle case law is explained by this formulation; n 136.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 119<br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights” and the “objective, normative value system” made<br />

manifest in the text <strong>of</strong> the Constitution as a whole’. 194 By contrast,<br />

the residuarity principles establish a rational link between direct<br />

application and constitutional remedies or validity challenges on the<br />

one hand and indirect application and protective litigation on the<br />

other. As was argued earlier, this link is justifiable in view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

normative roles it assigns to democratic processes and judicial review<br />

respectively. Moreover, it makes sense if considered from the<br />

perspective <strong>of</strong> remedies: direct application is aimed at reviewing the<br />

constitutional validity <strong>of</strong> legislation or the common law and will at<br />

least sometimes result in declarations <strong>of</strong> invalidity, which might not<br />

be what a litigant was after when seeking to protect her right. In some<br />

cases direct application can admittedly produce a special<br />

constitutional remedy and therefore the subsidiarity principles keep<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> direct application open for that purpose, but based<br />

on the respect-for-democracy norm the subsidiarity approach<br />

restricts this to a last resort solution rather than an open option that<br />

exists parallel to statutory or common law protection.<br />

By shifting the focus from constitutional validity challenge to<br />

protective litigation, where the point is to develop the common law<br />

in line with s 39(2), Masiya is consistent with SANDU. The<br />

Constitutional Court decided that the correct approach was to expand<br />

the common law definition by developing it in line with s 39(2), in this<br />

case to include at least non-consensual anal penetration <strong>of</strong><br />

females. 195 The minority decision shows that one can disagree with<br />

this narrow development <strong>of</strong> the definition and still agree that indirect<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law was the right approach. The<br />

cautious, restricted development undertaken by the majority cannot<br />

be blamed on their choice not to apply the constitutional provisions<br />

directly but to develop the common law; much rather, it results from<br />

earlier decisions in which it was said that the avoidance principle<br />

(subsidiarity) implies deciding just what is necessary for the facts <strong>of</strong><br />

the case and no more. 196 This is an exaggerated interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

subsidiarity and hardly defensible in view <strong>of</strong> constitutional provisions<br />

and decisions to the effect that all law is governed by the<br />

Constitution. The subsidiarity principle in Mhlungu and Zantsi could<br />

be read less restrictively (in view <strong>of</strong> SANDU) as saying that a court<br />

should not protect a constitutional right by way <strong>of</strong> a direct validity<br />

attack or by way <strong>of</strong> a direct constitutional remedy before considering<br />

whether the legislation or common law in question could be<br />

interpreted in a constitution-conforming and –confirming way.<br />

194 Woolman (n 89 above) 769.<br />

195 Masiya (n 88 above) par 27.<br />

196 Especially Zantsi (n 71 above) par 8.


120 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

Apart from an unnecessarily narrow view <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity or the<br />

avoidance principle, the Constitutional Court should also not have<br />

allowed itself to be pulled into common law talk about incremental<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law. Constitutional transformation will<br />

sometimes require large developments and changes. The warning in<br />

Mhlungu and Zantsi against undermining the separation <strong>of</strong> powers is<br />

important, but the subsidiarity principles in SANDU and Bato Star<br />

promote respect for the role <strong>of</strong> the legislature, without confusing that<br />

with respect for the common law logic <strong>of</strong> incremental development.<br />

Respect for democratic processes should not prevent the courts from<br />

rooting out remnants <strong>of</strong> tradition such as discrimination or inequality<br />

in conflict with the new constitutional dispensation; anal rape will be<br />

unconstitutional regardless <strong>of</strong> the sex or gender <strong>of</strong> the victim and<br />

hence the courts need not shy away from larger development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law out <strong>of</strong> respect for the legislature.<br />

The decision in NM 197 also turned on a choice whether to develop<br />

the common law; Woolman 198 again criticised it for failure to apply<br />

the constitutional provisions directly. The applicants claimed that the<br />

respondents had violated their rights to dignity and privacy by<br />

publishing their names and HIV status without permission. The case<br />

could support direct horizontal application <strong>of</strong> ss 10 and 14, but the<br />

applicants claimed on the basis <strong>of</strong> the common law actio iniuriarum<br />

and accordingly, in terms <strong>of</strong> residuarity, their claim must be<br />

considered on the basis <strong>of</strong> s 39(2) first. Initially, the question is<br />

therefore whether the common law provides a remedy as it stands<br />

and, if it doesn’t, whether it can be developed. The applicants<br />

brought the matter in the form <strong>of</strong> a constitutional case because they<br />

argued that the common law would have to be developed; the<br />

Constitutional Court decided that the case ‘involves a nuanced and<br />

sensitive approach to balancing the interests <strong>of</strong> the media, in<br />

advocating freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, privacy and dignity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

applicants irrespective <strong>of</strong> whether it is based on the constitutional<br />

law or the common law.’ 199 In other words, even though the claim is<br />

brought under the common law and the application and development<br />

<strong>of</strong> the common law are the main issues, balancing <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional rights raises a constitutional issue. This reflects the<br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> s 8(1) according to SANDU subsidiarity logic: the<br />

Constitution applies to all law, but not necessarily directly.<br />

The decision eventually turned on the majority’s factual finding<br />

that the respondents were aware that the applicants had not given<br />

permission for the publication <strong>of</strong> their names, followed by the legal<br />

decision that this was sufficient to establish intent for the actio<br />

197 n 87 above.<br />

198 n 89 above, 781-783.<br />

199 NM (n 87 above) par 31.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 121<br />

iniuriarum and that the requirements for the action were thus met.<br />

On the factual finding it was unnecessary to develop the common law.<br />

The minority, who disagreed with the majority’s factual finding,<br />

would nevertheless have developed the common law so that<br />

negligence could also satisfy the requirements. 200 In either case,<br />

direct application <strong>of</strong> the constitutional provisions remains uncalled<br />

for under the subsidiarity principles.<br />

Woolman 201 criticises Barkhuizen 202 for the same reason as<br />

Masiya and NM, namely that the Constitutional Court should have<br />

applied the constitutional provisions directly. Although it is difficult<br />

to tell whether Barkhuizen was decided in line with SANDU, the case<br />

was clearly brought as a direct constitutional challenge but not<br />

decided as one. The constitutional challenge was brought against a<br />

time-limitation clause in a short-term insurance contract; the<br />

applicant argued that the clause violated his s 34 right <strong>of</strong> access to<br />

court. The High Court upheld the claim but the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong><br />

Appeal dismissed it, arguing that the Constitution did not prevent<br />

time-limitation clauses in contracts entered into freely and<br />

voluntarily and that there was inadequate evidence in this case to<br />

indicate that the contract was not entered into freely and voluntarily.<br />

The Constitutional Court found that the 90 day time limitation was not<br />

manifestly unreasonable on the face <strong>of</strong> it, nor was it unfair, because<br />

there was no evidence that the contract was not concluded freely<br />

between parties in equal bargaining positions. Since the applicant did<br />

not furnish reasons for non-compliance it would not be unjust to<br />

enforce the time bar against him. 203<br />

Testing a contractual provision directly against a provision in the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights (s 34) amounts to horizontal application under s 8(2)-<br />

(3). 204 The Constitutional Court was uncomfortable with horizontal<br />

application, noting that the contractual time limitation reveals no law<br />

<strong>of</strong> general application. The Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal identified the<br />

underlying principle pacta sunt servanda as the law <strong>of</strong> general<br />

application, but the Constitutional Court dismissed this option,<br />

pointing out that the contractual term was challenged, not the<br />

general principle. 205 Enforcement <strong>of</strong> an allegedly unfair contractual<br />

term admittedly is not law <strong>of</strong> general application, but it is conduct<br />

that can be declared unconstitutional in terms <strong>of</strong> s 172(2). The fact<br />

200 NM (n 87) paras 44-47 57. Langa CJ and O’Regan J agreed that the journalist and<br />

publisher might have been negligent, but not that intent had been proved: paras<br />

111, 125. See Woolman (n 89) 781.<br />

201 n 89 above, 772-781.<br />

202 n 86 above.<br />

203 Barkhuizen (n 86 above) paras 63 66-67 84 86.<br />

204 Barkhuizen (n 86 above) par 23. It is untrue that the Court yet had to consider<br />

this issue: Khumalo (n 73 above).<br />

205 Barkhuizen (n 86 above) paras 24 26.


122 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

that conduct does not establish law <strong>of</strong> general application merely<br />

means that it cannot limit a constitutional right and cannot be saved<br />

by the general limitation clause, which is not surprising — the<br />

limitation clause is intended to give the state the opportunity to save<br />

otherwise unconstitutional law. However, conduct can infringe upon<br />

a right and can therefore be the focus <strong>of</strong> a constitutional validity<br />

attack. 206 It was therefore conceivable that this case could have been<br />

decided as a direct constitutional attack on allegedly unconstitutional<br />

private conduct. If the court should find, in such a case, that<br />

enforcement <strong>of</strong> the contract would indeed infringe s 34 or any other<br />

constitutional right, it would have to declare the conduct invalid. At<br />

the same time, private conduct that infringes a private right should,<br />

in most cases, be regulated by private law unless there is a<br />

constitutional reason for deciding the conflict on a constitutional<br />

basis.<br />

Barkhuizen could also have been decided purely on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

private law — time limitation clauses in private contracts are<br />

generally invalid if they are against public policy. The question is<br />

therefore whether there was a reason to decide the case on<br />

constitutional grounds. One such a reason could have been the desire<br />

to set a constitutional standard for contractual time limitation clauses<br />

that limit the right <strong>of</strong> access to courts. In that case the format <strong>of</strong> a<br />

direct constitutional attack on validity <strong>of</strong> the conduct would have<br />

been suitable. Another possibility could have been the need to<br />

develop the common law principle that gives credence to time<br />

limitation clauses, namely that contracts entered into freely between<br />

equal parties should be enforced — pacta sunt servanda. Such an<br />

approach would arguably have been justified if the Constitutional<br />

Court thought that the common law gave too much weight to the<br />

sanctity <strong>of</strong> contract principle and too little to justice, and that the<br />

common law should be developed in terms <strong>of</strong> s 39(2) to rectify the<br />

balance. However, this would have required the case to be<br />

transformed from a direct validity challenge to an indirect<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law protection case, as happened in NM<br />

and in Masiya. In the latter instance one would expect the court to<br />

test the relevant common law principle against central constitutional<br />

values and explain how it is to be amended in view <strong>of</strong> those values.<br />

In the event, the Constitutional Court did neither <strong>of</strong> the above,<br />

preferring to decide the case in another way altogether, namely to<br />

determine whether the contractual clause was contrary to the values<br />

underlying the constitutional democracy and contrary to public<br />

policy. 207 The Court pointed out that contractual terms denying<br />

206 Woolman (n 89 above) 774-775 makes much the same point.<br />

207 Barkhuizen (n 86 above) par 36.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 123<br />

access to the courts were contrary to public policy and therefore<br />

invalid in common law 208 — in principle, the time limitation clause<br />

could have been tested for fairness and validity purely on common law<br />

grounds, without any input from the Constitution. It then proceeded<br />

to analyse, in great detail but without much clarity, the relations<br />

between the substantive constitutional rights provisions such as s 34,<br />

the values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution and public policy. In effect, the<br />

Constitution and its underlying values are described as a source <strong>of</strong><br />

values that inform the public policy that plays a yardstick role in the<br />

common law. Woolman correctly describes this as deciding a direct<br />

constitutional challenge indirectly by ‘speaking in values’, 209 that is,<br />

not with reference to the relevant rights provisions in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights<br />

but mediated through a veil <strong>of</strong> values and policy vaguely infused by<br />

the substantive content <strong>of</strong> the constitutional provisions. In deciding<br />

the case this way, the Court did not set a constitutional standard for<br />

contractual time limitation clauses, but it also failed to either test or<br />

develop the underlying common law principle — in fact, the Court<br />

confirmed that the principle pacta sunt servanda ‘gives effect to the<br />

central constitutional values <strong>of</strong> freedom and dignity’, <strong>of</strong> which ‘selfautonomy,<br />

or the ability to regulate one’s own affairs, even to one’s<br />

own detriment’ is the very essence. 210 In other words, the Court not<br />

only implied that value analysis, rights analysis and policy analysis is<br />

the same thing 211 but also accepted that the central private-law<br />

principle pacta sunt servanda operates on the same level and enjoys<br />

the same status as constitutional values, without giving much<br />

indication how this should work out in the larger constitutional<br />

project.<br />

In a society torn apart by historical injustices and inequality,<br />

transformation under the aegis <strong>of</strong> a democratic and supreme<br />

Constitution means that the seemingly neutral but in fact highly<br />

contested principal tenets <strong>of</strong> private law, with pacta sunt servanda<br />

and absolute ownership top <strong>of</strong> the list, have to be treated with<br />

contextual sensitivity in the reconstruction <strong>of</strong> a new democratic legal<br />

order. By reducing concrete constitutional rights provisions to a veil<br />

<strong>of</strong> values that inform public policy, and by allowing private law<br />

principles like pacta sunt servanda to join those values in the shaping<br />

<strong>of</strong> public policy, the Constitutional Court might appear to subscribe to<br />

the highly problematic view, in decisions like Brisley 212 and Afrox, 213<br />

that there are no significant differences between constitutional and<br />

common law values and that the two systems could co-exist in a way<br />

208 Barkhuizen (n 86 above) par 34.<br />

209 n 89 above, 763.<br />

210 Barkhuizen (n 86 above) par 57.<br />

211 Woolman (n 89 above) 779.<br />

212 n 68 above. The critical comments <strong>of</strong> Roux (n 46 above) are highly relevant here.<br />

213 n 68 above.


124 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

that does not demand substantive changes <strong>of</strong> the common law.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> adapting the common law, it looks as if the constitutional<br />

values have been integrated into the common law.<br />

One could argue that this result is justifiable in view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> the principle involved, namely sanctity <strong>of</strong> contract, but<br />

even the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal is apparently not that set on pacta<br />

sunt servanda. In Linvestment 214 the Court overturned long-standing<br />

precedent and decided that the owner <strong>of</strong> a servient tenement can<br />

insist upon relocation <strong>of</strong> a defined and registered servitude <strong>of</strong> right <strong>of</strong><br />

way and that the dominant owner would be obliged to accept the<br />

relocation, against her will, if non-relocation would cause significant<br />

harm for the applicant and relocation would not cause significant<br />

harm for the respondent. The reasons for the decision and the result<br />

are justifiable on policy grounds, but it is puzzling that the Court<br />

would be so willing to make what is really a dramatic change to the<br />

common law on policy grounds, while being so unwilling, despite<br />

equally strong or stronger policy reasons, to change the common law<br />

very slightly in Tswelopele. Judging from Linvestment the best<br />

solution in Barkhuizen was the approach <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong><br />

Appeal, namely to focus on the general common law principle that<br />

supports enforcement <strong>of</strong> time limitations, pacta sunt servanda. Even<br />

when subjected to a healthy dose <strong>of</strong> constitutional skepticism, this<br />

principle embodies significant social and moral values and therefore<br />

it is highly unlikely that the courts would be willing to declare it<br />

unconstitutional just because it sometimes allows enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

unfair contracts. Instead, the approach in Masiya indicates that the<br />

courts would most likely, if this principle were challenged, attempt to<br />

rectify any shortcomings by developing it in view <strong>of</strong> s 39(2).<br />

Deciding Barkhuizen on this basis would have confirmed the<br />

subsidiarity approach that the Court seems to be developing, and it<br />

would have given a welcome indication that the Court is working<br />

towards a truly substantive, critical analysis <strong>of</strong> the common law in<br />

view <strong>of</strong> s 39(2). The point should not be whether the common law<br />

protects values like freedom and autonomy that are also important in<br />

constitutional law, but where and how common law principles need<br />

to be developed to give effect to the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. More concretely, it was necessary in Barkhuizen to ask<br />

where and how the principles <strong>of</strong> contract need to be developed to<br />

give effect to the right <strong>of</strong> access to the courts in s 34, given the<br />

historical and constitutional context within which inequalities in<br />

privilege and power developed and within which the right <strong>of</strong> access to<br />

courts was denied the poor and weak. It is in this context that the<br />

mere possibility that contractual time limitations could be unfair and<br />

214 Linvestment CC v Hammersley 2008 3 SA 283 (SCA).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 125<br />

against public policy in current private law doctrine might not pass<br />

constitutional muster — the test that was ultimately applied by the<br />

Constitutional Court majority in Barkhuizen is little more than the<br />

private law test and it lacks the critical sensitivity for context that<br />

one would expect <strong>of</strong> a full-on constitutional challenge. Moreover, as<br />

in NM, the Court’s analysis <strong>of</strong> the facts in Barkhuizen was<br />

disappointing; the factual analysis <strong>of</strong> Sachs J is a much better example<br />

<strong>of</strong> the kind <strong>of</strong> analysis that was required and that is to be expected.<br />

As it stands, Barkhuizen neither tested the parties’ conduct for<br />

constitutional validity, nor did it consider either development <strong>of</strong> or a<br />

challenge to the supporting common law principle; instead, common<br />

law principle was elevated to the sphere <strong>of</strong> constitutional values that<br />

indicate whether conduct is against public policy. In the broader<br />

context <strong>of</strong> the 2007 decisions, Barkhuizen looks like a constitutional<br />

non sequitur.<br />

6 Conclusions<br />

The subsidiarity principles set out in SANDU and Bato Star could,<br />

according to the analysis above, reasonably be expanded so as to<br />

include pre-1994 legislation, partial and competing legislation, and<br />

instances where no legislation is applicable at all. As has been argued<br />

in the sections above, the subsidiarity logic <strong>of</strong> these cases could be<br />

developed in a way that would make it possible simultaneously to<br />

promote constitutional reform goals and to respect democratic<br />

legislative interventions that reflect reformist or stabilising policies.<br />

Obviously the wider implications <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity have not been worked<br />

out by the courts and therefore the analysis above is purely<br />

speculative. Furthermore, the more comprehensively worked out<br />

subsidiarity logic set out in the previous sections is not presented as<br />

a proposal to develop or entrench a judicial doctrine <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity or<br />

deference — it is nothing more than an exercise in the logic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

SANDU and Bato Star decisions, and it is presented here purely in<br />

order to have an opportunity to test whether such a logic, if it were<br />

in fact adopted by the courts, would be justifiable in view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

broader normative and constitutional principles discussed in the first<br />

sections <strong>of</strong> the article.<br />

With the exception <strong>of</strong> Barkhuizen (and perhaps Sidumo), the<br />

Constitutional Court’s decisions in the 2007 term display a growing<br />

and reasonably consistent tendency to favour a particular subsidiarity<br />

approach, always present in our constitutional setup but apparently<br />

now emerging with increasing clarity, according to which direct<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the constitutional rights provisions is restricted to<br />

constitutional challenges against the validity <strong>of</strong> legislation. In the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> such a challenge, the Court prefers to treat cases for the


126 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

protection <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights as indirect application cases,<br />

involving either the interpretation <strong>of</strong> legislation or development <strong>of</strong><br />

the common law in terms <strong>of</strong> the constitution-compliance and<br />

—confirming prescriptions <strong>of</strong> s 39(2). By extension, taking into<br />

account earlier jurisprudence, direct application could also be<br />

possible in the absence <strong>of</strong> a direct validity challenge, if the goal is to<br />

craft a special constitutional remedy. However, again extrapolating<br />

from earlier jurisprudence, the subsidiarity approach indicates that<br />

direct application (to craft a constitutional remedy or to challenge a<br />

law) is considered only when indirect protection (interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

legislation or development <strong>of</strong> the common law) proves impossible for<br />

some reason. Furthermore, the subsidiarity hierarchy in the category<br />

<strong>of</strong> indirect protection cases prescribes that application and<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law should only be considered once and<br />

in so far as there is no legislation to apply.<br />

The subsidiarity approach <strong>of</strong> the 2007 cases <strong>of</strong>fers a fresh<br />

perspective on Mhlungu, according to which courts should, whenever<br />

possible, decide cases without reaching a constitutional issue. 215<br />

Woolman articulated five objections against the implication that the<br />

salutary ‘principle <strong>of</strong> avoidance’ — or subsidiarity — in Mhlungu should<br />

turn into a ‘full-blown doctrine in which a court must never<br />

“formulate a rule <strong>of</strong> constitutional law broader than is required by the<br />

precise facts to which it is to be applied”’; 216 some <strong>of</strong> these<br />

objections are relevant to my analysis. Firstly, a too narrow<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> the avoidance rule (as in Zantsi) contradicts the<br />

project that constitutional interpretation should evolve into a<br />

principled dialogue between the Constitutional court, other courts,<br />

the legal pr<strong>of</strong>ession, law schools, Parliament and, indirectly, the<br />

public at large. 217 In addition, a too narrow interpretation would<br />

undermine rational political discourse and the possibility <strong>of</strong> a<br />

coherent jurisprudence. These are convincing reasons why the<br />

subsidiarity principle should not be understood too narrowly, as it<br />

arguably was in at least Zantsi — it should not become a directive to<br />

avoid deciding constitutional issues per se. Subsidiarity should be<br />

understood in terms <strong>of</strong> its constitutional purpose and justification, as<br />

that has been spelled out in 2007: to preserve the constitutional<br />

power and obligation <strong>of</strong> the courts to control the constitutional<br />

validity <strong>of</strong> legislation, while at the same time paying due respect to<br />

the democratic power and legitimacy <strong>of</strong> policy makers and<br />

legislatures in giving effect to their reform obligations under the<br />

Constitution.<br />

215 n 71 above, par 59 (dissenting, Kentridge J); Zantsi (n 71 above) par 3.<br />

216 Woolman (n 89 above) 784-785, citing Zantsi (n 71 above) par 8.<br />

217 Mhlungu (n 71 above) par 129.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 127<br />

The purpose <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity can therefore not be pure avoidance.<br />

Much rather, it should be acknowledgement and respect for the fact<br />

that courts face the aporia <strong>of</strong> the countermajoritarian dilemma every<br />

time they hear a constitutional case. On the one hand they must<br />

respect and give full effect to the legitimate efforts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

democratically elected branches to honour their constitutional<br />

obligations in bringing about the reforms legitimised by the<br />

Constitution. Doing that requires the courts to consider the interplay<br />

between Constitution and legislation and to give the fullest possible<br />

purposive effect to legislation enacted by the legislature. At the same<br />

time the courts must apply pre-constitutional legislation and the<br />

common law in a way that acknowledges the undemocratic origin and<br />

history <strong>of</strong> those sources <strong>of</strong> law and the dilemmas caused by their<br />

continued validity, in both instances by reading them through the<br />

corrective lens <strong>of</strong> s 39(2). In addition to its obligations concerning the<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> legislation and development <strong>of</strong> the common law, the<br />

courts have the constitutional duty and power to control the<br />

legitimacy <strong>of</strong> new legislation made by democratically elected<br />

legislatures, testing it against Constitutional requirements and limits.<br />

The only way to juggle these tasks is to acknowledge, upfront, that<br />

these duties <strong>of</strong> the courts imply contradictory and conflicting<br />

normative values and that every decision sacrifices one for the sake<br />

<strong>of</strong> the other.<br />

In the introduction I identified the push for constitutional<br />

transformation and the preservative pull <strong>of</strong> the common law tradition<br />

as conflicting normative impulses. I pointed out that this instance <strong>of</strong><br />

normative pluralism differs from normative diversity as a positive<br />

constitutional value in that, in the case <strong>of</strong> the conflict between<br />

tradition and change, the complete picture is not enriched by the<br />

simultaneous presence <strong>of</strong> the more-than-one; these two impulses are<br />

locked in a zero-sum game for control over the balance between<br />

stability and reform. Either one wants and gets the upper hand at the<br />

direct cost <strong>of</strong> the other. Stability is attainable only at the cost <strong>of</strong><br />

reform; change is possible only by sacrificing certainty. You can’t do<br />

both. And yet, if you are a judge in the new South African<br />

constitutional order, you have to.<br />

Normative anarchy, always a threat in a situation like this, is only<br />

to be avoided, I argued in the introduction, by giving politics a<br />

chance, which starts with realising that all law is political, but politics<br />

cannot be enclosed in law. It proceeds with acknowledging that law<br />

does not resolve the aporia <strong>of</strong> stability and change; it merely<br />

sacrifices one for the other, for now. It requires making the sacrifice,<br />

as far as possible, with a view to open up rather than close down room<br />

for social deliberation and significant dissent. Obviously, any choice<br />

for an approach that would avoid anarchy could easily end up by<br />

entrenching reactionary formalism; in the face <strong>of</strong> uncertainty and


128 Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term<br />

anarchy it is only too easy to settle for the false security <strong>of</strong> shallow<br />

and cheap certainty.<br />

Giving effect to constitutional rights in a fragmented legal system<br />

consisting <strong>of</strong> legislation that was purposely enacted to protect and<br />

support those rights, legislation that pre-dates the political<br />

transformation and common law that was traditionally applied as if it<br />

embodied a-contextual neutral principles is a complex task. This task<br />

becomes more difficult when the courts are empowered both to<br />

protect constitutional rights and to control the constitutional validity<br />

and fittingness <strong>of</strong> all law, finding a justifiable balance between<br />

democratic will and constitutional legitimacy. Above all, the courts<br />

exercise this awesome responsibility as just one small part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

large project <strong>of</strong> social and political transformation, within a dynamic<br />

context that reflects both the ills <strong>of</strong> the past and the aspirations <strong>of</strong><br />

the future.<br />

The Constitutional Court appears to have chosen the analytic<br />

rhythm <strong>of</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity principles to direct the choices it must<br />

make in this arduous process; in 2007 it followed these principles with<br />

a measure <strong>of</strong> consistency and some sense <strong>of</strong> purpose and justification.<br />

Developing a subsidiarity approach to give effect to its contradictory<br />

and conflicting powers and responsibilities is dangerous because it<br />

could easily disintegrate into shallow formalism, but it also holds the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> evolving into a more reflective, democracy-confirming<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> the tension between the Constitution and existing law<br />

than has been evident from earlier judicial explorations into<br />

application issues. In that respect the direction <strong>of</strong> the pull <strong>of</strong> 2007<br />

must be welcomed.


1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

129<br />

LEGAL SUBSIDIARITY &<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS: A REPLY TO<br />

AJ VAN DER WALT<br />

* George J & Kathleen Waters Matthews Distinguished <strong>University</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, School<br />

<strong>of</strong> Law, Northeastern <strong>University</strong>, Boston (USA). Thanks to Lucy Williams and Sandra<br />

Liebenberg for comments and suggestions, and to André van der Walt for the<br />

friendship and the intellectual challenge.<br />

Karl Klare *<br />

The Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa is one <strong>of</strong> the most respected<br />

legal institutions in the world. Its work excites interest among lawyers<br />

and others far beyond South Africa’s borders who are inspired by the<br />

Constitution’s democratic and egalitarian aspirations. The<br />

Constitution 1 and the Court 2 are precious accomplishments in the<br />

human striving to discover and realise the institutional foundations <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom and self-determination. South Africans are guardians <strong>of</strong><br />

these achievements for all <strong>of</strong> the world’s people.<br />

It was therefore unnerving when inane and thuggish attacks were<br />

lobbed at the judiciary in the run-up to Nicholson J’s judgment in<br />

Zuma’s Case. 3 Prominent public figures branded the judiciary<br />

‘counter-revolutionaries’. Adolescent poseurs threatened to ‘kill’ for<br />

their heroes and ‘eliminate’ their enemies. The objects <strong>of</strong> these<br />

attacks included the Court’s great jurists such as Pius Langa CJ, who<br />

has devoted his lifetime to the cause <strong>of</strong> social justice under law, and<br />

Dikgang Moseneke DCJ, who at age 15 was the youngest political<br />

prisoner sent to Robben Island.<br />

1 ‘Constitution’ or ‘FC’ refers to the Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa,<br />

1996. (In the context <strong>of</strong> discussing US law, ‘Constitution’ is used in reference to<br />

the US Constitution.)<br />

2 The ‘Court’ (with an upper case ‘C’) or ‘the CC’ refers to the Constitutional<br />

Court. In the context <strong>of</strong> the concluding discussion <strong>of</strong> US law, ‘the Court’ refers, as<br />

is customary, to the United States Supreme Court. References to all other courts<br />

use a lower case ‘c’.<br />

3 Zuma v National Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions [2009] 1 All SA 54 (N) (setting<br />

aside decision to prosecute, reversed on appeal in National Director <strong>of</strong> Public<br />

Prosecutions v Zuma 2009 2 SA 277 (SCA)).


130 Reply to vd Walt<br />

In this fraught context, friends <strong>of</strong> the CC must avoid the<br />

temptation to rally around the Court by showering it with<br />

congratulatory platitudes. We best respect the Court by continuing as<br />

before to study its work meticulously and to provide the most rigorous<br />

and critical analysis <strong>of</strong> which we are capable. In that spirit, I have the<br />

honour, as a non-South African, to contribute this reply to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

van der Walt.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor van der Walt gifts us with a densely layered essay in<br />

which he tries to invent a new grammar for legal analysis. 4 He argues<br />

that we must become comfortable with gaps rather than seeking<br />

refuge in supposedly stable and all-inclusive rules because, first, this<br />

brings us closer to understanding what actually goes on in legal<br />

reasoning, and, second, because gaps open space for conversation,<br />

diversity, dissent, contestation, and judgment. That is, legal gaps<br />

open space for politics and the emergence <strong>of</strong> moral communities. Van<br />

der Walt believes, and I agree, that a legal discourse that embraces<br />

uncertainty and conflict fits better with a transformative constitution<br />

than arid syllogisms. Surely he is correct that South African jurists<br />

must work out new methods for addressing legal problems consonant<br />

with the Constitution’s transformative project. It is highly implausible<br />

that legal reasoning methods developed in earlier times, including<br />

apartheid times, are adequate for this task.<br />

It is important when reading van der Walt to appreciate that<br />

‘politics’ carries a positive valence. In the mainstream view,<br />

something has gone badly wrong when ‘politics’ enters legal decision<br />

making. By contrast, Van der Walt does not regard politics as an<br />

enemy <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law. A reception <strong>of</strong> politics into legal discourse<br />

can be a welcome contribution to democracy, 5 provided that (1)<br />

adjudicators acknowledge the discretion that permits and compels<br />

them to make value-laden (‘ideological’) choices in the routine course<br />

<strong>of</strong> their work, (2) they become deeply self-conscious, self-critical,<br />

and candid about the ‘inarticulate premises, culturally and<br />

historically ingrained’ 6 that inform their thinking and choices, and (3)<br />

4 AJ van der Walt ‘Normative pluralism and anarchy: Reflections on the 2007 term’<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 77.<br />

5<br />

From this perspective, the problem with the recent attacks on the judiciary is not<br />

that they were political. The problem is that they were uninformed, fatuous, and<br />

threatening, and they were aimed to achieve power for a particular political<br />

leader then facing serious criminal charges. In short, their purpose and their<br />

effect were to close down, rather than to open up, space for discussion and<br />

dissent.<br />

6<br />

Du Plessis v De Klerk 1996 3 SA 850 (CC), 1996 5 BCLR 658 (CC) para 119 (Kriegler<br />

J).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 131<br />

we understand law making processes as a conversation between<br />

adjudicators, the other branches, and the public. 7<br />

Van der Walt focuses on the proper relationship between three<br />

bodies or sources <strong>of</strong> law — the Constitution, legislation (pre- and post-<br />

1994), and the common law. He is concerned about the ‘preservative<br />

pull <strong>of</strong> the common law tradition’ in light <strong>of</strong> the common law’s<br />

‘undemocratic origin and history’. 8 He fears that the continued<br />

validity and prestige <strong>of</strong> the common law threaten to short-circuit the<br />

transformative project, and he wants to minimise that risk:<br />

An important premise <strong>of</strong> my argument is that the Constitution’s<br />

commitment to [political and ethical, as well as social] diversity as a<br />

positive value is premised upon the reduced authority <strong>of</strong> the common<br />

law. 9<br />

He warns that uncritical obeisance to common law thinking will<br />

immobilise the transformative project, and I could not agree more. 10<br />

2 From normative pluralism to legal subsidiarity<br />

In quick succession, van der Walt courses through a philosophical<br />

problem, a jurisprudential problem, and a question <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

interpretation. Subsidiarity comes in later as an instantiation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

approach van der Walt crafts to address more abstract considerations.<br />

The background philosophical problem is that modernism and postmodernism<br />

have undermined the foundations <strong>of</strong> epistemological<br />

fundamentalism: there is no knowledge-platform from which to<br />

identify trans-historical and trans-cultural (‘universal’) norms. The<br />

jurisprudential problem is that Legal Realism and Critical Legal<br />

Studies ‘destroyed the theoretical credibility <strong>of</strong> fundamentalism’ by<br />

demonstrating ‘the indeterminacy and contingency’ <strong>of</strong> legal norms. 11<br />

Superficially this would appear to leave lawyers with a choice<br />

between retreating to empty formalism, on the one hand; or, on the<br />

7 In this regard, see the comment <strong>of</strong> Sachs J in S v Mhlungu 1995 3 SA 897 (CC),<br />

1995 7 BCLR 793 (CC) para 129: ‘[T]he question <strong>of</strong> interpretation [is] one to which<br />

there can never be an absolute and definitive answer and ... in particular, the<br />

search <strong>of</strong> where to locate ourselves on the literal/purposive continuum or how to<br />

balance out competing provisions, will always take the form <strong>of</strong> a principled<br />

judicial dialogue, in the first place between members <strong>of</strong> this court, then between<br />

our court and other courts, the legal pr<strong>of</strong>ession, law schools, Parliament, and,<br />

indirectly, with the public at large’.<br />

8<br />

Van der Walt (n 4 above) 127.<br />

9 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 84 (footnote omitted).<br />

10 On this theme, see generally D Davis & K Klare, ‘Transformative constitutionalism<br />

and common and customary Law’ (forthcoming).<br />

11 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 79.


132 Reply to vd Walt<br />

other, sliding into normative anarchy (the idea that ‘anything<br />

goes’). 12<br />

Van der Walt refuses this binary, insisting that we can ‘recognis[e]<br />

that values are contingent and that everything is open for dissent and<br />

discussion, without implying that everything goes’. 13 He holds out for<br />

‘normative pluralism’ in the belief that rational discussion about<br />

values is possible and meaningful even in our post-modern condition.<br />

We must conceive legal practices and discourses as an opening to<br />

endless political debate and dissent. 14 This means that every legal<br />

decision involves a matter <strong>of</strong> judgment with a decisionist element. 15<br />

One value-set is chosen over and at the expense <strong>of</strong> others, but only<br />

‘for the time being’. All legal decisions are ‘provisional’ and may be<br />

qualified or superseded in the next case or next generation. Van der<br />

Walt craves ‘fundamentality without fundamentalism’, to use Morton<br />

Horwitz’s phrase. 16<br />

The constitutional problem is the built-in ‘tension between the<br />

push for constitutional reform and the pull <strong>of</strong> traditional stability’. 17<br />

Van der Walt’s ‘central premise’ 18 is that this tension reflects ‘a<br />

larger conflict between two opposing normative values or ideologies’:<br />

Those who think that the existing distribution <strong>of</strong> wealth, privilege and<br />

power and the law that helped create and uphold it are politically<br />

neutral and therefore not in need <strong>of</strong> political reconsideration favour a<br />

regime <strong>of</strong> rights in which the direct effect <strong>of</strong> the Constitution is<br />

preservation <strong>of</strong> the status quo; those who think that the existing regime<br />

and its laws are inherently politically constructed and hence in need <strong>of</strong><br />

political reconsideration favour the view that neither law nor rights are<br />

immune from constitutional effect or democratic redefinition ... 19<br />

How are jurists to negotiate the push and pull <strong>of</strong> these competing<br />

values without rejecting either in favour <strong>of</strong> the other — that is,<br />

12 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 103.<br />

13 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 84.<br />

14<br />

Van der Walt joins a growing number <strong>of</strong> commentators who think the time has<br />

come to replace the evocative and influential metaphor <strong>of</strong> the Constitution as a<br />

‘bridge’. See Interim Constitution, Postamble, ‘National unity and reconciliation’<br />

para 1 (‘[t]his Constitution provides a historic bridge ... ’); see also E Mureinik’s<br />

memorable ‘A bridge to where? <strong>Intro</strong>ducing the interim Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ 1994 (10)<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 31. A new metaphor is needed for the<br />

deliberative process launched by the Constitution, perhaps seeing it as an<br />

‘endless highway’.<br />

15 ‘Decisionist’ refers to Van der Walt’s insistence upon ‘the sacrificial nature’ <strong>of</strong><br />

legal decisions and their inability ever ‘to resolve social conflict with reference to<br />

a common will or purpose’ (Van der Walt (n 4 above) 6).<br />

16 M Horwitz ‘The Supreme Court 1992 term — Foreword — The constitution <strong>of</strong><br />

change: Legal fundamentality without fundamentalism’ (1993) 107 Harvard Law<br />

Review 32.<br />

17 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 88.<br />

18<br />

As above.<br />

19 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 89.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 133<br />

without retreating to a conservative formalism that sweeps the<br />

question under the rug, or to a moral anarchy that simply disregards<br />

it? The answer is to find an idiom <strong>of</strong> Constitutional adjudication that<br />

‘uphold[s] the tension’ 20 thereby ‘giving politics a chance’. 21 While<br />

no particular decision can be justified by reference to foundational<br />

principles, making decisions can be justified, provided that we are<br />

able to extract a direction-giving purpose from the Constitution. 22 A<br />

direction-giving purpose is not a ‘foundational principle’. It is a<br />

rudder to steer us between the Scylla <strong>of</strong> formalism and the Charybdis<br />

<strong>of</strong> anarchy.<br />

Borrowing in part from Frank Michelman, 23 van der Walt makes<br />

the crucial, albeit contestable, assumption that the Constitution does<br />

indeed provide a direction-giving purpose, viz, to ‘favour<br />

transformation’ — to renounce everything that the apartheid legal<br />

order stood for and to embrace the central transformative values <strong>of</strong><br />

human dignity, equality, freedom, social justice, democracy, and an<br />

open society, values which are the reverse <strong>of</strong> everything apartheid<br />

was. Constitutional analysis must ‘yield to the Constitution’s<br />

direction-giving (transformative) purpose’ while ‘holding open’ the<br />

tension between stability and transformation, between the law as it<br />

is and the law as it should be in the free society toward which South<br />

Africans are transitioning. 24<br />

At this point Van der Walt proposes subsidiarity theory as a<br />

transformation-oriented and closure-refusing approach to sorting out<br />

20 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 91.<br />

21 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 127. See also 105: ‘[L]aw ... in so far as it is inevitable,<br />

will only be justified to the extent that it promotes normative pluralism but does<br />

not descend into either anarchy or reactionary formalism. In allowing room for<br />

normative pluralism but simultaneously avoiding anarchy, it must give politics a<br />

chance by allowing for real social contention and dissent’.<br />

22 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 87.<br />

23 Michelman argues that constitutional supremacy means that all sites <strong>of</strong> legal<br />

practice and norm-creation must pull in the same direction, and that the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> constitutional supremacy is a value within the meaning <strong>of</strong> sec 1 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution (not just a trumping rule) when that direction is toward<br />

transformation <strong>of</strong> South African society in light <strong>of</strong> the ‘vision’ (such as it is)<br />

contained in the founding values (s 1) and elsewhere instinct in the Constitution.<br />

See ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law, legality and the supremacy <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) 11<br />

24<br />

- 36 — 11 - 38.<br />

Van der Walt (n 4 above) 82 - 90. I agree that, on its best reading, the<br />

Constitution contains the direction-giving purpose to ‘favour transformation’. But<br />

more work is needed on the content and historical provenance <strong>of</strong> the directiongiving<br />

purpose. As formulated by Van der Walt, the direction-giving purpose has<br />

greatest analytical power with respect to unravelling apartheid and abolishing its<br />

legal incidents. ‘Favour transformation’ provides less guidance with respect to<br />

the construction <strong>of</strong> the new society <strong>of</strong> democracy, freedom, and social justice.<br />

For example, what forms and degree <strong>of</strong> redistribution <strong>of</strong> social and political<br />

power and wealth does this ‘direction’ imply? Could a critic accept Van der Walt’s<br />

‘direction’ for purposes <strong>of</strong> discussion and yet plausibly claim that it is silent on<br />

such questions?


134 Reply to vd Walt<br />

the relationships between common law, legislation, and a<br />

transformative Constitution. Van der Walt’s subsidiarity refers to the<br />

hierarchy <strong>of</strong> sources <strong>of</strong> law — not, as in European law, to the hierarchy<br />

<strong>of</strong> decision making levels. 25 The core tenet is that courts should<br />

‘avoid[ ] a constitutional decision if the matter can be decided on a<br />

nonconstitutional basis’. 26 Van der Walt assumes that legislation<br />

embodies a forward-looking, transformative ‘pull’, whereas the<br />

common law tugs in a preservative direction. 27 Accordingly he seeks<br />

to prioritise legislation over the common law and to shield<br />

Parliament’s work from judicial encroachment. In this respect,<br />

subsidiarity restates a familiar norm <strong>of</strong> almost all modern, democratic<br />

legal systems that courts should defer to the legislature (except<br />

perhaps in special situations, for example, when the constitutional<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> politically excluded and subordinated groups are at stake). A<br />

second goal is to encourage courts to avoid any tendency to<br />

proliferate separate tracks or sub-systems <strong>of</strong> law such as, for<br />

example, parallel systems <strong>of</strong> remedies respectively grounded on the<br />

Constitution itself and on legislation or the common law.<br />

Van der Walt finds traces <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity thinking in the Court’s<br />

recent work, which appropriately balances stability and<br />

transformation. He ‘embroider[s] upon the logic <strong>of</strong> the subsidiarity<br />

principles that [he has] identified in [these] decisions’. 28 The<br />

provisional verdict is that the Court’s emerging subsidiarity perspective<br />

will permit normative pluralism to flourish by avoiding<br />

premature resolution <strong>of</strong> the stability/transformation tension. In van<br />

der Walt’s argot, the Court’s cases embrace aporia so as to give<br />

politics a chance on a continuing basis.<br />

25<br />

In EU law, ‘subsidiarity’ denotes a mandate for downward devolution <strong>of</strong> decision<br />

making to the lowest level at which a particular decision may appropriately be<br />

taken. The idea is to harvest local knowledge, facilitate public participation and<br />

empowerment, and respect local concerns. The principle was formally introduced<br />

into EU law by the Treaty <strong>of</strong> Maastricht (entered into force 1 November 1993).<br />

The present formulation is found in Article 5 <strong>of</strong> the Treaty Establishing the<br />

European Community (consolidated version following the Treaty <strong>of</strong> Nice (entered<br />

into force 1 February 2003)), which provides in relevant part: ‘In areas which do<br />

not fall within its exclusive competence, the Community shall take action, in<br />

accordance with the principle <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity, only if and in so far as the<br />

objectives <strong>of</strong> the proposed action cannot be sufficiently achieved by the Member<br />

States and can therefore, by reason <strong>of</strong> the scale or effects <strong>of</strong> the proposed<br />

action, be better achieved by the Community’. Strictly speaking, this type <strong>of</strong><br />

subsidiarity is not Van der Walt’s concern. At one point he mentions a precept<br />

that courts should refrain from taking a decision that can be taken by a lower<br />

court, but very little discussion is devoted to the hierarchy <strong>of</strong> courts.<br />

26 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 99 (footnote omitted). See also (95, 99, and 119 - 120)<br />

discussing S v Mhlungu 1995 3 SA 867 (CC), 7 BCLR 793 (CC) para 59 (giving rise to<br />

the principle, as somewhat reformulated by Van der Walt, that ‘a court should<br />

not protect a constitutional right by way <strong>of</strong> a direct validity attack or by way <strong>of</strong> a<br />

direct constitutional remedy before considering whether the legislation or<br />

common law in question could be interpreted in a constitution-conforming and<br />

-confirming way’) (n 4 above) 119.<br />

27<br />

Van der Walt (n 4 above) 104 - 106.<br />

28 Van der Walt (n 4 above) 105.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 135<br />

The orchestration might differ, but my thinking is largely in tune<br />

with van der Walt’s philosophy and jurisprudence. My misgivings<br />

concern his concluding discussion <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity. I am not persuaded<br />

that subsidiarity theory can perform the functions van der Walt asks<br />

<strong>of</strong> it or that it is a reliable starting point for developing the<br />

transformative constitutional methodology he seeks.<br />

3 Subsidiarity through a critical lens<br />

3.1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

The raison d’être <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity principles is to strike an authoritative<br />

balance between the conflicting values <strong>of</strong> judicial deference and<br />

constitutional supremacy, so that courts are not at large weighing the<br />

conflict on an ad hoc, case-by-case basis. The central weakness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

theory is that, when called upon to resolve difficult cases, subsidiarity<br />

does little more than instruct courts to reopen the question and<br />

conduct the ad hoc balancing exercise it counselled them to avoid.<br />

Moreover, at least as presently formulated, subsidiarity imports<br />

conventional separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers discourse without rigorous critical<br />

examination; it relies upon the deceptively simple but underexamined<br />

and ambiguous notion <strong>of</strong> a statute ‘giving effect’ to a<br />

constitutional right; and, as a result, it tends to skew analysis in the<br />

direction <strong>of</strong> stability rather than transformation.<br />

3.2 Imports<br />

The subsidiarity approach is not a critical theory. Like most<br />

conventional discourse <strong>of</strong> separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers, subsidiarity rests on<br />

timeworn and reified conceptions <strong>of</strong> the various branches and organs<br />

<strong>of</strong> government and their inter-relationships. This imagery relies as<br />

much on wishful thinking as on evidence or analysis. Van der Walt<br />

knows this <strong>of</strong> course, but when he recruits subsidiarity to the cause <strong>of</strong><br />

transformation, he cannot shed all <strong>of</strong> its baggage. Because this is a<br />

general problem in legal theory, I simply register my objection pro<br />

forma and leave detailed examination <strong>of</strong> these issues to another day.<br />

The trite assumption is that the legislature is the democratic and<br />

representative branch, to which non-elected judges owe deference.<br />

We twist ourselves into knots trying to explain why and under what<br />

circumstances counter-majoritarian judicial review might be<br />

legitimate in a democratic society. Jurists spin out a catechism <strong>of</strong><br />

legal fictions and maxims from the simplistic notion <strong>of</strong> legislative


136 Reply to vd Walt<br />

primacy, which on occasion van der Walt incongruously deploys. 29 Van<br />

der Walt no doubt takes a critical view <strong>of</strong> all this, but the discourse is<br />

implicit in the subsidiarity theory he imports. He even goes a step<br />

farther, consistently portraying the legislature as the forwardlooking,<br />

progressive branch and a repository <strong>of</strong> transformative<br />

intentions and energy, whereas he treats the courts as necessarily<br />

backward-looking, reactionary, and obstructionist.<br />

These assumptions fall to be interrogated in the perspective <strong>of</strong><br />

transformative constitutionalism. They make a fine starting point for<br />

discussion but ought not substitute for investigation and analysis. We<br />

must move outside the standard frame <strong>of</strong> the ‘counter majoritarian’<br />

dilemma, 30 for at least two reasons.<br />

First, political institutions (parliaments, courts, agencies) do not<br />

have an intrinsic nature or an inherent leaning toward or against<br />

transformation. Whether, for example, the legislature is representative<br />

and/or plays a democratic, let alone a progressive, role are<br />

matters <strong>of</strong> contextual judgment on the historical record. ‘Process<br />

failures’ happen. 31 Legislatures have been known to ally with<br />

reaction, to be captured by wealthy interests, and/or to be so<br />

dominated by an entrenched oligarchy as to lose touch with the grass<br />

roots. I do not say any such thing has occurred in South Africa since<br />

1994, although Parliament’s lock-step ratification <strong>of</strong> the arms deal<br />

provides food for thought. 32 The point is simply that any separation<strong>of</strong>-powers<br />

theory worth having in the 21st century cannot assume<br />

that, but must inquire whether, legislatures as we find them actually<br />

function in service to the popular will.<br />

Second, it is much too late in the day to assume that judicial<br />

review <strong>of</strong> legislation under a supreme and rights-rich constitution is<br />

inherently anti-democratic. Yes, judicial review may derogate from<br />

majority rule. But at the same time, judicial enforcement <strong>of</strong> rights<br />

and other constitutional provisions can deepen and enhance<br />

29 For example, he cites the fiction that the legislature approves that portion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law which it has not amended by statute (Van der Walt (n 4 above) 115).<br />

30<br />

It is worth noting that Van der Walt makes this precise point in an illuminating,<br />

earlier essay. See AJ van der Walt ‘Transformative constitutionalism and the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> South African property law’ (part 1) 2005 (4) Tydskrif vir die<br />

Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 655 (contrasting the ‘counter majoritarian dilemma’ — the<br />

familiar problem <strong>of</strong> the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> judicial review <strong>of</strong> legislation — with a new,<br />

‘transformative dilemma’). The Constitution ‘created a new adjudicative<br />

dilemma <strong>of</strong> simultaneously upholding the supremacy <strong>of</strong> the new constitution and<br />

the integrity <strong>of</strong> a well-developed and established system <strong>of</strong> private law’ (657<br />

(footnote omitted)).<br />

31<br />

By analogy to the terms ‘market failure’ and ‘regulatory failure’, I use ‘process<br />

failure’ to refer to a systemic breakdown in the idealised relationships between<br />

branches <strong>of</strong> government.<br />

32<br />

See P Govender Love and Courage: A Story <strong>of</strong> Insubordination (2007) 197 - 205<br />

(former ANC parliamentarian’s account <strong>of</strong> process <strong>of</strong> voting on arms deal).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 137<br />

democracy by making legislative bodies more responsive, legislative<br />

processes more transparent, or elections more competitive, or by<br />

opening communication channels between the populace and<br />

government <strong>of</strong>ficials. The net result in context might be that the<br />

democracy-enlarging consequences <strong>of</strong> the court’s decision outweigh<br />

its counter-majoritarian form. Treatment Action Campaign 33 comes<br />

to mind as an example.<br />

Moreover, South Africa’s Constitution embodies a conception <strong>of</strong><br />

democracy that goes well beyond representation, elections, and<br />

majority rule. South African constitutional democracy contemplates<br />

not only robust political rights, but also that the resources and social<br />

circumstances necessary for meaningful political participation and<br />

authentic experiences <strong>of</strong> self-determination will gradually be<br />

extended to all South Africans. As Theunis Roux meticulously<br />

demonstrates:<br />

The principle <strong>of</strong> democracy in South African constitutional law is not<br />

that collective decisions shall be taken by majority vote, but something<br />

far deeper than this, including, at the very least, the notion that the<br />

people’s will may be trumped by individual rights where this serves the<br />

democratic values <strong>of</strong> ‘human dignity, equality and freedom’. 34<br />

Depending on what they do with their power, a more assertive role for<br />

courts than is contemplated by the conventional wisdom may be<br />

consistent with or possibly even required by democracy as envisioned<br />

by this Constitution. Recognising that judicial enforcement <strong>of</strong> the Bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rights can be democracy-enhancing disrupts traditional separation<strong>of</strong>-powers<br />

assumptions and calls for a re-examination <strong>of</strong> the old<br />

shibboleths. 35<br />

33 Minister <strong>of</strong> Health v Treatment Action Campaign (No 2) 2002 5 SA 721 (CC), 2002<br />

10 BCLR 1033 (CC).<br />

34 T Roux ‘Democracy’ in S Woolman et al eds (n 23 above) 10 - 66 (quoting FC sec<br />

7(1)).<br />

35 At one point, Van der Walt discards the conventional discursive framework and<br />

reverts to his accustomed, critical self. His insight is so powerful that it deserves<br />

separate mention. The CC and other courts, he says, conflate the common law<br />

insistence that courts restrict themselves to incremental development <strong>of</strong> the law<br />

with the separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers imperative that courts defer to the legislature. He<br />

convincingly argues that courts are perfectly capable <strong>of</strong> respecting the superior<br />

authority <strong>of</strong> the legislature while at the same time taking bold steps as necessary<br />

and appropriate: ‘Respect for democratic processes should not prevent the courts<br />

from rooting out remnants <strong>of</strong> tradition such as discrimination or inequality in<br />

conflict with the new constitutional dispensation ... hence the courts need not<br />

shy away from larger development <strong>of</strong> the common law out <strong>of</strong> respect for the<br />

legislature’ (Van der Walt (n 4 above) 120). In fact, Van der Walt hopes that<br />

subsidiarity will provide courts with a decisional framework authorising and<br />

encouraging them to take big (transformative) steps when Parliament is silent and<br />

to challenge Parliament when its efforts to give effect to the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights are too<br />

grudging.


138 Reply to vd Walt<br />

3.3 Problems <strong>of</strong> application<br />

Subsidiarity performs a ‘gate-keeping function’. It instructs courts to<br />

answer certain threshold questions before entertaining suits seeking<br />

to vindicate a constitutional right or to obtain constitutional damages<br />

or other special relief on the Constitution itself (‘Constitution-based<br />

remedies’). In principle, subsidiarity analysis tells a court whether to<br />

proceed with an action styled as a claim on the Constitution itself (or<br />

for Constitution-based remedies); or whether, in the alternative, to<br />

limit the claimant to such rights and entitlements as are available<br />

within the compass <strong>of</strong> a pertinent statute giving effect to the<br />

constitutional right, if any, or the common law, if not. At stake in this<br />

inquiry is whether a court may heed its own judgment on how to give<br />

effect to the constitutional right or whether it must leave that task,<br />

and the prudential and fiscal choices involved, to the legislature. Van<br />

der Walt explains well enough why in a given type <strong>of</strong> case courts<br />

should take the approach prescribed by subsidiarity. Unfortunately,<br />

subsidiarity <strong>of</strong>ten cannot tell us which cases have the specified<br />

characteristics, notwithstanding van der Walt’s assiduous efforts to<br />

‘embroider’ the theory. As a practical matter, courts can only answer<br />

the threshold, gate-keeping questions by examining and balancing the<br />

pertinent constitutional values and principles. Courts cannot apply<br />

subsidiarity theory without addressing precisely the questions, and<br />

making precisely the value judgments, that the theory means them to<br />

avoid.<br />

Under SANDU, for example, if Parliament enacts legislation to<br />

give effect to a constitutional right (‘effect-giving statute’), a<br />

claimant seeking to protect or enforce that right must rely on the<br />

legislation and is precluded from bringing a claim directly on the<br />

Constitution. However SANDU preclusion does not apply when a<br />

claimant challenges the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> the statute. 36 Therefore,<br />

in order to apply SANDU, a court must be able to distinguish rightsenforcement<br />

claims from constitutional challenges. 37 Drawing that<br />

distinction will be easy in many cases, but not in others. Important<br />

cases fall into middle-ground, creating difficulties for the theory that<br />

limit its usefulness.<br />

A claimant eligible under an effect-giving statute for the relief<br />

sought will sue on the statute. She will sue on the Constitution or for<br />

Constitution-based remedies only if she cannot obtain what she wants<br />

on the statute. It is reasonable to assume, therefore, that after<br />

36<br />

See Van der Walt (n 4 above) 100 - 103, discussing South African National Defence<br />

Union v Minister <strong>of</strong> Defence (SANDU) 2007 5 SA 400 (CC), 2007 8 BCLR 863 (CC)<br />

paras 51 - 52.<br />

37<br />

Obviously the claimant’s own description <strong>of</strong> her claim cannot be determinative. If<br />

it were, the SANDU principle could be nullified by strategic pleading.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 139<br />

SANDU, whenever a claimant is ineligible for relief on an effect-giving<br />

statute, she will pursue her claim by alleging that the enforcement<br />

provisions <strong>of</strong> the statutory scheme are constitutionally inadequate. If<br />

the statute is constitutionally adequate as applied, and the claimant<br />

is remitted to her statutory remedies, she is out <strong>of</strong> luck. If the statute<br />

is not constitutionally adequate, the claimant may proceed on the<br />

Constitution, and the court must hear her case. Thus, every nonfrivolous<br />

case in which the effect-giving statute denies relief, that is,<br />

virtually every serious case likely to arise post-SANDU, raises a<br />

preclusion-avoiding, constitutional question. In all cases seeking<br />

constitutional relief beyond that provided in an effect-giving statute,<br />

the courts must make a pre-threshold determination as to whether<br />

the plaintiff has a legitimate claim <strong>of</strong> constitutional inadequacy<br />

before it can make the supposedly threshold, subsidiarity-prescribed<br />

determination whether the case should be decided on the statute<br />

alone.<br />

This renders the SANDU principle a nullity, unless courts are able<br />

to make the pre-threshold determination on the face <strong>of</strong> the pleadings.<br />

But how is a court to know whether it is in the presence <strong>of</strong> a bona fide<br />

constitutional question, short <strong>of</strong> airing and taking a view on the<br />

matter? Inevitably, the court must consider the full panoply <strong>of</strong><br />

relevant constitutional values, including separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers values.<br />

In addition to substantive constitutional concerns, the court must<br />

inquire whether the question <strong>of</strong> remedies is one peculiarly within the<br />

competence <strong>of</strong> the legislature, or whether the principle <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional supremacy authorises or obliges the court to consult its<br />

own views <strong>of</strong> the matter. By itself, the SANDU principle provides little<br />

guidance in determining whether a valid claim on the Constitution has<br />

been pleaded; that determination must be made before SANDU kicks<br />

in.<br />

In sum, unless a claim is patently frivolous, a court cannot answer<br />

the pre-threshold question — whether the remedies provided by an<br />

effect-giving statute are constitutionally adequate — without fully<br />

considering and reaching at least a tentative conclusion on that point.<br />

But the purpose <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity was to prevent claimants from<br />

precipitating full-dress adjudication <strong>of</strong> constitutional issues when the<br />

legislature has given effect to a constitutional right. The process <strong>of</strong><br />

applying subsidiarity principles reinstates the problem it is intended<br />

to solve.<br />

This dilemma, if it is one, derives ultimately from an ambiguity in<br />

the constitutional provisions that authorise or enjoin Parliament to


140 Reply to vd Walt<br />

‘give effect’ to an enumerated constitutional right. 38 The bare words<br />

<strong>of</strong> the text can bear at least two polar meanings and perhaps a range<br />

<strong>of</strong> others in between. To ‘give effect’ to a constitutional right might<br />

mean that the right is free-standing, with a content <strong>of</strong> its own, but<br />

that Parliament is invited or mandated to implement and give<br />

concrete, practical significance to the right. In this interpretation,<br />

the content <strong>of</strong> the right is not exhausted by the effect-giving statute.<br />

Alternatively, and in contrast to textual references to the<br />

‘progressive realisation’ <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights through legislation, 39<br />

the phrase ‘give effect’ might mean that the right has the meaning<br />

and effects that Parliament gives it. The case for the former<br />

interpretation seems overwhelming to me, but, followed to its logical<br />

end-point (a course which van der Walt does not advocate),<br />

subsidiarity pushes the law toward the latter approach.<br />

I should pause to say that, in my view, constitutional rights are in<br />

part constituted by the extent and scope <strong>of</strong> relief awarded for their<br />

violation. Generations ago, the Legal Realists argued that remedies<br />

define legal rights and entitlements, rather than the other way<br />

around. On the traditional view, courts fashion remedies based on<br />

their understanding <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the legally protected interests<br />

infringed and the character <strong>of</strong> the wrong to those interests. According<br />

to the Legal Realists, we learn the identity <strong>of</strong> the legally protected<br />

interests and the nature <strong>of</strong> wrongs by examining the remedies courts<br />

dispense. A wrongful injury to a legally protected interest is that for<br />

which and to the extent that the courts provide a remedy. 40 One need<br />

not press the point to an extreme to accept that to some significant<br />

extent, enforcement and remedies determine what a right means in<br />

practical effect in the lives <strong>of</strong> the parties. When Parliament ‘gives<br />

effect’ to a constitutional right, it may task itself with giving the right<br />

an enforceable floor <strong>of</strong> protections and implementations. In practice,<br />

it may also erect a ceiling and walls around the right. At a certain<br />

point, ‘giving effect’ to a constitutional right slides into defining the<br />

right by setting out its metes and bounds. The question we deal with<br />

here is whether and to what extent the courts are confined within the<br />

houses that Parliament builds.<br />

The constitutional adequacy <strong>of</strong> the relief afforded by an effectgiving<br />

statute is not, strictly speaking, a question subsidiarity theory<br />

addresses — it is a substantive problem <strong>of</strong> constitutional law that must<br />

be decided by courts. However, the issue <strong>of</strong> constitutional adequacy<br />

38 See, eg, FC sec 33(3) (just administrative action) (‘[n]ational legislation must be<br />

enacted to give effect to these rights’).<br />

39<br />

See, eg, FC secs 26(2) (housing) and 27 (health care, food, water & social<br />

security).<br />

40 See, eg, WH Hamilton & I Till Property (1933) 12 Encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> Social Science<br />

528 536 (‘[i]t is incorrect to say that the judiciary protect[s] property; rather they<br />

call[ ] property that to which they accord[ ] protection’).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 141<br />

does implicate core subsidiarity concerns in the sense that how one<br />

approaches it may be strongly influenced by one’s attitude regarding<br />

the appropriate roles <strong>of</strong> courts and legislatures. Too eager a judicial<br />

willingness to find constitutional fault with effect-giving statutes<br />

might deprive the legislature <strong>of</strong> the discretion to which it is properly<br />

entitled in a democratic society. But an overly cautious attitude,<br />

comfortable with directing most claimants to their statutory<br />

remedies, might abdicate the courts’ obligation to protect and<br />

promote the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.<br />

Particularly in the field <strong>of</strong> socio-economic rights, when Parliament<br />

enacts an effect-giving statute providing a range <strong>of</strong> benefits, rights,<br />

and entitlements to qualified applicants and imposing corresponding<br />

obligations and prohibitions on the government, it will trade <strong>of</strong>f<br />

limitations on the coverage, administration, and enforcement <strong>of</strong> the<br />

right in return for greater generosity <strong>of</strong> benefits and ease <strong>of</strong> access to<br />

them. Such trade<strong>of</strong>fs are entirely legitimate means to make<br />

economical use <strong>of</strong> scarce resources needed to fulfil other<br />

constitutional rights and to provide for orderly conduct <strong>of</strong> executive<br />

and judicial business. Legislatures are supposed to make such trade<strong>of</strong>fs,<br />

and the Constitution requires South African courts to respect the<br />

considered judgment <strong>of</strong> Parliament. 41 But must courts give it<br />

dispositive weight on practical questions <strong>of</strong> enforcement and<br />

remedies? Leave aside crudely under-protective and otherwise<br />

patently inadequate remedial schemes. Assume the legislature’s<br />

scheme falls within a range <strong>of</strong> reasonable decision making. In a<br />

democracy, are there any circumstances under which a court may<br />

properly substitute its own thinking for that <strong>of</strong> the legislature? What<br />

if a court concludes that a different choice <strong>of</strong> remedies would do a<br />

significantly better job <strong>of</strong> protecting the constitutional right in<br />

question, with a net gain to democracy? Is it nevertheless precluded<br />

by the legislative judgment (except in extreme cases)?<br />

Assume that in a statute giving effect to a constitutional right,<br />

Parliament provides relief for denial or infringement <strong>of</strong> the right by<br />

lawsuit, and that the statute specifies a four-year time-limitation<br />

period for instituting such proceedings. X sues on the statute against<br />

an appropriate defendant. Her claim is meritorious in all respects save<br />

that she waited five years to bring the claim. She was tardy for a<br />

combination <strong>of</strong> reasons: she was not well-schooled in her rights, she<br />

faced practical and financial difficulties in obtaining representation,<br />

and she pursued the claim with insufficient vigour and attention. X<br />

pleads her cause both on the statute and on the Constitution itself.<br />

She argues that the four-year cut-<strong>of</strong>f is unconstitutional, and that the<br />

court should either grant Constitution-based remedies or, alter-<br />

41 See FC sec 41(1)(e).


142 Reply to vd Walt<br />

natively, read a longer limitations-period into the statute and then<br />

grant relief on the statute so revised.<br />

If Parliament had specified a 24-hour limitations period, most<br />

everyone would agree that the statute is unconstitutional to that<br />

extent—both for failing to give meaningful effect to the substantive<br />

right and in terms <strong>of</strong> the section 34 right <strong>of</strong> access to courts. 42 Assume<br />

for purposes <strong>of</strong> discussion, however, that the Constitutional Court had<br />

previously ruled that Parliament does not <strong>of</strong>fend the Constitution<br />

merely by imposing some reasonable limitations-periods in effectgiving<br />

statutes, the constitutionally acceptable minimum length to be<br />

determined in light <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the right, the nature <strong>of</strong> potential<br />

violations, and any other relevant considerations. If the court in X’s<br />

case were to conclude that a four-year prescription period plainly,<br />

unjustifiably, and unreasonably limits enjoyment <strong>of</strong> the constitutional<br />

right, presumably it would be common cause that the court may<br />

properly, indeed must, hold the statute invalid to that extent.<br />

Suppose instead that the court concludes (1) a four-year time-frame<br />

is within the range that could reasonably be regarded as appropriate<br />

and constitutional, but nevertheless (2) a seven-year period would<br />

better safeguard the right in question. The court arrives at this<br />

conclusion because it deems the substantive right to be very<br />

fundamental and in need <strong>of</strong> generous protection; because <strong>of</strong> its<br />

concern about the practical barriers to rights-enforcement faced by<br />

millions <strong>of</strong> poor South Africans; and because it feels the more<br />

forgiving limitations period better comports with ‘the values that<br />

underlie an open and democratic society based on human dignity,<br />

equality, and freedom’. 43 May the court impose its preference for<br />

seven years, thereby trumping Parliament’s choice among a range <strong>of</strong><br />

reasonably acceptable approaches to time-limitation? Are courts, or<br />

at least the Constitutional Court, charged with the authority to<br />

optimise protection <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights? Or would such a decision<br />

violate a proper understanding <strong>of</strong> separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers?<br />

42 In Moise v Transitional Local Council <strong>of</strong> Greater Germiston 2001 4 SA 491 (CC),<br />

2001 8 BCLR 765 (CC), the CC confirmed an order <strong>of</strong> the Witwatersrand High Court<br />

finding unconstitutional and invalid sec 2(1)(a) <strong>of</strong> the Limitation <strong>of</strong> Legal<br />

Proceedings (Provincial and Local Authorities) Act 94 <strong>of</strong> 1970, which barred suits<br />

against local authorities unless the claimant gave written notice <strong>of</strong> a claim within<br />

90 days <strong>of</strong> the date on which it arose. (Plaintiffs had 24 months within which to<br />

file suit.) The short notice period was held to impair the FC sec 34 right <strong>of</strong> access<br />

to courts in a manner that was not reasonably justifiable within FC sec 36(1). In<br />

Engelbrecht v Road Accident Fund 2007 6 SA 96 (CC), 2007 5 BCLR 457 (CC), the<br />

Court held unconstitutional regulation 2(1)(c), GN 17939, 25 April 1997,<br />

promulgated in terms <strong>of</strong> the Road Accident Fund 56 <strong>of</strong> 1996. With some<br />

qualifications, the regulation barred compensation to a victim <strong>of</strong> a hit-and-run<br />

accident unless the claimand filed a police affidavit within 14 days <strong>of</strong> the<br />

accident.<br />

43 FC sec 39(1)(a) (concerning interpretation <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 143<br />

Subsidiarity demands that the court dismiss X’s case even though<br />

it is in part styled as a constitutional challenge. If we rule out ultrashort<br />

and patently unfair limitations periods, setting the precise timelimit<br />

on claims is quintessentially a question <strong>of</strong> ‘policy’ as to which<br />

courts should refrain from substituting their own judgment for<br />

Parliament’s. This is so even if the legislature, in reaching its<br />

decision, predictably and properly took into account such nonconstitutional<br />

factors as the government’s need for efficient and<br />

frugal management <strong>of</strong> its legal and material resources, its desire to<br />

remove impediments to economic development, and/or its unadorned<br />

interest in avoiding litigation. It is surely defensible to argue that<br />

courts have no business critically scrutinising, let alone secondguessing,<br />

Parliament. It is worth noting that there is nothing<br />

particularly ‘transformative’ about this position. Most jurists who<br />

administer democratic constitutions providing for judicial review<br />

would probably counsel deference in this situation. Is that the best<br />

approach for South Africa or one that the Constitution obliges South<br />

African courts to take?<br />

It is not obvious, at least to me, that the familiar separation-<strong>of</strong>powers<br />

considerations supporting judicial deference are equally<br />

compelling when invoked in a case the outcome <strong>of</strong> which will define<br />

the operative bounds <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right. The legislature may<br />

have superior institutional competence to make what are<br />

conventionally called ‘policy decisions’, but it is not necessarily<br />

better situated than the Constitutional Court to strike the appropriate<br />

balance between majoritarian interest and constitutional principle. Is<br />

it not paradoxical to entrench judicially enforceable rights in a<br />

supreme constitution — a constitution meant to constrain the<br />

legislature — and then leave it to the legislature effectively to<br />

determine how those rights are to be protected and enforced, subject<br />

only to highly deferential judicial review? Given the paramount<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> constitutional supremacy in South Africa’s evolving<br />

constitutional understanding, the courts might legitimately be<br />

entitled to greater latitude in cases involving the effective definition<br />

and enforcement <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights than they may rightly claim<br />

in reviewing social and economic legislation that does not derogate<br />

from important rights and freedoms. In a transformative context, a<br />

bit more active role for the courts (or at least the Constitutional<br />

Court) and a bit more back-and-forth between the branches might be<br />

in order. 44<br />

44<br />

44<br />

Courts — particularly the peak level courts (CC and SCA) — could evolve practices<br />

designed to reduce the institutional tension between the branches and establish a<br />

more ‘dialogic’ relationship between them. A reviewing court could, for example,<br />

announce its conclusions but withhold judgment, pending further representations<br />

from the government or Parliament itself. A court could declare the four-year<br />

time limitation constitutionally deficient, but suspend the effective date <strong>of</strong> its<br />

order to give the legislature time to reconsider and, perhaps, devise an


144 Reply to vd Walt<br />

If the reader will grant that these questions are at least worthy <strong>of</strong><br />

debate, subsidiarity provides us no new tools with which to approach<br />

them. The theory instructs courts to leave to legislation (or to the<br />

common law, developing under the mandate <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) 45 ) cases<br />

in which it is appropriate in light <strong>of</strong> separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers theory to do<br />

so, but not in cases where that course is inappropriate. But the theory<br />

lacks the analytical traction necessary to perform any real work in<br />

assigning actual claims to their appropriate category. Any application<br />

<strong>of</strong> subsidiarity in a borderline case pushes the decision maker back to<br />

the general debate about separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers. Subsidiarity recites<br />

some <strong>of</strong> the countervailing considerations <strong>of</strong> which account ought to<br />

be taken, but it adds no new insight as to how they should be<br />

balanced.<br />

Likely van der Walt would say that this is exactly his point — there<br />

are no easy answers to such questions. Precisely what he wants is a<br />

general acknowledgment that resolving such conundrums calls for<br />

‘politics’ — discussion, debate, dissent, and the taking <strong>of</strong> judgments<br />

about how best to serve competing imperatives (‘for the time being’).<br />

Discuss, debate, and balance; decide provisionally; hold tensions<br />

open — I could not agree more. But van der Walt told us that before<br />

he brought subsidiarity into the picture. Subsidiarity cannot help us in<br />

pursuing the discussion.<br />

The reader may doubt that anything <strong>of</strong> constitutional substance<br />

can turn on the length <strong>of</strong> a limitations period. If so, she will find<br />

sobering a US case in which the Supreme Court sanctioned a man’s<br />

execution without affording a hearing on his constitutional claims<br />

because his lawyer was three days late in filing a notice <strong>of</strong> appeal in<br />

a lower court. 46 Nevertheless, I turn to examples in which the<br />

substantive constitutional stakes are more apparent.<br />

intermediate solution or approach the problem from a different angle. A court<br />

could invite, ask, or order Parliament to reconsider, standing ready to defer to the<br />

legislature or review its work with less exacting scrutiny if, upon reconsideration,<br />

it reaffirms the choice <strong>of</strong> a four-year limitations period. It could invite, ask, or<br />

order Parliament to propose a new solution within stipulated guidelines. The<br />

invention <strong>of</strong> intermediate review practices between the extremes <strong>of</strong> deference<br />

and trumping is one <strong>of</strong> the great challenges to constitutional law in our time.<br />

45 FC 39(2) (development <strong>of</strong> the common law and customary law ‘must promote the<br />

spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’).<br />

46 Coleman v Thompson 501 US 722 (1991) (O’Connor J). Coleman was convicted <strong>of</strong><br />

crimes and sentenced to death. He contended that his trial was infected by<br />

violations <strong>of</strong> his constitutional rights. The Court held that the attorney’s latefiling<br />

was a procedural default rendering Coleman’s conviction final under <strong>of</strong> the<br />

state law <strong>of</strong> Virginia, and therefore unreviewable in the US Supreme Court.<br />

Coleman was condemned by the equivalent <strong>of</strong> a ‘subsidiarity rule’ in the<br />

federalism context. The rule was based on two legal foundations — limitations on<br />

federal jurisdiction imposed by Article III <strong>of</strong> the US Constitution, and principles <strong>of</strong><br />

federal/state comity. (The ‘procedural default’ doctrine has exceptions, but the<br />

Court did not find them applicable in Coleman’s case.)


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 145<br />

Imagine that in response to Carmichele 47 and its progeny,<br />

Parliament enacted a comprehensive programme (the ‘domestic<br />

violence programme’ or DVP) intended to give effect to women’s<br />

equality rights (FC section 9), children’s rights (FC section 28), the<br />

right to security <strong>of</strong> the person (FC section 12), and the obligation <strong>of</strong><br />

government to protect against violence (FC section 12(1)(c) read with<br />

FC section 7(2)) in the context <strong>of</strong> violence against women and other<br />

domestic violence. DVP commits the national government to massive<br />

expenditures for increased policing, a well-designed scheme <strong>of</strong><br />

initiatives for police and other <strong>of</strong>ficials to receive training on violence<br />

against women and children, a victim advocate programme in the<br />

courts and in the community, and secure shelters and temporary<br />

financial assistance to victims and potential victims. DVP also<br />

provides scheduled compensation, obtainable through simple and<br />

prompt administrative procedures, for injuries caused by negligent<br />

acts or omissions <strong>of</strong> the police, court authorities, and other public<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials. In response to concerns about costs, the statute declares the<br />

specified administrative compensation to be the exclusive remedy in<br />

such cases, and moreover it grants the government and police<br />

absolute immunity from suit for negligence in any case involving<br />

violence against women or children. Assume that all interested groups<br />

in civil society and leading experts from numerous disciplines were<br />

consulted and had substantial input into the design <strong>of</strong> DVP. Many<br />

objections were raised in the consultation process, but in the end a<br />

wide consensus emerged that DVP is a state-<strong>of</strong>-the-art programme<br />

promising great benefits to vulnerable or victimised persons and to<br />

the community at large. The vote in Parliament in favour <strong>of</strong> DVP was<br />

unanimous.<br />

H attacks and shoots his wife W with an illegally possessed<br />

firearm, so seriously injuring and disabling her that she will need caretaking<br />

assistance, social work, and other services for life. Her young<br />

children witnessed the attack and suffered deep emotional trauma;<br />

they will require specialised services for the foreseeable future. H’s<br />

attack occurs under circumstances reminiscent <strong>of</strong> Carmichele and<br />

related cases — H had a history <strong>of</strong> violence known to local authorities;<br />

the police failed, for no legitimate reason, to impound H’s guns; and<br />

no warning or protection was given to W after police <strong>of</strong>ficers observed<br />

H intoxicated and threatening to kill her. H is arrested shortly after<br />

the attack and is eventually sentenced to a long prison term.<br />

W claims administrative compensation under DVP, to which she is<br />

unquestionably entitled. However, the DVP benefits do not provide<br />

redress for the emotional injury to her or the children, and they do<br />

47<br />

Carmichele v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security (Centre for Applied Legal Studies<br />

Intervening) 2001 4 SA 938 (CC), 2001 10 BCLR 995 (CC).


146 Reply to vd Walt<br />

not come close to the estimated life-time cost <strong>of</strong> her and the<br />

children’s caring needs. W therefore sues the local police and the<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security for unlawful omission to protect her.<br />

W brings the claim in delict, urging that, if necessary, the common<br />

law be developed so as to promote the spirit and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. Alternatively, she sues on the Constitution itself seeking<br />

Constitution-based damages. The defence concedes that the police<br />

were guilty <strong>of</strong> wrongful omissions, that these omissions proximately<br />

caused W’s injuries, and that the police’s omissions violated common<br />

law and constitutional duties owed to W. Nevertheless the police and<br />

Minister seek dismissal <strong>of</strong> both branches <strong>of</strong> W’s claim based on the<br />

DVP immunity provision. W in turn concedes that the defendants are<br />

immune in terms <strong>of</strong> DVP, but she argues that in application the<br />

statutory scheme is unconstitutional to that extent.<br />

May or must a court hear either her delictual and/or her<br />

constitutional claim? Should the court remit her to her remedies<br />

under DVP (with the result that a large portion <strong>of</strong> her injuries will go<br />

uncompensated and her constitutional challenge will go unheard)? At<br />

first glance, the Bato Star principle 48 suggests that W’s common law<br />

claim is precluded, but she escapes that tenet because she has<br />

challenged the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> DVP. If bypass is so easy, can<br />

subsidiarity effectively constrain courts from second-guessing the<br />

legislature and from undermining its carefully engineered policy<br />

compromises? If the court hears W’s claim on the Constitution, must<br />

it defer to the legislature’s policy judgment, and if so, how much<br />

deference must it show? On the other hand, if the court may not<br />

independently examine the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> the immunity<br />

provision — if, for example, subsidiarity directs the court to abstain<br />

from hearing W’s claim on the Constitution — have we not vested the<br />

legislature with effective power to define and limit the constitutional<br />

rights at stake, in violation <strong>of</strong> the fundamental principle <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional supremacy?<br />

I do not mean to suggest that there are easy or clear answers to<br />

these questions. My point is simply that subsidiarity brings us to their<br />

threshold, and then its analytic power runs out. It leaves us without<br />

moorings in attempting to figure out the appropriate roles and interrelationships<br />

<strong>of</strong> legislation and judge-made law.<br />

48<br />

See Van der Walt (n 4 above) 103 - 105 discussing Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Environmental Affairs 2004 4 SA 490 (CC), 2004 7 BCLR 687 (CC) para<br />

25 and Chirwa v Transnet Ltd 2008 2 SA 24 (CC), 2008 3 BCLR 251 (CC) para 23.<br />

According to Van der Walt (103), these cases state the principle that ‘once<br />

legislation has been enacted to give effect to a right in the Constitution, and in so<br />

far as the legislation was intended to codify the common law, litigants may not<br />

rely directly on the common law when seeking to protect that right against<br />

infringement’ (italics in original).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 147<br />

3.4 A cautionary tale — <strong>of</strong> Schweiker v Chilicky 49<br />

In this case, the US Supreme Court denied claimants the right to<br />

pursue constitutional claims because Congress had enacted an<br />

administrative scheme to redress their grievances. At first glance,<br />

Chilicky is SANDU with an American accent. But subsidiarity thinking<br />

runs wild in the Court’s opinion, which would make Kafka proud. To<br />

be clear, I do not believe that subsidiarity theory entails the Chilicky<br />

result, and I am confident that van der Walt would regard the case as<br />

wrongly decided. I <strong>of</strong>fer it as a cautionary tale for South Africans — to<br />

show how much damage can be done when jurists who do not possess<br />

van der Walt’s sophistication and intellectual integrity use<br />

subsidiarity-talk to resolve a case.<br />

Comparative discussion <strong>of</strong> constitutional torts requires caution<br />

because the US system is shaped by several factors that do not play a<br />

role South Africa. The US states are conceived as semi-autonomous<br />

sovereigns with a much more significant and independent legal<br />

identity than is associated with South African provinces. US federal<br />

courts are courts <strong>of</strong> constitutionally limited, not general, jurisdiction.<br />

US law seems to be more fastidious in distinguishing between rights,<br />

sources <strong>of</strong> law, and causes-<strong>of</strong>-action for redress <strong>of</strong> violations.<br />

Notably, the US Constitution does not contain a general ‘standing’<br />

provision such as found in FC section 38, 50 and the case-law is<br />

generally more restrictive than what FC section 38 permits. 51 The key<br />

point for present purposes is that the US Constitution does not<br />

expressly create any causes-<strong>of</strong>-action under which individuals may<br />

seek redress for constitutional violations. Congress long ago enacted<br />

statutes expressly creating causes-<strong>of</strong>-action against persons acting<br />

under the colour <strong>of</strong> state law who deprive individuals <strong>of</strong> federal<br />

constitutional rights. 52 There is no comparably generic cause-<strong>of</strong>action<br />

for violation <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights by the federal government<br />

or others acting under the colour <strong>of</strong> federal law. As a historical<br />

matter, it was generally assumed, but not entirely certain, that an<br />

individual could sue a federal actor for redress <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights<br />

49<br />

Schweiker v Chilicky 487 US 412 (1988) (‘Chilicky’) (O’Connor J). Brennan J,<br />

joined by Marshall and Blackmun JJ, dissented.<br />

50 FC sec 38 (enforcement <strong>of</strong> rights) both lists the parties who may approach a court<br />

when a right in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights ‘has been infringed or threatened’ and gives<br />

them a constitutional right to do so.<br />

51 The picture is further complicated because South African constitutional law has<br />

numerous distinctive features missing or largely absent in the US. These include<br />

affirmative governmental duties, social and economic rights, and direct<br />

horizontal application. The latter exists in the US — eg, the Thirteenth<br />

Amendment prohibition <strong>of</strong> slavery has direct horizontal application — but US<br />

constitutional jurisprudence is dominated by a powerful public/private<br />

distinction.<br />

52<br />

The most salient <strong>of</strong> these is the provision <strong>of</strong> the Civil Rights Act <strong>of</strong> 1871 now<br />

codified at 42 USC § 1983.


148 Reply to vd Walt<br />

violations. In the modern Bivens case, 53 the Court held that the<br />

Constitution impliedly gives rise <strong>of</strong> its own force to a cause-<strong>of</strong>-action<br />

in favour <strong>of</strong> an individual deprived <strong>of</strong> federal constitutional rights by<br />

a person acting under colour <strong>of</strong> federal law.<br />

Bivens remains good law, but the Court has narrowed its scope in<br />

recent years. In my view, the Court moved in this direction partly<br />

because <strong>of</strong> hostility to the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and an unarticulated<br />

antipathy to some <strong>of</strong> the kinds <strong>of</strong> people (eg, poor people) that<br />

attempt to bring Bivens claims. The Court’s stated reasons are based<br />

on subsidiarity principles. Specifically, the Court has held that a<br />

claimant may not pursue a Bivens tort where Congress has enacted an<br />

enforcement scheme providing meaningful remedies for<br />

unconstitutional action. In a leading case, Bush v Lucas, 54 a federal<br />

government employee claimed that his employer had violated his<br />

constitutional right <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> speech. 55 He was precluded from<br />

bringing a Bivens action and was instead confined to the<br />

administrative relief available under statutes governing the<br />

employment <strong>of</strong> federal civil servants, even though he alleged that<br />

these remedies were inadequate to deter unconstitutional<br />

wrongdoing and did not allow compensation for certain <strong>of</strong> his injuries<br />

(eg, emotional harms). 56<br />

The Bush Court assumed that the civil service procedure was<br />

constitutionally adequate. 57 One might think that, had the Court<br />

treated Bush’s claim as a direct challenge to the constitutional<br />

sufficiency <strong>of</strong> the administrative remedies, 58 it would have permitted<br />

his Bivens claim to go forward. This would bring the US approach into<br />

53<br />

Bivens v Six Unknown Named Agents <strong>of</strong> Federal Bureau <strong>of</strong> Narcotics 403 US 388<br />

(1971). Actions pursuant to the rule <strong>of</strong> this case are called ‘Bivens torts’.<br />

54<br />

462 US 367 (1983).<br />

55 See US Constitution, 1st amend.<br />

56 Mr Bush is not related to either <strong>of</strong> the former Presidents Bush. The Supreme Court<br />

affirmed that federal courts have the power to establish remedies needed and<br />

appropriate to vindicate constitutional rights, even if not expressly authorised by<br />

Congress (Bush (n 54 above) 374). However, it declined to exercise that power in<br />

Bush’s case because, after careful consideration, Congress had struck a balance<br />

between ‘the conflicting interests involved in providing job security, protecting<br />

the right to speak freely, and maintaining discipline and efficiency in the federal<br />

work force’ (385). Congress had developed ‘an elaborate, comprehensive scheme<br />

... by which improper [personnel] action may be redressed’, (385), and which<br />

‘provides meaningful remedies for employees who may have been unfairly<br />

disciplined for making critical comments about their agencies’ (386) (footnote<br />

omitted). The Court saw as the central question in the case whether the remedial<br />

system established by Congress ‘should be augmented by the creation <strong>of</strong> a new<br />

judicial remedy for the constitutional violation at issue’ (388). That question<br />

requires a ‘policy judgment’, including a cost-benefit analysis <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong><br />

additional remedies and their possible impact on the efficiency <strong>of</strong> the civil<br />

service, a policy judgment that Congress is in a far better position than the Court<br />

to make (388 - 389).<br />

57 Bush (n 54 above) 378 n 14.<br />

58<br />

Bush’s pleadings were unclear on this point, although on a generous reading his<br />

suit did advance a constitutional challenge to the administrative scheme.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 149<br />

conformity with SANDU. If one thought that, one would be mistaken.<br />

Chilicky, to which I now turn, disallows a Bivens tort even where the<br />

claimant raises an explicit constitutional challenge to the statute (as<br />

applied), and even though the alternative, statutory scheme to which<br />

she is remitted excludes recovery for unconstitutional conduct.<br />

The Federal Government (in cooperation with the states) operates<br />

several programs dispensing monetary benefits to persons who suffer<br />

specified forms <strong>of</strong> income interruption (due, for example, to<br />

unemployment, retirement, spouse’s death). Chilicky concerned a<br />

benefits programme for certain categories <strong>of</strong> people unable to<br />

perform paid work due to disability. Many recipients rely entirely on<br />

these benefits for their livelihood and that <strong>of</strong> their families. At the<br />

time, eligibility for disability (or other welfare) benefits was in many<br />

cases a requirement <strong>of</strong> access to Medicaid, the programme <strong>of</strong> healthcare<br />

coverage for poor people.<br />

Former President Ronald Reagan’s Administration was hostile to<br />

all forms <strong>of</strong> welfare and in the early 1980s imposed directives and<br />

informal pressures on programme managers designed to get them<br />

drastically to reduce the number <strong>of</strong> social welfare recipients. As a<br />

result, the disability-benefit programme alone terminated hundreds<br />

<strong>of</strong> thousands <strong>of</strong> benefit-recipients over a period <strong>of</strong> years using<br />

questionable, and <strong>of</strong>ten sleazy, methods. The Chilicky claimants<br />

argued that the procedures the Government used to clear the welfare<br />

rolls violated the right to Due Process guaranteed by the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. 59 Congress eventually brought a halt to the wholesale<br />

terminations and introduced procedural safeguards. By then,<br />

approximately 200,000 recipients had been wrongfully terminated,<br />

by the Government’s own reckoning. Many were eventually<br />

reinstated, but the episode caused heart-breaking and traumatic<br />

suffering. Many thousands <strong>of</strong> recipients and their families lost their<br />

livelihood, became homeless, and/or scraped by on the kindness <strong>of</strong><br />

friends and relatives for long periods. Regrettably, South Africa is also<br />

familiar with large-scale delivery-failures in social welfare<br />

programmes.<br />

The disability-benefits programme was enacted under the Social<br />

Security Act, 60 which incorporates an administrative appeals<br />

procedure for correcting errors. Terminated recipients who were in<br />

fact eligible invoked these procedures. They were entitled to, and<br />

most eventually received, reinstatement for future benefits and<br />

59<br />

See US Constitution, 5th amend. (‘No person shall ... be deprived <strong>of</strong> life, liberty,<br />

or property [by the Federal Government], without due process <strong>of</strong> law’). The<br />

Fourteenth Amendment guarantees Due Process in deprivations undertaken by<br />

state governments.<br />

60 Social Security Act, Title II (1935), principally codified at 42 USC §§ 420 - 425.


150 Reply to vd Walt<br />

retroactive payment <strong>of</strong> past benefits wrongfully withheld. The<br />

problem was that these were the only remedies available under the<br />

administrative system. In other words, a fully successful claimant<br />

received at the end <strong>of</strong> the administrative process only what she was<br />

entitled to in the first place. The procedure made no provision for<br />

mandatory or injunctive relief, it afforded no compensation for the<br />

turmoil and dislocation caused by wrongful termination, and it did not<br />

entertain, let alone remedy, constitutional claims.<br />

The claimants in Chilicky were eligible but wrongfully terminated<br />

benefits-recipients who sought monetary damages for ‘emotional<br />

distress and for loss <strong>of</strong> food, shelter and other necessities proximately<br />

caused by [the Government’s] denial <strong>of</strong> benefits without due<br />

process’. 61 Consequential damages and the other remedies requested<br />

were not available through the administrative appeals system.<br />

Lacking any other vehicle, plaintiffs lodged their claim as a Bivens<br />

tort.<br />

Chilicky differs from the cases van der Walt discusses in that the<br />

Social Security Act was not enacted in order to ‘give effect’ to a<br />

constitutional right. The US Constitution contains no guarantee <strong>of</strong><br />

social security such as appears in FC section 27(1)(c). This should not<br />

greatly alter the analysis <strong>of</strong> Chilicky, however, because the claim was<br />

grounded on a constitutional right, the right to Due Process.<br />

Indisputably, the remedial scheme attached to the disability benefits<br />

programme must provide constitutional Due Process — in that sense,<br />

it is a statute designed in relevant part to ‘give effect’ to a<br />

constitutional right.<br />

In a 1970s case called Arnett, Justice Rehnquist floated a theory<br />

that recipients <strong>of</strong> government largesse or public employment must<br />

‘take the bitter with the sweet’. 62 By this he meant that any nonconstitutional<br />

benefit created or extended by law is qualified and<br />

limited by the procedures specified in the legislation for removal or<br />

discontinuance <strong>of</strong> the benefit, even if such procedures do not<br />

measure up to the minimum requirements <strong>of</strong> constitutional Due<br />

Process. Rehnquist J reasoned that no deprivation <strong>of</strong> property occurs<br />

if a benefit is terminated or removed according to the procedures for<br />

removal specified in the law creating the benefit. In these<br />

circumstances, the claimant is deprived <strong>of</strong> nothing to which she has a<br />

61<br />

62<br />

Chilicky v Schweiker 796 F 2d 1131 1134 (9th Cir. 1986) (quoting plaintiffs’<br />

complaint), reversed by Schweiker v Chilicky 487 US 412 (1988). Other remedies<br />

were sought, notably an interdict against the benefit cut-<strong>of</strong>fs. The additional<br />

remedial requests dropped out <strong>of</strong> the case partly because it meandered through<br />

the courts for about six years, by which time Congress had halted the Reagan<br />

campaign to slash the rolls and had provided enhanced procedural safeguards.<br />

See Arnett v Kennedy 416 US 134 151 - 54 (Rehnquist J for the plurality),<br />

rehearing denied 417 US 977 (1974).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 151<br />

legal claim <strong>of</strong> entitlement. Therefore, Rehnquist J argued, the<br />

strictures <strong>of</strong> Due Process are inapplicable. 63<br />

A majority <strong>of</strong> the Court emphatically rejected Justice Rehnquist’s<br />

thesis, both in the Arnett decision itself and on subsequent<br />

occasions. 64 Under settled doctrine, even though the government is<br />

not constitutionally obliged to confer a certain benefit, once it elects<br />

to do so, it may not remove or terminate the benefit except by<br />

procedures consistent with constitutional Due Process. The<br />

Constitution, not the statute, sets the procedural floor.<br />

Evidently the Court forgot this when it decided Chilicky, which<br />

shows legislatures how to immunise their work from constitutional<br />

review. Therein lies a warning for South Africans. The Chilicky Court<br />

held that ‘[w]hen the design <strong>of</strong> a Government program suggests that<br />

Congress has provided what it considers adequate remedial<br />

mechanisms for constitutional violations that may occur in the course<br />

<strong>of</strong> its administration, we have not created additional Bivens<br />

remedies’. 65 In the result, the Court precluded the plaintiffs from<br />

proceeding with an action on the Constitution. Under the banner <strong>of</strong><br />

subsidiarity, they were remitted to statutory remedies which, it was<br />

common cause, did not even consider, let alone remedy, claims <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional injury. Under American-style subsidiarity, constitutional<br />

claimants were channelled to and compelled exclusively to<br />

utilise a forum that did not entertain constitutional claims. This<br />

meant that the claimants could not obtain a hearing for their<br />

constitutional claims in any forum. In practical effect, the legislation<br />

simply erased their constitutional right to Due Process.<br />

One might have thought that a self-respecting court would be<br />

embarrassed to decree something so absurd. But no, the US Supreme<br />

Court made its conclusion <strong>of</strong>ficial: ‘the relief sought by the<br />

[claimaints] is unavailable as a matter <strong>of</strong> law ... ’. 66 In sum, when<br />

enacting a benefits programme, the legislature may render the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights inoperative by attaching remedial procedures that claimants<br />

are exclusively constrained to utilise when challenging the<br />

63 See Arnett (n 62 above) (under constitutional text, a ‘deprivation’ is required to<br />

trigger Due Process guarantees).<br />

64<br />

See, eg, Cleveland Board <strong>of</strong> Education v Loudermill 470 US 532 (1985).<br />

65 Chilicky (n 49 above) 423. The Court could find no legal distinction between<br />

Chilicky and Bush: ‘[W]e declined in Bush to create a new substantive legal<br />

liability [on the Constitution] ... because we [were] convinced that Congress is in<br />

a better position [than the judiciary] to decide whether or not the public interest<br />

would be served by creating it. That reasoning applies as much, or more, in this<br />

case ... In neither case ... does the presence <strong>of</strong> alleged unconstitutional conduct<br />

that is not separately remedied under the statutory scheme imply that the<br />

statute has provided ‘no remedy’ for the constitutional wrong at issue (426 – 428)<br />

(citations and internal quotation marks omitted; italics in original).<br />

66 Chilicky (n 49 above) 429.


152 Reply to vd Walt<br />

constitutionality <strong>of</strong> the programme’s administration, even though<br />

those procedures expressly disallow constitutional challenges <strong>of</strong> any<br />

kind. Chilicky allows Congress to stamp ‘void’ on the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 67<br />

The Court’s deference to the statutory remedies fully accords<br />

with subsidiarity thinking. True, the Court’s articulated rationale<br />

invoked the theory <strong>of</strong> institutional competence (the legislature is<br />

better situated than the courts to study complicated policy matters<br />

and to engineer comprehensive solutions) rather than classical<br />

separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers doctrine (the legislature is representative and<br />

acts democratically). The distinction might be highly significant in<br />

some contexts, but here the two theories seem closely intertwined.<br />

Subsidiarity draws on both. Substitute ‘Parliament’ for ‘Congress’,<br />

and ‘government agencies’ for ‘state agencies’, and one can easily<br />

imagine a South African court committed to the SANDU principle<br />

denying an action on the Constitution with words similar to the<br />

following:<br />

Congress ... has addressed the problems created by state agencies’<br />

wrongful termination <strong>of</strong> disability benefits. Whether or not we believe<br />

that its response was the best response, Congress is the body charged<br />

with making the inevitable compromises required by the design <strong>of</strong> a<br />

massive and complex welfare benefits program ... Congress has<br />

discharged that responsibility to the extent that it affects the case<br />

before us, and we see no legal basis that would allow us to revise its<br />

decision. 68<br />

I am confident that van der Walt would say that Chilicky goes too far.<br />

His version <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity is more flexible than its US counterpart and<br />

does not rule out constitutional challenges to effect-giving statutes.<br />

But these subtleties can easily be lost in less able hands than his.<br />

67 Chilicky is in a line <strong>of</strong> disastrous Nixon-Reagan era decisions that eviscerated the<br />

Due Process clauses. In Bishop v Wood 426 US 341 (1976), the Court held that a<br />

public employer may discharge an employee for cause without providing a<br />

hearing, an opportunity to respond to the charges against him, or any other<br />

minimum component <strong>of</strong> constitutional Due Process, if the government structures<br />

its relationship with its employees on an at-will basis. In Paul v Davis 424 US 693<br />

(1976), a local police department distributed circulars to merchants containing<br />

the names and photographs <strong>of</strong> individuals identified by the police as known to be<br />

actively engaged in shoplifting. The names were selected ex parte, without<br />

notice to the individuals involved, hearing, or any other opportunity for the<br />

accused to respond. The Supreme Court found no constitutional deficiency in this<br />

procedure, holding that those who were ‘merely’ publicly branded as criminals<br />

without trial suffered no impairment <strong>of</strong> any interest protected by the Due Process<br />

clauses. Justice Brennan remarked in dissent that ‘[t]he potential <strong>of</strong> today’s<br />

decision is frightening for a free people’ (721).<br />

68 Chilicky (n 49 above) 429 (citations omitted). The legal basis the Court had<br />

difficulty seeing is, <strong>of</strong> course, the Constitution’s Fifth Amendment and the Court’s<br />

own case-law.


5 Conclusion<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 153<br />

I conclude with a hypothetical problem aimed to identify interpretive<br />

questions that await South Africa’s courts. My purpose is to show the<br />

limitations <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity analysis, but also to <strong>of</strong>fer a platform for<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> issues that may well arise as the jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> SANDU<br />

and Bato Star evolves. In fact, the hypothetical bears more than a<br />

passing resemblance to matters that have already concerned South<br />

African courts. 69<br />

Imagine that Parliament enacts legislation to give effect to the<br />

right to social security guaranteed by FC section 27(1)(c). In addition<br />

to setting forth the substantive content <strong>of</strong> the programme, the<br />

legislation contains a remedial scheme intended to address and<br />

remedy all wrongs committed by the government in connection with<br />

the benefits programme, including any constitutional violations that<br />

may occur. Successful claimants are entitled to retroactive payment<br />

<strong>of</strong> benefits wrongfully withheld, access to the programme if it was<br />

wrongfully denied, and restoration to the programme in the event <strong>of</strong><br />

wrongful termination. In addition, a claimant may receive monetary<br />

compensation for consequential damages, including damages<br />

proximately caused by a constitutional violation, up to a maximum <strong>of</strong><br />

R100. The statutory procedure makes no provision for mandatory<br />

relief and does not allow class actions. These restrictions were<br />

included after careful study, consultation with experts and affected<br />

stakeholders, and plenary discussion in Parliament. The drafters are<br />

in good faith convinced that it is necessary to limit litigation and<br />

remedies in connection with delivery problems in order to preserve<br />

scarce resources for the beneficial purposes <strong>of</strong> the programme.<br />

Parliament declares the statutory remedial procedure to be the<br />

exclusive avenue <strong>of</strong> redress for any grievance in connection with the<br />

programme. Neither the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Administrative Justice Act<br />

(PAJA) 70 nor any other statute applies, and any claim that might arise<br />

under the common law is expressly pre-empted.<br />

69 See, eg, Permanent Secretary, Department <strong>of</strong> Welfare v Ngxuza 2001 4 SA 1184<br />

(SCA), 2001 10 BCLR 1039 (SCA); MEC, Department <strong>of</strong> Welfare v Nontembiso<br />

Norah Kate 2006 2 All SA 455 (SCA). In Kate, the SCA sustained an award <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional damages in a case <strong>of</strong> excessive delay in the processing <strong>of</strong> a social<br />

grant application, as against the view that the claimant should be restricted to<br />

statutory or delictual remedies. See (para 27) stating that the relief permitted by<br />

FC sec 38 (enforcement <strong>of</strong> Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights): ‘is not a remedy <strong>of</strong> last resort, to be<br />

looked to only where there is no alternative — and indirect — means <strong>of</strong> asserting<br />

and vindicating constitutional rights. While that possibility is a consideration to<br />

be borne in mind in determining whether to grant or to withhold a direct section<br />

38 remedy, it is by no means decisive, for there will be cases in which the direct<br />

assertion and vindication <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights is required ... [T]he endemic<br />

breach <strong>of</strong> the rights that are now in issue justifies — indeed, it calls out for — the<br />

clear assertion <strong>of</strong> their independent existence’.<br />

70 Act 3 <strong>of</strong> 2000.


154 Reply to vd Walt<br />

An eligible recipient <strong>of</strong> welfare benefits is arbitrarily terminated<br />

from the program for no good reason and without notice or an<br />

opportunity to be heard. She suffers consequential damages in an<br />

amount greater than R100 and asserts that the cap on remedies<br />

renders the statutory remedial procedure constitutionally<br />

inadequate, citing FC section 27(1)(c) itself and perhaps FC section 33<br />

(just administrative action), FC section 34 (access to courts), and<br />

other provisions <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. May she prosecute a claim on the<br />

Constitution for the full amount <strong>of</strong> her damages? Suppose an<br />

additional 100,000 eligible recipients experience similar problems<br />

due to the incompetence or malfeasance <strong>of</strong> the authorities. May they<br />

sue on the Constitution as a class to remedy their own injuries and<br />

interdict the authorities from future, administrative misbehaviour?<br />

If we conclude that these claimants may not proceed on the<br />

Constitution and are limited to working within the statutory<br />

procedure, we vindicate the pro-legislature, pro-representation spirit<br />

<strong>of</strong> subsidiarity at the expense <strong>of</strong> constitutional supremacy and<br />

substantive constitutional rights. We put the legislature in a position<br />

effectively to define rights entrenched by a Constitution intended to<br />

constrain it. And because an interdict is precluded by the statute, we<br />

effectively prevent the courts from granting a timeous remedy that<br />

might induce the authorities to straighten out the mess. But suppose<br />

we conclude that these suits may go forward. Would we not be saying,<br />

in practical effect, that we will observe the tenets <strong>of</strong> subsidiarity<br />

except in cases where we prefer not to? And if this is what it comes<br />

down to, what has subsidiarity taught us?


‘OH WHAT A TANGLED WEB WE WEAVE ...’ *<br />

HEGEMONY, FREEDOM OF CONTRACT,<br />

GOOD FAITH AND TRANSFORMATION -<br />

TOWARDS A POLITICS OF FRIENDSHIP IN THE<br />

POLITICS OF CONTRACT<br />

* ‘... when first we practice to deceive.’ Sir Walter Scott Marmion (1825) Canto VI<br />

Stanza XVII, 349.<br />

�� BCom(Law) LLB LLD(<strong>Pretoria</strong>). Senior lecturer, Department <strong>of</strong> Private Law,<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Cape Town. The author would like to thank the following people for<br />

valuable discussions and comments on earlier drafts <strong>of</strong> this essay: Karin van Marle,<br />

Danie Brand, Drucilla Cornell, Dennis Davis and Karl Klare.<br />

155<br />

AJ Barnard-Naude**<br />

‘Q6: “ ... and I wondered how you think your concept <strong>of</strong> friendship, your<br />

non-canonical concept <strong>of</strong> friendship, can address economic exclusion in<br />

its most extreme form which is the exclusion by those who own capital<br />

<strong>of</strong> everyone else. You can’t ask those who own capital to be hospitable<br />

...”.<br />

JD: “I ask them nevertheless [laughter].”<br />

Q6: “It’s naïve to ask them, it’s a naïve request.”<br />

JD: “Perhaps, but I still do.”’ 1<br />

‘One must speak for a struggle for a new culture, that is, for a new<br />

moral life that cannot but be intimately connected to a new intuition <strong>of</strong><br />

life, until it becomes a new way <strong>of</strong> feeling and seeing reality.’ 2<br />

1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

The pivot on which this contribution hinges is hegemony in the<br />

context 3 <strong>of</strong> the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract. I must point out at the<br />

1 From ‘Politics and friendship: A discussion with Jacques Derrida’ available at<br />

http://www.hydra.umn.edu/derrida/pol+fr.html (accessed 29 May 2008).<br />

2 A Gramsci Selections from cultural writings (1985) 98.<br />

3 And it will <strong>of</strong> course be unavoidable when considering the lexicography <strong>of</strong><br />

hegemony, that the concept <strong>of</strong> conning (in both its senses) — and the conning <strong>of</strong>/<br />

by the text; the context — will raise its head.


156 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

outset that the purpose or aim <strong>of</strong> this ‘hinging’ on hegemony and/in<br />

the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract, is not necessarily to take issue with,<br />

underscore or re-illustrate the claim that contract holds hegemony —<br />

in the sense that it ‘occupies a privileged position’ — in the South<br />

African legal system. 4 Nevertheless, it might very well be the case<br />

that Alfred Cockrell’s admirable illustration <strong>of</strong> the hegemony <strong>of</strong><br />

contract in the South African legal system can be explained also by<br />

the particular focus on hegemony in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

on which I embark in this contribution. In other words, the hegemony<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract might well be attributable to the hegemony within<br />

contract. This is the case because the hegemony within might very<br />

well sustain the hegemony <strong>of</strong> and perhaps also vice versa. (A symbiosis<br />

comes to mind.) This hegemony within contract relates to a particular<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract. Thus, the focus and point <strong>of</strong><br />

departure in this contribution will be the hegemony — or hegemonic<br />

order(ing) 5 — <strong>of</strong>/in a particular understanding <strong>of</strong> (freedom <strong>of</strong>)<br />

contract. This understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract — and indeed <strong>of</strong><br />

contract itself — is the individualist, rule-committed 6 — liberal 7 —<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract.<br />

The enactment <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, 8 the transformative hopes it<br />

disseminates and the view that its normative framework is explicitly<br />

post-liberal 9 occasions an opportunity for a re-evaluation <strong>of</strong> and a<br />

challenge to the individualist (hegemonic) understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract, its concomitant commitments and, as we shall see, the<br />

tangled web it weaves in order to sustain the false consciousness on<br />

4 A Cockrell ‘The hegemony <strong>of</strong> contract’ (1998) 115 South African Law Journal 286<br />

286.<br />

5<br />

I want to insist on this marking according to which both senses <strong>of</strong> the word ‘order’<br />

remain constantly in play, namely order as socio-political concept <strong>of</strong> hierarchy<br />

and order as sequential arrangement.<br />

6 D Kennedy ‘Form and substance in private law adjudication’ (1976) 89 Harvard<br />

Law Review 1685 1685: ‘individualism seems to harmonise with an insistence on<br />

rigid rules rigidly applied.’<br />

7 See the description <strong>of</strong> the liberal self — grounded in individualist morality —<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered by F Michelman ‘The subject <strong>of</strong> liberalism’ (1994) 46 Stanford Law Review<br />

1807 1812. Also see van K Marle & D Brand ‘Enkele opmerkings oor formele<br />

geregtigheid, substantiewe oordeel en horisontaliteit in Jooste v Botha’ (2001)<br />

12(3) Stellenbosch Law Review 408 415.<br />

8<br />

Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa, 1996.<br />

9 See H Botha ‘Democracy and rights: Constitutional interpretation in a postrealist<br />

world’ 2000 (63) Tydskrif vir die Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 561 574.<br />

Botha notes three reasons why the Constitution requires more than a classical<br />

liberal interpretation. First, he points out that the Constitution contains a<br />

commitment to an open, value-orientated, participatory democracy. This is a<br />

commitment that cannot be reconciled with the reduced concept <strong>of</strong> democracy<br />

which pervades liberal theory. Secondly, Botha argues that the Constitution does<br />

not support a liberal conception <strong>of</strong> rights as boundaries between the individual<br />

and the collective; the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights have a contingent and nonabsolute<br />

meaning and to that extent they do not operate as a shield against<br />

government intervention or as trumps over collective interests. Thirdly, the<br />

Constitution is structured such that it requires a far more activist stance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

judiciary than what would be acceptable under a liberal interpretation (574-576).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 157<br />

which its legitimacy turns. However, in order to embark upon such a<br />

re-evaluation it will be necessary to begin by revisiting the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

hegemony as encountered in the work <strong>of</strong> Antonio Gramsci as well as<br />

the expansions and reformulations <strong>of</strong> Gramsci’s concept as it relates<br />

to law. Second, I will articulate more fully what is meant with and<br />

what are the commitments <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic liberal understanding <strong>of</strong><br />

contract and freedom <strong>of</strong> contract. Third, I will track the rise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

hegemonic order(ing) in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract. I will argue<br />

that the story <strong>of</strong> its rise can and must be considered as the story <strong>of</strong><br />

the fall (that is, the marginalisation) <strong>of</strong> values and concepts in the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract that came to be understood as somehow threatening the<br />

hegemonic order(ing) (notably in this regard, good faith). 10 An<br />

ongoing moment in this contribution interrogates the way in which the<br />

hegemony confronts the Constitution (both as an interruption, 11 as a<br />

value system and as law) in order continuously to pose the question<br />

whether the hegemonic order(ing) within the South African law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract (and the adjudication that keeps this hegemony in place)<br />

should be resisted in the name <strong>of</strong> the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitution.<br />

A primary contention in this article will be that the hegemony <strong>of</strong><br />

a radically individualist understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract is as<br />

firmly in place under the newly constituted legal order as it was under<br />

the apartheid legal order in South Africa. The law <strong>of</strong> contract is still<br />

seen as an institution <strong>of</strong> separation rather than relation, <strong>of</strong> apartness,<br />

rather than togetherness. That ‘nothing changed again’ 12 is evident in<br />

a series <strong>of</strong> cases decided after the reconstitution <strong>of</strong> the South African<br />

legal order. 13 What will also become evident, however, is the series<br />

<strong>of</strong> contradictions and deconstructions that emerge in the course <strong>of</strong><br />

10 See in this regard G du Toit ‘The significance <strong>of</strong> postmodern theories <strong>of</strong><br />

interpretation for contractual interpretation: A critical analysis’ unpublished LLD<br />

thesis, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Stellenbosch, 2006 234-235.<br />

11 See, for instance, J Gilbert-Walsh ‘Deconstruction as narrative interruption’<br />

(2007) 38(4) Interchange 317.<br />

12 For a variety <strong>of</strong> reasons I want to draw explicit attention here to Karin van Marle’s<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> the inscription ‘and nothing changed again’ on one <strong>of</strong> the etchings in<br />

Dianne Victor’s celebrated series Disasters <strong>of</strong> Peace. Van Marle remarks as<br />

follows: ‘“And nothing changed again”, portrays the state <strong>of</strong> mind <strong>of</strong> many South<br />

Africans who do not experience easy living in post-apartheid South Africa. For<br />

them, nothing has changed again.’ See K van Marle ‘Art democracy and<br />

resistance: A response to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Heyns’ (2005) Pulp Fictions: Disasters <strong>of</strong><br />

13<br />

Peace: An Exchange 15 26.<br />

The most important <strong>of</strong> these cases are De Beer v Keyser 2002 1 SA 827 (SCA) (De<br />

Beer), Brisley v Drotsky 2002 4 SA 1 (SCA) (Brisley), Afrox Healthcare Bpk v<br />

Strydom 2002 6 SA 21 (SCA) (Afrox Healthcare), Johannesburg Country Club v<br />

Scott and Another 2004 5 SA 511 (SCA) (Johannesburg Country Club), Juglal NO v<br />

Shoprite Checkers t/a OK Franchise Division 2004 5 SA 248 (SCA) (Juglal N0),<br />

South African Forestry Co Ltd v York Timbers 2005 3 SA 323 (SCA) (South African<br />

Forestry Co), Napier v Barkhuizen 2006 4 SA 1 (SCA) (Napier) and Barkhuizen v<br />

Napier 2007 5 SA 323 (CC) (Barkhuizen).


158 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

the marginalisation <strong>of</strong> good faith in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract,<br />

which <strong>of</strong> course mirrors the rise <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic order(ing).<br />

In the last part <strong>of</strong> the article I will argue why the hegemonic<br />

order(ing) <strong>of</strong> contract, mirrored by the marginalisation <strong>of</strong> good faith<br />

can and should be questioned in light <strong>of</strong> the transformative<br />

commitments inherent in the spirit <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. I will argue<br />

that good faith as the ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract directly involves the<br />

constitutional ideal <strong>of</strong> civic friendship in the South African law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract. Civic friendship as an aspirational ideal <strong>of</strong> the new legal<br />

order then enjoins us to transform the hegemonic order(ing) in the<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract by way <strong>of</strong> a direct involvement <strong>of</strong> good faith. 14 I see<br />

the starting point <strong>of</strong> this transformation as a call for the politics <strong>of</strong><br />

friendship in the politics <strong>of</strong> contract. In this context, I will argue that<br />

the provisions <strong>of</strong> the Draft Consumer Protection Bill stand in stark<br />

contrast to the commitments <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic understanding <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract and, although inadequate, these provisions point<br />

to a future law <strong>of</strong> contract that will have to be far more concerned<br />

with the ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract than it has been up to now.<br />

These provisions require a transformed understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract in which good faith as the ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract comes<br />

to again play a constitutive role in the understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract. This has obvious transformative implications for<br />

adjudication in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract. In this context I will<br />

take issue with the Constitutional Court’s 2007 judgement in<br />

Barkhuizen in which it followed a hesitant approach to the transformative<br />

role <strong>of</strong> good faith in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract.<br />

Ultimately my contention will be that good faith interpreted in line<br />

with a transformative reading <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract mandates a<br />

relational interpretation <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract that is far removed<br />

from its standard libertarian version.<br />

2 Gramsci, hegemony and the law<br />

In order to come to terms with the present focus on the hegemonic<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> (freedom <strong>of</strong>) contract, it is necessary — as a point <strong>of</strong><br />

departure — to review the development <strong>of</strong> hegemony as a conceptual<br />

tool <strong>of</strong> critique. For the benefit <strong>of</strong> the argument that will follow, it<br />

will also be necessary to enquire into contemporary views on the<br />

relationship between hegemony and law.<br />

14 I realise and concede that the theoretical and methodological framework<br />

developed here is contested. Apart from the justifications <strong>of</strong>fered in the text, the<br />

primary focus <strong>of</strong> this article (adjudication on the interaction between the<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> contract and the Constitution in 2007) does not allow me to fully<br />

defend this approach. In this regard, I intend to embark more fully on such an<br />

explanation in future work.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 159<br />

Hegemony as a critical concept was originally developed in the<br />

work <strong>of</strong> Antonio Gramsci 15 who employed the word to explain how<br />

capitalism maintains control ‘not just through violence and political<br />

and economic coercion, but also ideologically, through a culture in<br />

which the values <strong>of</strong> the bourgeoisie became the “common sense”<br />

values <strong>of</strong> all.’ 16 In Gramsci ideology operates in such a way that the<br />

dominant class in fact instills a false sense in the dominated class that<br />

the good <strong>of</strong> the dominant class is also the good <strong>of</strong> the dominated class.<br />

This condition serves conformity and perpetuates a status quo. 17 John<br />

and Jean Comar<strong>of</strong>f aptly describe the cultural effect <strong>of</strong> hegemony:<br />

[W]e take hegemony to refer to that order <strong>of</strong> signs and practices,<br />

relations and distinctions, images and epistemologies — drawn from a<br />

historically situated cultural field — that have come to be taken-forgranted<br />

as the natural and received shape <strong>of</strong> the world and everything<br />

that inhabits it. 18<br />

Gramsci insisted that hegemony is only transformed once the<br />

dominated class realised the importance <strong>of</strong> creating its own culture<br />

which depends on the realisation that it had unwittingly adopted the<br />

values <strong>of</strong> the bourgeoisie and that its own values in fact opposed the<br />

values <strong>of</strong> the bourgeoisie. 19 Breaking hegemony thus depends<br />

fundamentally on the contestation <strong>of</strong> values and ideals and perhaps<br />

more importantly on the contestation <strong>of</strong> the relationships between<br />

and the content <strong>of</strong> these values and ideals. 20<br />

When it comes to the relationship between law and hegemony,<br />

Litowitz points out that law fulfils a dual function in relation to<br />

hegemony. 21 On the one hand, the law represses (through the State’s<br />

monopoly on physical force) any disturbance that might challenge the<br />

hegemony. On the other hand, the law authorises and legitimates the<br />

status quo and so produces and perpetuates the hegemony without<br />

the need to revert to physical force. 22 This contribution will focus<br />

primarily on this second dimension <strong>of</strong> hegemony, as I shall interrogate<br />

15<br />

A Gramsci Selections from the prison notebooks trans Q Hoare & GN Smith (1971).<br />

16 JM Russel Philosophical classics (2007) 94.<br />

17 As above. Also see TR Bates ‘Gramsci and the theory <strong>of</strong> hegemony’ (1975) 36(2)<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas 351 352: ‘The concept <strong>of</strong> hegemony is really a very<br />

simple one. It means political leadership based on the consent <strong>of</strong> the led, a<br />

consent which is secured by the diffusion and popularisation <strong>of</strong> the world view <strong>of</strong><br />

the ruling class.’<br />

18 J Comar<strong>of</strong>f & J Comar<strong>of</strong>f Of revelation and revolution: Christianity, colonialism<br />

and consciousness in South Africa (1991) 23.<br />

19<br />

Russell (n 16 above) 95.<br />

20 Bates (n 17 above) makes the point that the theory <strong>of</strong> hegemony recognises that<br />

man is ruled not just by force but also by ideas. The author also points to the<br />

Marxist mantra that ‘the ruling ideas <strong>of</strong> each age have ever been the ideas <strong>of</strong> its<br />

ruling class.’<br />

21 D Litowitz ‘Gramsci, hegemony and the law’ (2000) Brigham Young <strong>University</strong> Law<br />

Review 515 531.<br />

22 As above.


160 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

specifically how law — a particular version <strong>of</strong> contract law — endorses<br />

and thus normalises or legitimates the individualist or libertarian<br />

worldview. For Gramsci as for Litowitz this second dimension <strong>of</strong><br />

hegemony is the more dangerous one as it carries within it the<br />

potential to paralyse all resistance and silence all questioning.<br />

Litowitz argues that the concept <strong>of</strong> hegemony requires the attention<br />

<strong>of</strong> students <strong>of</strong> law, precisely because it possesses this pr<strong>of</strong>ound<br />

‘ability to induce submission to a dominant worldview.’ 23<br />

Whereas Gramsci originally maintained that law is a hegemonic<br />

tool <strong>of</strong> the dominant class, Litowitz argues that when it comes to<br />

contemporary legal analysis a more nuanced notion <strong>of</strong> hegemony is<br />

required. Litowitz contends that under conditions <strong>of</strong> post-modernity<br />

we need an understanding <strong>of</strong> hegemony that avoids ‘Gramsci’s<br />

reliance on orthodox Marxist categories that are no longer tenable.’ 24<br />

Litowitz argues that postmodern theory brought about a pr<strong>of</strong>ound but<br />

gradual shift in the understanding <strong>of</strong> hegemony away from essentialist<br />

Marxist discourse rooted in rigid class distinction. 25 Postmodern<br />

theorists understood that oppression does not exclusively exist as the<br />

imposition <strong>of</strong> a dominant class and recognised that oppression is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

invisible and can exist merely in the silencing <strong>of</strong> alternative<br />

perspectives. 26 Postmodernism thus changed the operative<br />

terminology in discourse about hegemony from ‘“class/exploitation”<br />

to “discourse/marginalisation.”’ 27<br />

Litowitz explains that this development in hegemony discourse<br />

can help legal scholars to recognise that law is hegemonic at the<br />

meta-level (in that it always already represents and legitimises<br />

dominant interests) while contesting hegemony at the micro-level.<br />

For Litowitz law participates in the establishment <strong>of</strong> hegemony<br />

through the dissemination <strong>of</strong> a ‘dominant code or map’ 28 that relies<br />

on ‘unchallenged background assumptions that undergird the law.’ 29<br />

Thus law always already is hegemonic in that it ‘induces people to<br />

comply with a dominant set <strong>of</strong> practices and institutions without the<br />

threat <strong>of</strong> physical force’ 30 because people are lulled into a false<br />

consciousness about the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> law which causes them<br />

uncritically to accept legal practices and institutions that might in<br />

fact be harmful and exploitative. In other words the meta-level at<br />

which law is hegemony sustains and keeps in place law’s hegemonies<br />

at micro-level — and vice versa.<br />

23<br />

Litowitz (n 21 above) 516.<br />

24 Litowitz (n 21 above) 518.<br />

25 Litowitz (note 21 above) 533.<br />

26<br />

Litowitz (n 21 above) 534.<br />

27 As above.<br />

28 n 21 above, 517.<br />

29<br />

As above.<br />

30 As above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 161<br />

Under the force <strong>of</strong> hegemony the assertion that ‘law ... is also the<br />

site <strong>of</strong> everyday resistance and struggle’ 31 comes to be either<br />

dismissed and ignored or actively undermined and suppressed.<br />

However, contesting the hegemonies upon which the law as hegemony<br />

is founded can be the first step in raising consciousness upon which<br />

refusal and resistance <strong>of</strong> things as they are and supposedly always<br />

have been, can be built. 32 This is the central motivation behind the<br />

present focus on the hegemonic order(ing) in the South African law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract. I do not want to suggest that the Marxist roots <strong>of</strong> hegemony<br />

discourse can or should be simply or finally denied or that escape from<br />

these roots should be relentlessly pursued. 33 As we shall see, the<br />

South African law <strong>of</strong> contract vividly reflects the Gramscian insight<br />

that bourgeois best interests come to be uncritically accepted as the<br />

best interests <strong>of</strong> the working classes and the poor through the<br />

phenomenon <strong>of</strong> false consciousness which generates false consent.<br />

However, what postmodern theory contributes to hegemony discourse<br />

is the notion <strong>of</strong> discourse marginalisation. I will argue in what follows<br />

that the rise <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic order(ing) in the law <strong>of</strong> contract occurs<br />

through an explicit judicial marginalisation <strong>of</strong> discourses on equity,<br />

fairness and good faith. 34 In the context <strong>of</strong> the reconstitution <strong>of</strong> the<br />

South African legal order this raises important and difficult questions<br />

about the potential <strong>of</strong> the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract (in its current<br />

guise) to contribute to the project <strong>of</strong> transformative<br />

constitutionalism. 35<br />

31 K Calavita ‘Book review: M Lazarus-Black et al Contested states: Law, hegemony<br />

and resistance’ (1996) 25(1) Contemporary Sociology 94 94-96.<br />

32 Litowitz (note 21 above) 518. Also see D Kennedy ‘Antonio Gramsci and the legal<br />

system’ (1982) VI(1) ALSA Forum 32 37: ‘What the Gramscian analysis suggests is<br />

that one <strong>of</strong> the ways out <strong>of</strong> the reform/revolution problem in all these legal<br />

activities is to try to develop, at the level <strong>of</strong> conscious communication with other<br />

people, the extent to which they are letting their goals be perverted by the<br />

hegemonic false consciousness generated by law.’<br />

33 See in this regard E Laclau & C Mouffe Hegemony and socialist strategy (2ed,<br />

34<br />

35<br />

2001) viii.<br />

A detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> the link between, on the one hand, the ideas that<br />

predominate in judicial decisions in the law <strong>of</strong> contract and, on the other, the<br />

beliefs about social organisation that are dominant in elites and the general<br />

populace, falls beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this article. But see, for instance, E Mensch<br />

‘Freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as ideology’ (1981) 33 Stanford Law Review 753 757 who<br />

points out that the rise <strong>of</strong> the classical view <strong>of</strong> contract in the courts can be<br />

attributed to the popularity <strong>of</strong> Victorian moralism amongst the elites <strong>of</strong> the time.<br />

There are, in addition, several places in this article where I do not use the term<br />

‘hegemony’ in any purist Gramscian sense <strong>of</strong> the word but rather in its more<br />

general sense to denote predominance. Where the word is primarily used in this<br />

way there is nevertheless a secondary allusion to the Gramscian notion operating<br />

in the background.<br />

See K Klare ‘Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 146 146.


162 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

3 The rise <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic order(ing) in<br />

contract<br />

3.1 The rise <strong>of</strong> the market economy, the subjectivity <strong>of</strong><br />

value and the will theory<br />

The present hegemonic order(ing) in contract begins, <strong>of</strong> course, in the<br />

late 18 th century. At this point in history, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract still had<br />

an explicit and intricate connection with principles <strong>of</strong> morality such<br />

as fairness, conscience and justice. 36 The maxim pacta servanda sunt,<br />

in this understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, was still regarded as<br />

‘the imperative <strong>of</strong> good faith in contracts’. 37 As Atiyah points out,<br />

this meant that: ‘the Courts were, at that time, still more interested<br />

in seeing that parties to a contract made a fair exchange, than they<br />

were in enforcing bare promises.’ 38 On this approach, contracts were<br />

not enforced meticulously. Instead, they were meticulously subjected<br />

to enquiries into the fairness <strong>of</strong> the exchange.<br />

The problem with this approach to freedom <strong>of</strong> contract was that<br />

by the nineteenth century it became regarded as anachronistic,<br />

because it did not serve the interests <strong>of</strong> the rising commercial classes<br />

<strong>of</strong> the emerging market economies. 39 In these emerging economies<br />

value became regarded as entirely subjective. Horwitz indicates that,<br />

for this very reason, the late 18th century businessman became<br />

interested in a freedom <strong>of</strong> contract that would guarantee the express<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the agreed performance, regardless <strong>of</strong> the substantive<br />

equality <strong>of</strong> the exchange. 40 This meant that, as the market economies<br />

and the commercial classes became dominant, the law <strong>of</strong> contract as<br />

it existed up to that point came to be considered unsuited for the<br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> the new economies. In short, the eighteenth century<br />

equitable understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract was far too invested<br />

in the concept <strong>of</strong> objective value. The general view <strong>of</strong> the eighteenth<br />

36 MJ Horwitz ‘The historical foundations <strong>of</strong> modern contract law’ (1974) 87(5)<br />

Harvard Law Review 917 920. The eighteenth century approach is stated<br />

succinctly in Evans v Llewellyn [1787] 29 ER 1191 (Evans) 1191: ‘if the party is in<br />

a situation in which he is not a free agent and is not equal to protecting himself,<br />

this Court will protect him.’<br />

37 Van der Merwe et al Contract general principles (3 ed, 2007) 21 n 7 quoting H<br />

Eichler Die rechtslere vom vertrauen (1950) 8 (emphasis added). C Visser ‘The<br />

principle pacta servanda sunt in Roman and Roman-Dutch law’ (1984) 101 South<br />

African Law Journal 641 647 points out that originally pacta servanda sunt is<br />

integrally connected to good faith: ‘it would therefore appear that both canon<br />

law and the lex mercatoria from very early on accepted a general principle <strong>of</strong><br />

sanctity <strong>of</strong> contract, based upon a moral conception <strong>of</strong> good faith ...’ (emphasis<br />

added.)<br />

38 PS Atiyah The rise and fall <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract (1979) 438.<br />

39 Horwitz (n 36 above) 945-946.<br />

40 MJ Horwitz ‘The triumph <strong>of</strong> contract’ in AC Hutchinson (ed) Critical legal studies<br />

(1989) 104 106.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 163<br />

century was that substantive justice existed to ensure that legal<br />

subjects do not abuse the legal system to exploit each other. 41 In the<br />

nineteenth century the role and function <strong>of</strong> contract was no longer<br />

regarded as guaranteeing the justice <strong>of</strong> the exchange but to enforce<br />

so-called ‘willed’ transactions inter partes. 42 So arises the so-called<br />

‘modern’ or ‘classical’ law <strong>of</strong> contract in which the source <strong>of</strong><br />

contractual obligation shifted from equitable exchange to<br />

consensus. 43<br />

The pervasive political view <strong>of</strong> the nineteenth century — that <strong>of</strong><br />

unlimited liberal freedom — informed and provided the justification<br />

for a conception <strong>of</strong> ‘freedom’ <strong>of</strong> contract as the shibboleth for the<br />

privileging <strong>of</strong> the parties’ wills in conceptualising their<br />

relationships. 44 Once the concept <strong>of</strong> value became perceived as<br />

entirely subjective, the only basis for ascribing value could be<br />

concurrent, individual will. Principles <strong>of</strong> substantive justice came to<br />

be regarded as necessarily arbitrary and an uncertain standard <strong>of</strong><br />

value. 45 At the point where intrinsic value could no longer be ascribed<br />

to anything, so the argument went, no substantive measure could<br />

exist by reference to which it could be determined whether one party<br />

was exploiting the other. 46 On this view, the appearance <strong>of</strong> consensus<br />

came to represent the ‘evidence’ that the contractual exchange itself<br />

was a fair one.<br />

However, the loss incurred as a result <strong>of</strong> this shift in emphasis was<br />

particularly acute. Gordley indicates that nineteenth century jurists<br />

in fact entirely eliminated the concept <strong>of</strong> virtue from their discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract and were left with the will alone. 47 The motto <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

contract thus became this: ‘a man is obliged in conscience to perform<br />

a contract which he has entered into freely, although it be a hard one<br />

...’. 48 As Hahlo so aptly described it: Darwinian survival <strong>of</strong> the fittest,<br />

the law <strong>of</strong> nature, also became the law <strong>of</strong> the marketplace. 49<br />

41 Mensch (n 34 above) 753, 756.<br />

42 As above.<br />

43 Horwitz (n 36 above) 946.<br />

44 Horwitz (n 36 above) 917. Also see J Gordley The philosophical origins <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

contract doctrine (1991) 161 where the point is made that consensus was applied<br />

almost exclusively to explain the basis <strong>of</strong> contractual obligations.<br />

45 Horwitz (n 36 above) 917.<br />

46 As above.<br />

47 Gordley (n 44 above) 162.<br />

48 IJ Powell ‘Essay upon the law <strong>of</strong> contracts and agreements’ (1790) as quoted in<br />

Horwitz (n 36 above) 917.<br />

49 HR Hahlo ‘Unfair contract terms in civil-law systems’ (1981) 98 South African Law<br />

Journal 70.


164 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

3.2 The role <strong>of</strong> individualism<br />

The above formulation evinces the understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract <strong>of</strong> advancing and advanced liberal capitalism underpinned by<br />

what is euphemistically called the ‘morality’ <strong>of</strong> individualism. 50<br />

Individualism accepts as given a world <strong>of</strong> independent individuals who<br />

are encouraged to prefer the pursuit <strong>of</strong> self-interest rigorously. A<br />

consideration or sensitivity for the interests <strong>of</strong> others falls outside <strong>of</strong><br />

the aims <strong>of</strong> this way <strong>of</strong> life, although one should be prepared to obey<br />

the rules that make it possible to co-exist with other self-interested<br />

individuals. 51 Other than this, the individual is entirely self-reliant.<br />

His conduct conforms to the belief that other individuals in the<br />

community are themselves motivated only by pure self-interest. 52 As<br />

regards individualism’s economic manifestation, Cockrell puts it<br />

succinctly: ‘[I]ndividualism assumes a world <strong>of</strong> traders who meet<br />

briefly on the market floor, where they engage in discrete and furtive<br />

transactions.’ 53 This view is <strong>of</strong>ten described as market-individualism<br />

and reveals that the capitalist idea <strong>of</strong> the market and the ‘moral’ idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> individualism are heavily invested in each other. 54<br />

Individualist beliefs regarding the role <strong>of</strong> law in society follow<br />

from the above convictions. Individualism holds that the law cannot<br />

impose upon legal subjects as a group the liability <strong>of</strong> shared pr<strong>of</strong>its or<br />

loss. 55 The law merely fixes the boundaries <strong>of</strong> individual freedom by<br />

defining and enforcing rights. 56 In the context <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract,<br />

individualism believes that the parties create their own law through<br />

agreement (consensus) which is itself a manifestation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual’s autonomy. Mensch refers to this phenomenon as a ‘magic<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> formation, when individual wills created a right whose<br />

enforcement was necessary for the protection <strong>of</strong> free will itself.’ 57<br />

Contractual liability is thus only determined by the formal agreement<br />

(consensus) <strong>of</strong> the parties. The law <strong>of</strong> contract in an individualistic<br />

world, to borrow from Macaulay, provides the glue that binds<br />

50<br />

Kennedy (n 6 above) 1774. Kennedy goes so far as to argue that ‘[t]he “freedom”<br />

<strong>of</strong> individualism is negative, alienated and arbitrary. It consists in the absence <strong>of</strong><br />

restraint on the individual's choice <strong>of</strong> ends, and has no moral content whatever.’<br />

51<br />

JM Feinman ‘Critical approaches to contract law’ (1983) 30 UCLA Law Review 829<br />

839; Kennedy (n 6 above) 1713.<br />

52 Kennedy points out that the individualist ethic should be distinguished from the<br />

egotistical ethic in the sense that the individualist ethic has a strong positive<br />

‘moral’ content whereas the egotist believes that it is entirely impossible and<br />

undesirable to place any limits on the perusal <strong>of</strong> self-interest. See Kennedy (n 6<br />

above) 1714–1715.<br />

53 A Cockrell ‘Substance and form in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract’ (1992) 109<br />

South African Law Journal 40 41.<br />

54<br />

See CJ Pretorius ‘Individualism, collectivism and the limits <strong>of</strong> good faith’ (2003)<br />

66 Tydskrif vir die Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 638 639.<br />

55 Kennedy (n 6 above) 1713.<br />

56<br />

Cockrell (n 53 above) 42.<br />

57 Mensch (n 34 above) 760.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 165<br />

individuals to their agreements. 58 This emphasis on the creation <strong>of</strong> an<br />

own law through the agreement causes individualism to take the view<br />

that courts should enforce agreements rather than intervene in<br />

relation to their terms on grounds <strong>of</strong> fairness or equity. 59<br />

With the rise <strong>of</strong> the market economy in the nineteenth century,<br />

the entire conceptual apparatus <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract thus developed<br />

around this understanding <strong>of</strong> the relationship between the individual<br />

and society, the individual and the State and the individual and the<br />

law. 60 As Feinman indicates:<br />

Classical legal thought imagined a world <strong>of</strong> independent individuals,<br />

each <strong>of</strong> whom acts within a broad sphere <strong>of</strong> legal autonomy to pursue<br />

her own self-interest. The market was the model <strong>of</strong> social organisation<br />

and the acquisitive capitalist the paragon <strong>of</strong> personal behavior. 61<br />

In the law <strong>of</strong> contract this thought established freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as<br />

the hegemony (predominance) <strong>of</strong> the will theory. Duncan Kennedy<br />

famously added that the hegemony <strong>of</strong> individualism on the level <strong>of</strong><br />

substance, in turn established the hegemony <strong>of</strong> rules on the level <strong>of</strong><br />

contract law’s formal commitments. 62<br />

But because <strong>of</strong> the fact that domination is implied in the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> hegemony it would be inaccurate to contend that hegemony<br />

manages to liquidate its other entirely. This means that hegemony<br />

always implies a relation — a relation <strong>of</strong> domination and privileging,<br />

yes, but nevertheless, a relation. The trace <strong>of</strong> the Other thus always<br />

haunts any hegemony. The reason why this particular privileging or<br />

domination is hegemonic is because, as Cockrell indicates, ‘this<br />

privileging invariably proceeds on the basis that the preference for<br />

individualism and the rule-form is an axiomatic truth rather than a<br />

controversial premise in an ongoing argument.’ 63 The danger is that<br />

the hegemonic version <strong>of</strong> contract can lead us to think that this is the<br />

only order(ing) available in the law <strong>of</strong> contract — that freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract grounded in individualism and the commitment to the ruleform,<br />

is the only version <strong>of</strong> contract that exists. 64<br />

58<br />

S Macaulay ‘An empirical view <strong>of</strong> contract’ (1985) Wisconsin Law Review 465 466.<br />

59 Pretorius (n 54 above) 640.<br />

60 As Dalton points out, the will theory <strong>of</strong> contract flows from the political doctrine<br />

<strong>of</strong> contractualism, which holds that ‘all restraint is evil and that the government<br />

that governs least is best.’ See C Dalton ‘An essay in the deconstruction <strong>of</strong><br />

contract doctrine’ (1985) 94 The Yale Law Journal 997 1013.<br />

61<br />

J Feinman ‘The conservatives, the market and the common Law’ (2005) 37<br />

Review <strong>of</strong> Radical Political Economics 288 290.<br />

62 Kennedy (n 6 above) 1685: ‘[t]he substantive and formal dimensions are related<br />

because the same moral, economic and political arguments appear in each.’<br />

63 Cockrell (n 53 above) 46.<br />

64 Pretorius (n 54 above) 644: ‘There is no difficulty in recognising that individualism<br />

is the primary ideology underlying the law <strong>of</strong> contract. The problem lies in<br />

suggesting that it is the only one.’


166 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

The individualistic or liberal worldview in the understanding <strong>of</strong><br />

contract did not and could not manage to altogether absent the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract from alternative worldviews. Applied to our current<br />

context this insight would imply that the traces <strong>of</strong> the pre-nineteenth<br />

century understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract could not be erased by<br />

either the domination <strong>of</strong> the commercial classes <strong>of</strong> the nineteenth<br />

century or by the courts that represented their interests. The old<br />

underlying moral conceptions on which the law <strong>of</strong> contract was<br />

founded prior to the domination <strong>of</strong> individualism could thus not be<br />

abandoned outright. 65 For one, the courts still naively wanted to<br />

believe that parties to the contract were in fact reaching consensus<br />

on its terms as honest, just, fair and non-exploitative persons (that is,<br />

persons who are in good faith). To this extent the courts still<br />

acknowledged external standards <strong>of</strong> justice. But the critical legal<br />

issue had shifted from whether the contract was fair to whether there<br />

objectively appeared to have been a ‘meeting <strong>of</strong> the minds’ between<br />

the contracting parties. 66<br />

Horwitz points out that although nineteenth century courts could<br />

not succeed in negating the ancient relation between natural law and<br />

contract law, they did succeed in setting up a system in which the<br />

courts could effectively ‘pick and choose’ which groups within the<br />

broad society they wanted to benefit in a given case. 67 The discourse<br />

<strong>of</strong> the nineteenth century managed to set-up an intellectual divide<br />

between the system <strong>of</strong> formal rules (associated with the ‘rule <strong>of</strong> law’<br />

or law as rules) 68 and the ancient perceptions <strong>of</strong> morality and equity<br />

(which was seen as necessarily undermining the rule <strong>of</strong> law or<br />

perhaps, then, the law <strong>of</strong> rules). As already mentioned, the argument<br />

in Critical Legal Studies has been that this preference for rules was<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the classical laissez-faire individualist morality grounded in<br />

non-interventionism. 69 It is thus no coincidence that most <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

general contract law consists <strong>of</strong> rules by way <strong>of</strong> which one determines<br />

whether the will <strong>of</strong> the parties coincided and if not, rules that<br />

regulate the undoing <strong>of</strong> the exchange. 70 These rules are ordered<br />

around the doctrines <strong>of</strong> misrepresentation, duress, undue influence<br />

and so forth — theories that allegedly turn on the negation <strong>of</strong> the will<br />

— and do not visit explicitly — or explicitly do not visit — matters such<br />

65 Horwitz (n 36 above) 953.<br />

66<br />

Horwitz (n 36 above) 955.<br />

67 As above.<br />

68 C Douzinas & A Geary Critical jurisprudence (2005) 7.<br />

69<br />

Kennedy (n 6 above) 1741.<br />

70 See Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 19-32.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 167<br />

as the fairness <strong>of</strong> the bargain or the good faith <strong>of</strong> the parties. 71 The<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> reasonable reliance on the appearance <strong>of</strong> consensus — as an<br />

alternative basis for the existence <strong>of</strong> a contract — is itself simply seen<br />

as a qualification <strong>of</strong> the will theory and not as a negation or in any way<br />

a complete alternative to it. 72 Yet, as Cockrell indicates, the origin <strong>of</strong><br />

the defect in the defences based on the negation <strong>of</strong> the will does not<br />

in fact reside in the will <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the parties, but rather in the<br />

improper conduct. The same reasoning applies to the theory <strong>of</strong><br />

reasonable reliance. These defences, as Cockrell argues, are all<br />

concerned with the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> conduct, and one way to link them<br />

would be to say that they all amount to instances <strong>of</strong> bad faith on the<br />

part <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the parties. 73 On the hegemonic understanding,<br />

however, the open-ended norms or standards <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

cannot do this work. It cannot be directly employed or appealed to in<br />

the adjudication <strong>of</strong> contractual disputes. In this regard, the point that<br />

has repeatedly been made by our own courts in the recent past is that<br />

good faith, reasonableness and fairness, although subjacent to, or<br />

underpinning the law <strong>of</strong> contract, can only be used in the resolution<br />

<strong>of</strong> contractual disputes to the extent that they have become<br />

embodied in so-called crystallised rules <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract. 74 We<br />

will return to this problematic assertion below but for now it is<br />

important to state the general contention that these assertions serve<br />

only (in very real political ways) to keep the hegemony firmly in<br />

place.<br />

4 The hegemonic order(ing) in the South African<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

4.1 Public policy as handmaiden and adversary <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract<br />

Colonialism and imperialism <strong>of</strong> course carried the individualist<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract grounded in the will to the<br />

numerous colonies. It is thus not surprising that the South African law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract from its very inception reflects the hegemony <strong>of</strong> the will<br />

71 CFC Van der Walt ‘Die huidige posisie in die Suid-Afrikaanse reg met betrekking<br />

tot onbillike kontraksbedinge’ (1986) 103 South African Law Journal 646 658. Also<br />

see Dalton (n 60 above) 1001 who makes the point that dealing with unfairness via<br />

those constructs that affect the will <strong>of</strong> the parties (duress, misrepresentation,<br />

undue influence etc) effectively constitutes a privatisation <strong>of</strong> the public enquiry<br />

into contract when ‘the undoing <strong>of</strong> a defective deal [is] presented as depending<br />

upon the absence <strong>of</strong> will or intent rather than on mere inequivalence <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange.’<br />

72 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 22.<br />

73 Cockrell (n 53 above) 56.<br />

74<br />

See Brisley (n 13 above) 16B-C; Afrox Healthcare (n 13 above) 40H-41A; South<br />

African Forestry (n 13 above) 338J-339B; and Napier (n 13 above) para 7.


168 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> contract. One <strong>of</strong> the most frequently quoted passages — ‘the<br />

most privileged statement <strong>of</strong> all’ 75 — justifying the privileging <strong>of</strong> (the<br />

‘will theory version’ <strong>of</strong>) freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

contractual obligation in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract, is to be<br />

found in a late nineteenth century case from the English law, Printing<br />

and Numerical Registering Co v Sampson: 76<br />

If there is one thing more than another which public policy requires, it is<br />

that men <strong>of</strong> full age and competent understanding shall have the utmost<br />

liberty in contracting, and their contracts, when entered into freely and<br />

voluntarily, shall be held sacred and shall be enforced by Courts <strong>of</strong><br />

Justice. Therefore you have this paramount public policy to consider —<br />

that you are not lightly to interfere with this freedom <strong>of</strong> contract. 77<br />

In Burger v Central South African Railways 78 Innes CJ ‘developed’ this<br />

basic premise and held in no uncertain terms that the South African<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract does not recognise the right <strong>of</strong> a court to release a<br />

party to a contract from his obligations on considerations <strong>of</strong><br />

fairness. 79 And this is precisely the point, (as will hopefully become<br />

clearer below): when the focus is on the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

particularly, the rise <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic order(ing) <strong>of</strong> (freedom <strong>of</strong>)<br />

contract should be considered in the context <strong>of</strong> the fall <strong>of</strong> numerous<br />

values, principles and rights that came to be understood as freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract’s adversaries and so became regarded as opposed to it.<br />

A doctrinal aspect that has remained uncontroversial in the grand<br />

narrative <strong>of</strong> the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract has been the<br />

recognition that contracts concluded contra bonos mores and/or<br />

contrary to public policy fall foul <strong>of</strong> the validity requirement <strong>of</strong><br />

legality and are therefore either void or unenforceable. 80 The extent<br />

<strong>of</strong> this power to declare void or unenforceable contracts or terms<br />

75 Cockrell (n 53 above) 46. See, for example, Wells v South African Alumenite<br />

Company 1927 AD 69 73 (Wells); R<strong>of</strong>fey v Catterall, Edwards & Goudré (Pty) Ltd<br />

1977 4 SA 494 (N) (R<strong>of</strong>fey) 504G-H; Sasfin (Pty) Ltd v Beukes 1989 1 SA 1 (A)<br />

(Sasfin) 9F; Edouard v Administrator, Natal 1989 2 SA 368 (D) (Edouard) 379A;<br />

Baart v Malan 1990 2 SA 862 (E) (Baart) 868A; De Klerk v Old Mutual Insurance Co<br />

Ltd 1990 3 SA 34 (E) (De Klerk) 44; Benlou Properties (Pty) Ltd v Vector Graphics<br />

(Pty) Ltd 1993 1 SA 179 (A) (Benlou Properties) 187H; Standard Bank <strong>of</strong> SA Ltd v<br />

Wilkinson 1993 3 SA 822 (C) (Standard Bank) 830D; and Basson v Chilwan and<br />

Others 1993 3 SA 742 (A) (Basson) 761G. See also V Terblanche (2002) ‘The<br />

Constitution and general equitable jurisdiction in South African contract law’<br />

unpublished LLD thesis, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong>, 2002 153 who refers to the<br />

‘privileged position <strong>of</strong> 19th century contract law theory in South Africa.’<br />

76 1875 LR 19 (Printing and Numerical Registering Co) Eq 462 per Jessel MR.<br />

77<br />

Printing and Numerical Registering Co (n 76 above) Eq 465. The mood is also<br />

expressed in more general terms by Kotze CJ in Brown v Leyds (1897) 4 OR 17<br />

(Brown) 31 who held that ‘no Court <strong>of</strong> Justice is competent to inquire into the<br />

internal value, in the sense <strong>of</strong> the policy, <strong>of</strong> the law, but only in the sense <strong>of</strong> the<br />

meaning or matter <strong>of</strong> the law’.<br />

78 1903 TS 571 (Burger).<br />

79<br />

Burger case (n 78 above) 576.<br />

80 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 192-193, 200-203.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 169<br />

contrary to public policy was expressed as follows in Morrison v<br />

Angelo Deep Gold Mines Ltd: 81<br />

[I]t is a general principle that a man contracting without duress, without<br />

fraud and understanding what he does, may freely waive any <strong>of</strong> his<br />

rights. There are certain exceptions to that rule, and certainly the law<br />

will not recognise any arrangement which is contrary to public policy.<br />

The dialectic that emerges here is that, on the one hand, public policy<br />

generally favours the utmost freedom <strong>of</strong> contract but, on the other,<br />

contracts concluded in violation <strong>of</strong> public policy are unenforceable or<br />

void. Public policy is thus regarded (from the perspective <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract) as both a legitimating and controlling device in our law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract. 82 The resolution/synthesis <strong>of</strong> this dialectic is, however,<br />

not impossible when one understands that the exercise <strong>of</strong> alleged<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract is precisely not freedom <strong>of</strong> contract — that is, it<br />

is not freedom that can legitimate a contractual arrangement — when<br />

it is exercised contrary to public policy. This understanding also points<br />

to a deeper problem with the notion <strong>of</strong> autonomy as freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract, which is said to form the cornerstone or foundational<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract. The public policy requirement<br />

communicates that some contracts that are freely entered into (that<br />

is, in which the wills <strong>of</strong> legally competent parties overlap) will not be<br />

enforced for want <strong>of</strong> legality (in the broad sense). This means that, as<br />

a matter <strong>of</strong> a contract’s validity, there is a constitutive limit on<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract that inevitably denies absolute party autonomy.<br />

And since legality is determined externally (not by the parties but<br />

with reference to ‘the interests and convictions’ <strong>of</strong> the society in<br />

which the contract is concluded) 83 it means that the cornerstone <strong>of</strong><br />

the law <strong>of</strong> contract is both autonomous and heteronymous.<br />

Our courts, however, do not approach the matter in this way.<br />

Freedom <strong>of</strong> contract is consistently opposed to other ideals, values<br />

and rights, instead <strong>of</strong> integrally connected to and thus determined by<br />

those other values and rights. When public policy is, for instance,<br />

considered in relation to restraint <strong>of</strong> trade clauses the position is<br />

taken that ‘two values or freedoms come into conflict ... namely<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract and freedom <strong>of</strong> trade.’ 84 In our law the position<br />

(since the decision in Magna Alloys) 85 has been that restraints <strong>of</strong> trade<br />

are in principle enforceable in accordance with freedom <strong>of</strong> contract,<br />

81<br />

1905 TS 775 (Morrison) 779.<br />

82 See Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 17.<br />

83 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 191.<br />

84<br />

Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 213. Also see R<strong>of</strong>fey (n 75 above) 505F (per<br />

Didcott J): ‘I am satisfied that South African law prefers the sanctity <strong>of</strong> contracts<br />

... Freedom <strong>of</strong> trade does not vibrate nearly as strongly through our jurisprudence<br />

... it is intrinsically the less commanding <strong>of</strong> the two ideas.’<br />

85 Magna Alloys & Research (SA) (Pty) Ltd v Ellis 1984 4 SA 874 (A) (Magna Alloys).


170 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

unless the restraint is contrary to public policy, the measure <strong>of</strong> public<br />

policy in relation to restraints <strong>of</strong> trade being reasonableness. 86 On<br />

this formulation, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract is said to be the ‘preferred<br />

value’. 87<br />

Recently the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> the Magna Alloys formulation<br />

was questioned in the case <strong>of</strong> Reddy v Siemens Telecommunications<br />

(Pty) Ltd 88 where it was argued that restraints <strong>of</strong> trade constitute<br />

limitations on the right to freely choose a trade, occupation or<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ession — a right expressly protected in section 22 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution. 89 This means, so the argument went, that a restraint <strong>of</strong><br />

trade is enforceable only when it can be proved by the employer who<br />

wants to enforce it to be a reasonable and justifiable limitation (as<br />

required by section 36 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution) on the section 22 right. 90<br />

The Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal (per Malan AJA) held that this argument<br />

effectively constituted an argument regarding onus and did not<br />

contest the earlier findings <strong>of</strong> the courts<br />

that a restraint that is found to be reasonably required for the<br />

protection <strong>of</strong> the party who seeks to enforce it, in accordance with the<br />

test that has been laid down in the cases, is constitutionally<br />

permitted. 91<br />

The Court declined to adjudicate the issue <strong>of</strong> onus, holding that,<br />

‘whether the onus was reversed or not, the result in the present case<br />

would be the same.’ 92 It continued to hold that what is called for in<br />

86 In the context <strong>of</strong> the rules/standards discourse it should be pointed out that our<br />

courts do not seem to experience difficulty with the standard <strong>of</strong> ‘reasonableness’<br />

both in the context <strong>of</strong> the public policy requirement and outside <strong>of</strong> it. In addition<br />

to its role in the area <strong>of</strong> restraints <strong>of</strong> trade provisions and public policy,<br />

reasonableness also plays a decisive role in the determination <strong>of</strong> contractual<br />

liability on the basis <strong>of</strong> reliance or the doctrine <strong>of</strong> quasi-mutual assent. In this<br />

regard see, for instance, Sonap Petroleum (SA) (Pty) Ltd v Pappadogianis 1992 3<br />

SA 234 (A) (Sonap Petroleum) and Constantia Insurance v Compusource (Pty) Ltd<br />

2005 4 SA 345 (SCA) (Constantia Insurance).<br />

87 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 215.<br />

88<br />

2007 2 SA 486 (SCA) (Reddy).<br />

89 In Canon KwaZulu-Natal (Pty) Ltd t/a Canon Office Automation v Booth 2005 3 SA<br />

205 (N) (Canon) 208-209 the court endorsed this reasoning.<br />

90<br />

Reddy (n 88 above) 495C-E.<br />

91 Reddy (n 88 above) 495D. See Waltons Stationery Co (Edms) Bpk v Fourie en 'n<br />

Ander 1994 4 SA 507 (O) (Waltons Stationary) 510I-511F (SA); Kotze & Genis<br />

(Edms) Bpk en 'n Ander v Potgieter en Andere 1995 3 SA 783 (C) (Kotze & Genis)<br />

786E-I; Knox D'Arcy Ltd and Another v Shaw and Another 1996 2 SA 651 (W) (Knox)<br />

657Hff and 661D-F, CTP Ltd and Others v Independent Newspaper Holdings Ltd<br />

1999 1 SA 452 (W) (CTP) 468G-H; Fidelity Guards Holdings (Pty) Ltd t/a Fidelity<br />

Guards v Pearmain 2001 2 SA 853 (SE) (Fidelity Guards) 861F-862G; and Oasis<br />

Group Holdings (Pty) Ltd and Another v Bray [2006] 4 All SA 183 (C) (Oasis Group)<br />

paras 23-25.<br />

92 Reddy (n 88 above) 496A-B.


the case <strong>of</strong> restraints <strong>of</strong> trade is a value judgment<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 171<br />

with two principal policy considerations in mind in determining the<br />

reasonableness <strong>of</strong> a restraint. The first is that the public interest<br />

requires that parties should comply with their contractual obligations, a<br />

notion expressed by the maxim pacta servanda sunt. The second is that<br />

all persons should in the interests <strong>of</strong> society be productive and be<br />

permitted to engage in trade and commerce or the pr<strong>of</strong>essions. 93<br />

It concluded that the common law approach to the determination <strong>of</strong><br />

the reasonableness or not <strong>of</strong> the restraint ‘gives effect to the precepts<br />

<strong>of</strong> section 36(1) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’. 94 Thus the enquiry into the<br />

reasonableness <strong>of</strong> the restraint simultaneously answers the question<br />

whether the restraint is a reasonable and justifiable limitation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

right in question.<br />

Clearly, the Court here views the right to choose a trade,<br />

occupation or pr<strong>of</strong>ession freely as coming into conflict with freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract as pacta servanda sunt. However, an alternative approach<br />

was followed in the later judgment <strong>of</strong> Davis J in Advtech Resourcing<br />

t/a Communicate Personnel Group v Kuhn. 95 In this judgment Davis J<br />

held that if contractual autonomy is part <strong>of</strong> the constitutional value<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom and informs the ideal <strong>of</strong> dignity, 96 then under a<br />

transformative Constitution such as ours, contractual autonomy must<br />

be read as internally limited by the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and ‘the<br />

spirit <strong>of</strong> the Constitution read as a whole’. 97 In the context <strong>of</strong><br />

restraints <strong>of</strong> trade this means that section 22 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

places an internal limit on freedom <strong>of</strong> contract to the extent that<br />

agreements in restraint <strong>of</strong> trade that constitute unreasonable and<br />

unjustifiable limitations on the section 22 right, will not be enforced.<br />

And since a restraint <strong>of</strong> trade constitutes a prima facie violation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

section 22 right, an employer who wants to enforce the restraint must<br />

prove that it is a reasonable and justifiable limitation <strong>of</strong> the right. 98<br />

When the Constitution states that the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights does not deny<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> any other rights or freedoms that are recognised or<br />

conferred by common law ‘to the extent that they are consistent with<br />

the Bill’ <strong>of</strong> Rights 99 it places the common law notion <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract on an equal footing with all the rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. In<br />

so doing, it contests the a priori elevation <strong>of</strong> a liberal notion <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract in the common law in the sense that it calls for<br />

93 Reddy (n 88 above) 496D.<br />

94 Reddy (n 88 above) 497 F/G.<br />

95<br />

2008 2 SA 375 (C) (Advtech).<br />

96 Advtech (n 95 above) 387I.<br />

97 Advtech (n 95 above) 388A.<br />

98<br />

Advtech (n 95 above) 387A.<br />

99 Section 39(3) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.


172 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

a synchronisation <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract with the ideals, values and<br />

rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. Drucilla Cornell distinguishes the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> synchronisation from both Dworkinian coherence and liberal<br />

conceptions <strong>of</strong> balancing: ‘Synchronisation recognises that there are<br />

competing rights situations and real conflicts, which may not be able<br />

to yield a “coherent” whole.’ 100 For Cornell synchronisation refuses<br />

closure and so calls for an ongoing, never-ended (re-)thinking <strong>of</strong> the<br />

whole even as it marks the failure <strong>of</strong> constructive coherence. For<br />

Cornell ‘the tension between the promise <strong>of</strong> synchronisation and the<br />

failure <strong>of</strong> its achievement’ opens the law to its transformative<br />

potential. 101<br />

In this context and on this approach, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as pacta<br />

servanda sunt, becomes internally defined by the right in section 22<br />

and, for that matter, any other right in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights as well as the<br />

founding values and ideals <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. But such an approach<br />

is only possible once one accepts that section 22 (and indeed all the<br />

rights in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights) is on an equal footing with freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract (as the Constitution clearly says it is). Simply put, there<br />

cannot be talk <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract where the restraint <strong>of</strong> trade (or<br />

whatever contractual provision) is found to unreasonably and<br />

unjustifiably limit a right in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights or can be said to be<br />

contrary to the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. It goes<br />

without saying that where the limitation <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right is<br />

alleged in the context <strong>of</strong> restraints <strong>of</strong> trade, such an approach would<br />

— in this context — require the prioritisation <strong>of</strong> direct horizontal<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, even though indirect horizontal<br />

application might lead to the same result. 102<br />

The oppositional/dualistic reading <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract — by<br />

way <strong>of</strong> which its hegemonic understanding is maintained — is, in<br />

addition, also clearly illustrated through the unwillingness to read a<br />

fairness jurisdiction into the public policy requirement. 103 As Glover<br />

argues, the defence that the enforcement <strong>of</strong> a contract is in specific<br />

circumstances unfair or unconscionable, has only been approved <strong>of</strong> in<br />

100 D Cornell Transformations (1993) 36.<br />

101 n 100 above, 35.<br />

102 See in this regard S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing bill <strong>of</strong> rights’ (2007) 3 South<br />

African Law Journal 762 777. To reach directly for the baton <strong>of</strong> indirect horizontal<br />

application by way <strong>of</strong> sec 39(2) when a constitutional right is alleged to have been<br />

infringed is to render sec 8 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution redundant. As Woolman indicates,<br />

such an approach is inconsistent with the Constitutional Court’s decision in<br />

Khumalo v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 (CC) (Khumalo) para 32 where O’Regan J made<br />

it clear ‘that we should not attribute a meaning to one section <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

that renders another section, quite literally, senseless.’<br />

103 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 199. P Aronstam Consumer protection, freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract and the law (1979) 43.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 173<br />

the restraint <strong>of</strong> trade context where, as we have seen, the restraint<br />

<strong>of</strong> trade is subjected to a reasonableness enquiry. 104<br />

However, in Sasfin v Beukes 105 the Appellate Division considered<br />

the extent to which ‘simple justice between man and man’ 106 can<br />

trump the public interest in the strict enforcement <strong>of</strong> contracts<br />

generally. Primarily, the case centred around the validity <strong>of</strong> a deed<br />

<strong>of</strong> cession in which a customer <strong>of</strong> a bank (a doctor) ceded all his future<br />

debtors to the bank regardless <strong>of</strong> whether he owed the bank money<br />

or not. 107 The cession effectively rendered the doctor the slave <strong>of</strong> the<br />

bank. The majority <strong>of</strong> the court was <strong>of</strong> the opinion that these aspects<br />

<strong>of</strong> the cession could not be severed from the rest <strong>of</strong> the agreement<br />

and held that the entire transaction was unenforceable. 108<br />

In this case the Appellate Division was willing to evaluate the<br />

substantive fairness <strong>of</strong> the disputed deed <strong>of</strong> cession to come to a<br />

conclusion that the cession was clearly unreasonable and<br />

irreconcilable with the public interest. Lewis describes the decision<br />

as ‘the one decision which yields a ray <strong>of</strong> light in the field <strong>of</strong><br />

contractual policy, where the court was both bold and innovative in<br />

escaping the shackles <strong>of</strong> formalism’. 109 Be that as it may, one again<br />

sees the opposition between freedom <strong>of</strong> contract and other values in<br />

Smalberger JA’s judgment where it is held that unlawfulness comes<br />

into play where the public interest in the strict enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

contracts in accordance with the principle <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, is<br />

trumped by other relevant factors. 110 These relevant factors are<br />

expressed by the Court to ensure that ‘public policy ... properly take<br />

into account the doing <strong>of</strong> simple justice between man and man.’ 111<br />

The uneasiness with which the Appellate Division approaches the<br />

issue <strong>of</strong> unfair contracts is illustrated in the following famous dictum:<br />

No court should therefore shrink from the duty <strong>of</strong> declaring a contract<br />

contrary to public policy when the occasion so demands. The power to<br />

declare contracts contrary to public policy should however be exercised<br />

sparingly and only in the clearest <strong>of</strong> cases, lest uncertainty as to the<br />

validity <strong>of</strong> contracts result from an arbitrary and indiscriminate use <strong>of</strong><br />

the power. One must be careful not to conclude that a contract is<br />

104 G Glover ‘Lazarus in the Constitutional Court: An exhumation <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli<br />

generalis?’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 449 451.<br />

105 1989 1 SA 1 (A) (Sasfin).<br />

106 As above.<br />

107 Sasfin (n 105 above) 6A-D.<br />

108 Sasfin (n 105 above) 17-19.<br />

109 C Lewis ‘Towards an equitable theory <strong>of</strong> contract: The contribution <strong>of</strong> Mr Justice<br />

EL Jansen to the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract’ (1991) 108 South African Law<br />

Journal 249 264 n76.<br />

110 Sasfin (n 105 above) 9D-G.<br />

111 Sasfin (n 105 above) 13J.


174 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

contrary to public policy merely because its terms (or some <strong>of</strong> them)<br />

<strong>of</strong>fend one's individual sense <strong>of</strong> propriety and fairness. 112<br />

Hawthorne has remarked that the dicta above merely emphasises the<br />

South African judiciary’s narrow interpretation <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong><br />

equity considerations in the public interest. 113 By holding that it is<br />

only in the ‘clearest <strong>of</strong> cases’ that a court may use its power to refuse<br />

to enforce an unfair term, and that the power to do this must be used<br />

‘sparingly’, the court suggests that unconscionability in and <strong>of</strong> itself<br />

cannot invalidate a contract. 114 The promise that we can correct for<br />

clear or extreme cases only, simply suggests, to paraphrase Dalton,<br />

that the worst features <strong>of</strong> the system can be held in check, without<br />

tinkering with its regular operation. 115 Van der Merwe et al confirm<br />

the matter:<br />

Sasfin’s decision must not be interpreted to mean that the unreasonably<br />

harsh or unconscionable effect <strong>of</strong> a term between the parties is by itself<br />

a sufficient ground for making an agreement illegal. 116<br />

In Donelly 117 Kriegler J stressed this point and placed a great deal <strong>of</strong><br />

emphasis on the fact that the Sasfin judgment should not be regarded<br />

‘as a free pardon to recalcitrant and otherwise defenceless<br />

debtors’ 118 because it is ‘decidedly not that’. 119 Kriegler J also did<br />

not let the opportunity pass to emphasise that ‘pacta servanda sunt<br />

is still a cornerstone <strong>of</strong> our law <strong>of</strong> contract’ 120 and that ‘nothing said<br />

or implied’ 121 in the Sasfin principle can be said to derogate from this<br />

important fact. 122 In Botha (now Griessel) v Finanscredit (Pty) Ltd 123<br />

the Appellate Division confirmed that<br />

a Court’s power to declare contracts contrary to public policy should be<br />

exercised sparingly and only in cases in which the impropriety <strong>of</strong> the<br />

transaction and the element <strong>of</strong> public harm are manifest. 124<br />

112 Sasfin (n 105 above) 9A-B. (emphasis added)<br />

113 L Hawthorne ‘Public policy and micro lending — has the unruly horse died?’ (2003)<br />

66 THRHR 116 118.<br />

114 These sentiments are also reflected in cases decided by the lower courts in the<br />

aftermath <strong>of</strong> Sasfin. See in this regard Standard Bank (n 75 above) 825C-827A and<br />

Pangbourne Properties Ltd v Nitor Construction (Pty) Ltd 1993 4 SA 206 (W)<br />

(Pangbourne Properties) 210G-214F.<br />

115 Dalton (n 60 above) 1037.<br />

116 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 219.<br />

117 Donelly v Barclays National Bank Ltd 1990 1 SA 375 (W) (Donelly).<br />

118 n 117 above, 381F.<br />

119 As above.<br />

120 Donelly (n 117 above) 381H.<br />

121 As above.<br />

122 As above.<br />

123 1989 3 SA 773 (A) (Botha).<br />

124 Botha (n 123 above) 782I-783C.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 175<br />

In this case the court refused to declare a deed <strong>of</strong> suretyship void<br />

on the grounds <strong>of</strong> public policy, holding that, although ‘somewhat<br />

rigorous’, the surety was not left ‘helpless in the clutches <strong>of</strong> the<br />

plaintiff’. 125 This prompts one to ask whether one party should<br />

necessarily be left helpless in the clutches <strong>of</strong> the other for the court<br />

to exercise its Sasfin power? If so, very little <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> reform and<br />

transformation <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract can be expected to be done<br />

through the utilisation <strong>of</strong> the Sasfin principle.<br />

But the point that I would like to stress going forward is that the<br />

courts’ concern with maintaining the hegemony <strong>of</strong> the will theory <strong>of</strong><br />

contract causes them to assume that there is an area in which<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract can be exercised independent <strong>of</strong> public policy,<br />

fairness, reasonableness and good faith. From a political point <strong>of</strong><br />

view, the paradox which inscribes itself in this opposition between<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract and the so-called constraints <strong>of</strong> public policy,<br />

fairness, reasonableness and good faith exists in that the claim that<br />

the reliance on freedom <strong>of</strong> contract and its concomitant rules is<br />

somehow a-political and thus unproblematic, generates increasing<br />

and proliferating politics in the law <strong>of</strong> contract. The more the courts<br />

attempt to depoliticise the law <strong>of</strong> contract by way <strong>of</strong> limiting the<br />

open-ended norms in favour <strong>of</strong> liberal legalism grounded in a rule<br />

jurisprudence, the more it politicises it by way <strong>of</strong> these oppositions<br />

and dualisms.<br />

Below I will argue that the unwillingness to deal with unfair<br />

contracts in terms <strong>of</strong> the public policy requirement is symptomatic <strong>of</strong><br />

a deeper illness, namely the courts’ refusal to accept that the ethical<br />

element <strong>of</strong> contract (good faith or the bona fides) — as a foundational<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract — forms part and parcel <strong>of</strong> not only the<br />

public policy requirement 126 but also <strong>of</strong> the very maxim pacta<br />

servanda sunt. 127 In other words, the opposition between the<br />

foundational norms <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract and good faith serves — as<br />

we shall see — to maintain a certain instrumental politics in the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract weighted in favour <strong>of</strong> commercial interests. The<br />

opposition itself thus furthers the privileging or hegemony <strong>of</strong> a liberal<br />

version <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, which closes <strong>of</strong>f the law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

from the question <strong>of</strong> the ethical embodied in the good faith<br />

requirement.<br />

125 Botha (n 123 above) 783J.<br />

126 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 200: ‘in the context <strong>of</strong> legality there is a close<br />

relationship between what is fair and reasonable and what is in accordance with<br />

good faith’.<br />

127 See n 37 above.


176 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

4.2 Good faith and the exceptio doli generalis in the South<br />

African law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

The South African law <strong>of</strong> contract has long considered all contracts as<br />

acts <strong>of</strong> good faith. 128 This is the case because we inherited substantial<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> the Roman-Dutch law <strong>of</strong> contract in which contracts were<br />

considered iudicia bonae fidei. 129 In Roman law, however, a<br />

distinction existed between negotia stricti iuris and the negotia<br />

bonae fidei. 130 Contracts from the ius stricti bound the debtor to<br />

perform strictly in accordance with what he promised in the formula<br />

and not in accordance with what the bona fides could expect <strong>of</strong> him,<br />

unless the formula itself referred to the bona fides. 131 In the case <strong>of</strong><br />

the negotia bonae fidei the bona fides were conclusive and the<br />

absence there<strong>of</strong>, whether during negotiations, conclusion or<br />

institution <strong>of</strong> the action, gave rise to a defence. 132 The bona fides<br />

thus operated as an evaluative yardstick to determine the<br />

enforceability <strong>of</strong> the negotia bonae fidei.<br />

To curb possible injustices or unconscionable conduct as a result<br />

<strong>of</strong> the enforcement <strong>of</strong> the negotia stricti iuris, the praetor introduced<br />

the exceptio doli generalis. 133 Here the defendant was allowed to<br />

submit facts that he would otherwise not have been able to submit<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the operation <strong>of</strong> the strict ius civile. 134 The exceptio<br />

therefore functioned to curb the abuse <strong>of</strong> rights in appropriate<br />

circumstances and became the instrument with which more equitable<br />

128 Meskin v Anglo-American Corporation <strong>of</strong> SA Ltd (1968) 4 SA 793 (W) (Meskin) 802;<br />

Paddock Motors (Pty) Ltd v Ingesund 1976 3 SA 16 (AD) (Paddock Motors) 28;<br />

Magna Alloys (n 85 above) 893C; Tuckers Land & Development Corporation (Pty)<br />

Ltd v Hovis 1980 1 SA 645 (A) (Tuckers Land) 652; Mutual & Federal Insurance Co<br />

Ltd v Oudtshoorn Municipality 1985 1 SA 419 (A) (Mutual & Federal) 433; Savage<br />

& Lovemore Mining (Pty) Ltd v International Shipping Co (Pty) Ltd 1987 2 SA 149<br />

(W) (Savage & Lovemore Mining)198A, Sasfin (n 75 above) 8C-D; Botha (n 123<br />

above) 782J; LTA Construction Bpk v Administrateur Transvaal 1992 1 SA 473 (A)<br />

(LTA Construction) 480D; Eerste Nasionale Bank van Suidelike Afrika Bpk v<br />

Saayman NO 1997 4 SA 302 (SCA) (Eerste Nasionale Bank) 321; Janse van Rensburg<br />

v Grieve Trust 2000 1 SA 315 (C) (Janse van Rensburg) 325-326; Afrox Healthcare<br />

(n 13 above) 40I-J; Van der Westhuizen v Arnold 2002 6 SA 453 (SCA) (Van der<br />

Westhuizen) 469E-F.<br />

129 Van der Merwe et al (n 37 above) 319. Aronstam (n 103 above) 173: ‘the sole<br />

question facing a court in Roman-Dutch law was whether the conduct <strong>of</strong> a party<br />

to a contract, either in any negotiations that preceded the contract, or in any<br />

action that was based upon it, had complied with the requirements <strong>of</strong> good<br />

faith.’<br />

130 See CFC van der Walt (n 71 above) 648 and NJ Grové ‘Kontraktuele gebondenheid,<br />

die vereistes van die goeie trou, redelikheid en billikheid’ (1998) 61 Tydskrif vir<br />

Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 687 688 who show that the distinction was<br />

closely related to the Roman procedural law and the specific defences it allowed<br />

for in different cases.<br />

131 Van der Walt (n 71 above) 648.<br />

132 As above.<br />

133 As above.<br />

134 As above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 177<br />

principles were introduced in the law <strong>of</strong> contract by the praetorian<br />

law. 135<br />

The question regarding the reception <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli<br />

generalis into the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract has been contentious.<br />

The question is complicated by the fact that all contracts became<br />

negotia bonae fidei in Roman-Dutch Law, thus appearing to do away<br />

with the need for such a defence. However, Aronstam argues that the<br />

exceptio doli generalis became part <strong>of</strong> the Roman-Dutch law in that<br />

it was implied by good faith: 136<br />

if all contracts were bonae fidei they had to be performed in accordance<br />

with the dictates <strong>of</strong> good faith, and any absence <strong>of</strong> bona fides could be<br />

taken into account by a judge in any action based on such contracts. 137<br />

Aronstam’s argument thus is that the exceptio doli generalis formed<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the requirement <strong>of</strong> good faith and as such was received into<br />

the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract.<br />

Six months before the decision in Sasfin (discussed above), the<br />

Appellate Division had occasion to consider the question regarding the<br />

reception <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis into the South African law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract in the case <strong>of</strong> Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon and South Africa v De Ornelas<br />

& Others. 138 In this case the court primarily concerned itself with the<br />

question whether the exceptio survived the reception <strong>of</strong> Roman Law<br />

into Roman-Dutch Law and <strong>of</strong> Roman-Dutch Law into the South African<br />

law. The court held that the exceptio doli generalis never formed part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Roman-Dutch law, 139 could therefore not have been received<br />

into the South African law 140 and that its occasional appearances on<br />

the scene <strong>of</strong> the South African law 141 should finally be prohibited by<br />

burying it ‘as a superfluous, defunct anachronism.’ 142<br />

This decision is also generally regarded as the decision in which<br />

the Appellate Division did away with the perception that a contract<br />

could be adjudicated and declared unenforceable by a court on the<br />

135 G Lubbe ‘Bona fides, billikheid en die openbare belang in die Suid-Afrikaanse<br />

kontraktereg’ (1990) 1 Stellenbosch Law Review 9. Also see C Lewis ‘The demise<br />

<strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli: Another route to contractual equity?’ (1990) 107 South<br />

African Law Journal 26 31-32.<br />

136 n 103 above, 173.<br />

137 n 103 above, 172.<br />

138 1988 3 SA 580 (A) (Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon).<br />

139 Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon (n 138 above) 605H.<br />

140 Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon (n 138 above) 607A.<br />

141 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the various interpretations <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis see<br />

SWJ Van der Merwe et al ‘The exceptio doli generalis: Requiescat in pace — vivat<br />

aequitas’ (1989) 106 South African Law Journal 235. Also see Weinerlein v Goch<br />

Buildings Ltd 1925 AD 282 (Weinerlein); Zuurbekom Ltd v Union Corporation Ltd<br />

1947 1 SA 514 (AD) (Zuurbekom); Paddock Motors (n 128 above); and Arprint Ltd v<br />

Gerber Goldschmidt Group South Africa (Pty) Ltd 1983 1 SA 254 (A) (Arprint).<br />

142 Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon (n 138 above) 607B. Also see Lubbe (n 135 above) 9.


178 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> good faith. 143 The conflation <strong>of</strong> these two issues (the<br />

abolition <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis on the one hand and the<br />

abolition <strong>of</strong> an explicit good faith jurisdiction, on the other) finds its<br />

origin in the following dictum <strong>of</strong> Joubert JA:<br />

Nor can I find any evidence <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> a general substantive<br />

defence based on equity. This is not surprising inasmuch as the Dutch<br />

Courts, unlike the English Courts until the Judicature Act 1873 became<br />

operative in 1875, did not administer a system <strong>of</strong> equity as distinct from<br />

a system <strong>of</strong> law. Roman-Dutch law is itself an inherently equitable legal<br />

system. In administering the law the Dutch Courts paid due regard to<br />

considerations <strong>of</strong> equity but only where equity was not inconsistent with<br />

the principles <strong>of</strong> law. Equity could not override a clear rule <strong>of</strong> law. That<br />

is also the position <strong>of</strong> our Courts as regards their equitable jurisdiction<br />

... Moreover, I cannot find any support in Roman-Dutch law for the<br />

proposition that in the law <strong>of</strong> contract an equitable exception or<br />

defence, similar in effect to the exceptio doli generalis, was utilised<br />

under the aegis <strong>of</strong> bona fides. 144<br />

In his discussion <strong>of</strong> the majority decision, Cockrell shows that the<br />

decision that the exceptio doli constitutes ‘a superfluous, defunct<br />

anachronism’, 145 is founded upon an extreme form <strong>of</strong> individualism<br />

which denies that the law may ‘legitimately superimpose an<br />

overriding duty to act in good faith’ 146 upon the voluntary agreements<br />

<strong>of</strong> legal subjects with full capacity. 147 As Cockrell points out, the<br />

Court’s problem with accepting the exceptio was that it enjoins a<br />

judge to employ a standard that cannot be cast in ‘a clear rule <strong>of</strong><br />

law’. 148 As the Court held, quoting Van der Linden’s account <strong>of</strong> Voet<br />

1.1.16: ‘... [j]udges and jurists ought to look to nothing more<br />

carefully than this, that they do not forsake the written law for some<br />

headstrong equity ...’. 149 Joubert JA’s rejection <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli<br />

143 See Eerste Nasionale Bank (n 128 above) 323B.<br />

144 Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon (n 138 above) 605I-606D.<br />

145 Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon (n 138 above) 607B.<br />

146 n 53 above, 44.<br />

147 As above.<br />

148 Also see the judgment in Tjollo Ateljees (Eins) Bpk v Small 1949 1 SA 856 (A)<br />

(Tjollo Ateljees). In this decision the Appellate Division recommended the<br />

abolition by the legislature <strong>of</strong> the doctrine <strong>of</strong> laesio enormis. According to laesio<br />

enormis a party who had either agreed to pay a price <strong>of</strong> more than double the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the thing or agreed to sell for less than half <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the thing<br />

could either cancel the agreement or claim price adjustment (see Van der Merwe<br />

et al (n 37 above) 132). Cockrell (n 53 above) 45 illustrates clearly that the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the decision was, on the one hand, that laesio enormis constituted an altruist<br />

intrusion on the terrain <strong>of</strong> individualism and, on the other, that laesio enormis<br />

could not be cast in the rule form.<br />

149 Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon (n 138 above) 610D-E.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 179<br />

is thus clearly linked to his disapproval <strong>of</strong> the discretion which will be<br />

afforded to judges by its acceptance. 150<br />

The attempt to rid our law <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis should<br />

then, given these observations, be understood as part and parcel <strong>of</strong><br />

the attempt to keep the hegemony <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as the will<br />

theory and the maxim pacta servanda sunt, firmly in place. With this<br />

decision, the Appellate Division attempted finally to seal the<br />

hegemony <strong>of</strong> the will theory as freedom <strong>of</strong> contract. This is<br />

particularly evident when Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon is considered in the light <strong>of</strong><br />

the Sasfin decision six months later in which possible interference<br />

with liberal freedom <strong>of</strong> contract by way <strong>of</strong> public policy was further<br />

curtailed. 151 The abolition <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis confirmed<br />

that the enquiry in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract when it comes<br />

to enforceability is conducted with reference to so-called clear rules<br />

<strong>of</strong> law that are grounded in individualism. Consequently as we shall<br />

see, the Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon decision forms the focal point when it comes<br />

to the marginalisation <strong>of</strong> good faith as the ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

in South Africa.<br />

This marginalisation, however, was not achieved without some<br />

strife. In the first place — regarding the exceptio doli generalis as a<br />

technical remedy — the Appellate Division contradicted itself when it<br />

held in the later case <strong>of</strong> Van der Merwe v Meades 152 that the<br />

replicatio doli still formed part <strong>of</strong> our law. As Kerr argued at the time,<br />

the same court had previously held in Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon that the<br />

conclusions about the non-reception <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis<br />

‘equally hold for the replicatio doli generalis’. 153 Kerr submits that<br />

the linking was correct. 154 If, as Kerr points out, the replicatio doli,<br />

on the later decision <strong>of</strong> the court, survived the reception, and the<br />

same court linked the replicatio with the exceptio and has not<br />

departed from that position, then the only conclusion that can follow<br />

is that the exceptio doli generalis must also have survived the<br />

reception. 155<br />

150 The majority decision clearly does not take account <strong>of</strong>, or acknowledge, the<br />

subjectivity/discretion which is at play in considering whether ‘a clear rule <strong>of</strong><br />

law’ is in fact that and, even more problematic, the subjectivity that is at play in<br />

any decision as regards the question whether the ‘clear rule <strong>of</strong> law’ is applicable<br />

or not.<br />

151 The mantra that public policy should properly take into account the doing <strong>of</strong><br />

simple justice between man and man and the way in which that mantra was<br />

employed in Sasfin does not, without more, lead to a conclusion that Sasfin<br />

somehow provided an escape route from strict enforcement <strong>of</strong> contract. This is<br />

evident from the cases that followed Sasfin, as discussed earlier.<br />

152 1991 2 SA 1 (A) (Van der Merwe) 2F-3A.<br />

153 Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon (n 138 above) 608F-G.<br />

154 AJ Kerr ‘The replicatio doli reaffirmed. The exceptio doli available in our law’<br />

(1991) 106 South African Law Journal 583 584.<br />

155 n 154 above, 585.


180 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

Regarding the question whether the Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon judgment — in<br />

doing away with the exceptio doli — in fact did away with the power<br />

to declare a contract or a provision there<strong>of</strong> as void or unenforceable<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> good faith, Olivier JA argued strongly in his famous<br />

(perhaps notorious) minority judgment in Eerste Nasionale Bank van<br />

Suidelike Afrika Bpk v Saayman NO 156 that Bank <strong>of</strong> Lisbon did not and<br />

could not have done away with this power. Olivier JA argued that the<br />

reception <strong>of</strong> all contracts as iudicia bonae fidei into the South African<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract made the exceptio doli generalis (as a technical<br />

remedy that had to be pleaded), superfluous in that it was implied in<br />

the idea <strong>of</strong> iudicia bonae fidei that a court would have discretion to<br />

examine and pronounce on the bona fides. Olivier JA continued that<br />

this would be the position from the perspective <strong>of</strong> those who accept<br />

the broad, dynamic working <strong>of</strong> the bona fides and the discretion <strong>of</strong><br />

judges to apply the bona fides. 157 Olivier JA argued bravely that the<br />

bona fides principle forms part <strong>of</strong> the public policy requirement 158<br />

and could be directly applied to the facts before him. This was a<br />

certain attempt to radicalise the public policy principle as enunciated<br />

in Sasfin. To quote Olivier JA:<br />

[e]k hou dit as my oortuiging na dat die beginsels van die goeie trou,<br />

gegrond op openbare beleid, steeds in ons kontraktereg 'n belangrike rol<br />

speel en moet speel, soos in enige regstelsel wat gevoelig is vir die<br />

opvattinge van die gemeenskap, wat die uiteindelike skepper en<br />

gebruiker van die reg is, met betrekking tot die morele en sedelike<br />

waardes van regverdigheid, billikheid en behoorlikheid. 159<br />

(I believe that the principles <strong>of</strong> good faith, based on public policy, still<br />

play and should continue to play an important role in our law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

as it does in any legal system which is sensitive to the convictions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

community — the ultimate creator and user <strong>of</strong> the law — with respect to<br />

the moral and ethical values <strong>of</strong> justice, fairness and propriety.)<br />

In his discussion <strong>of</strong> unfair contracts in the fourth edition <strong>of</strong> The law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract in South Africa, Richard Christie remarked that<br />

[t]here is every reason to hope that when the opportunity arises the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal will apply Olivier JA’s reasoning, harnessed to<br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> public policy, in the context <strong>of</strong> the unfair enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

a contract. 160<br />

In NBS Boland Bank Ltd v One Berg River Drive CC and Others; Deeb<br />

and Another v ABSA Bank Ltd; Friedman v Standard Bank <strong>of</strong> SA Ltd 161<br />

156 n 128 above.<br />

157 Eerste Nasionale Bank (n 128 above) 323.<br />

158 Eerste Nasionale Bank (n 128 above) 323-324<br />

159 Eerste Nasionale Bank (n 128 above) 326 F-H.<br />

160 RH Christie The law <strong>of</strong> contract in South Africa (4ed, 2001) 19.<br />

161 1999 4 SA 928 (SCA) (Friedman).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 181<br />

the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal (SCA) held obiter that in the matter<br />

before it<br />

[a]n analogous conclusion may well be reached if one applies the<br />

modern concept <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> public policy, bona fides and contractual<br />

equity to the question in issue (see for example, Eerste Nasionale Bank<br />

van Suidelike Afrika Bpk v Saayman NO [reference omitted] per Olivier<br />

JA. 162<br />

This appeared at the time to have constituted at least an implicit<br />

endorsement <strong>of</strong> what Olivier JA said in that case.<br />

In Miller 163 Ntsebeza AJ interpreted the judgment <strong>of</strong> Olivier JA in<br />

Saayman to mean that a court can indeed refuse to uphold a so-called<br />

non-variation or Shifren clause 164 on the basis <strong>of</strong> considerations <strong>of</strong><br />

good faith. 165 In turn, Van Zyl J argued — relying explicitly on Olivier<br />

JA’s judgment in Saayman — in Janse van Rensburg v Grieve Trust 166<br />

that ‘the principles <strong>of</strong> justice, equity, reasonableness and good faith’<br />

required the development <strong>of</strong> the common law in the case before<br />

him. 167 Davis J, in obiter remarks in Mort NO v Henry Shields-Chiat 168<br />

also invoked Olivier JA’s judgment and added that<br />

it is clear that if the doctrine [<strong>of</strong> bona fides] is to be taken seriously then<br />

the primary importance accorded to the private autonomy <strong>of</strong> contracting<br />

parties must be reconsidered as must the hegemony <strong>of</strong> the will theory <strong>of</strong><br />

contract which survives even in the context <strong>of</strong> dicta which nod in the<br />

direction <strong>of</strong> social responsibility. 169<br />

Davis J implicitly accepted Olivier JA’s reasoning in Eerste Nasionale<br />

Bank that good faith forms part <strong>of</strong> the public policy requirement when<br />

he stated that Olivier JA’s approach builds on the judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

Smalberger JA in Sasfin and particularly on the dictum from that case<br />

as quoted earlier. 170 Similar to Olivier JA, Davis J attempted to<br />

radicalise Sasfin by the attempt to infuse it with the bona fides.<br />

But what sets Davis J’s judgment in Mort apart is the express link<br />

made in the judgment between, on the one hand, the argument in<br />

favour <strong>of</strong> the bona fides and, on the other, the ethical implications<br />

162 Friedman (n 161 above) 937F. Also see Pretorius (n 54 above) 643.<br />

163 Miller and Another NNO v Dannecker 2001 1 SA 928 (C) (Miller).<br />

164 This name for a non-variation clause (which generally stipulates that no<br />

amendments to a written agreement shall be valid unless reduced to writing) is<br />

derived from the decision in SA Sentrale Ko-op Graanmaatskappy Beperk v<br />

Shifren en Andere 1964 4 SA 760 (A) (Shifren).<br />

165 Miller (n 163 above) 938 para 19<br />

166 n 128 above.<br />

167 n 128 above, 325D-F.<br />

168 2001 1 SA 464 (C) (Mort).<br />

169 n 168 above, 474I (Emphasis added).<br />

170 See note 112 above.


182 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

for adjudication in the law <strong>of</strong> contract <strong>of</strong> the reconstitution <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legal order occasioned by the enactment <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. To<br />

quote Davis J:<br />

Like the concept <strong>of</strong> boni mores in our law <strong>of</strong> delict, the concept <strong>of</strong> good<br />

faith is shaped by the legal convictions <strong>of</strong> the community. While Roman-<br />

Dutch law may well supply the conceptual apparatus for our law, the<br />

content with which concepts are filled depends on an examination <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legal conviction <strong>of</strong> the community — a far more difficult task. This task<br />

requires that careful account be taken <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> our<br />

constitutional community, based as it is upon principles <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

equality and dignity. The principle <strong>of</strong> freedom does, to an extent,<br />

support the view that the contractual autonomy <strong>of</strong> the parties should be<br />

respected and that failure to recognise such autonomy could cause<br />

contractual litigation to mushroom and the expectations <strong>of</strong> contractual<br />

parties to be frustrated. [Reference omitted.] But the principles <strong>of</strong><br />

equality and dignity direct attention in another direction. Parties to a<br />

contract must adhere to a minimum threshold <strong>of</strong> mutual respect in<br />

which ‘the unreasonable and one-sided promotion <strong>of</strong> one's own interest<br />

at the expense <strong>of</strong> the other infringes the principle <strong>of</strong> good faith to such a<br />

degree as to outweigh the public interest in the sanctity <strong>of</strong> contracts.’<br />

[Reference omitted.] The task is not to disguise equity or principle but<br />

to develop contractual principles in the image <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. 171<br />

However, in Brisley v Drotsky 172 the majority <strong>of</strong> the SCA rejected —<br />

in no uncertain terms — both Olivier JA’s Eerste Nasional Bank<br />

judgment as well as the judgments that built on it. In the first<br />

instance, the majority criticised Olivier JA’s judgment for attempting<br />

indirectly to resurrect the exceptio doli generalis. 173 With this<br />

statement the majority seems to have uncritically accepted that the<br />

exceptio doli generalis is not a part <strong>of</strong> our law. But as we have seen,<br />

on the Court’s own jurisprudence it is not at all clear whether the<br />

exceptio doli generalis has in fact been abolished. The terse<br />

statement in Brisley regarding the attempt to resurrect the exceptio<br />

doli generalis dismisses this controversy/contradiction by pretending<br />

that the exceptio is in fact dead and buried. This statement in Brisley<br />

can <strong>of</strong> course be seen as implicitly overriding the court’s Van der<br />

Merwe decision (in which it, ironically, resurrected the exceptio doli<br />

generalis), but the Court explicitly stated in a footnote that the<br />

question regarding the reconsideration <strong>of</strong> the exceptio did not arise<br />

in Brisley. 174 This left as uncertain as ever the position in our law<br />

regarding the status <strong>of</strong> the exceptio.<br />

171 Mort (n 168 above) 474I-475D<br />

172 n 13 above. The dispute in this case also concerned the question regarding the<br />

enforceability <strong>of</strong> contractual terms (including a Shifren clause) in circumstances<br />

where oral amendments to the agreement were made but not reduced to writing.<br />

173 Brisley (n 13 above) 14 para 17.<br />

174 Brisley (n 13 above) n 10.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 183<br />

As regards Davis J’s view in Mort that the bona fides (like the boni<br />

mores in the law <strong>of</strong> delict) are shaped by the legal convictions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional community (as an ideal community), the majority held<br />

that if this means that the enforcement <strong>of</strong> contractual terms depends<br />

on the convictions <strong>of</strong> the community (gemeenskapsgevoel), then it<br />

cannot agree because there are material policy differences between<br />

the approach to the law <strong>of</strong> delict and the approach to the law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract. 175 According to the majority the unqualified acceptance <strong>of</strong><br />

Davis J’s judgment will create a state <strong>of</strong> unacceptable chaos and<br />

disorder in the law <strong>of</strong> contract. 176 A court cannot seek shelter in the<br />

shadow <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, writes the Brisley court, in order to<br />

attack and overthrow principles. 177 In this regard it should be<br />

emphasised that Davis J did not appeal to an unqualified, actually<br />

existing community in his judgment. He explicitly referred to the<br />

constitutional community — which can only be an ideal community —<br />

and that is why Davis J explicitly invoked the constitutional ideals <strong>of</strong><br />

dignity, equality and freedom. The point Davis J was making was that<br />

the very reconstitution <strong>of</strong> the legal order required that good faith<br />

should be given content with reference to the normative (and<br />

transformative) commitments <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. He was not hiding<br />

in the shadow <strong>of</strong> the Constitution in order to attack and overthrow<br />

principles from that vantage point.<br />

Be that as it may, the majority in Brisley accordingly rejected the<br />

idea that good faith can be utilised as an independent, free-floating<br />

basis for the invalidation or unenforceability <strong>of</strong> contractual<br />

provisions 178 on the basis that good faith as ‘the legal convictions <strong>of</strong><br />

the community’ would prove to be too nebulous a concept to<br />

determine the enforceability <strong>of</strong> contractual terms. The Court stated,<br />

however, that good faith is a fundamental principle which in general<br />

underlies the law <strong>of</strong> contract and becomes expressed in its particular<br />

rules and principles. 179<br />

At this point in the judgment the Brisley court introduced what it<br />

called another underlying value <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract: the principle<br />

175 Brisley (n 13 above) para 21.<br />

176 Brisley (n 13 above) 15 para 21. ‘Om eensklaps aan regters 'n diskresie te verleen<br />

om kontraktuele beginsels te verontagsaam wanneer hulle dit as onredelik <strong>of</strong><br />

onbillik beskou, is in stryd met hierdie werkswyse. Die gevolg sal immers wees dat<br />

die beginsel van pacta sunt servanda grotendeels verontagsaam sal word omdat<br />

die afdwingbaarheid van kontraktuele bepalings sal afhang van wat 'n bepaalde<br />

regter in die omstandighede as redelik en billik beskou.’ This statement<br />

prompted L Hawthorne ‘The end <strong>of</strong> bona fides’ (2003) South African Mercantile<br />

Law Journal 271 276 to remark as follows: ‘This cri de coeur has two deplorable<br />

aspects: the tacit belief that the majority <strong>of</strong> contractual terms are not<br />

reasonable or equitable, and the belief that judges are not to be trusted with<br />

what is reasonable and equitable.’<br />

177 Brisley (n 13 above) 16D para 24.<br />

178 Brisley (n 13 above) 16D para 22<br />

179 Brisley (as above).


184 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

that public policy requires that contracts that have been entered into<br />

freely and in all earnest by parties with full capacity should be<br />

enforced. 180 The Court continued to hold that these two underlying<br />

values (good faith and freedom <strong>of</strong> contract) sometimes come into<br />

conflict with each other and that it is the task <strong>of</strong> the Courts and the<br />

SCA principally to weigh these values against each other and to make<br />

gradual and slow changes on occasions when they appear to be<br />

necessary. 181<br />

Again, this judgment makes it clear that good faith and pacta<br />

servanda sunt are positioned as opposing values, that is to say an<br />

instrumental politics is set up between the two underlying values. But<br />

it is also the case that it is at this point that the Brisley judgment<br />

deconstructs itself. 182 It does so in the following way: When the court<br />

discusses the idea <strong>of</strong> an underlying value in relation to good faith, it<br />

makes the point that it is in the very nature <strong>of</strong> an underlying value<br />

that courts do not use it directly to adjudicate contracts. Rather, they<br />

wait for the underlying value to become embodied in the particular<br />

rules <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract. For this reason the Court concludes that<br />

good faith is not an independent or free-floating basis for the<br />

invalidation <strong>of</strong> contractual terms. But when it comes to the discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the other underlying value — the enforcement <strong>of</strong> contracts in the<br />

public interest — the Court does not realise the implications <strong>of</strong> its own<br />

opinion regarding underlying values. Certainly, the consequences <strong>of</strong><br />

identifying freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as an underlying value should be the<br />

same — courts should wait for the underlying value to become<br />

embodied in the rules <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract. Yet, the history <strong>of</strong> the<br />

South African law <strong>of</strong> contract is the history <strong>of</strong> the direct reliance on<br />

the so-called underlying principle <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract. If there<br />

were to be no direct reliance on so-called underlying values, then it<br />

would be hard to imagine how the rules <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract were<br />

formulated in the first place. The fact that freedom <strong>of</strong> contract is an<br />

underlying value has never prevented a court from directly relying on<br />

it. Why then should the ‘underlying value’-character <strong>of</strong> good faith<br />

prevent direct reliance on it? Yet this is exactly what the Brisley<br />

majority wants us to believe: good faith cannot be directly relied<br />

upon because it is an underlying value. This was stated even more<br />

explicitly in Afrox Healthcare Bpk v Strydom: 183<br />

180 Brisley (n 13 above) 16D para 23 quoting Magna Alloys (n 85 above) 893I-894A.<br />

181 Brisley (n 13 above) 16D para 24.<br />

182 J Derrida & M Ferraris A Taste for the Secret (2001) 80: ‘I ought to have specified<br />

that what happens deconstructs itself in the process. It is not I who deconstruct;<br />

rather something I called “deconstruction” happens to the experience <strong>of</strong> a world,<br />

a culture, a philosophic tradition: “it” deconstructs, ça ne va pas, there is<br />

something that budges, that is in the process <strong>of</strong> being dislocated, disjointed,<br />

disadjoined, and <strong>of</strong> which I begin to be aware. Something is “deconstructing” and<br />

it has to be answered for.’<br />

183 Afrox Healthcare (n 13 above).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 185<br />

Concerning the place and role <strong>of</strong> abstract ideas such as good faith,<br />

reasonableness, fairness and justice, the majority in the Brisley case<br />

held that, although these considerations are subjacent to our law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract, they do not constitute an independent or ‘free-floating’ basis<br />

for the setting aside or the non-enforcement <strong>of</strong> contractual provisions;<br />

put differently, although these abstract considerations represent the<br />

foundation and very right <strong>of</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> law and can also lead<br />

to the shaping and transformation <strong>of</strong> these rules, they are not selfcontained<br />

rules <strong>of</strong> law. When it comes to the enforcement <strong>of</strong> a<br />

contractual provision, the Court has no discretion and does not act on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> abstract ideas, but precisely on the basis <strong>of</strong> crystallised and<br />

established rules <strong>of</strong> law. 184<br />

One clearly sees in this dictum the consistent political privileging <strong>of</strong><br />

the individualism/rules position by way <strong>of</strong> which the hegemonic<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract is kept firmly in place (which in<br />

turn keeps the hegemonic order(ing) <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract in place).<br />

The Court’s unease with good faith (described by Cockrell as ‘the<br />

epitome <strong>of</strong> a legal standard that embodies communitarian values <strong>of</strong><br />

altruism, care and concern’ 185 (the opposite thus <strong>of</strong> individualism)) is<br />

that it cannot be regarded as a rule <strong>of</strong> law. On the other hand,<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract is simply, unproblematically understood as being<br />

both an underlying value and a rule which could be relied upon to hold<br />

the defendant in Afrox for instance, to an agreement that exempted<br />

a hospital from liability for everything but its intentional infliction <strong>of</strong><br />

harm. 186<br />

A number <strong>of</strong> deductions regarding good faith and freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract can be made at this<br />

point. The first is that good faith is currently not considered in the<br />

South African law <strong>of</strong> contract to be a part <strong>of</strong> the public policy<br />

requirement (which, from a transformative point <strong>of</strong> view, presents its<br />

own set <strong>of</strong> problems, primarily in that public policy becomes closed<br />

<strong>of</strong>f from the ethical question generally when good faith does not form<br />

part <strong>of</strong> it). Second, good faith is not considered to be an independent<br />

or free-floating basis for the invalidation or non-enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

contracts or contractual terms. Third, the latter is the case because<br />

good faith is an underlying value <strong>of</strong> the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

and is/becomes embodied in the particular rules <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong><br />

184 Afrox Healthcare (n 13 above) 40H-41A (author’s translation from the original<br />

Afrikaans). The point was restated in South African Forestry (note 13 above)<br />

338J-339B as follows: ‘although abstract values such as good faith, reasonableness<br />

and fairness are fundamental to our law <strong>of</strong> contract, they do not<br />

constitute independent substantive rules that courts can employ to intervene in<br />

contractual relationships. These abstract values perform creative, informative<br />

and controlling functions through established rules <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract. They<br />

cannot be acted upon by the courts directly ... After all, it has been said that<br />

fairness and justice, like beauty, <strong>of</strong>ten lie in the eye <strong>of</strong> the beholder.’<br />

185 Cockrell (n 53 above) 55.<br />

186 Afrox Healthcare (n 13 above).


186 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

contract. (How this happens is uncertain given that courts are not<br />

allowed to touch good faith.) Fourth, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract understood<br />

as the maxim pacta servanda sunt, although itself an underlying value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract, is and can be used in a direct way. 187 Fifth,<br />

there appears to be no reason other than an ideological or political<br />

one which would explain why one underlying value — freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract — can be used to develop rules by way <strong>of</strong> which a party can<br />

be held to or released from her agreements, whereas another<br />

underlying value — good faith — cannot be used in this way.<br />

In addition, a matter that is repeatedly ignored in the debate<br />

regarding the role <strong>of</strong> good faith in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract is<br />

the implications for the law <strong>of</strong> contract <strong>of</strong> the newly constituted legal<br />

order. In the Brisley case, for instance, the Court faulted Davis J’s and<br />

other judges’ appeal to this order as putting in place an ideal<br />

community to which can be appealed in the law <strong>of</strong> contract by way <strong>of</strong><br />

good faith (as part <strong>of</strong> the public policy requirement). The stance <strong>of</strong><br />

the Brisley court represents a static, closed view <strong>of</strong> a legal system in<br />

which good faith has somehow been worked out in the past and<br />

incorporated into the rules <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract. As such, this view<br />

questions the dynamic role <strong>of</strong> the bona fides in relation to the<br />

transformation <strong>of</strong> the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract and, as Olivier JA<br />

suggested in Eerste Nasionale Bank, it is out <strong>of</strong> step both with the<br />

spirit <strong>of</strong> our law and with the needs <strong>of</strong> the community. 188<br />

In 2007 the Constitutional Court delivered two decisions that<br />

involved the tangled web weaved with freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good<br />

faith, the exceptio doli generalis and public policy in the South<br />

African law <strong>of</strong> contract. Below I shall critically evaluate these<br />

decisions after which I shall argue for a re-emphasis on good faith as<br />

the ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract. I believe that this re-emphasis is<br />

mandated by an understanding <strong>of</strong> the new legal order as aspiring to<br />

the ideal <strong>of</strong> civic friendship. By deploying the word ‘re-emphasis’ I<br />

want to signal my belief that the normative character <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution requires us to consider good faith as part <strong>of</strong> the public<br />

policy requirement in two ways — both in that contracts concluded<br />

contrary to public policy are unenforceable but also in that public<br />

policy requires that parties who enter into agreements freely<br />

187<br />

In this context, D Hutchison ‘Non-variation clauses in contract: any escape from<br />

the Shifren straitjacket?’ (2001) 118 South African Law Journal 720 745 has<br />

remarked that ‘to reach directly for the baton <strong>of</strong> good faith would be to confess<br />

to a want <strong>of</strong> technical expertise or creativity. Palm-tree justice no doubt has its<br />

virtues, but as lawyers we should adhere to the ideal <strong>of</strong> justice according to law.’<br />

Hutchison does not explain why it is acceptable and in accordance with the ‘ideal<br />

<strong>of</strong> justice according to law’ to reach directly for the baton <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

contract. Surely, another form <strong>of</strong> ‘palm-tree justice’ is in play when one reaches<br />

directly for the baton <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as itself an underlying value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract?<br />

188 Eerste Nasionale Bank (n 128 above) 319H-320B.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 187<br />

(ethically, in good faith) should be held to them. The meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract in this way becomes constituted by a<br />

transformative understanding <strong>of</strong> good faith.<br />

5 Good faith and the Constitution: Towards<br />

transforming 189 the hegemony<br />

5.1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

In the Preface to the fifth edition <strong>of</strong> The Law <strong>of</strong> Contract in South<br />

Africa, Richard Christie wrote as follows:<br />

In the preface to the fourth edition I was rash enough to express the<br />

hope that the judges would further develop the concepts <strong>of</strong> good faith<br />

and public policy. This they have done, but not in the way I expected.<br />

Since Brisley v Drotsky, Afrox Healthcare Bpk v Strydom and South<br />

African Forestry Co Ltd v York Timbers good faith as an abstract value<br />

cannot be used to intervene in contractual relationships, but public<br />

policy still can. To achieve a just result there are advantages in using the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> public policy which our law has developed over the centuries<br />

and has linked to the Constitution, rather than the less familiar concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> good faith. But it will be a mistake to regard the door as forever<br />

closed ...’ 190<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong> Christie has also suggested that the courts are likely to find that<br />

the Sasfin principle (namely that a court will not enforce a contract<br />

if its enforcement would be contrary to public policy) is the most<br />

serviceable instrument for developing the common law <strong>of</strong> contract to<br />

give effect to a provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 191 Below we shall see<br />

that this has indeed become the preferred route when it comes to the<br />

enforceability (and <strong>of</strong> course also constitutionality) <strong>of</strong> contractual<br />

terms. But we shall also see that the Constitutional Court did indeed<br />

leave the door wide open in its 2007 decision in Barkhuizen. 192 The<br />

question thus currently looming large in the South African law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract is whether the ‘objective, normative value system’ 193 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution requires the introduction <strong>of</strong> a good faith jurisdiction in<br />

the law <strong>of</strong> contract as part <strong>of</strong> the Sasfin principle. The judgments that<br />

189 The way in which I employ transformation in relation to hegemony closely relates<br />

to Drucilla Cornell’s description <strong>of</strong> transformation. For her transformation means<br />

that ‘a system can so alter itself that it not only no longer confirms its identity,<br />

but disconfirms it and, indeed, through its very iterability, generates new<br />

meanings which can be further pursued and enhanced by the sociosymbolic<br />

practice <strong>of</strong> the political contestant within its milieu.’ Cornell (n 100 above) 2.<br />

190 RH Christie The law <strong>of</strong> contract in South Africa (5ed, 006) v.<br />

191 n 190 above, 348.<br />

192 Barkhuizen (n 13 above).<br />

193 Carmichele v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security and Another (Centre for Applied<br />

Legal Studies Intervening) 2001 4 SA 938 (CC) (Carmichele) para 54.


188 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

supported Olivier JA’s opinion in Eerste Nasionale Bank certainly<br />

argue that it does. It is implicit in the judgments <strong>of</strong> the SCA that it<br />

does not. A related question is whether the above question requires<br />

reconsideration <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis as a technical remedy.<br />

The latter question was also before the Constitutional Court in 2007.<br />

5.2 Crown Restaurant CC v Gold Reef City Theme Park<br />

(Pty) Ltd 194<br />

The facts in this case were substantially similar to the facts in Brisley<br />

save for the fact that the parties were both commercial entities.<br />

Crown Restaurant fell into arrears in terms <strong>of</strong> a written lease<br />

agreement with Gold Reef City Theme Park, which subsequently<br />

cancelled the lease and applied for an ejectment order. Crown<br />

Restaurant, however, contended that Gold Reef City ‘had verbally<br />

agreed to grant it an indulgence and allow it time within which to<br />

make proposals for settling the rental arrears.’ 195 This verbal<br />

indulgence, it was argued on behalf <strong>of</strong> Crown Restaurant, meant that<br />

the company implicitly waived its right to cancel the lease. Gold Reef<br />

City, however, initially denied the verbal agreement, then conceded<br />

that it did ‘allow’ Crown Restaurant to make proposals for settlement<br />

within a stipulated time period 196 but ultimately contended that it<br />

was in any event entitled to rely on the non-variation clause in the<br />

written agreement. Gold Reef City further relied on a clause that<br />

stipulated that no indulgence granted precluded either party from<br />

enforcing any <strong>of</strong> its rights in terms <strong>of</strong> the agreement. 197<br />

Gold Reef City was successful in the Court a quo. An application<br />

for leave to appeal to the SCA was unsuccessful. Crown Restaurant<br />

subsequently applied for leave to appeal to the Constitutional<br />

Court. 198 In the application for leave to appeal to the Constitutional<br />

Court, the Court was asked — for the first time in the proceedings - to<br />

consider the reintroduction <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis by way <strong>of</strong> a<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the common law under section 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution. The applicant contended that the remedy as an<br />

‘equitable remedy is in line with constitutional values’ 199 and that on<br />

these particular facts it would — given the verbal agreement — be<br />

unconscionable for Gold Reef City to rely on the written agreement.<br />

There were thus two distinct issues before the court: first, whether<br />

the common law should be developed so as to reintroduce the<br />

exceptio doli generalis as an ‘equitable remedy in line with<br />

194 2008 4 SA 16 (CC) (Crown Restaurant).<br />

195 n 194 above, para 1<br />

196 See n 194 above, Applicant’s Founding Affidavit para 23.2.(d).<br />

197 n 194 above, para 2.<br />

198 n 194 above, para 3.<br />

199 As above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 189<br />

constitutional values’ and second, if the answer to the first question<br />

is in the affirmative, whether on the facts the applicant could succeed<br />

with such a defence.<br />

In its judgment the Constitutional Court pointed out that the trial<br />

court judge ‘was called upon to deal only with the waiver defence and<br />

did so. He was not invited to develop the common law <strong>of</strong> contract to<br />

promote the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, nor to<br />

address any <strong>of</strong> the other constitutional issues now raised by the<br />

applicant.’ 200 After this statement the Court elaborated on the<br />

undesirability for it to sit as a court <strong>of</strong> first and last instance. It stated<br />

that the High Court and the SCA have a vital role to play when it comes<br />

to the development <strong>of</strong> the common law <strong>of</strong> contract and concluded<br />

that there are no compelling reasons for the Court to deal (as a court<br />

<strong>of</strong> first and last instance) with the issues raised by the applicant. It<br />

again warned litigants that ‘care should be taken to identify properly<br />

at the time <strong>of</strong> the institution <strong>of</strong> the proceedings which constitutional<br />

issue they wish to have addressed.’ 201 Accordingly, the application for<br />

leave to appeal was dismissed.<br />

In order to evaluate critically the apparently unproblematic<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s dismissal <strong>of</strong> the application for<br />

leave to appeal, it is necessary that we recall here what was said in<br />

the decision <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court in Carmichele. In this case the<br />

applicant (plaintiff in the Court a quo) also did not invite either the<br />

trial court or the SCA to develop the common law in accordance with<br />

the spirit, purport or objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 202 She argued the<br />

issue relating to the development <strong>of</strong> the common law for the first<br />

time in the Constitutional Court and contended that had the High<br />

Court and the SCA applied the relevant provisions <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

in determining whether a legal duty (in the context <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong><br />

delict) was owed to her, it would have developed the common law and<br />

would have found that such a legal duty exists. 203 To quote from the<br />

judgment <strong>of</strong> Ackermann and Goldstone JJ:<br />

Despite the failure by the applicant to rely directly upon the provisions<br />

<strong>of</strong> either section 35(3) <strong>of</strong> the [Interim Constitution] or section 39(2) <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitution in the High Court and SCA, counsel for the respondent<br />

did not object to this issue being raised in this Court. If covered by the<br />

pleadings, and in the absence <strong>of</strong> unfairness, parties are ordinarily not<br />

200 Crown Restaurant (n 194 above) para 4 (emphasis added).<br />

201 Crown Restaurant (n 194 above) para 6.<br />

202 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 41.<br />

203 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 28.


190 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

precluded from raising new legal arguments on appeal. [Reference<br />

omitted.] 204<br />

Furthermore, in the course <strong>of</strong> the Carmichele judgment the Court<br />

stated the following:<br />

In South Africa, the [Interim Constitution] brought into operation, in one<br />

fell swoop, a completely new and different set <strong>of</strong> legal norms. In these<br />

circumstances the courts must remain vigilant and should not hesitate to<br />

ensure that the common law is developed to reflect the spirit, purport<br />

and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. We would add, too, that this duty upon<br />

judges arises in respect both <strong>of</strong> the civil and criminal law, whether or<br />

not the parties in any particular case request the court to develop the<br />

common law under section 39(2). 205<br />

The Carmichele judgment made it clear that there is a general<br />

obligation on courts to develop the common law in accordance with<br />

the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. The judgment also<br />

makes it clear that the duty exists whether or not the parties in any<br />

particular case explicitly invite the court to develop the common law.<br />

Furthermore, it is clear that the Carmichele judgment envisages that<br />

there might be circumstances where a court is obliged to raise the<br />

matter on its own and require full argument. This would be required<br />

presumably when the legal issue ‘can hardly be described as an<br />

insignificant one, lying at an exotic periphery’ 206 <strong>of</strong> the law in<br />

question.<br />

In the light <strong>of</strong> these findings in Carmichele regarding the general<br />

obligation to develop the common law, it is not clear why the<br />

Constitutional Court considered it material (and thus fatal to the<br />

applicant’s application for leave to appeal) in Crown Restaurant that<br />

the trial court was not invited to develop the common law.<br />

Carmichele tells us that judges have a general obligation to consider<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> the common law in light <strong>of</strong> the spirit, purport and<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, even when they are not invited by parties<br />

before them to do so. This is particularly important when a significant<br />

legal issue calls for constitutional resolution. By the time that this<br />

case came before the trial court it was clear that much dispute<br />

existed over, inter alia, the status <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis in<br />

204 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 31. Also see para 38: ‘It does not appear to have<br />

been suggested that there was any obligation on the High Court or the SCA to<br />

develop the common law <strong>of</strong> delict in terms <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.’<br />

205 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 36. Also see para 39: ‘we do not mean to suggest<br />

that a court must, in each and every case where the common law is involved,<br />

embark on an independent exercise as to whether the common law is in need <strong>of</strong><br />

development and, if so, how it is to be developed under section 39(2). At the<br />

same time there might be circumstances where a court is obliged to raise the<br />

matter on its own and require full argument from the parties.’ (emphasis<br />

added.)<br />

206 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 59.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 191<br />

our law, the role <strong>of</strong> good faith and the enforceability <strong>of</strong> a Shifren<br />

clause and/or a no indulgence clause in circumstances <strong>of</strong> subsequent<br />

verbal amendments/indulgences (that is, in the context <strong>of</strong> the waiver<br />

question). 207 Moreover, it was (and still is) by no means clear how<br />

these matters are affected by the normative transformation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legal order occasioned by the Constitution. Given the fact that the<br />

Constitution ‘brought into operation, in one fell swoop, a completely<br />

new and different set <strong>of</strong> legal norms’ it could certainly be asked<br />

whether the question <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> the common law in this<br />

area should not have been raised by the trial court judge — as<br />

mandated by Carmichele — even though he was not explicitly invited<br />

to consider the development <strong>of</strong> the common law. It is thus not clear,<br />

under the circumstances, why further exploration by the trial court <strong>of</strong><br />

the issues that were eventually raised in the Constitutional Court, was<br />

‘understandably not undertaken’. 208<br />

In Carmichele the court held that the trial court and the SCA<br />

should indeed have considered the question regarding the effect <strong>of</strong><br />

section 39(2) even though the parties did not raise the matter<br />

regarding development <strong>of</strong> the common law initially. The way in which<br />

the court dealt with this difficulty in Carmichele is very different from<br />

the way in which the Crown Restaurant matter was handled. Crown<br />

Restaurant was dealt with in terms <strong>of</strong> Constitutional Court rule<br />

19(6)(b) which states that ‘[a]pplications for leave to appeal may be<br />

dealt with summarily, without receiving oral or written argument<br />

other than that contained in the application itself.’ In Carmichele the<br />

court heard argument on the merits <strong>of</strong> the dispute in accordance with<br />

the principle enunciated in what is now Constitutional Court Rule<br />

19(6)(c). Inter alia, this move allowed the court to deal with the<br />

question regarding the prospects <strong>of</strong> success in considering whether to<br />

grant the application for special leave to appeal. In Crown Restaurant<br />

the court did not utilise rule 19(6)(c) and did not explicitly deal in its<br />

judgment with the question <strong>of</strong> the prospects <strong>of</strong> success. The refusal<br />

to make an order in terms <strong>of</strong> rule 19(6)(c) leaves one to assume that<br />

in the view <strong>of</strong> the court the prospects <strong>of</strong> success were improbable on<br />

the papers. Yet this is not the reason the court gives for denying the<br />

application for leave to appeal. The reason it gives for the failure <strong>of</strong><br />

the application is that the applicant did not invite the trial court to<br />

develop the common law, that is, it did not raise the constitutional<br />

argument timeously. In Carmichele the remedy decided on in<br />

circumstances where the constitutional argument was not considered<br />

by the trial court or the SCA was to refer the matter back to the trial<br />

207 The trial judge in fact referred to Brisley v Drotsky (n 13 above). See Gold Reef<br />

City Theme Park (Pty) Ltd v The Crown Restaurant CC unreported, case no: 2006/<br />

595 WLD, 7 June 2006 para 23 — where the controversy regarding good faith and<br />

the exceptio doli generalis arose in the context <strong>of</strong> waiver.<br />

208 Crown Restaurant (n 194 above) para 6.


192 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

court. Admittedly, a difference between the Crown Restaurant<br />

matter and the Carmichele matter is that in Carmichele absolution<br />

was granted whereas in Crown Restaurant a full trial took place. In<br />

Carmichele, the fact that absolution was granted by the trial court<br />

provided a reason for referring the matter back to the trial court in<br />

addition to the referral on the grounds that the trial court had to be<br />

given the opportunity to consider section 39(2) in relation to the<br />

matter before it. 209 Even though a full trial had taken place in Crown<br />

Restaurant, there is in principle no reason why the matter could not<br />

be referred back to the trial court in that instance for a consideration<br />

<strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> section 39(2). Given the controversy and<br />

uncertainty in relation to the contract law issues raised in this matter<br />

and given that many <strong>of</strong> these contentious issues are raised in the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> waiver, a case could well be made that it would have been<br />

in the interests <strong>of</strong> justice for the Constitutional Court to have granted<br />

leave to appeal, upheld the appeal, set aside the order <strong>of</strong> the trial<br />

court and to have referred the matter back to the trial court for a<br />

proper consideration <strong>of</strong> the section 39(2) obligation in relation to the<br />

exceptio doli generalis and its philosophical underpinning — good<br />

faith. 210 This may be a costly exercise — as was the case in Carmichele<br />

— but it allows opportunity for the constitutional resolution <strong>of</strong> an issue<br />

that is crucially in need <strong>of</strong> it. However, this did not happen because<br />

the Constitutional Court was clearly <strong>of</strong> the view that on the papers<br />

there were not sufficient prospects <strong>of</strong> success even if the section<br />

39(2) enquiry required development <strong>of</strong> the common law in such a way<br />

that the exceptio doli generalis be reintroduced.<br />

From the point <strong>of</strong> view that even if there were prospects <strong>of</strong><br />

success on appeal, a full trial had already occurred in the High Court<br />

and the cost to have the matter referred back to the trial court would<br />

have been prohibitive and unfair to the respondent, the<br />

Constitutional Court could itself have granted leave to appeal and<br />

could have decided the issue <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> the common law<br />

on appeal. However, this was again not considered a viable option<br />

both presumably on the basis that there were not sufficient prospects<br />

<strong>of</strong> success on appeal and on the basis that it would have been<br />

extraordinary for the Constitutional Court to sit as court <strong>of</strong> first and<br />

last instance, because, as was indicated in Carmichele (referring to<br />

Bequinot) 211 the Court would be put at a ‘grave disadvantage’ were<br />

it not to have ‘the benefit <strong>of</strong> a fully considered judgment from either<br />

the SCA or the High Court’ 212 on the point <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law. In the Crown Restaurant matter it is a pity that a point<br />

<strong>of</strong> law in such urgent need <strong>of</strong> constitutional resolution fell through the<br />

209 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 81.<br />

210 See Glover (n 104 above) 451.<br />

211 S v Bequinot 1997 2 SA 887 (CC) (Bequinot).<br />

212 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 58.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 193<br />

cracks as it were and led to a judicial impasse which, seemingly, could<br />

only be normalised/justified by invoking the idea that the common<br />

law can only be developed when parties invite the courts to develop<br />

the common law. And it is this idea that sits uncomfortably with the<br />

‘general obligation’ to develop the common law in line with<br />

constitutional values enunciated in Carmichele. 213<br />

However, it is quite possible that there might be another reason<br />

for the Court’s decision not to grant leave to appeal in the Crown<br />

Restaurant matter. This reason might relate particularly to the<br />

controversy regarding the status <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis and<br />

good faith in our law <strong>of</strong> contract. In other words, the Constitutional<br />

Court’s refusal to hear argument on the merits and thus also its<br />

refusal to grant leave to appeal in Crown Restaurant might relate to<br />

the apprehensive way in which the substantive legal issue is generally<br />

treated in our law <strong>of</strong> contract. Simply put, my contention is that the<br />

Constitutional Court made a policy decision to deal with this case by<br />

not dealing with it. Implicit in the Court’s reasoning is that it would<br />

be inappropriate for it to sit as Court <strong>of</strong> first and last instance (that is<br />

without the benefit <strong>of</strong> judgments from the lower courts) on a matter<br />

as contentious and as vexed as the status <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli<br />

generalis and the good faith approach in our law <strong>of</strong> contract. In and<br />

<strong>of</strong> itself, this refusal might well have amounted to a silent<br />

endorsement <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic order(ing) in our law <strong>of</strong> contract.<br />

But when considered in the light <strong>of</strong> the other contract law case<br />

before the Constitutional Court in 2007, the judgment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court in Crown Restaurant might have been influenced<br />

by the fact that a more appropriate contract law case for the<br />

Constitutional Court (that is, a case where the constitutional issue<br />

had already passed through the trial court and the SCA) was before it<br />

at the time <strong>of</strong> Crown Restaurant that would, in any event, provide the<br />

Court with the opportunity to pronounce on good faith (as the<br />

philosophical underpinning <strong>of</strong> the exceptio doli generalis), albeit by<br />

not pronouncing on it. In other words, the silence we see in Crown<br />

Restaurant regarding the exceptio (and for that matter, good faith as<br />

its philosophical underpinning) foreshadows the silence about good<br />

faith that we shall see in Barkhuizen. The silence in Barkhuizen,<br />

however, is different in that it is a silence that opens Kafka’s<br />

proverbial door <strong>of</strong> the law, whereas Crown Restaurant closed it. 214<br />

213 Carmichele (n 193 above) para 39.<br />

214 See, in general, F Kafka The trial trans B Mitchell (1998).


194 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

5.3 Barkhuizen v Napier<br />

In this case the Constitutional Court had to consider the<br />

constitutionality <strong>of</strong> a time limitation clause in a short-term insurance<br />

policy. 215 The case came before the Constitutional Court on appeal<br />

from the SCA which held that there was no evidence before it that<br />

indicated that the contract/policy containing the time-bar clause was<br />

not entered into freely and voluntarily in the exercise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional rights to dignity, equality and freedom. This led the<br />

court to the conclusion that constitutional norms and values could not<br />

operate to invalidate the bargain concluded. 216<br />

Before proceeding to the judgment <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court, a<br />

few important points should be made regarding the SCA’s Barkhuizen<br />

judgment not the least <strong>of</strong> which is that this judgment constitutes the<br />

latest in the series <strong>of</strong> judgments that attempt to provide a<br />

constitutional fit and justification for the hegemonic order(ing) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract in South Africa. 217 This legitimation <strong>of</strong> the hegemonic<br />

order(ing) was most prominent in the Brisley majority judgment and<br />

separate concurring judgment <strong>of</strong> Cameron JA. Of his separate<br />

concurring judgment in Brisley Cameron JA says the following in his<br />

judgment in Barkhuizen:<br />

Brisley rejected the notion that the Constitution and its value system<br />

confer on Judges a general jurisdiction ... or power to decide that<br />

contractual terms cannot be enforced on the basis <strong>of</strong> imprecise notions<br />

<strong>of</strong> good faith. 218<br />

Cameron JA then added that the judgments in Brisley and Afrox<br />

‘affirmed that the common law <strong>of</strong> contract is subject to the<br />

Constitution’ 219 and that public policy, as rooted in the founding<br />

values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution — human dignity, the achievement <strong>of</strong><br />

equality and the advancement <strong>of</strong> human rights and freedoms, nonracialism<br />

and non-sexism — is the proper instrument by way <strong>of</strong> which<br />

the courts can invalidate agreements that are <strong>of</strong>fensive to the values<br />

<strong>of</strong> the new constitutional order. 220<br />

Cameron JA’s judgment openly maintains an explicit opposition<br />

between public policy and good faith. However, Cameron JA <strong>of</strong>fers no<br />

215 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 1.<br />

216 Napier (n 13 above) para 28. The court held that this lack <strong>of</strong> evidence was<br />

attributable to the way in which the matter came before it, namely by way <strong>of</strong> ‘a<br />

terse statement <strong>of</strong> facts’ (para 9).<br />

217 In a critique <strong>of</strong> the judgment <strong>of</strong> the SCA, Deeksha Bhana argues that the SCA<br />

reaffirmed the classical liberal position. See D Bhana ‘The law <strong>of</strong> contract and the<br />

Constitution: Napier v Barkhuizen (SCA)’ (2007) 2 South African Law Journal 269.<br />

218 Napier (n 13 above) para 7 (emphasis added).<br />

219 Napier (n 13 above) para 6.<br />

220 Napier (n 13 above) para 7.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 195<br />

justification as to why good faith should be regarded as more <strong>of</strong> an<br />

imprecise and vague notion than the notions in which public policy are<br />

supposedly rooted: dignity, the achievement <strong>of</strong> equality, the<br />

advancement <strong>of</strong> human rights and freedoms, non-racialism and nonsexism.<br />

Dignity particularly has in the past been repeatedly criticised<br />

for being, an imprecise notion. 221 Some have even gone so far as to<br />

describe equality as an empty concept. 222 Are the concepts <strong>of</strong> nonracialism<br />

and non-sexism not also open concepts? And what about ‘the<br />

advancement <strong>of</strong> human rights and freedoms’? Moreover, can it not be<br />

said that in a constitutional democracy founded on these values, good<br />

faith — as the ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract — encompasses, in fact<br />

embraces, all these founding values at once? Hector MacQueen and<br />

Alfred Cockrell have argued that the South African courts have long<br />

conceded that public policy is a dynamic concept in the South African<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract. It nevertheless, argues MacQueen and Cockrell, falls<br />

to be distinguished from good faith. 223 Whereas good faith applies<br />

community standards ‘much more directly’ to the relationship<br />

between the contracting parties, public policy enunciates moral and<br />

social standards that are not necessarily dependent on the<br />

relationship between the parties. 224 The SCA appears to have, at least<br />

implicitly, accepted a dynamic conception <strong>of</strong> public policy. 225 At the<br />

same time it appears to have adopted the view that public policy<br />

should be distinguished from good faith, but not along the lines<br />

suggested by MacQueen and Cockrell. 226 The SCA rejects any direct<br />

reliance on good faith on the basis that it is too imprecise a notion.<br />

Yet, it accepts direct reliance on public policy — a concept as dynamic<br />

and as imprecise as public policy. Such a basis for the opposition<br />

between good faith and public policy is incoherent and arbitrary. The<br />

point is that both good faith and public policy are open-ended norms,<br />

imprecise notions, text that calls for interpretation and justification<br />

much like the entire Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and the founding values and ideals<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitution. Both good faith and public policy amount to<br />

devices by way <strong>of</strong> which freedom <strong>of</strong> contract (as embodying the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> autonomy) is limited (and thus constituted) in the South African<br />

law <strong>of</strong> contract. 227 To privilege public policy on the basis that good<br />

221 See for instance D Davis ‘Equality: The majesty <strong>of</strong> Legoland jurisprudence’ (1999)<br />

116 South African Law Journal 398 413 and C McCrudden ‘Human dignity’<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Oxford Faculty <strong>of</strong> Law Legal Studies Research Paper Series Working<br />

Paper 10/2006, April 2006.<br />

222 P Westen ‘The empty idea <strong>of</strong> equality’ (1982) 95 Harvard Law Review 537.<br />

223 H MacQueen & A Cockrell ‘Illegal contracts’ in R Zimmerman et al (eds) Mixed<br />

legal systems in comparative perspective: Property and obligations in Scotland<br />

and South Africa (2004) 143 173.<br />

224 As above.<br />

225 See Magna Alloys (n 85 above) 891 and Sasfin (n 75 above) 7I-J.<br />

226 See South African Forestry (n 13 above) para 32.<br />

227 Perhaps the privileging <strong>of</strong> public policy can be explained by reference to the<br />

privileging <strong>of</strong> the mantra that public policy generally favours the strict<br />

enforcement <strong>of</strong> contracts, whereas good faith does not, without more, favour<br />

such a privileging <strong>of</strong> liberal ideology.


196 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

faith is too imprecise a notion (and thereby suggesting that public<br />

policy is somehow more precise) sits uncomfortably with the context<br />

<strong>of</strong> — and openness to — an entire legal order that is founded on more<br />

or less ‘imprecise’ notions namely dignity, equality and freedom,<br />

notions to which meaning is given in a long process over time at the<br />

same time as their meaning always depends — at least to a certain<br />

extent — on context.<br />

A further aspect <strong>of</strong> the SCA’s Barkhuizen judgment to which I want<br />

to draw attention is the uncritical — and alarming — assumption in the<br />

judgment that the hegemonic order(ing) <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract in<br />

South Africa is already constitutionally entrenched. I use the word<br />

‘alarming’ here given the vast economic disempowerment in South<br />

Africa and the grossly unequal, undignified and in fact unfree<br />

bargaining relations and situations in South Africa that the law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract normalises and on a continuing basis sustains. From this<br />

perspective, it is hard to believe the SCA when it argues that the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract — in its current permutation — approximates the ideals <strong>of</strong><br />

a transformative legal order in the best possible way, even when it<br />

concedes that public policy is a dynamic concept the meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

which is to be determined by reference to the values and rights in the<br />

Constitution. Of course, some argue that the achievement <strong>of</strong> socioeconomic<br />

equality is not — and should not be — something which a<br />

general law <strong>of</strong> contract can do much — if anything substantial —<br />

about. Yet, this approach fails to take into account what Woolman<br />

calls ‘the structured silence <strong>of</strong> [contractual] disputes that never make<br />

it to court.’ 228 Moreover, when the Constitution requires in section<br />

39(2) that when the common law is developed it must be developed<br />

taking into account the spirit, purport and object <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights,<br />

the Constitution explicitly involves all law in the project <strong>of</strong><br />

transformative constitutionalism. It thus explicitly requires that one<br />

takes a view <strong>of</strong> the common law as something other than the neutral<br />

backdrop against which interactions between legal subjects occur.<br />

Judgments such as those delivered in Brisley, Afrox and the SCA’s<br />

Barkhuizen judgment are attempts to provide the authoritative<br />

statements that the Constitution did not significantly change/affect<br />

— that is, it attempts to legitimise — the hegemonic order(ing) in the<br />

South African law <strong>of</strong> contract. The positions taken in these judgments<br />

<strong>of</strong> course <strong>of</strong>fer a particular ideological reading <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.<br />

The ideology that prevails reads the Constitution in a classical liberal<br />

way against which it is easy to legitimise the hegemonic order(ing) <strong>of</strong><br />

a classical liberal law <strong>of</strong> contract as in accordance with it. Cameron<br />

JA’s judgment in Brisley is exemplary <strong>of</strong> such a classical liberal<br />

ideology when it comes to the relationship between the Constitution<br />

228 See S Woolman ‘Category mistakes and the waiver <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights: A<br />

response to Deeksha Bhana on Barkhuizen’ (2008) 1 South African Law Journal 10<br />

11.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 197<br />

and the law <strong>of</strong> contract. To recall, Cameron JA held that ‘[t]he<br />

constitutional values <strong>of</strong> dignity and equality and freedom require that<br />

courts approach their task <strong>of</strong> striking down contracts or declining to<br />

enforce them with perceptive restraint ... contractual autonomy is<br />

part <strong>of</strong> freedom’ 229 and ‘shorn <strong>of</strong> its obscene excesses’ 230 it ‘informs<br />

also the constitutional value <strong>of</strong> dignity.’ 231 This judgment (like the<br />

judgment <strong>of</strong> the majority) is predicated upon an individualist ethic<br />

that is not only difficult to square with the altruistic ideals inherent<br />

in the spirit <strong>of</strong> a Constitution that aspires to a post-apartheid society;<br />

it also uncritically assumes that the strict enforcement <strong>of</strong> contracts<br />

(that is, a principled — and thus political — commitment to nonintervention<br />

by the courts in contractual matters) is in service <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional values <strong>of</strong> dignity, equality and freedom.<br />

The way in which Cameron JA’s judgment in Brisley was later used<br />

in Afrox was criticised along the lines suggested above. 232 Lubbe for<br />

instance argued that when the foundational concepts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution are marshalled in the under-nuanced way in which they<br />

were in Afrox, the founding values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution serve to do only<br />

one thing and that is to dissipate pressure on the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> this<br />

hegemony. 233 As Wagener argued, the linking <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

with dignity does not, without more, favour the strict enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

contracts. 234 On the contrary, dignity might well be invoked to justify<br />

more active judicial control. Bhana and Pieterse also argued in this<br />

regard that ‘the [constitutional] value <strong>of</strong> freedom does not equate<br />

with complete individual liberty and does not found an independent<br />

right to unlimited contractual liberty.’ 235<br />

Turning now to the Constitutional Court’s decision in Barkhuizen,<br />

it must be said that this decision <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court is, in a<br />

very real sense, not possible without the decisions and positions taken<br />

229 Brisley (n 13 above) 35E.<br />

230 Brisley (n 13 above) 35F. (I am also interested in understanding in which<br />

circumstances the court will regard freedom <strong>of</strong> contract as sufficiently ‘shorn <strong>of</strong><br />

its obscene excesses’.)<br />

231 Brisley (as above).<br />

232 D Bhana & M Pieterse ‘Towards a reconciliation <strong>of</strong> contract law and constitutional<br />

values: Brisley and Afrox revisited’(2005) 122 South African Law Journal 865 874;<br />

G Lubbe ‘Taking fundamental rights seriously: The Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and its<br />

implications for the development <strong>of</strong> contract law’ (2004) 121 South African Law<br />

Journal 395.<br />

233 See Lubbe (n 232 above) 420.<br />

234 S Wagener ‘A proposal for the reform <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> contract brought about by the<br />

judicial development <strong>of</strong> novel naturalia’ (2005) Responsa Meridiana 19 39-40.<br />

Also see K Hopkins ‘The influence <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights on the enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

contract’ (2003) 425 De Rebus 25.<br />

235 n 232 above, 879. Bhana and Pieterse also argue that the value <strong>of</strong> freedom ‘is<br />

reined in significantly by its interaction with the constitutional values <strong>of</strong> equality<br />

and dignity’. Again, I do not believe that freedom is somehow reined in by its<br />

interaction with equality and dignity. Rather, freedom is constituted by its<br />

interaction with equality and dignity.


198 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

in Brisley and Afrox and <strong>of</strong> course also in the SCA decision in<br />

Barkhuizen. Here, in the first case before the Constitutional Court on<br />

the law <strong>of</strong> contract, it had the benefit <strong>of</strong> the judgments <strong>of</strong> the lower<br />

courts. Things were as they should be.<br />

In Barkhuizen the appellant argued that the time limitation<br />

constituted an unjustifiable limitation on the constitutional right to<br />

approach a court for redress. 236 In the High Court the appellant<br />

argued on the basis <strong>of</strong> the direct horizontal application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional right and succeeded in his claim. 237 However, the<br />

Constitutional Court confirmed in this case the approach followed in<br />

the decision by the SCA. The proper approach when dealing with the<br />

constitutionality <strong>of</strong> contractual provisions is to subject the term to<br />

the public policy test ‘as evidenced by the constitutional values, in<br />

particular, those found in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.’ 238 This means, <strong>of</strong> course,<br />

that the route <strong>of</strong> indirect horizontal application is the preferred route<br />

when considering the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> a contractual<br />

arrangement. 239 In determining whether a particular clause <strong>of</strong>fends<br />

public policy as animated by the Constitution, the court held that the<br />

first question is whether the clause itself is reasonable. 240 The second<br />

question, held the Court, is whether the clause should be enforced in<br />

light <strong>of</strong> the circumstances that prevented compliance with it. 241 In<br />

this leg <strong>of</strong> the enquiry unequal bargaining power is a factor, but not<br />

the only factor, that plays a role in the determination <strong>of</strong> public<br />

policy. 242 On the first question, the court held that the<br />

reasonableness <strong>of</strong> the provision is determined by weighing up the<br />

public interest in compliance with freely and voluntarily concluded<br />

terms (or, otherwise put, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract) against the public<br />

interest in the right <strong>of</strong> access to courts. 243 The second question<br />

effectively involves an enquiry into the reasons why non-compliance<br />

is manifest. The onus to prove that it was impossible or unreasonable<br />

in the circumstances to comply with the clause rests on the party who<br />

alleges it. 244 Thus, where the clause has been found not to be in<br />

violation <strong>of</strong> public policy (objectively speaking), it can still be<br />

escaped where the defendant proves good reason why there was<br />

failure to comply.<br />

But there are two aspects regarding the Court’s statements on<br />

public policy on which I want to dwell for the moment because they<br />

236 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 1.<br />

237 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 9.<br />

238 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 30.<br />

239 For criticism see Woolman (note 102 above) 774-781.<br />

240 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 59.<br />

241 As above.<br />

242 As above.<br />

243 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 57.<br />

244 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 58.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 199<br />

have implications for good faith. First, I want to emphasise that the<br />

Court reconfirmed the trite notion that the validity or otherwise <strong>of</strong><br />

contractual terms is determined by asking whether the clause is in<br />

accordance with public policy. Second, the Court emphatically stated<br />

that ‘public policy represents the legal convictions <strong>of</strong> the community;<br />

it represents those values held most dear by the society.’ 245 It also<br />

held that ‘[p]ublic policy imports the notions <strong>of</strong> fairness, justice and<br />

reasonableness.’ 246 According to the Constitutional Court then, the<br />

enforceability or not <strong>of</strong> contractual terms are determined by the legal<br />

convictions <strong>of</strong> the community as represented by ‘the values that<br />

underlie our constitutional democracy’. 247 This statement flies in the<br />

face <strong>of</strong> the Brisley judgment in which the Court explicitly and in the<br />

strongest terms overruled Davis J’s judgment in Mort because it<br />

attempted to make the enforceability <strong>of</strong> contractual terms dependent<br />

on the legal convictions <strong>of</strong> the community.<br />

Recall, however, that Davis J referred to the legal convictions <strong>of</strong><br />

the community in relation not to public policy but to good faith. It<br />

thus appears that, to the extent that Davis J did indicate that the<br />

enforceability <strong>of</strong> contractual terms depends on the legal convictions<br />

<strong>of</strong> the constitutional community — as that term is understood as the<br />

aspirational ‘community <strong>of</strong> the “ought to be”’ 248 — the Constitutional<br />

Court is in agreement with him and disagrees with the SCA. The only<br />

disagreement between the Constitutional Court and Davis J is the<br />

doctrinal name <strong>of</strong> these legal convictions. The Constitutional Court<br />

calls it public policy, Davis J calls it good faith. Can it be that the<br />

Constitutional Court in this case in fact merged public policy with<br />

good faith? Can it be that good faith after all forms part <strong>of</strong> public<br />

policy as Olivier JA argued in his much-maligned judgment in Eerste<br />

Nasionale Bank? The answer to this question is by no means clear given<br />

Ngcobo J’s emphatic statement that the facts <strong>of</strong> the case did not<br />

require the Court to answer the question whether, under the<br />

Constitution, the limited role for good faith expounded since Brisley,<br />

is appropriate. 249 Yet, the Court attributes exactly the same meaning<br />

to public policy as the meanings that have been attributed to good<br />

faith. A striking example is the similarity between the definition by<br />

the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> public policy as ‘importing the notions <strong>of</strong><br />

fairness, justice and reasonableness’ 250 and Olivier JA’s definition <strong>of</strong><br />

245 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 28.<br />

246 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 73.<br />

247 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 29.<br />

248 See D Cornell Moral images <strong>of</strong> freedom (2007) 22.<br />

249 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 82. This point is emphasised in the judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

O’Regan J (Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 120): ‘there is in my view no need for<br />

this court to consider in what circumstances a court may, in terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

principles <strong>of</strong> contract, decline to enforce a time-limitation clause against a<br />

particular applicant based on the defences <strong>of</strong> impossibility or good faith. That<br />

difficult question can stand over for decision in an appropriate matter.’<br />

250 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 73.


200 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

good faith as realising the community’s legal convictions regarding<br />

propriety, reasonableness and fairness. 251<br />

On the other hand, the Court raised the good faith issue as it was<br />

dealing with the second leg <strong>of</strong> its test to determine the enforceability<br />

<strong>of</strong> the term on the ground <strong>of</strong> public policy: whether the terms are<br />

contrary to public policy in the light <strong>of</strong> the relative situation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

contracting parties. The court held that the applicability <strong>of</strong> the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> good faith would depend on the reason advanced for noncompliance.<br />

However, the applicant did not disclose his reason for<br />

non-compliance. This made it impossible to say whether<br />

‘enforcement <strong>of</strong> the clause against the applicant would be unfair and<br />

thus contrary to public policy.’ 252 In other words, the absence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

reason for non-compliance blocked, it seems, the consideration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

good faith requirement within the public policy test. In the absence<br />

<strong>of</strong> pleaded reasons for non-compliance, it would, according to the<br />

Court, be unfair to the respondent and contrary to pacta servanda<br />

sunt to excuse Barkhuizen from non-compliance with the time-bar<br />

clause. 253 For these reasons, the majority accordingly dismissed the<br />

appeal.<br />

On my reading it seems then at least probable that the court<br />

would have been willing to consider good faith (in the context <strong>of</strong> its<br />

formulated public policy test) had reasons been advanced for noncompliance<br />

with the term. In this way the court seems to both accept<br />

and reject the category distinction that MacQueen and Cockrell make<br />

between public policy and good faith. The Court clearly views good<br />

faith as the measure that would curb the enforcement <strong>of</strong> the term if<br />

enforcement ‘would be unfair or unjust to the applicant.’ 254 Given<br />

the Court’s statement regarding the role <strong>of</strong> unequal bargaining power<br />

in this leg <strong>of</strong> its public policy test, the suggestion seems to be that<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the good faith test will involve enquiring into the relative<br />

bargaining position <strong>of</strong> the parties and the way in which this impacted<br />

on the contractual arrangement. In this way it appears that the Court<br />

left the door wide open as regards good faith’s potential role as part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the public policy test. Moreover, this means that the exceptio doli<br />

generalis, albeit in drag, has risen from the grave 255 — a grave in<br />

which it was in any event never interred. Another implication <strong>of</strong> the<br />

judgment is that the Constitutional Court has confirmed that the<br />

alleged exercise <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract in violation <strong>of</strong> both the rights<br />

in and the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, will not be<br />

enforced on grounds <strong>of</strong> public policy.<br />

251 Eerste Nasionale Bank (n 128 above) 319B.<br />

252 Barkhuizen (n 13 above) para 84.<br />

253 n 13 above, para 85.<br />

254 As above.<br />

255 Glover (n 104 above) 455.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 201<br />

To what extent this confirmation will constitute internal<br />

limitations on freedom <strong>of</strong> contract — and thus amount to a<br />

synchronisation <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract with the other constitutional<br />

rights and freedoms in furtherance <strong>of</strong> a transformative understanding<br />

— depends on whether there will be a departure from/transformation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the hegemonic order(ing) we have interrogated. Moreover, by<br />

leaving the door <strong>of</strong> public policy open to good faith, the court has<br />

created the possibility that good faith may in the future again become<br />

constitutive <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, rather than marginalised and<br />

seen as opposed to it. Again, everything here depends on the content<br />

that will be afforded to good faith. It goes without saying that it is<br />

always possible (and indeed likely) that good faith can be afforded<br />

weak content that would just further legitimise the hegemonic<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> contract. To put it perhaps more<br />

dramatically, it is <strong>of</strong> course always an imminent danger that good<br />

faith will simply become a private and privatising device. 256 For this<br />

reason it becomes necessary to defend a progressive and<br />

transformative version <strong>of</strong> good faith.<br />

6 Negotiating otherwise — good faith, civic<br />

friendship and freedom <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

When considering the justifiable potential content <strong>of</strong> good faith — as<br />

the ethical ideal that undergirds the law <strong>of</strong> contract — I believe it is<br />

necessary to take as one’s point <strong>of</strong> departure the nature and the<br />

aspirations <strong>of</strong> the reconstituted legal order within which the law <strong>of</strong><br />

contract operates as an institution <strong>of</strong> the common law subordinated<br />

to the Constitution. If it is the case that the ‘proper’ approach (post-<br />

Barkhuizen) to the influence <strong>of</strong> the Constitution on the common law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract is the public policy enquiry, then good faith — as the<br />

ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract, as ‘the law <strong>of</strong> the responsible<br />

transaction’ 257 — can and must come to play a role in the<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> the public policy requirement in order for the spirit<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitution as a whole to have a better chance <strong>of</strong> a<br />

transformative effect in the law <strong>of</strong> contract. In other words if there is<br />

to be talk <strong>of</strong> and hope for what Johan van der Walt has called<br />

progressive indirect horizontal application 258 then we cannot afford<br />

to lose sight <strong>of</strong> good faith and the transformative potential it holds for<br />

the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract. Good faith holds this<br />

256 See JWG van der Walt ‘Die toekoms van die onderskeid tussen die publiekreg en<br />

die privaatreg in die lig van die horisontale werking van die grondwet (deel 2)’<br />

2000 Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 605 612.<br />

257 J Derrida ‘On forgiveness’ in J Derrida On cosmopolitanism and forgiveness (2001)<br />

56.<br />

258 See in general JWG van der Walt ‘Progressive indirect horizontal application:<br />

Towards a co-operative relation between common-law and constitutional<br />

jurisprudence’ (2001) South African Journal on Human Rights 341.


202 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

transformative potential because, more than any other normative<br />

contractual device, it is good faith that invokes, as an ethical notion,<br />

respect for the dignity <strong>of</strong> contracting parties, precisely because, as<br />

MacQueen and Cockrell suggest, good faith focuses the enquiry<br />

explicitly on the relationship between the particular contractual<br />

parties. This respect for dignity when it comes to legal relations is a<br />

core aspect <strong>of</strong> the newly constituted legal order and its aspirations to<br />

civic friendship.<br />

I would like to suggest, in conclusion then, that the Constitution<br />

aspires to an ideal <strong>of</strong> civic friendship (a ‘politics’ <strong>of</strong> friendship if you<br />

will) which requires, mandates and demands negotiation<br />

(contracting) otherwise — that is, with respect for and consideration<br />

<strong>of</strong> the other contracting party. I believe that the Constitution aspires<br />

to the post-liberal ideal <strong>of</strong> civic friendship precisely because <strong>of</strong> its<br />

foundational injunction to respect the dignity <strong>of</strong> all others. 259 This, I<br />

would argue, requires that we afford content to good faith in the law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract that would maintain it as a post-liberal concept. I want to<br />

emphasise here that I do not consider the dignity <strong>of</strong> which the<br />

Constitution speaks (and on which the instant conception <strong>of</strong> civic<br />

friendship and good faith turns) to be inevitably fated as a radically<br />

individualistic concept that, moreover, forms the basis <strong>of</strong> exclusively<br />

negative freedom. This argument is possible because <strong>of</strong> the links<br />

drawn in our early dignity jurisprudence between dignity and<br />

ubuntu. 260 Drucilla Cornell draws the further link between ubuntu,<br />

(Kantian) dignity and friendship as follows:<br />

In Kant, I am a friend to myself because <strong>of</strong> the dignity <strong>of</strong> my humanity.<br />

Under ubuntu, I am a friend to myself because others in my community<br />

have already been friends to me, making me someone who could survive<br />

at all, and therefore be in the community. It is only because I have<br />

always been together with others and they with me that I am gathered<br />

together as a person and sustained in that self-gathering. 261<br />

It was Hannah Arendt who, in modern political theory, resuscitated<br />

and defended a ‘politics <strong>of</strong> friendship’ relying heavily on the work <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle. 262 Arendt’s theory <strong>of</strong> civic friendship <strong>of</strong>fers an account <strong>of</strong><br />

politics that is both post-individualist and post-liberal. In fact,<br />

Arendt’s theory <strong>of</strong> civic friendship invokes an understanding <strong>of</strong><br />

citizenship as a radically ‘horizontal allegiance to friends.’ 263 She<br />

sees in this understanding <strong>of</strong> political life the possibility <strong>of</strong> ‘words that<br />

259 Constitution sec 10.<br />

260 See, for instance, S v Makwanyane 1995 3 SA 391 (CC) paras 224, 308 & 311.<br />

261 D Cornell ‘A call for a nuanced constitutional jurisprudence: Ubuntu, dignity and<br />

reconciliation’ (2004) 19 SA Public Law 666 669.<br />

262 H Arendt The human condition ed M Canovan (1998) 243.<br />

263 ME Stortz ‘Beyond justice: friendship in the city’ (1994) XIV(4) Word & World 409<br />

414 (emphasis added).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 203<br />

are not empty and deeds that are not brutal.’ 264 As Martha Stortz<br />

comments on Arendt’s concept <strong>of</strong> civic friendship:<br />

Civic friendship <strong>of</strong> all sorts emphasises the interdependence <strong>of</strong> citizens<br />

in public life. It articulates a horizontal understanding <strong>of</strong> citizenship,<br />

which prizes the relationship to another citizen and places that<br />

relationship at the centre <strong>of</strong> civic life. 265<br />

Most importantly, though, this form <strong>of</strong> friendship is not at all about<br />

the association <strong>of</strong> the self and the same. At its heart, Arendt’s<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> civic friendship turns on plurality — that is,<br />

difference — because it is plurality in Arendt that is constitutive <strong>of</strong> the<br />

political. 266 And plurality conditions us in the sense that our very<br />

individuality only takes shape through our recognition that we share<br />

the world with others.<br />

This immediately implicates the idea <strong>of</strong> respect, for without<br />

respect there can be no durability for plurality. And as Arendt puts it<br />

in The human condition: ‘what love is in its own, narrowly<br />

circumscribed sphere, respect is in the larger domain <strong>of</strong> human<br />

affairs.’ ‘... [R]espect’, so she continues,<br />

is a kind <strong>of</strong> ‘friendship’ ... it is a regard for the person from the distance<br />

which the space <strong>of</strong> the world puts between us, and this regard is<br />

independent <strong>of</strong> qualities which we may admire or <strong>of</strong> achievements which<br />

we may highly esteem. 267<br />

For Arendt then there can be no talk <strong>of</strong> civic friendship without this<br />

respect, which, to emphasise, does not depend on conditions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

self and the same. However, Arendt conceded that the modern age is<br />

characterised by the loss <strong>of</strong> respect and this ‘constitutes a clear<br />

symptom <strong>of</strong> the increasing depersonalisation <strong>of</strong> public and social<br />

life.’ 268 It is also because <strong>of</strong> Arendt’s acute awareness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

implications <strong>of</strong> this depersonalisation due to the loss <strong>of</strong> respect that<br />

she insists famously at the end <strong>of</strong> the preface to The origins <strong>of</strong><br />

totalitarianism that, in the aftermath <strong>of</strong> the disasters <strong>of</strong> modernity<br />

‘human dignity needs a new guarantee which can be found only in a<br />

new law on earth.’ 269<br />

264 As above.<br />

265 As above.<br />

266 Arendt (n 262 above) 7.<br />

267 n 262 above, 243.<br />

268 As above.<br />

269 H Arendt The origins <strong>of</strong> totalitarianism (1973) ix.


204 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

If we recall Derrida’s assertion in Politics <strong>of</strong> Friendship that there<br />

is no friendship without respect <strong>of</strong> the other, that ‘the co-implication<br />

<strong>of</strong> responsibility and respect can be felt at the heart <strong>of</strong> friendship’ 270<br />

we will begin to see the trembling overlap between the ethical, the<br />

political and the juridical in the South African Constitution in which<br />

respect for the dignity <strong>of</strong> all others comes to play a constitutive role.<br />

Justice O’Regan has referred explicitly to respect and responsibility<br />

as ‘the building blocks <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.’ 271 And this respect is<br />

owed to the equal human dignity <strong>of</strong> everyone. 272 On my reading, this<br />

unconditional horizontality <strong>of</strong> the South African Constitution appeals<br />

to a prioritisation <strong>of</strong> Arendt’s, but also Derrida’s, vision <strong>of</strong> friendship<br />

in which the Greek form <strong>of</strong> love as philia is instituted as a sociopolitical<br />

concept but here in holding out the promise <strong>of</strong> a beyond to<br />

any condition <strong>of</strong> fraternity or ‘confraternisation’. 273 Shin Chiba<br />

argues that it is this form <strong>of</strong> love that permeates Arendt’s search for<br />

a new and durable vinculum or social bond, which, let us recall, is the<br />

original name for law. 274 The implication <strong>of</strong> this institutionalisation is<br />

that it is in fact respect, as phronesis and praxis for the Other 275 —<br />

respect that resides in love <strong>of</strong> the Other — that becomes constitutive<br />

<strong>of</strong> the legal order.<br />

Judge Dennis Davis has been foremost amongst those who have<br />

argued that the notion <strong>of</strong> respect for equal dignity (civic friendship)<br />

is translated into the law <strong>of</strong> contract by way <strong>of</strong> good faith. 276 He has<br />

also opposed this concept to South Africa’s political past. As Davis J<br />

puts it:<br />

this concept <strong>of</strong> good faith is congruent with the underlying vision <strong>of</strong> our<br />

Constitution ... to the extent that our Constitution seeks to transform<br />

our society from its past, it is self-evident that apartheid represented<br />

the very opposite <strong>of</strong> good faith ... Our Constitution seeks to develop a<br />

community where each will have respect for the other ... Whatever the<br />

uncertainty, the principle <strong>of</strong> good faith must require that the parties act<br />

honestly in their commercial dealings. Where one party promotes its<br />

own interests at the expense <strong>of</strong> another in so unreasonable a manner as<br />

to destroy the very basis <strong>of</strong> consensus between the two parties, the<br />

270 J Derrida Politics <strong>of</strong> friendship trans G Collins (1997) 252. Of course, Derrida is<br />

problematising Kant’s formulations with regard to friendship here, notably Kant’s<br />

separation <strong>of</strong> love from friendship. Time and space does not permit a discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> this deconstruction.<br />

271 C O’Regan ‘The three r's <strong>of</strong> the Constitution: Responsibility, respect and rights’<br />

(2004) Acta Juridica 86.<br />

272 As above.<br />

273 See S Chiba ‘Hannah Arendt on love and the political: Love, friendship, and<br />

citizenship’ (1995) 57 The Review <strong>of</strong> Politics 505 512-513. Also see Derrida (n 267<br />

above) viii.<br />

274 n 273 above, 509.<br />

275 Douzinas & Geary (n 68 above) 40.<br />

276 But also see Grové (n 130 above) 689.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 205<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> good faith can be employed to trump the public interest<br />

inherent in the principle <strong>of</strong> the enforcement <strong>of</strong> a contract. 277<br />

In his judgment in Mort Davis J quoted the words <strong>of</strong> Reinhard<br />

Zimmermann 278 in relation to this aspect:<br />

the principles <strong>of</strong> equality and dignity require that the parties to a<br />

contract do none other but ‘adhere to a minimum threshold <strong>of</strong> mutual<br />

respect in which the unreasonable and one-sided promotion <strong>of</strong> one’s own<br />

interest at the expense <strong>of</strong> the other infringes the principle <strong>of</strong> good faith<br />

to such a degree as to outweigh the public interest in the sanctity <strong>of</strong><br />

contracts’. 279<br />

This is the formulation for which Barkhuizen leaves the door open.<br />

Ultimately in our context, respect for the Other resides, as Davis J has<br />

also indicated, in the acknowledgement that:<br />

[a] transformative constitution needs to engage with concepts <strong>of</strong> power<br />

and community ... the concept <strong>of</strong> contractual autonomy within the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> a community <strong>of</strong> contracting persons must mean something<br />

distinct from a libertarian connotation, particularly if the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

ubuntu is to play any role in our law. 280<br />

These statements about the law <strong>of</strong> contract as law subordinated<br />

under the new Constitution are explicit interpretations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional mandate as requiring a re-emphasis on the ethical<br />

element <strong>of</strong> contract in the furtherance <strong>of</strong> a post-liberal or positive<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> contract. A freedom <strong>of</strong> contract that comes to understand<br />

that conduct cannot be characterised as free when it disrespects/<br />

violates dignity, 281 when it pretends that contract is a relation<br />

between things and not between persons, when it does not proceed<br />

according to respect for whoever is on the other side <strong>of</strong> the<br />

negotiation. To quote Colombo: ‘Good faith implies a developed sense<br />

277 Shoprite Checkers (Pty) Ltd v Bumpers Schwarmas CC and Others 2002 6 SA 202<br />

(C) (Shoprite) 215G-216A.<br />

278 R Zimmermann ‘Good faith and equity’ in R Zimmerman and D Visser (eds)<br />

Southern cross: civil and common law in South Africa (1996) 259-260.<br />

279 n 168 above, 475B-C.<br />

280 Advtech (n 95 above) 388A.<br />

281 The mantra in Ackermann J’s celebrated minority judgment in Ferreira v Levin<br />

NO and Others; Vryenhoek and Others v Powell NO and Others 1996 1 SA 984 (CC)<br />

(Ferreira) para 49 ‘to deny people their freedom is to deny them their dignity’<br />

should perhaps then be reconsidered in this light because, on this understanding<br />

in the law <strong>of</strong> contract, to deny people their dignity is to deny one’s own freedom<br />

(<strong>of</strong> contract).


206 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

<strong>of</strong> community and a high level <strong>of</strong> awareness <strong>of</strong> personal<br />

responsibilities towards society.’ 282<br />

When Lubbe argues that our understanding <strong>of</strong> dignity in contract<br />

should be informed by Kant’s precept that people should not<br />

act contrary to the equally necessary self-esteem <strong>of</strong> others, as human<br />

beings, that is, [they are] under obligation to acknowledge, in a<br />

practical way, the dignity <strong>of</strong> humanity in every other human being 283<br />

he already acknowledges the relational aspect <strong>of</strong> contract that would<br />

amount to a Hegelian version <strong>of</strong> contract as ‘reciprocal<br />

recognition.’ 284 Rosenfeld explains that<br />

under this paradigm contract is not only compatible with the<br />

reconciliation <strong>of</strong> individual autonomy and communal values, but it is also<br />

suited to foster the mutual determination <strong>of</strong> the individual and — or,<br />

perhaps more precisely, against — the communal. 285<br />

In turn this understanding <strong>of</strong> contract in terms <strong>of</strong> relationality and<br />

mutual recognition bears marked resemblances with Nancy’s analysis<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence as ‘being singular plural.’ 286 Once we understand that<br />

both good faith and freedom <strong>of</strong> contract are essentially relational<br />

concepts it becomes possible to think a law <strong>of</strong> contract beyond<br />

continuing and continuous exploitation, subservience and injustice —<br />

beyond ‘our proud and deadly dualisms.’ 287<br />

The legislature has made substantial inroads in this regard and, at<br />

the time <strong>of</strong> writing the Consumer Protection Bill had been approved<br />

by Parliament and is awaiting the President’s signature. Amongst<br />

various other consumer protection mechanisms the Bill explicitly<br />

prohibits ‘unfair, unreasonable or unjust’ contracting. 288 In addition,<br />

courts will be required in terms <strong>of</strong> clause 52(3) to decide whether a<br />

contract is unconscionable, unjust, unreasonable or unfair. Although<br />

guidelines for the determination <strong>of</strong> the unreasonableness, injustice or<br />

unfairness are set out in clause 48(2) they are explicitly intended not<br />

282 S Colombo ‘Fascism, community and the paradox <strong>of</strong> good faith’ (1994) 113 South<br />

African Law Journal 482 482.<br />

283 Lubbe (n 232 above) 422, quoting I Kant The Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals M Gregor ed<br />

(1996) 209.<br />

284 M Rosenfeld ‘Hegel and the dialectics <strong>of</strong> contract’ (1989) 10 Cardozo Law Review<br />

1199 1200.<br />

285 As above.<br />

286 JL Nancy Being singular plural (2000). In this work Nancy denounces the liberal<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> an individual atomistic self as the subject <strong>of</strong> ontology. As Nancy puts it:<br />

‘That which exists, ... coexists because it exists. The co-implication <strong>of</strong> existing<br />

[l’exister] is the sharing <strong>of</strong> the world.’<br />

287 G Rose Mourning becomes the law (1996) 76.<br />

288 Consumer Protection Bill 2008 clause 48(1) available at http://<br />

www.thedti.gov.za/ccrdlawreview/DraftConsumerProtectionBill.htm (accessed<br />

20 June 2008).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 207<br />

to limit the generality <strong>of</strong> the section prohibiting unreasonable, unfair<br />

or unjust contracting. 289 This Bill thus already points to a future law<br />

<strong>of</strong> contract that will be required to be far more concerned than it has<br />

been up to now, with good faith as the ethical element <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

and thus with the spirit <strong>of</strong> the ideal <strong>of</strong> civic friendship in South Africa.<br />

7 Conclusion<br />

At the heart <strong>of</strong> contract lies the idea that I have an interest in<br />

something <strong>of</strong> yours and that you have an interest in something <strong>of</strong><br />

mine. The hegemonic capitalist over-emphasis on the things and the<br />

utter neglect <strong>of</strong> the persons who have these things, has provided an<br />

extremely distorted version <strong>of</strong> what the word ‘interest’ in the above<br />

formulation originally entails. Levinas takes his cue in his re-emphasis<br />

on the original meaning <strong>of</strong> the word ‘interest’ from Hegel, for whom<br />

contract exists as reciprocal recognition and freedom <strong>of</strong> contract<br />

exists in the free willing <strong>of</strong> one’s duty on the road to selfactualisation.<br />

290 In his essay ‘Sociality and money’, 291 Levinas<br />

reminds us that the word interest is a composite <strong>of</strong> ‘inter’ that is, <strong>of</strong><br />

‘between’ and <strong>of</strong> ‘esse’, that is ‘being’. For Levinas, essence is always<br />

interestedness or differently put being is always inter-estedness.<br />

Thus, to have a contractual interest always already implies<br />

289 For incisive criticism and important suggestions see TJ Naudé ‘Unfair contract<br />

terms legislation: The implications <strong>of</strong> why we need it for its formulation and<br />

application’ (2006) 17 Stellenbosch Law Review 361 374. Also see TJ Naudé ‘The<br />

use <strong>of</strong> black and grey lists in unfair contract terms legislation in comparative<br />

perspective’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 128. In the latter article (135-<br />

136) Pr<strong>of</strong> Naudé criticises this author for — in her opinion, exclusively —<br />

supporting an open-ended version (based on good faith) <strong>of</strong> the Unfair Contractual<br />

Terms Bill proposed by the Working Committee <strong>of</strong> the South African Law<br />

Commission (as it then was) in SA Law Commission Discussion Paper 65<br />

Unreasonable Stipulations in Contracts and the Rectification <strong>of</strong> Contracts (July<br />

1996). See AJ Barnard ‘A critical legal argument for contractual justice in the<br />

South African law <strong>of</strong> contract’ unpublished LLD dissertation, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Pretoria</strong>, 2005 241. Apart from the fact that there is no disagreement between<br />

myself and Pr<strong>of</strong> Naudé that, to quote Pr<strong>of</strong> Naudé, ‘the use <strong>of</strong> non-exhaustive<br />

guidelines and a grey list by a court cannot be equated with the “mechanical<br />

application <strong>of</strong> precedent” and does not preclude a decision guided by “the<br />

relational, the collective and the transformative” at all’, I wish to make it clear<br />

that my doctoral study focused on the rhetorical history and lexicon <strong>of</strong><br />

adjudication in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract (which was and still is primarily<br />

based on the application <strong>of</strong> precedent). This mode, I argued, was, and still is in<br />

danger <strong>of</strong> perpetuating an individualistic interpretation <strong>of</strong> both future guidelines<br />

or lists <strong>of</strong> suspect terms and an individualistic reification <strong>of</strong> open-ended norms.<br />

This is an issue Pr<strong>of</strong> Naudé herself raises — but then dismisses — as a potential<br />

problem with so-called ‘grey lists’. Where Pr<strong>of</strong> Naudé and I part company as I see<br />

it, is that whereas I support Kennedy’s belief that individualism prefers the rule<br />

form and the commitment to formal realisability (which in turn fuels the false<br />

belief in neutrality), Pr<strong>of</strong> Naudé believes that the rule form does not necessarily<br />

follow individualist political morality.<br />

290 See GWF Hegel Elements <strong>of</strong> the philosophy <strong>of</strong> right ed A Wood (1991) 104.<br />

291 E Levinas ‘Sociality and money’ (2007) 16 Business Ethics: A European Review 203<br />

206-207.


208 Hegemony, freedom <strong>of</strong> contract, good faith and transformation<br />

togetherness, being between and with. Levinas admits that ‘in the<br />

concrete <strong>of</strong> everyday life, human interestedness always already<br />

conceals itself’ 292 but at the same time this concealment points to a<br />

beyond to it. This is the astonishing possibility <strong>of</strong> the human being<br />

between, or amongst, beings: the possibility <strong>of</strong> unconcealment, <strong>of</strong><br />

giving his place, <strong>of</strong> sacrificing himself for the other, <strong>of</strong> the goodness<br />

<strong>of</strong> giving, ‘the positivity <strong>of</strong> an attachment to being as being for the<br />

Other.’ 293<br />

What is needed in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract is the best<br />

possible negotiation between these two dimensions <strong>of</strong> the human<br />

condition — inter-est and dis-inter-estedness. The hegemonic<br />

order(ing) <strong>of</strong> the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract at present does not<br />

allow for the best possible negotiation between human interestedness<br />

and human dis-interest. This is the case because<br />

‘individualism is the structure <strong>of</strong> the status quo.’ 294 In this sense it<br />

does not allow for real transformation. This is the case because the<br />

obsession with individualism and the rule form does not allow for that<br />

which is inherent in transformation: the turn towards the Other. Yet,<br />

as Cornell reminds us: ‘[t]ransformation is demanded <strong>of</strong> us precisely<br />

because there is no self-enclosed subject who can truly cut herself <strong>of</strong>f<br />

from the Other. We are constantly being challenged by otherness’. 295<br />

It is only once the (im)possibility <strong>of</strong> the ethical relation is explicitly<br />

inscribed and described in the South African law <strong>of</strong> contract by way <strong>of</strong><br />

at least the explicit incorporation and exploration <strong>of</strong> good faith in the<br />

public policy/legality requirement that the best negotiation/the<br />

negotiation otherwise, becomes possible. The Constitutional Court’s<br />

decision in Barkhuizen and the Consumer Protection Bill allow for this<br />

possibility. To that extent the possibility <strong>of</strong> the impossible ethical<br />

relation can be part <strong>of</strong> the law’s work.<br />

In the second <strong>of</strong> the films in the famous Matrix trilogy, the lead<br />

character, Neo, consults a present day (or perhaps futuristic) version<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ancient Greek oracle, which in the film is represented as a wise<br />

older woman. Let me end with the counsel the Oracle gives to Neo.<br />

Emphatically she states: ‘I am interested in one thing Neo — the<br />

future. And believe me, the only way to get there is together.’ 296<br />

292 n 290 above, 204.<br />

293 Levinas (n 290 above) 205.<br />

294 Kennedy (n 6 above) 1775.<br />

295 Cornell (n 100 above) 41.<br />

296 A & L Wachowski (dirs) The Matrix reloaded (2003).


CLEARING THE INTERSECTION?<br />

ADMINISTRATIVE LAW AND LABOUR LAW<br />

IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL COURT<br />

* Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Law, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg. I am grateful to<br />

those who read and commented on the first draft <strong>of</strong> this article: Clive Plasket, the<br />

participants in the <strong>CCR</strong> Conference <strong>of</strong> 6-7 August 2008 and the <strong>CCR</strong>’s anonymous<br />

reviewers. Their perceptive comments were <strong>of</strong> great assistance to me, and they<br />

are not to blame for any deficiencies that remain.<br />

209<br />

Cora Hoexter *<br />

The dismissal <strong>of</strong> employees in the public sector is as much a matter <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative law as it is one <strong>of</strong> labour law — or so we all thought,<br />

encouraged by the judgment <strong>of</strong> the Appellate Division in<br />

Administrator, Transvaal v Zenzile. 1 But that decision comes from an<br />

era in which labour law was notable for its failure to protect<br />

employees in the public sector and administrative law had to be<br />

called on to perform this role. 2 Much has changed since then, and in<br />

recent years there has been debate about the continuing relevance <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative law in cases <strong>of</strong> dismissal and other employmentrelated<br />

conduct.<br />

In 2007 the Constitutional Court was asked to settle the debate in<br />

Chirwa v Transnet Ltd & Others, 3 a case <strong>of</strong> public-sector dismissal<br />

that called attention to Zenzile once more. The Court also dealt with<br />

two other cases <strong>of</strong> dismissal that touched on questions pertinent to<br />

administrative law. Masetlha v President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South<br />

Africa & Another 4 raised the issue <strong>of</strong> procedural fairness in the<br />

dismissal <strong>of</strong> a high-ranking public <strong>of</strong>ficial. Sidumo & Another v<br />

Rustenburg Platinum Mines Ltd & Others 5 arose out <strong>of</strong> a dismissal in<br />

the private rather than the public sector, but administrative law was<br />

again relevant by virtue <strong>of</strong> an arbitration award by the Commission for<br />

1<br />

2<br />

1991 1 SA 21 (A) (Zenzile).<br />

The legislation <strong>of</strong> the time, the Labour Relations Act 28 <strong>of</strong> 1956, excluded state<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

employees from its ambit.<br />

2008 29 ILJ 73 (CC), handed down on 28 November 2007 (Chirwa).<br />

2008 1 SA 566 (CC), handed down on 3 October 2007 (Masetlha).<br />

2008 2 SA 24 (CC), handed down on 5 October 2007 (Sidumo).


210 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

Conciliation, Mediation and Arbitration (CCMA). In all, the Court had<br />

three opportunities in 2007 to explore the intersection <strong>of</strong> labour law<br />

and administrative law and to elucidate the relationship between<br />

sections 23 and 33 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution — and between the statutes<br />

that are supposed to give effect to those rights, the Labour Relations<br />

Act 66 <strong>of</strong> 1995 (LRA) and the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Administrative Justice Act<br />

3 <strong>of</strong> 2000 (PAJA).<br />

As I shall show in this article, the results are interesting; but they<br />

are also rather disappointing, at least from the perspective <strong>of</strong> an<br />

administrative lawyer. In my commentary on these three cases (in the<br />

order Sidumo, Chirwa and Masetlha) that is the perspective I adopt.<br />

My aim is to elucidate aspects <strong>of</strong> these cases as they touch on<br />

administrative law and, in the process, to make three main points.<br />

First, it seems to me that from the various judgments <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court no coherent picture emerges <strong>of</strong> this intersection<br />

or <strong>of</strong> the relationship between the rights concerned. Indeed, in their<br />

constitutional approach or ethos the Sidumo and Chirwa majority<br />

judgments seem quite different, notwithstanding that the two cases<br />

were decided by almost identical benches and within weeks <strong>of</strong> each<br />

other. A theme emerging strongly from Sidumo, and to a lesser extent<br />

from Masetlha, is that fundamental rights cannot be hermetically<br />

sealed from one other. In Sidumo labour law and administrative law<br />

intermingle and converge, and in Masetlha administrative law in the<br />

broad sense is permitted to solve a problem that labour law<br />

apparently fails to address. In Chirwa, by contrast, the majority<br />

insists on the strict compartmentalisation <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights and<br />

on the pre-eminence <strong>of</strong> one right to the exclusion <strong>of</strong> the other.<br />

Sections 23 and 33 <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights are placed in separate<br />

jurisdictional boxes, and the attitude seems to be that labour law and<br />

administrative law must have nothing to do with one other.<br />

Secondly, in Chirwa the various approaches to the ‘administrative<br />

action’ issue are all problematic to some extent, and the majority<br />

view on the question <strong>of</strong> jurisdiction is wholly unconvincing. While the<br />

Court certainly managed to tidy up the busy intersection <strong>of</strong> labour law<br />

and administrative law in this case, it did so at the expense <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court’s own precedent — and apparently without much<br />

faith in the success <strong>of</strong> its efforts.<br />

Thirdly, whatever labour lawyers may think <strong>of</strong> the majority<br />

judgment in Masetlha, administrative lawyers are likely to be<br />

perturbed by it. For us it is a decision that appears to set the law <strong>of</strong><br />

procedural fairness back twenty years.


1 Sidumo<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 211<br />

The appellant, Mr Sidumo, had been employed by Rustenburg<br />

Platinum Mines Ltd (the mine) for almost fifteen years when he was<br />

dismissed for negligent failure to apply established search procedures<br />

at a redressing station. He contested his dismissal and referred the<br />

dispute to the CCMA in terms <strong>of</strong> section 191 <strong>of</strong> the LRA. Conciliation<br />

failed and the matter went for compulsory arbitration. The<br />

commissioner found that while Sidumo was indeed guilty <strong>of</strong><br />

misconduct, dismissal was not a fair or appropriate sanction; and he<br />

was reinstated with three months’ compensation.<br />

The mine applied for review <strong>of</strong> the award under s 145 <strong>of</strong> the LRA.<br />

The Labour Court dismissed its application, and the Labour Appeal<br />

Court dismissed an appeal to it. The mine was more successful on<br />

subsequent appeal to the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal, which overturned<br />

these two decisions and found the dismissal to have been fair. In<br />

Rustenburg Platinum Mines Ltd (Rustenburg Section) v Commission<br />

for Conciliation, Mediation and Arbitration 6 it held that the<br />

commissioner’s decision to reinstate Sidumo had not been rationally<br />

connected to the information before him.<br />

The reasoning behind this conclusion is significant, for section 145<br />

<strong>of</strong> the LRA lists only four grounds for the review <strong>of</strong> arbitration awards<br />

and irrationality does not feature explicitly amongst them. 7 However,<br />

Cameron JA found for the Court that the PAJA had extended the<br />

grounds <strong>of</strong> review available to parties to CCMA arbitrations — there<br />

being no doubt that CCMA arbitrations qualified as administrative<br />

action. 8 In this regard he drew on Carephone (Pty) Ltd v Marcus NO, 9<br />

a pre-PAJA case in which the Labour Appeal Court held that section<br />

145 was suffused with the standard <strong>of</strong> justifiability in section 24 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

interim Constitution 10 (the predecessor to section 33). Cameron JA<br />

held that as general legislation relating to administrative action the<br />

PAJA had ‘superseded the LRA’s specialised enactment within the<br />

[labour] field’, 11 and it thus subsumed and overrode the more<br />

restrictive grounds <strong>of</strong> review in section 145 <strong>of</strong> the LRA. 12 An unrelated<br />

but equally significant holding <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal in<br />

6 2007 1 SA 576 (SCA) (Rustenburg).<br />

7 Section 145(2)(a) allows review to be obtained for misconduct on the part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commissioner; for a gross irregularity in the conduct <strong>of</strong> the arbitration<br />

proceedings; and where the commissioner exceeded his powers. Section 145(2)(b)<br />

provides for review where ‘an award has been improperly obtained’.<br />

8<br />

Rustenburg (n 6 above) para 25, though without detailed analysis <strong>of</strong> the question.<br />

9 1999 3 SA 304 (LAC) (Carephone) paras 15 and 30 et seq.<br />

10 Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa, 1993.<br />

11<br />

Rustenburg (n 6 above) para 24.<br />

12 Rustenburg (n 6 above) para 25.


212 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

Rustenburg was that CCMA commissioners should give some deference<br />

to the employer’s choice <strong>of</strong> sanction. 13<br />

An appeal to the Constitutional Court was unanimously upheld and<br />

the award <strong>of</strong> the commissioner restored. The Court considered two<br />

main issues. On the first it held that a commissioner is not required to<br />

defer to the decision <strong>of</strong> the employer but rather to consider all the<br />

relevant circumstances. 14 On the second issue, the applicability <strong>of</strong><br />

the PAJA, the Court agreed on the result but was divided in its<br />

approach.<br />

Writing for a narrow majority, Navsa AJ held that arbitral<br />

decisions <strong>of</strong> CCMA commissioners were indeed administrative action<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> section 33 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, 15 but that the PAJA was not<br />

applicable to such decisions. In his judgment the LRA had to be<br />

regarded as specialised legislation alongside the PAJA — that is, as<br />

legislation dealing with ‘administrative action’ in the labour sphere. 16<br />

As such, the LRA had to be interpreted in accordance with section<br />

33. 17 Thus section 145 <strong>of</strong> the LRA was suffused with the content <strong>of</strong><br />

section 33, including the constitutional standard <strong>of</strong> reasonableness 18<br />

— just as in Carephone the Labour Appeal Court had found section 145<br />

to be suffused with the former standard <strong>of</strong> justifiability. Applying the<br />

new standard, Navsa AJ found that the commissioner’s decision was a<br />

reasonable one: it was not a decision ‘that a reasonable decisionmaker<br />

could not reach’. 19 Four justices concurred in his judgment. 20<br />

Ngcobo J, who had the support <strong>of</strong> three colleagues, 21 arrived at a<br />

similar conclusion by means <strong>of</strong> different reasoning. In his judgment<br />

CCMA arbitrations were not administrative but judicial action, which<br />

meant that section 33 had no role to play. 22 However, CCMA<br />

commissioners exercised public power and were thus constrained by<br />

other constitutional requirements, including those found in the<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> legality — an aspect <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law — and in sections<br />

23 and 34 <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 23 These constraints all informed the<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> section 145(2)(a) <strong>of</strong> the LRA and considerably<br />

13<br />

14<br />

Rustenburg (n 6 above) para 42 et seq, and see para 48(d).<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) para 79 in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Navsa JA, and see para 161 in the<br />

15<br />

16<br />

17<br />

18<br />

19<br />

judgment <strong>of</strong> Ngcobo J.<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) para 88.<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) para 89.<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) paras 89 and 91.<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) paras 106 and 110.<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) para 119, using the words <strong>of</strong> O’ Regan J in Bato Star Fishing<br />

(Pty) Ltd v Minister <strong>of</strong> Environmental Affairs 2004 4 SA 490 (CC) (Bato Star) para<br />

20<br />

21<br />

22<br />

23<br />

44.<br />

Moseneke DCJ and Madala, O’Regan and Van der Westhuizen JJ.<br />

Mokgoro, Nkabinde and Skweyiya JJ.<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) paras 207-40.<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) para 260.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 213<br />

expanded the three grounds <strong>of</strong> review listed there. 24 Ultimately,<br />

however, the facts did not establish any <strong>of</strong> those grounds <strong>of</strong> review. 25<br />

O’Regan J, who concurred in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Navsa AJ, wrote a<br />

separate judgment in which she responded to Ngcobo J and gave<br />

additional reasons for supporting the view that CCMA arbitrations are<br />

administrative action. 26<br />

Sachs J, too, produced a separate judgment in which he found<br />

himself ‘in the pleasant but awkward position <strong>of</strong> agreeing with<br />

colleagues who disagree with each other’. 27 He saw the judgments <strong>of</strong><br />

Navsa AJ and Ngcobo J as being animated by the same goal — to<br />

determine what standard <strong>of</strong> conduct the Constitution expects <strong>of</strong> a<br />

CCMA commissioner — and as substantially in agreement on the<br />

interests and values involved. 28 The key to the case, as he saw it, was<br />

to make those interests and values explicit. This he proceeded to do,<br />

identifying values such as fair dealing and rationality in sections 23,<br />

33 and 34. His application <strong>of</strong> these standards to the commissioner’s<br />

conduct then led him to the same conclusion as his colleagues.<br />

Of the many points <strong>of</strong> interest raised by Sidumo, I wish to highlight<br />

three features for the attention <strong>of</strong> constitutional lawyers in general<br />

and administrative lawyers in particular.<br />

The first is the slender majority achieved on the ‘administrative<br />

action’ issue — an improvement on the bewildering inconclusiveness<br />

<strong>of</strong> New Clicks, 29 but surely further evidence <strong>of</strong> the intrinsic difficulty<br />

<strong>of</strong> deciding what is and what is not administrative action. That<br />

difficulty exists even when, as here, the Court is relying on the<br />

general conception <strong>of</strong> administrative action developed judicially<br />

under section 33 rather than the more nit-picking definition in the<br />

PAJA. I think the majority gets it right. Navsa AJ reasons convincingly<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> significant differences between a court <strong>of</strong> law and a<br />

tribunal such as the CCMA, including the relative informality <strong>of</strong> its<br />

processes, the absence <strong>of</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> binding precedent and the less<br />

secure tenure <strong>of</strong> its presiding <strong>of</strong>ficers, 30 and O’Regan J adds that ‘it<br />

is entirely consistent with our constitutional order that the<br />

24 Sidumo (n 5 above) paras 256-77, and for the grounds <strong>of</strong> review see n 7 above.<br />

25 Sidumo (n 5 above) para 289.<br />

26<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) paras 122-41.<br />

27 Sidumo (n 5 above) para 146.<br />

28 As above.<br />

29<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Health v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd 2006 2 SA 311 (CC) (New<br />

Clicks), a case concerning pharmaceutical regulations. Two members <strong>of</strong> the Court<br />

found that regulation-making in general amounted to administrative action under<br />

the PAJA, while three others regarded the Act as applicable but on a narrower<br />

basis. Five members found it unnecessary to decide the question, and one found<br />

that subordinate legislation was generally governed by the principle <strong>of</strong> legality<br />

rather than the PAJA.<br />

30 Sidumo (n 5 above) para 85.


214 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

procedures and decisions <strong>of</strong> the CCMA should be lawful, reasonable<br />

and procedurally fair’. 31 But the merits are not my main concern<br />

here. I wish merely to note that Sidumo bears out (yet again) the<br />

Court’s gloomy prognostication in the SARFU case 32 about the difficult<br />

boundaries that would have to be drawn in the administrative action<br />

inquiry.<br />

The second feature is the further development, or complication,<br />

<strong>of</strong> administrative law by the <strong>of</strong>ficial recognition <strong>of</strong> yet another<br />

pathway to review. The pre-democratic era knew only two such<br />

routes: ‘ordinary’ review <strong>of</strong> the decisions <strong>of</strong> public bodies at common<br />

law 33 and the special statutory review jurisdiction created<br />

occasionally by the legislature (<strong>of</strong> which section 145 <strong>of</strong> the LRA was a<br />

prime example). With this second type <strong>of</strong> review the grounds<br />

specified by the legislature, and indeed the remedies available, could<br />

be wider or narrower than those associated with ordinary review. 34<br />

The democratic constitution brought with it a new constitutional<br />

pathway to administrative-law review in the form <strong>of</strong> section 33<br />

(previously section 24 <strong>of</strong> the interim Constitution), duly informed by<br />

the common law; but this third route was reserved for exercises <strong>of</strong><br />

‘administrative action’. A few years later the Constitutional Court<br />

identified a fourth pathway, the principle <strong>of</strong> legality, for the residual<br />

review <strong>of</strong> all those exercises <strong>of</strong> public power that did not qualify as<br />

administrative action, 35 and proceeded to develop the principle so<br />

that it mimics the content <strong>of</strong> section 33 to a considerable extent. 36<br />

Then came the PAJA, the national legislation enacted to give effect<br />

to section 33 and supposedly the default pathway to review 37 — but<br />

one that <strong>of</strong>ten cannot be used because the conduct being reviewed<br />

does not qualify as administrative action in terms <strong>of</strong> the Act’s very<br />

demanding definition. That makes five pathways, as we still have<br />

common-law review (though it is used only for exercises <strong>of</strong> private<br />

power these days) 38 and presumably we still have instances <strong>of</strong> special<br />

statutory review in the traditional sense.<br />

31 Sidumo (n 5 above) para 140.<br />

32<br />

President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa v South African Rugby Football Union<br />

2000 1 SA 1 (CC) (SARFU) para 143.<br />

33 Johannesburg Consolidated Investment Co Ltd v Johannesburg Town Council 1903<br />

TS 111 115.<br />

34 See Nel NO v The Master 2005 1 SA 276 (SCA) para 23 and the discussion by<br />

Froneman J in the court a quo: Nel NO v Master <strong>of</strong> the High Court ECD case no<br />

1633/2001 (undated) 8-9, unreported.<br />

35 Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd v Greater Johannesburg Transitional Metropolitan<br />

Council 1999 1 SA 374 (CC) (Fedsure) paras 56-9.<br />

36<br />

SARFU (n 32 above) and in Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association <strong>of</strong> SA: In re<br />

Ex parte President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa 2000 2 SA 674 (CC)<br />

37<br />

38<br />

(Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association).<br />

Bato Star (n 19 above) para 25.<br />

See C Hoexter Administrative law in South Africa (2007) 119ff.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 215<br />

The majority judgment in Sidumo would seem authoritatively to<br />

have opened up a sixth route: special statutory review under the LRA<br />

for labour-related action that also qualifies as administrative action<br />

under section 33. This, then, is not special statutory review in the<br />

traditional sense — review, wide or narrow, on whatever grounds the<br />

legislature specifies within a particular statutory regime. In this new<br />

type <strong>of</strong> (extra-special?) statutory review the grounds specified in the<br />

LRA are suffused with the content <strong>of</strong> the rights to administrative<br />

justice in section 33, thus as it were achieving full administrative-law<br />

review via labour law. Presumably this will apply to other statutory<br />

regimes too, such as section 131 <strong>of</strong> the Liquor Act 27 <strong>of</strong> 1989 39 and<br />

section 151 <strong>of</strong> the Insolvency Act 24 <strong>of</strong> 1936: whenever the conduct in<br />

question qualifies as administrative action under section 33, the<br />

grounds <strong>of</strong> review in such statutes will also be suffused with the<br />

content <strong>of</strong> section 33.<br />

If this is correct, an interesting situation will arise in relation to<br />

the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Access to Information Act 2 <strong>of</strong> 2000. Decisions taken<br />

by information <strong>of</strong>ficers are specially reviewable under that statute 40<br />

and would almost certainly qualify as administrative action for the<br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> section 33 — but they are expressly excluded from the<br />

more detailed definition <strong>of</strong> administrative action in the PAJA. 41 This<br />

piquant scenario is no doubt further evidence <strong>of</strong> the constitutional<br />

untenability <strong>of</strong> having two different and sometimes incompatible<br />

meanings for ‘administrative action’. 42 (It remains one <strong>of</strong> life’s<br />

mysteries that the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> the PAJA definition has not yet<br />

been challenged in court.)<br />

That brings me to a related point, which is that the approach <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitutional Court has a distinct practical advantage over that<br />

<strong>of</strong> Cameron JA in the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal: it means not having<br />

to engage with the detail <strong>of</strong> the PAJA. In Rustenburg Cameron JA is<br />

faced with conflicting time limits within which review must be sought<br />

— six weeks in terms <strong>of</strong> section 145 <strong>of</strong> the LRA and six months in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the PAJA — and his choice <strong>of</strong> the shorter time limit 43 sits rather<br />

awkwardly with the proposition that the PAJA overrides section 145<br />

<strong>of</strong> the LRA. For Navsa AJ the difficulty does not arise: the PAJA and<br />

section 145 <strong>of</strong> the LRA exist alongside one another as separate and<br />

39 Cf the approach in Bulk Deals Six CC v Chairperson, Western Cape Liquor Board<br />

2002 2 SA 99 (C), where the court applied the grounds in the PAJA to a review<br />

under s 131 <strong>of</strong> the Liquor Act.<br />

40 Secs 78-82.<br />

41<br />

Sec 1(hh).<br />

42 On the various problems arising from the PAJA definition and the disparity<br />

between the two meanings, see C Hoexter ‘“Administrative action” in the courts’<br />

2006 Acta Juridica 303 and Hoexter (n 38 above) 216ff.<br />

43 Rustenburg (n 6 above) para 27.


216 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

equally valid manifestations <strong>of</strong> section 33, and there can thus be no<br />

conflict between them.<br />

The third feature to note about Sidumo is the ethos or vision <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitution that underlies the judgments handed down by the<br />

Constitutional Court. The majority judgment <strong>of</strong> Navsa AJ, in<br />

particular, supports a view <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights as interconnected<br />

and overlapping. Nor is this view merely implicit in the judgment.<br />

There is strong and explicit affirmation <strong>of</strong> it when Navsa AJ is<br />

rejecting an argument that the rights implicated in CCMA arbitrations<br />

are those in sections 23 and 34, and not section 33, <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution:<br />

This submission is based on the misconception that the rights in ss 23, 33<br />

and 34 are necessarily exclusive and have to be dealt with in sealed<br />

compartments. The right to fair labour practices, in the present context,<br />

is consonant with the right to administrative action that is lawful,<br />

reasonable and procedurally fair. Everyone has the right to have these<br />

rights enforced before the CCMA acting as an impartial tribunal. In the<br />

present context, these rights in part overlap and are interconnected. 44<br />

Although Ngcobo J may not share this view <strong>of</strong> things, 45 it is given<br />

particularly strong expression in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Sachs J. He sees the<br />

function <strong>of</strong> the commissioner as a hybrid one, ‘composed <strong>of</strong> an<br />

amalgam <strong>of</strong> three separate but intermingling constitutional rights’ 46<br />

whose underlying values ‘resist compartmentalisation’. 47 The Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights ‘should not always be seen as establishing independent<br />

normative regimes operating in isolation from each other, each with<br />

exclusive sway over a defined realm <strong>of</strong> public and private activity’, 48<br />

and indeed the relationship <strong>of</strong> the various rights should be regarded<br />

as ‘osmotic rather than hermetic’. 49 In this judgment ‘seepage’,<br />

‘permeability’, ‘interpenetration’ and ‘hybridity’ are all desirable<br />

qualities that help ensure the full achievement <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

justice, while an attempt to establish the primacy <strong>of</strong> one right or<br />

another could actually defeat the constitutional objectives to be<br />

realised. 50<br />

To say the least, the constitutional vision outlined here seems to<br />

be absent from the two main judgments in Chirwa. Rather, these<br />

judgments insist on the primacy <strong>of</strong> section 23 and the LRA in a labour<br />

matter, and indeed do their utmost to exclude section 33 and the<br />

PAJA from the picture. It is to Chirwa that I now turn.<br />

44 Sidumo (n 5 above) para 112.<br />

45 There are hints <strong>of</strong> it, however: see eg Sidumo (n 5 above) para 266.<br />

46<br />

Sidumo (n 5 above) para 147.<br />

47 Sidumo (n 5 above) para 149.<br />

48 Sidumo (n 5 above) para 151.<br />

49<br />

As above.<br />

50 Sidumo (n 5 above) paras 151-7.


2 Chirwa<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 217<br />

Ms Chirwa, the appellant, had been dismissed by the Transnet Pension<br />

Fund pursuant to a disciplinary hearing. She alleged procedural<br />

unfairness in the hearing and referred the dispute to the CCMA for<br />

conciliation. When that failed she sought administrative-law review <strong>of</strong><br />

the dismissal in the Witwatersrand Local Division. There, relying on<br />

the common law rather than the PAJA, Brassey AJ set aside the<br />

decision to dismiss Ms Chirwa and ordered her reinstatement. 51 He<br />

followed the reasoning <strong>of</strong> the Appellate Division in Zenzile, 52 holding<br />

that the termination <strong>of</strong> an employment contract in the public sector<br />

is an exercise <strong>of</strong> public power and not (as the respondent argued) a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> pure contract falling beyond the reach <strong>of</strong> administrative<br />

law. Zenzile-type reasoning had indeed become the dominant<br />

approach 53 in such cases, and here I may mention an important and<br />

more recent example <strong>of</strong> it: the judgment <strong>of</strong> Plasket J in POPCRU v<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Correctional Services. 54 But, as evidenced by cases such<br />

as South African Police Union v National Commissioner <strong>of</strong> the South<br />

African Police Service, 55 a contrary approach had begun to gain<br />

momentum — one that challenged the post-1994 status <strong>of</strong> Zenzile and<br />

denied administrative law a role in employment matters.<br />

In Transnet’s appeal against the decision <strong>of</strong> Brassey AJ two main<br />

questions were raised: whether this was a matter over which the High<br />

Court had jurisdiction, and whether the dismissal qualified as<br />

administrative action under the PAJA. 56 Though the Court agreed that<br />

the appeal had to be upheld, its members adopted three quite<br />

different approaches. Cameron JA, Mpati DP concurring, endorsed<br />

both Zenzile and POPCRU. 57 These judges held that this was a case <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative action and that the High Court did have jurisdiction,<br />

concurrently with the Labour Court, to hear it in terms <strong>of</strong> section 157<br />

51 Chirwa v Transnet Ltd WLD case no 03/01052 <strong>of</strong> 4 January 2005, unreported.<br />

52<br />

Zenzile (n 1 above).<br />

53 Before 1994 the approach in Zenzile was applied and extended beyond dismissal<br />

in cases including Administrator, Natal v Sibiya 1992 2 SA 532 (A), Bula v Minister<br />

<strong>of</strong> Education 1992 4 SA 716 (Tk) and Hlongwa v Minister <strong>of</strong> Justice, KwaZulu-<br />

Natal 1993 2 SA 269 (D); and after 1994 it was applied in cases such as Mbayeka v<br />

MEC for Welfare, Eastern Cape 2001 1 All SA 567 (Tk) and Simela v MEC for<br />

Education, Eastern Cape 2001 9 BLLR 1085 (LC).<br />

54 2006 4 BLLR 385 (E) (POPCRU). See also Nxele v Chief Deputy Commissioner,<br />

Corporate Services, Department <strong>of</strong> Correctional Services 2006 10 BLLR 960 (LC)<br />

(Nxele).<br />

55 2005 26 ILJ 2403 (LC) (SAPU). Other examples <strong>of</strong> this approach are Public<br />

Servants’ Association obo Haschke v MEC for Agriculture 2004 25 ILJ 1750 (LC),<br />

Louw v SA Rail Commuter Corporation Ltd 2005 26 ILJ 1960 (W), Western Cape<br />

Workers Association v Minister <strong>of</strong> Labour 2006 1 BLLR 79 (LC) and Hlope v<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security 2006 3 BLLR 297 (LC).<br />

56<br />

Transnet Ltd v Chirwa 2006 27 ILJ 2294 (SCA) (Chirwa SCA).<br />

57 n 54 above.


218 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

<strong>of</strong> the LRA. 58 The relevant parts <strong>of</strong> the provision read as follows:<br />

(1) Subject to the Constitution and section 173, and except where this<br />

Act provides otherwise, the Labour Court has exclusive jurisdiction in<br />

respect <strong>of</strong> all matters that elsewhere in terms <strong>of</strong> this Act or in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

any other law are to be determined by the Labour Court.<br />

(2) The Labour Court has concurrent jurisdiction with the High Court in<br />

respect <strong>of</strong> any alleged or threatened violation <strong>of</strong> any fundamental right<br />

entrenched in Chapter 2 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South<br />

Africa, 1996, arising from –<br />

(a) employment and from labour relations;<br />

(b) any dispute over the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> any executive or<br />

administrative act or conduct, or any threatened executive or<br />

administrative conduct, by the State in its capacity as an employer;<br />

(c) the application <strong>of</strong> any law for the administration <strong>of</strong> which the<br />

Minister is responsible.<br />

Mthiyane and Jafta JJA agreed that the High Court had jurisdiction<br />

concurrently with the Labour Court but held that this was not an<br />

instance <strong>of</strong> administrative action. These judges relied on SAPU 59 and<br />

on Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal authority, Cape Metropolitan Council v<br />

Metro Inspection Services (Western Cape) CC, 60 in holding that the<br />

dismissal was based on contract and so did not satisfy one <strong>of</strong> the most<br />

important elements <strong>of</strong> the PAJA definition: it was not an exercise <strong>of</strong><br />

public power. 61<br />

Conradie JA was prepared to accept that the dismissal amounted<br />

to administrative action but held that the High Court did not have<br />

jurisdiction over what was quintessentially a labour matter. The<br />

legislature, he reasoned, had set its face against labour matters being<br />

litigated in other courts. 62 Thus, even if Chirwa had a cause <strong>of</strong> action<br />

under the PAJA she was required to pursue it under the LRA in the<br />

Labour Court. 63<br />

The two issues were aired again on further appeal to the<br />

Constitutional Court. 64 Skweyiya J gave judgment for the majority<br />

with the concurrence <strong>of</strong> seven justices. 65 Essentially he supported the<br />

line taken by Conradie JA, and held that the High Court did not have<br />

58 Chirwa SCA (n 56 above) paras 57-65. Similar reasoning was subsequently adopted<br />

by the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal in Old Mutual Life Assurance Co SA Ltd v Gumbi<br />

2007 5 SA 552 (SCA) (Gumbi) and Boxer Superstores Mthatha v Mbenya 2007 5 SA<br />

450 (SCA).<br />

59<br />

n 55 above.<br />

60 2001 3 SA 1013 (SCA) (Cape Metropolitan).<br />

61 Chirwa SCA (n 56 above) para 15.<br />

62<br />

Chirwa SCA (n 56 above) para 32.<br />

63 Chirwa SCA (n 56 above) para 33.<br />

64 Chirwa (n 3 above).<br />

65<br />

Moseneke DCJ, Navsa AJ and Madala, Ngcobo, Nkabinde, Sachs and Van der<br />

Westhuizen JJ.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 219<br />

jurisdiction. The appellant should therefore have followed to its end<br />

the route laid down by the LRA for resolving her dispute. Ngcobo J<br />

produced a separate concurring judgment which dealt in addition<br />

with the ‘administrative action’ issue and was supported by six<br />

justices. 66 Langa CJ dissented with the support <strong>of</strong> Mokgoro and<br />

O’Regan JJ.<br />

2.1 Jurisdiction<br />

The majority conclusion that the Labour Court had exclusive<br />

jurisdiction in the matter was evidently inspired by considerations <strong>of</strong><br />

policy, and by the legislature’s failure to heed various calls for the<br />

amendment <strong>of</strong> section 157. Both Skweyiya and Ngcobo JJ reasoned<br />

that employees ought not to be in a preferential position merely by<br />

virtue <strong>of</strong> their employment in the public sector. Public and private<br />

employees ought rather to be treated equally, and parity was indeed<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the main aims <strong>of</strong> the current labour regime. 67 That regime<br />

included a ‘one-stop shop’, 68 a specialised and purpose-built system<br />

for resolving labour disputes, which should be pursued to its end. 69<br />

Furthermore, to allow the High Court concurrent jurisdiction with the<br />

Labour Court in employment matters would be to encourage forumshopping<br />

and the development <strong>of</strong> a dual 70 and possibly less coherent 71<br />

system <strong>of</strong> law. In the light <strong>of</strong> these considerations, Ncgobo J thought<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> the word concurrent in section 157(2) was ‘unfortunate’. 72<br />

The problem, however, is that policy arguments cannot alter the<br />

express terms <strong>of</strong> section 157 <strong>of</strong> the LRA — however unfortunate those<br />

terms may seem. Leaving aside for a moment the cogency <strong>of</strong> the<br />

arguments, the majority’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> the provision is in conflict<br />

not only with the wording <strong>of</strong> section 157 but also with the Court’s own<br />

previous interpretation <strong>of</strong> that wording in Fredericks & Others v MEC<br />

for Education and Training, Eastern Cape, & Others. 73<br />

In Fredericks, teachers who had been refused voluntary<br />

retrenchment sought review <strong>of</strong> this action in a High Court, alleging a<br />

violation <strong>of</strong> their constitutional rights to equality and just<br />

administrative action. White J found that his Court had no jurisdiction<br />

66<br />

Moseneke DCJ, Navsa AJ and Madala, Nkabinde, Sachs and Van der Westhuizen JJ.<br />

67 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 66 (Skweyiya J) and paras 99-102 and 149 (Ncgobo J).<br />

68 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 47 (Skweyiya J).<br />

69<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) paras 65-7 (Skweyiya J), and see paras 105, 110-13 and 117-20<br />

(Ngcobo J).<br />

70 Chirwa (n 3 above) paras 65 (Skweyiya J) and 121, 124 (Ngcobo J).<br />

71<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 118 (Ngcobo J).<br />

72 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 121.<br />

73 2002 2 SA 693 (CC) (Fredericks). See also Fedlife Assurance Ltd v Wolfaardt 2002<br />

1 SA 49 (SCA); United Public Servants Association <strong>of</strong> South Africa v Digomo NO<br />

2005 26 ILJ 1957 (SCA).


220 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

in the matter. He saw it in essence as a labour case that had to be<br />

dealt with under section 24 <strong>of</strong> the LRA, a provision that envisages the<br />

involvement <strong>of</strong> the CCMA. On appeal, however, a unanimous<br />

Constitutional Court corrected this misapprehension. O’Regan J<br />

pointed out that section 157(2) is the sole source <strong>of</strong> the Labour<br />

Court’s jurisdiction to determine disputes arising from the alleged<br />

infringement <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights, and that it clearly gives the<br />

Labour Court and the High Court concurrent jurisdiction over such<br />

matters. 74 She emphasised that the LRA gives the Labour Court no<br />

general jurisdiction over labour matters, so that the High Court’s<br />

jurisdiction is not ousted by the mere fact that something happens to<br />

be a labour matter. 75 Nor could section 158(2)(h) be read with section<br />

157(1) <strong>of</strong> the LRA to oust the High Court’s jurisdiction, since section<br />

158(1)(h) ‘does not expressly confer on the Labour Court<br />

constitutional jurisdiction to determine disputes arising out <strong>of</strong> alleged<br />

infringements <strong>of</strong> the Constitution by the state acting as an<br />

employer’. 76 O’Regan J also made it clear that in terms <strong>of</strong> section 169<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitution, such ousting <strong>of</strong> the High Court’s jurisdiction is<br />

permissible only where the matter is assigned to a court <strong>of</strong> similar<br />

status — which the CCMA clearly is not. 77<br />

In Chirwa, notwithstanding the way the matter was framed and<br />

the many detailed references to the PAJA in the papers, Skweyiya J<br />

chose to fix on the appellant’s brief reference to provisions in the LRA<br />

(evidently included for the purpose <strong>of</strong> establishing grounds <strong>of</strong> review<br />

in the PAJA). 78 He held that this was a dispute envisaged by section<br />

191 <strong>of</strong> the LRA, which provides a procedure for the resolution <strong>of</strong><br />

disputes about unfair dismissals. It was thus a matter that ‘must,<br />

under the LRA, be determined exclusively by the Labour Court’. 79<br />

While Fredericks clearly stood in the way <strong>of</strong> such an interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

section 157, Skweyiya J distinguished it on the basis that there had<br />

been no reliance in the earlier case on section 23 or on the LRA. 80<br />

That, with respect, seems an unconvincing point <strong>of</strong> distinction.<br />

After all, Fredericks was so obviously a ‘labour’ matter that the High<br />

Court believed it lacked jurisdiction to hear it — despite the<br />

applicants’ own characterisation <strong>of</strong> the case as one relating to<br />

sections 9 and 33 <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. Conversely, what about the<br />

inconvenient fact that the appellant in Chirwa evidently abandoned<br />

74<br />

75<br />

76<br />

Fredericks (n 73 above) para 41.<br />

Fredericks (n 73 above) paras 38 and 40.<br />

Fredericks (n 73 above) para 43. Section 158(1)(h) allows the Labour Court to<br />

review ‘any decision taken or any act performed by the State in its capacity as<br />

77<br />

78<br />

79<br />

80<br />

employer on such grounds as are permissible in law’.<br />

Fredericks (n 73 above) paras 29-31.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 157 in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 63.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 58.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 221<br />

her initial reliance on section 23 and the LRA 81 and deliberately<br />

framed her case as one in administrative law? 82<br />

As Nugent JA has remarked, it is difficult to find a ‘clear legal —<br />

as opposed to policy — reason for the outcome in Chirwa’. 83 The<br />

majority was apparently bent on characterising the case purely as a<br />

labour matter whatever the cost. It thus depicted the appellant’s High<br />

Court application as an instance <strong>of</strong> asking an ordinary court to decide<br />

a specialist dispute. 84 Langa CJ bluntly described this manoeuvre as a<br />

mischaracterisation, 85 for in truth Ms Chirwa was ‘asking a High Court<br />

to consider an administrative law issue’. 86 Langa CJ pointed out that<br />

in most cases unfair dismissal claims are decided not by the Labour<br />

Court but by the CCMA, so that in terms <strong>of</strong> section 169 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution exclusive jurisdiction could not lawfully be conferred on<br />

the Labour Court in any event. 87 The Chief Justice also indicated the<br />

irrelevance <strong>of</strong> the various policy considerations to the issue <strong>of</strong><br />

jurisdiction, which in this instance was a matter <strong>of</strong> legislative choice.<br />

Ultimately, as he said, ‘[w]hile we may question that intention and<br />

may have preferred a legislative scheme that more neatly divided<br />

responsibilities between the various courts, that is not the path the<br />

legislature has chosen.’ 88<br />

Skweyiya J seems indeed to have been aware <strong>of</strong> this, and not<br />

entirely convinced by his own strained interpretation <strong>of</strong> section 157.<br />

Otherwise it is hard to see why he ends his judgment by underscoring<br />

the ‘urgent need for the legislature to revisit the provisions <strong>of</strong> s 157(2)<br />

<strong>of</strong> the LRA’ 89 — for his account <strong>of</strong> the provision suggests no such need.<br />

At any rate, wishful thinking cannot change the fact that in<br />

practice labour law and administrative law are not neatly divided, and<br />

that in many cases they do overlap. I doubt that neatness will ever be<br />

achieved at this intersection, legislatively or otherwise, for it seems<br />

to me that some untidiness is both natural and unavoidable. Nor, I<br />

think, should neatness be regarded as a particularly worthy aim in this<br />

81 Chirwa (n 3 above); see para 67 in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Skweyiya J and paras 84-5 in<br />

82<br />

83<br />

the judgment <strong>of</strong> Ngcobo J.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above); see paras 157-9 in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ.<br />

In a separate concurring judgment in Makambi v MEC for Education, Eastern Cape<br />

84<br />

85<br />

86<br />

2008 5 SA 449 (SCA) (Makambi) para 21.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 61 (Skweyiya J) and paras 124-5 (Ngcobo J).<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 159.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 173. Not only was the claim couched in the language <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative law, but it was ‘based squarely on the PAJA’. Chirwa (n 3 above)<br />

87<br />

para 157.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 170. Furthermore, s 157(5) <strong>of</strong> the LRA states: ‘Except as<br />

provided for in section 158(2), the Labour Court does not have jurisdiction to<br />

adjudicate an unresolved dispute if this Act requires the dispute to be resolved<br />

88<br />

89<br />

through arbitration.’<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 174.<br />

Chirwa (n 3 above) para 71.


222 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

area <strong>of</strong> the law. Both <strong>of</strong> these propositions find some support in the<br />

facts and reasoning applied in a post-Chirwa case, Nakin v MEC,<br />

Department <strong>of</strong> Education, Eastern Cape & Another. 90<br />

The applicant in Nakin was a school principal who had been<br />

transferred to a lower-level post through no fault <strong>of</strong> his own. This<br />

injustice was <strong>of</strong>ficially rectified several years later when the<br />

department agreed to reinstate him and to correct the accumulated<br />

shortfall in salary and benefits. The department neglected to effect<br />

the correction, however, and the applicant approached a High Court<br />

for an order compelling it to do so in terms <strong>of</strong> the PAJA. In argument<br />

the respondents challenged the Court’s jurisdiction to deal with what<br />

they saw as an unfair labour practice within the meaning <strong>of</strong> section<br />

186(2) <strong>of</strong> the LRA. But Froneman J upheld the High Court’s jurisdiction<br />

to determine the case as one <strong>of</strong> unlawful administrative action. 91<br />

Fredericks, which had not been overruled in Chirwa, was still good<br />

law, all the more so in a matter not involving dismissal. 92<br />

The facts <strong>of</strong> Nakin nicely illustrate the natural overlap just<br />

referred to. More importantly, however, Froneman J challenges the<br />

policy behind the tidy-minded majority view in Chirwa. In relation to<br />

the concerns about forum-shopping and the growth <strong>of</strong> parallel systems<br />

<strong>of</strong> law, he points out that the coherence <strong>of</strong> labour jurisprudence<br />

depends on its giving proper expression to section 23 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution rather than its development in a single forum. 93<br />

Froneman J goes on to show that in practice, labour law has gained<br />

and not lost from administrative-law insights — an example being the<br />

recent development <strong>of</strong> the common-law contract <strong>of</strong> employment so<br />

as to include a right to a pre-dismissal hearing. 94 His judgment also<br />

suggests that the policy <strong>of</strong> equality may be a misdirected one.<br />

Froneman J points out that in public employment fairness ‘may<br />

conceivably have a different content to that in the private sector, for<br />

reasons relating to constitutional demands <strong>of</strong> responsiveness, public<br />

accountability, democracy and efficiency in the public service’. 95<br />

This is a point <strong>of</strong> fundamental importance. Public and private<br />

employers are not the same, for under our Constitution they are not<br />

under the same public duties. To put it simply, employers in the<br />

private sector have the luxury (to the extent that they are not<br />

90<br />

91<br />

92<br />

2008 6 SA 320 (Ck) (Nakin).<br />

Nakin (n 90 above) para 39.<br />

Nakin (n 90 above); see paras 27-39. Cf Makambi (n 83 above) para 17, where<br />

Farlam JA found it was ‘not possible to hold that this case falls on the Fredericks<br />

93<br />

94<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the line <strong>of</strong> distinction drawn in the Chirwa case’.<br />

Nakin (n 90 above) para 30.<br />

Nakin (n 90 above) para 30, with reference to Gumbi (n 58 above); and see also<br />

95<br />

paras 31 et seq.<br />

Nakin (n 90 above) para 34.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 223<br />

thwarted by regulation) <strong>of</strong> acting out <strong>of</strong> pure self-interest. Organs <strong>of</strong><br />

state do not have the same freedom, for they are generally<br />

constrained by their duty to act in the public interest — even when<br />

there is no legislation explicitly saying so. 96 Thus, while the aim <strong>of</strong><br />

achieving equality between all employees certainly appeals to one’s<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> justice, it may not be an attainable ideal under our present<br />

constitutional dispensation; not, at any rate, if one conceives <strong>of</strong> that<br />

equality as a matter <strong>of</strong> paring down the rights <strong>of</strong> public-sector<br />

employees to match those <strong>of</strong> other employees.<br />

That does not, however, rule out the possibility <strong>of</strong> equalising up<br />

rather than down by allowing the insights <strong>of</strong> administrative law (or<br />

some <strong>of</strong> them) 97 to benefit employees more generally. To borrow the<br />

words <strong>of</strong> Froneman J, ‘the substantive coherence and development <strong>of</strong><br />

employment law can only gain’ from administrative law. 98 While such<br />

reform would optimally be achieved by methodical legislative means,<br />

one must not underestimate the potential <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution. As I have suggested elsewhere, section 39(2) may be<br />

regarded as constitutional authority for the courts to set public-law<br />

standards for ‘private administrators’ to follow, especially in<br />

relationships characterised by inequality (as the employment<br />

relationship tends to be) or where coercive power is being<br />

exercised. 99<br />

2.2 Administrative action<br />

Though the Court in Chirwa agreed that the dismissal was not an<br />

instance <strong>of</strong> administrative action, its members displayed three<br />

different approaches to the issue. As I suggest in what follows, none<br />

<strong>of</strong> these approaches is unproblematic.<br />

Skweyiya J found that it was unnecessary to decide the<br />

administrative action question since the case could be resolved on the<br />

jurisdictional issue (though he indicated his agreement, obiter, with<br />

the judgment <strong>of</strong> Ngcobo J on the administrative action diagnosis). 100<br />

96<br />

97<br />

98<br />

This most basic principle <strong>of</strong> administrative law was expressed by Schreiner JA in<br />

his dissenting judgment in Mustapha v Receiver <strong>of</strong> Revenue, Lichtenburg 1958 3<br />

SA 343 (A) at 347E-G — a judgment vindicated by the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal in<br />

Logbro Properties CC v Bedderson NO 2003 1 SA 460 (SCA) (Logbro) para 13. It is<br />

in fact unusual for enabling legislation to specify that action has to be taken ‘in<br />

the public interest’, but an example appears in Nxele supra note 54 para 59.<br />

The requirements implied by ‘reasonable’ and ‘procedurally fair’ administrative<br />

action could certainly be extended in this way, but imposing the various<br />

requirements <strong>of</strong> ‘lawfulness’ on private employers would make less sense.<br />

Nakin (n 90 above) para 34.<br />

99 Hoexter (n 38 above) 124. Unlike the direct horizontal application <strong>of</strong> rights under<br />

s 8(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, indirect application under s 39(2) does not depend on<br />

the ‘nature’ <strong>of</strong> the right sought to be applied.<br />

100 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 73.


224 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

This approach is clearly mistaken, however. As the Chief Justice<br />

pointed out, the administrative action inquiry could not legitimately<br />

be avoided: it was indeed the ‘primary question’ 101 in the case, for<br />

the Court’s jurisdiction depended on whether the dismissal was ‘an<br />

administrative act or conduct ... by the State in its capacity as an<br />

employer’ for the purposes <strong>of</strong> section 157 <strong>of</strong> the LRA.<br />

Ngcobo J did not seek to avoid the inquiry. Relying on the section<br />

33 meaning <strong>of</strong> administrative action, he found (rightly, I believe) that<br />

the dismissal clearly amounted to an exercise <strong>of</strong> public power. 102<br />

However, it lacked one <strong>of</strong> the hallmarks <strong>of</strong> administrative action<br />

listed in the SARFU case: 103 it did not involve the implementation <strong>of</strong><br />

legislation but had rather been effected in terms <strong>of</strong> the contract<br />

between the parties. 104 Ngcobo J thus treated a single factor as<br />

decisive in a manner arguably not contemplated by the Court in<br />

SARFU. But the real issue for him seems to have been that the<br />

dismissal was ‘more concerned with labour and employment<br />

relations’ than with administration, 105 and he went on to emphasise<br />

the formal division in the Constitution between labour relations and<br />

administrative conduct. 106<br />

By contrast, Langa CJ relied on the definition <strong>of</strong> administrative<br />

action in the PAJA, which covers decisions made by an organ <strong>of</strong> state<br />

when ‘exercising a public power or performing a public function in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> any legislation’. 107 He, too, held that in the absence <strong>of</strong> any<br />

particular statutory authority the dismissal had taken place in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the contract itself; 108 but unlike Ngcobo J, he went on to find that<br />

the dismissal was not an exercise <strong>of</strong> public power. In this regard Langa<br />

CJ noted the absence <strong>of</strong> features that tend to point to the existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> a public power: any imbalance in the employment relationship was<br />

not attributable to the respondent’s status as a public body; the<br />

dismissal had little or no impact on the public; and the source <strong>of</strong> the<br />

power to dismiss was contractual. 109 Furthermore, he could see none<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘strengthening factors’ that had been present in the POPCRU<br />

case. 110 The Transnet Pension Fund did not have the same obviously<br />

public character as the Department <strong>of</strong> Correctional Services, the<br />

respondent in POPCRU; unlike that department it pursued no<br />

obviously public goals; and, unlike in POPCRU, the public interest in<br />

101 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 154.<br />

102 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 138, quoting with approval from the judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

Cameron JA in the court below.<br />

103 n 32, para 143.<br />

104 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 142.<br />

105 As above.<br />

106 Chirwa (n 3 above) paras 143 et seq.<br />

107 Section 1 <strong>of</strong> the PAJA, my emphasis.<br />

108 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 185.<br />

109 Chirwa (n 3 above) paras 186-94.<br />

110 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 192, referring to POPCRU (n 54 above) para 54.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 225<br />

the administration <strong>of</strong> the Transnet Pension Fund was not preeminent.<br />

111<br />

The different approaches <strong>of</strong> Ngcobo J and Langa CJ illustrate,<br />

once again, the problem <strong>of</strong> having two meanings for ‘administrative<br />

action’. Given that reality, however, Langa CJ is surely correct to rely<br />

on the PAJA definition. This approach accords with the constitutional<br />

principle that general norms should be resorted to only when norms<br />

<strong>of</strong> greater specificity have run out, 112 or when testing the<br />

constitutionality <strong>of</strong> a specific norm (the PAJA or other original<br />

legislation) against the more general norm (section 33). 113<br />

Ngcobo J, who has preferred the section 33 meaning in other cases<br />

too, 114 does so on the basis that ‘PAJA only comes into the picture<br />

once it is determined that the conduct in question constitutes<br />

administrative action within the meaning <strong>of</strong> section 33.’ 115 This<br />

approach is rather cumbersome as it calls for two separate inquiries:<br />

Is the conduct administrative action for the purposes <strong>of</strong> s 33? If so,<br />

does the PAJA definition nevertheless exclude it? (Stopping at the first<br />

inquiry would <strong>of</strong> course make the PAJA definition completely<br />

redundant.) 116 More importantly, this approach seems to be<br />

inconsistent with the principle mentioned above and with the<br />

Constitutional Court’s jurisprudence on the subject <strong>of</strong> constitutionally<br />

mandated legislation. As the statute giving effect to the rights in<br />

section 33, the PAJA should be resorted to directly — a point that has<br />

indeed been stressed by Ngcobo J himself. 117 Even if it does not have<br />

the effect <strong>of</strong> bypassing the PAJA altogether, the mediation through<br />

section 33 he insists on seems quite unwarranted. It means, too, that<br />

in this instance we are deprived <strong>of</strong> his views on the application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

various elements <strong>of</strong> the PAJA definition.<br />

As to the merits <strong>of</strong> the ‘administrative action’ diagnosis in Chirwa,<br />

it depended largely on a curiosity. Like appointment, dismissal in the<br />

public sector is almost always governed by statute. It certainly was in<br />

Zenzile, where ‘the element <strong>of</strong> public service injected by statute’ 118<br />

played a considerable part in the reasoning <strong>of</strong> Hoexter JA. A quirk <strong>of</strong><br />

111 As above.<br />

112 See I Currie & J de Waal The bill <strong>of</strong> rights handbook (5 ed 2005) 13.<br />

113 See Hoexter (n 38 above) 115.<br />

114 See eg New Clicks (n 29 above) para 446.<br />

115 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 139.<br />

116 Construing the PAJA consistently with s 33 is constitutionally appropriate (as<br />

indicated by Nugent JA in Grey’s Marine Hout Bay (Pty) Ltd v Minister <strong>of</strong> Public<br />

Works 2005 6 SA 313 (SCA) para 22), but it is quite another thing to behave as if<br />

the statute and its detailed definition <strong>of</strong> administrative action did not exist. See<br />

further Hoexter (n 42 above) and I Currie ‘What difference does the Promotion <strong>of</strong><br />

Administrative Justice Act make to administrative law?’ 2006 Acta Juridica 325.<br />

117 See eg New Clicks (n 29 above) para 436, and in relation to s 23 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution see eg Sidumo (n 5 above) paras 248-9.<br />

118 n 1 above, 34C.


226 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

the Chirwa case was the absence <strong>of</strong> governing legislation after the<br />

repeal <strong>of</strong> the South African Transport Services Conditions <strong>of</strong> Service<br />

Act 41 <strong>of</strong> 1988. Technically, then, the dismissal really did seem to be<br />

a purely contractual matter in this instance — if not in others. 119<br />

But the judgment <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ (and that <strong>of</strong> Mthiyane JA before<br />

him) is nevertheless open to criticism on the contractual issue. As<br />

Stacey has pointed out in a perceptive article, 120 it is difficult to<br />

square with the approach <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court in AAA<br />

Investments (Pty) Ltd v Micro Finance Regulatory Council. 121 There<br />

the Court firmly rejected the idea that a decision loses its public<br />

character simply because the most immediate source <strong>of</strong> the power<br />

happens to be a contract. In that case the contractual element led the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal to regard the Micro Finance Regulatory<br />

Council as ‘a private regulator <strong>of</strong> lenders who choose to submit to its<br />

authority by agreement’ 122 — and was rebuked by the Constitutional<br />

Court for putting form above substance. 123 Is the Chief Justice not<br />

open to the same charge here?<br />

In Transnet Ltd v Chirwa, it is interesting to note, the absence <strong>of</strong><br />

governing legislation does not trouble Cameron JA at all. As he sees it,<br />

Transnet is a public entity created by legislation and operating under<br />

statutory authority. It would not exist without statute. Its every act<br />

derives from its public, statutory character, including the dismissal at<br />

issue here. 124<br />

On this approach public entities can never be on exactly the same<br />

footing as private ones, contract or no contract; and even when there<br />

is a contract, the principles <strong>of</strong> administrative justice (in one form or<br />

another) still frame the contractual relationship. 125 In the<br />

Constitutional Court Ngcobo J supports this line <strong>of</strong> reasoning: 126<br />

In my view, what makes the power in question a public power is the fact<br />

that it has been vested in a public functionary, who is required to<br />

exercise the power in the public interest. When a public <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

performs a function in relation to his or her duties, the public <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

119 Cf for instance SAPU (n 55 above), where the ‘purely contractual’ label is far less<br />

convincing, and see further C Hoexter ‘Contracts in administrative law: Life after<br />

formalism?’ (2004) 121 South African Law Journal 595.<br />

120 R Stacey ‘Administrative law in public-sector employment relationships’ (2008)<br />

125 South African Law Journal 307 315.<br />

121 2006 11 BCLR 1255 (CC) (AAA Investments).<br />

122 Micro Finance Regulatory Council v AAA Investments (Pty) Ltd 2006 2 SA 27 (SCA)<br />

para 24.<br />

123 AAA Investments (n 121 above) para 45.<br />

124 Chirwa SCA (n 56 above) para 52.<br />

125 Cameron JA for a unanimous court in Logbro (n 96 above) para 8, writing an<br />

important gloss on the Cape Metropolitan case (n 60 above)<br />

126 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 138.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 227<br />

exercises public power. I agree with Cameron JA that Transnet is a<br />

creature <strong>of</strong> statute. It is a public entity created by statute and it<br />

operates under statutory authority. As a public authority, its decision to<br />

dismiss necessarily involves the exercise <strong>of</strong> public power, and ‘(t)hat<br />

power is always sourced in statutory provision, whether general or<br />

specific, and, behind it, in the Constitution’.<br />

By contrast, Langa CJ finds that the dismissal is not an exercise <strong>of</strong><br />

public power. In arriving at this conclusion he relies on a number <strong>of</strong><br />

factors that have been used by the courts for determining whether a<br />

power or function is public. However, his paradigm seems to be quite<br />

different from that <strong>of</strong> Cameron JA and Ngcobo J, for in his analysis the<br />

public and intrinsically statutory nature <strong>of</strong> the entity apparently<br />

carries no independent weight. The factors seem to be applied just as<br />

they would be to a completely private entity such as a club or a<br />

business. Because <strong>of</strong> this, and notwithstanding the detailed and<br />

nuanced reasoning <strong>of</strong> the Chief Justice and the cumulative force <strong>of</strong><br />

the various features listed by him, one is left with questions.<br />

Here are some <strong>of</strong> them. Given that Transnet would not exist<br />

without statute, does it really matter that a contract happened to<br />

intervene in this instance? (Langa CJ is clear that where it is achieved<br />

‘in terms <strong>of</strong> a specific legislative provision’ a dismissal may amount to<br />

administrative action.) 127 Given the undoubted public status <strong>of</strong><br />

Transnet, does it really matter that the Transnet Pension Fund is not<br />

as distinctively public as the Department <strong>of</strong> Correctional Services was<br />

in POPCRU, or that it does not pursue its public goals in so obvious a<br />

manner? Given that Transnet is generally supposed to serve the public<br />

interest, does it really matter that this particular dismissal was <strong>of</strong><br />

scant interest to the public or that it had no real impact on the public?<br />

(As Plasket J pointed out in POPCRU, very many actions acknowledged<br />

to be administrative have little or no such impact.) 128 And is it<br />

realistic to say — is it ever entirely realistic to say — that no power<br />

imbalance derived from the employer’s public status?<br />

Similarly, there is something troubling about the Chief Justice’s<br />

statement that ‘[w]hilst Transnet is certainly subservient to the<br />

Constitution, so are all business entities in South Africa’. 129 This fails<br />

to acknowledge that as an organ <strong>of</strong> state Transnet is under special<br />

duties (such as the obligation in section 7(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution) that<br />

simply do not apply to private employers.<br />

In short, I wonder whether an entity like Transnet is ever entirely<br />

free to do as it pleases, and whether it is capable <strong>of</strong> shedding its<br />

127 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 194.<br />

128 n 54 above, para 53.<br />

129 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 192.


228 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

public, statutory nature so conveniently and completely. I doubt that<br />

public entities are capable <strong>of</strong> acting ‘simply in [their] capacity as<br />

employer’, as Mthiyane JA would have it; 130 and with respect, nothing<br />

said in Chirwa eliminates that doubt.<br />

2.3 The interconnectedness <strong>of</strong> rights<br />

In Sidumo, 131 as we have seen, the majority fully acknowledges the<br />

interconnectedness <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights and their natural<br />

tendency to overlap. This view <strong>of</strong> things is also clearly apparent in the<br />

dissenting judgment in Chirwa, in which Langa CJ more than once<br />

recognises the overlap <strong>of</strong> the LRA and the PAJA and their parent<br />

rights. 132 But there is little hint <strong>of</strong> this understanding in the majority<br />

judgments in Chirwa. Instead, emphasis is laid on the entrenchment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the respective rights in two separate provisions in the Constitution,<br />

‘each with its own aims and specialised legislation ... that seeks to<br />

give effect to its own distinct objectives’. 133 While Skweyiya J<br />

concedes that the dismissals <strong>of</strong> public sector employees ‘appear to<br />

implicate’ not only labour rights but also those <strong>of</strong> administrative<br />

justice (or that this ‘is at least what Ms Chirwa is asserting’), 134 and<br />

though he briefly admits a possible overlap <strong>of</strong> the LRA and the<br />

PAJA, 135 he is clear about the ‘pre-eminence <strong>of</strong> the LRA’ in labour<br />

disputes, and about the absence <strong>of</strong> any legislative intention that the<br />

PAJA should detract from it. 136 In short, he refuses to see Chirwa as<br />

a case involving administrative law at all. Ngcobo J achieves this view<br />

<strong>of</strong> the case too, and he does so by relying heavily on the Constitution’s<br />

‘clear distinction between administrative action on the one hand and<br />

employment and labour relations on the other’. 137<br />

This categorical view <strong>of</strong> things is a pity — not just because the<br />

vision <strong>of</strong> the majority is so completely at variance with the ethos <strong>of</strong><br />

Sidumo, but also because it ignores an important constitutional<br />

principle. In POPCRU Plasket J warns against formalistic attempts to<br />

pigeonhole administrative law and labour law, which are after all<br />

mere classifications <strong>of</strong> convenience. 138 Under our Constitution, he<br />

observes,<br />

[t]here is nothing incongruous about individuals having more legal<br />

protection rather than less, or <strong>of</strong> more than one fundamental right<br />

130 Chirwa SCA (n 56 above) para 15.<br />

131 n 5 above.<br />

132 Chirwa (n 3 above) paras 167 and 176.<br />

133 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 46 (Skweyiya J).<br />

134 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 46.<br />

135 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 71.<br />

136 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 50.<br />

137 Chirwa (n 3 above) paras 143-4.<br />

138 n 54 above, para 61.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 229<br />

applying to one act, or <strong>of</strong> more than one branch <strong>of</strong> law applying to the<br />

same set <strong>of</strong> facts. 139<br />

In Transnet Ltd v Chirwa Cameron JA finds in the Constitution ‘no<br />

suggestion that, where more than one right may be in issue, its<br />

beneficiaries should be confined to a single legislatively created<br />

scheme’. 140 In Chirwa the Chief Justice expresses the same principle<br />

in the following way: 141<br />

Both PAJA and the LRA protect important constitutional rights and we<br />

should not presume that one should be protected before another or<br />

presume to determine that the ‘essence’ <strong>of</strong> a claim engages one right<br />

more than another. A litigant is entitled to the full protection <strong>of</strong> both<br />

rights, even when they seem to cover the same ground.<br />

It is unfortunate that the majority is impervious to this wisdom.<br />

3 Masetlha<br />

Masetlha, 142 chronologically the first case in the series, arose out <strong>of</strong><br />

an atypical case <strong>of</strong> ‘executive’ dismissal featuring the President <strong>of</strong><br />

the Republic and the head <strong>of</strong> the National Intelligence Agency (NIA).<br />

The ‘one-stop shop’ <strong>of</strong> the LRA was not open to the appellant in this<br />

case, and nor was the PAJA <strong>of</strong> application; but it is nevertheless a<br />

matter that touches both labour law and administrative law more<br />

broadly. For administrative lawyers its main interest lies in what the<br />

majority judgment says, or fails to say, about procedural fairness.<br />

The facts are widely known. Briefly, in December 2004 the<br />

President appointed the appellant, Mr Billy Masetlha, head and<br />

Director-General <strong>of</strong> the NIA for a period <strong>of</strong> three years. In October<br />

2005 Masetlha was suspended from this position as a result <strong>of</strong> the<br />

‘Macozoma affair’, wherein a prominent businessman was placed<br />

under surveillance and subsequently lodged a complaint about it with<br />

the Minister. The suspension followed an investigation by the<br />

Inspector-General <strong>of</strong> Intelligence, and was challenged by Masetlha in<br />

an application for setting aside. In March 2006, before that had been<br />

decided, the President unilaterally amended Masetlha’s term <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice<br />

so that it expired two days later — thus effectively dismissing him 21<br />

months before his term was due to end. The President’s justification<br />

was that the relationship <strong>of</strong> trust between him and the NIA head had<br />

139 POPCRU (n 54 above) para 60. See further Stacey (n 120 above) 323ff, where he<br />

demonstrates the potentially absurd consequences <strong>of</strong> the proposition that the<br />

remedies <strong>of</strong>fered by one branch <strong>of</strong> the law oust those <strong>of</strong> another.<br />

140 Chirwa SCA (n 56 above) para 65.<br />

141 Chirwa (n 3 above) para 175.<br />

142 n 4 above.


230 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

broken down irreparably. Masetlha was <strong>of</strong>fered his full salary and<br />

benefits for the unexpired period. He declined the <strong>of</strong>fer and sought<br />

review <strong>of</strong> the President’s decisions and reinstatement in his position.<br />

Du Plessis J held for the <strong>Pretoria</strong> High Court that the dispute about<br />

the suspension had been rendered moot by the dismissal, and that the<br />

dismissal itself amounted to lawful executive action. 143 This decision<br />

was upheld on appeal to the Constitutional Court (which did not doubt<br />

that the President’s action amounted to a dismissal). 144 Moseneke<br />

DCJ gave judgment for the majority with the concurrence <strong>of</strong> six<br />

colleagues; 145 Ngcobo J dissented with the support <strong>of</strong> Madala J; and<br />

Sachs J produced a separate judgment.<br />

The first main issue related to lawfulness. Neither the<br />

Constitution nor the relevant legislation mentioned dismissal <strong>of</strong> the<br />

head <strong>of</strong> the NIA but, notwithstanding some disagreement about where<br />

the authority resided, all the justices agreed that the President had<br />

the implied authority to do what he did. 146 More interesting was the<br />

second issue: what constraints there were on the exercise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

power to dismiss, and whether they included a requirement <strong>of</strong><br />

procedural fairness — for the President had acted without giving the<br />

appellant notice or a hearing on the issue <strong>of</strong> his dismissal. 147<br />

The usual constraints were soon ruled out. They clearly did not<br />

include the LRA, since it does not apply to members <strong>of</strong> the NIA. 148 The<br />

majority did not pause to consider whether the appellant still had the<br />

benefit <strong>of</strong> the section 23 right to fair labour practices — which was the<br />

solution favoured by Sachs J in his separate judgment — and so there<br />

was no hint here <strong>of</strong> the Chirwa insistence on the primacy <strong>of</strong> labour law<br />

in a case <strong>of</strong> dismissal. In fact administrative law ultimately came to<br />

the rescue, though not in the form <strong>of</strong> the PAJA. The latter did not<br />

apply either: the dismissal was an exercise <strong>of</strong> executive powers that<br />

are specifically excluded from the definition <strong>of</strong> administrative action<br />

in the PAJA (and would not count as administrative action for the<br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> section 33). 149 As for the common-law right to a predismissal<br />

hearing recognised by the Appellate Division in Zenzile, 150<br />

the majority reasoned that this case was distinguishable from the<br />

143 See Masetlha (n 4 above) paras 22-4 in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Moseneke DCJ.<br />

144 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 52.<br />

145 Langa CJ, Navsa AJ and Nkabinde, O’Regan, Skweyiya and Van der Westhuizen JJ.<br />

146 The majority found that the necessary power lay in s 209(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

and s 3(3) <strong>of</strong> the Intelligence Services Act 65 <strong>of</strong> 2002 (see Masetlha n 4 above,<br />

para 73), whereas Ngcobo J found that provisions <strong>of</strong> the Public Service Act 103 <strong>of</strong><br />

1994 were equally relevant (Masetlha n 4 above, para 157).<br />

147 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 84, and see para 197 in the judgment <strong>of</strong> Ngcobo J.<br />

148 See s 2(b) <strong>of</strong> the LRA.<br />

149 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 76n39, though Moseneke DCJ does not deal fully with<br />

the s 33 meaning.<br />

150 n 1 above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 231<br />

earlier one: it concerned a ‘special legal relationship’ between the<br />

President and the head <strong>of</strong> the NIA, and the dismissal involved the<br />

exercise <strong>of</strong> an executive power deriving from the Constitution and<br />

national legislation. 151 In the view <strong>of</strong> the majority the dismissal<br />

attracted only the grounds <strong>of</strong> review implied by that residual pathway<br />

to administrative-law review, the principle <strong>of</strong> legality. 152<br />

As already noted, the content <strong>of</strong> the principle has been developed<br />

considerably over the years: it has been held to imply that those who<br />

wield public power must act lawfully 153 and in good faith, 154 must not<br />

misconstrue their power, 155 and must act rationally in relation to the<br />

purpose for which the power was given. 156 These requirements<br />

effectively cover many <strong>of</strong> the grounds <strong>of</strong> review in ‘regular’<br />

administrative law (the PAJA), and they explain why the rule <strong>of</strong> law<br />

in general, and the principle <strong>of</strong> legality in particular, have been<br />

described as ‘administrative law applied under another name’. 157 But<br />

while procedural fairness may be a standard component <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong><br />

law, 158 the narrower principle <strong>of</strong> legality has not yet been held to<br />

require such fairness. In Masetlha the majority showed no inclination<br />

to change the position. Moseneke DCJ observed that powers to<br />

appoint and dismiss this type <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial were conferred specially on<br />

the President for the effective business <strong>of</strong> government and the pursuit<br />

<strong>of</strong> national security, and he concluded that ‘it would not be<br />

appropriate to constrain executive powers to requirements <strong>of</strong><br />

procedural fairness’. 159<br />

When one considers how well established the audi alteram<br />

partem principle is in our law generally, and how well established it<br />

is in the context <strong>of</strong> dismissal (at least in administrative law), 160 the<br />

majority’s conclusion seems sadly retrogressive. First, in what way<br />

would national security or effective government be jeopardised by<br />

requiring the President to hear the appellant? Secondly, as Ngcobo J<br />

indicates in his dissenting judgment, it seems inconceivable that the<br />

content <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law should be less today than it was under the<br />

151 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 75.<br />

152 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 81, where it is referred to as ‘the principle <strong>of</strong> legality<br />

and rationality’.<br />

153 Fedsure (n 35 above) paras 56-9.<br />

154 The SARFU case (n 32 above) para 148.<br />

155 As above.<br />

156 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association (n 36 above) para 85.<br />

157 C Plasket ‘The fundamental right to just administrative action: Judicial review <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative action in the democratic South Africa’ unpublished doctoral thesis,<br />

Rhodes <strong>University</strong>, 2002 164.<br />

158 See C Hoexter ‘The principle <strong>of</strong> legality in South African administrative law’<br />

(2004) 4 Macquarie Law Journal 165.<br />

159 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 77; and see also para 78.<br />

160 See the cases cited in n 53 above.


232 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

old regime. 161 In Zenzile, a judgment handed down during the<br />

apartheid era, the lowliest employees, temporary hospital workers,<br />

were held to have the right to be heard before being dismissed. Now,<br />

in the democratic era — under a constitution committed to<br />

accountability, responsiveness and openness 162 — a member <strong>of</strong> the<br />

public service 163 is held to have no entitlement at all to procedural<br />

fairness. The majority apparently made nothing <strong>of</strong> the differences<br />

between this appointment and ‘purely political appointees’ such as<br />

Cabinet Ministers; 164 though I remain unconvinced that under our<br />

Constitution it is justifiable to dismiss anyone, however political their<br />

appointment, without the benefit <strong>of</strong> a hearing.<br />

In his dissenting judgment Ngcobo J held that the rule <strong>of</strong> law<br />

required the appellant to be heard before being dismissed. He linked<br />

this procedural requirement to the existing substantive requirement<br />

<strong>of</strong> rationality, pointing out that fairness provides insurance against<br />

irrationality or arbitrariness — it ensures that the decision-maker has<br />

all the facts before making a decision. 165 Ngcobo J also reminded us<br />

<strong>of</strong> the importance <strong>of</strong> the audi principle by quoting from the Court’s<br />

own judgment in Zondi v MEC for Traditional and Local Government<br />

Affairs: 166<br />

A hearing can convert a case that was considered to be open and shut to<br />

be open to some doubt, and a case that was considered to be<br />

inexplicable to be fully explained.<br />

It was not necessary for Ngcobo J to point out that if the President had<br />

acted fairly before dismissing the appellant, misunderstandings<br />

between them might conceivably have been cleared up. 167<br />

Judicial disagreement about the content <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> law is not<br />

all there was to the case, however. Moseneke DCJ went on to say that<br />

if procedural fairness were indeed a requirement, it had been<br />

satisfied in this instance. The appellant had had ‘ample occasion’ 168<br />

to respond to the allegations made against him in relation to the<br />

Macozoma affair: he had had at least two meetings with the Minister<br />

at which he was called upon to explain the surveillance and his role in<br />

161 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 188.<br />

162 Section 1 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.<br />

163 See Masetlha (n 4 above) para 37.<br />

164 Masetlha (n 4 above) paras 288-9, where Sachs J records the differences:<br />

Ministers ‘know they are hired and can be fired at the will <strong>of</strong> the President; and if<br />

fired, they can mobilise politically’, whereas the head <strong>of</strong> the NIA has ‘one foot in<br />

government and one in the public administration’ and has no equivalent political<br />

remedies.<br />

165 Masetlha (n 4 above) paras 184-7.<br />

166 2005 3 SA 589 (CC) para 112, quoted in para 204 <strong>of</strong> his dissenting judgment.<br />

167 Whether they would have been is <strong>of</strong> course immaterial: see Masetlha (n 4 above)<br />

para 204.<br />

168 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 83.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 233<br />

it, and he had made submissions to the Inspector-General’s<br />

investigation. There had also been a meeting with the President at<br />

which the appellant had expressed his dissatisfaction with the<br />

Inspector-General’s findings and the recommendation that<br />

disciplinary action should be taken against him. So,<br />

[a]lthough the President did not ask the applicant for his views at the<br />

point <strong>of</strong> dismissing him, he had the benefit <strong>of</strong> the views <strong>of</strong> the applicant<br />

on all material issues that led to the dismissal. 169<br />

With respect, this reasoning gives cause for concern. To say that there<br />

is no right to procedural fairness at all in this unique executive setting<br />

is one thing. It is quite another to say that if there was such a right,<br />

it was satisfied in the circumstances. The potential effect is to dilute<br />

the content <strong>of</strong> the audi alteram partem principle in relation to<br />

dismissal — which is just where it deserves to be applied rigorously.<br />

As Ngcobo J points out in his dissenting judgment, fairness surely<br />

demands that any person being dismissed be heard on the proposed<br />

dismissal itself. 170 It is certainly not enough, at least not in<br />

administrative law, for one party to have had the benefit <strong>of</strong> the other<br />

party’s views in general. The essence <strong>of</strong> a fair hearing is that the<br />

person adversely affected has a chance to comment specifically on<br />

the proposed adverse action. 171 It is a pity, then, that the majority<br />

did not make it clearer that this was an exception to the general<br />

principles <strong>of</strong> procedural fairness, and it is to be hoped that its<br />

proposition does not infect those general principles.<br />

The judgment <strong>of</strong> Sachs J, too, is worrying in this regard. While he<br />

found that the appellant was entitled to be treated fairly under<br />

section 23 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution and took a broad view <strong>of</strong> what<br />

substantive fairness demanded, Sachs J seemed to take a strangely<br />

constrained view <strong>of</strong> what procedural fairness required in the<br />

circumstances. In his judgment the President ought to have consulted<br />

the appellant on the manner in which the termination was to be<br />

publicly communicated; 172 but, in the absence <strong>of</strong> a charge <strong>of</strong><br />

misconduct or other form <strong>of</strong> breach, Sachs J apparently saw no need<br />

for a hearing on the dismissal itself. 173 This seems a somewhat<br />

formalistic approach, too, since misconduct was surely implied: the<br />

Court apparently accepted that the breakdown <strong>of</strong> trust between the<br />

parties was a direct result <strong>of</strong> the appellant’s conduct in the Macozoma<br />

affair — for which the Inspector-General had recommended<br />

disciplinary action against him.<br />

169 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 84.<br />

170 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 205.<br />

171 As to the common law, see L Baxter Administrative law (1984) 546; and more<br />

generally, see Hoexter (n 38 above) 332ff.<br />

172 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 236.<br />

173 Masetlha (n 4 above) para 234.


234 Clearing the intersection? Administrative law and labour law in the CC<br />

4 Conclusion<br />

The cases <strong>of</strong> Masetlha, Sidumo and Chirwa presented the<br />

Constitutional Court with opportunities to pronounce on the<br />

intersection <strong>of</strong> labour law and administrative law in employment<br />

matters, and to expound on the relationship between the<br />

constitutional rights concerned and their associated pieces <strong>of</strong><br />

legislation. As I have tried to show in this article, the judgments <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court are full <strong>of</strong> interest. Sidumo in particular develops<br />

the connection between the relevant rights in a creative manner,<br />

while Chirwa raises fundamental questions about the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

administrative action and the nature <strong>of</strong> public power.<br />

But the judgments <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court in these cases also<br />

leave one with a sense <strong>of</strong> wasted opportunity. Masetlha seems a<br />

retrogressive decision, at least to an administrative lawyer, for<br />

allowing an unfortunate exception to the established principles <strong>of</strong><br />

procedural fairness. And Sidumo and Chirwa appear to be far apart in<br />

the constitutional vision or ethos expressed by the majority in each<br />

case, for the former encourages the interconnectedness <strong>of</strong> rights<br />

while the latter disavows it. As I have argued above, Chirwa is<br />

unsatisfying in other respects as well: none <strong>of</strong> the Court’s approaches<br />

to the ‘administrative action’ issue is unproblematic, and the<br />

majority’s reasoning on the question <strong>of</strong> jurisdiction is not only<br />

unconvincing but also contradicts the Court’s own jurisprudence. The<br />

decision in this case certainly clears up the intersection between<br />

labour law and administrative law, but the cost <strong>of</strong> that tidiness may<br />

be thought unacceptably high.


SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT IN PRACTICE: FUEL<br />

RETAILERS ASSOCIATION OF SOUTHERN AFRICA V<br />

DIRECTOR-GENERAL ENVIRONMENTAL<br />

MANAGEMENT, DEPARTMENT OF AGRICULTURE,<br />

CONSERVATION AND ENVIRONMENT,<br />

MPUMALANGA PROVINCE<br />

1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

* Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Department <strong>of</strong> Public Law, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong>.<br />

1<br />

2007 6 SA 4 (CC) (Fuel Retailers).<br />

2 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 109.<br />

3 The so-called filling station or fuel related cases include All the Best Trading CC<br />

t/a Parkville Motors, and Others v S N Nayagar Property Development and<br />

Construction CC and Others 2005 3 SA 396 (TPD); BP Southern Africa (Pty) Ltd v<br />

MEC for Agriculture, Conservation, Environment and Land Affairs 2004 5 SA 124<br />

(W); Capital Park Motors CC and Fuel Retailers Association <strong>of</strong> SA (Pty) Ltd v Shell<br />

SA Marketing (Pty) Ltd unreported, case no 3016/05, 18 March 2005 (TPD); Sasol<br />

Oil (Pty) Ltd & another v Metcalf 2004 5 SA 161 (W); and MEC for Agriculture,<br />

Conservation, Environment and Land Affairs, Gauteng v Sasol Oil and Another<br />

(368/2004) (2005) SCA 76.<br />

235<br />

Loretta Feris*<br />

In the opening salvo <strong>of</strong> his dissenting judgment in Fuel Retailers 1<br />

Justice Sachs notes the irony behind the fact that the first<br />

environmental rights case before the Constitutional Court came from<br />

‘an organised section <strong>of</strong> an industry frequently lambasted both for<br />

establishing world-wide reliance on non-renewable energy sources<br />

and for spawning pollution’. 2 However, this fact does not come as a<br />

total surprise. The fuel sector and filling stations in particular have<br />

been involved in several cases concerning environmental matters. In<br />

some <strong>of</strong> these cases the issue <strong>of</strong> sustainable development, which is<br />

guaranteed in the South African environmental right, has taken centre<br />

stage. 3 As a result, even before Fuel Retailers, we have seen the<br />

emergence <strong>of</strong> a South African jurisprudence on sustainable<br />

development. Fuel Retailers distinguishes itself by having made it all<br />

the way to the Constitutional Court and so having provided an<br />

opportunity for this court to express itself on this matter.


236 Sustainable development in practice<br />

However, it has to be made clear that this case is not primarily<br />

about section 24, the environmental right 4 <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. It does<br />

not focus on the substance and normative content <strong>of</strong> the right.<br />

Rather, the cause <strong>of</strong> action lies in administrative law and governance<br />

and it is through this prism that one <strong>of</strong> the concepts central to section<br />

24, ‘sustainable development’, is explored, analysed and evaluated.<br />

Much <strong>of</strong> the case is in fact devoted to sustainable development and<br />

Ngcobo J, writing on behalf <strong>of</strong> the majority, spent a significant part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the judgment exploring the development <strong>of</strong> the concept in<br />

international law, its application in South African law and finally its<br />

import and consequence for the matter at hand. In addition, Sachs J<br />

in his dissent provides a contrary, and to my mind a more conceptually<br />

sound analysis <strong>of</strong> sustainable development.<br />

As a result <strong>of</strong> the majority’s expansive overview <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development and Sach’s cogent construction there<strong>of</strong>, the case<br />

contributes significantly to the conceptualisation <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development in environmental law, a process that is by its very nature<br />

ongoing. It underscores and buttresses the development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

concept through earlier case law and as such stimulates the debate on<br />

how exactly we should apply sustainable development.<br />

In this note I view Fuel Retailers through the lens <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development and explore the way in which the Constitutional Court<br />

has approached the concept. I refrain from engaging in a<br />

comprehensive analysis <strong>of</strong> the historical development <strong>of</strong> the concept<br />

or an in-depth analysis <strong>of</strong> the normative content there<strong>of</strong>. I do,<br />

however, consider one <strong>of</strong> the core elements <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development — integration, an element that took centre stage in Fuel<br />

Retailers and is at the heart <strong>of</strong> sustainable development decisionmaking.<br />

In particular, I investigate the value choices inherent in<br />

sustainable development decision-making and consider the failure <strong>of</strong><br />

the Court to interrogate the practical and normative application <strong>of</strong><br />

integration thoroughly. I furthermore assess the dissenting judgement<br />

<strong>of</strong> Sachs J and conclude that his interpretation provides some<br />

guidance on how to interpret instruments such as legislation and<br />

policy that require sustainable development.<br />

4<br />

Section 24 reads: ‘Everyone has the right —<br />

(a) to an environment that is not harmful to their health or well-being; and<br />

(b) to have the environment protected, for the benefit <strong>of</strong> present and future<br />

generations, through reasonable legislative and other measures that —<br />

(i) prevent pollution and ecological degradation<br />

(ii) promote conservation; and<br />

(iii) secure ecologically sustainable development and use <strong>of</strong> natural resources<br />

while promoting justifiable economic and social development.’


2 The facts<br />

(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 237<br />

The applicants in this matter objected to an authorisation that was<br />

granted by the Mpumalanga provincial environmental authorities for<br />

the establishment <strong>of</strong> a filling station in White River in Mpumalanga.<br />

The filling station was to be established in an area that was already<br />

the site <strong>of</strong> six filling stations within a five kilometre radius. An<br />

environmental impact assessment (EIA) was submitted to the<br />

Mpumalanga Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture, Conservation and Environment<br />

(DACE) in terms <strong>of</strong> GN R1182 <strong>of</strong> 1997 5 issued under the<br />

Environment Conservation Act (ECA). 6 A record <strong>of</strong> decision (ROD) was<br />

signed on 9 January 2002 for the installation <strong>of</strong> three tanks for petrol<br />

and diesel, the erection <strong>of</strong> a convenience store, and ablution<br />

facilities. The ROD was issued on the basis <strong>of</strong> a scoping report, a<br />

geotechnical report and a geohydrological report.<br />

The scoping report dealt with the potential impact <strong>of</strong> noise, visual<br />

factors and traffic and the effect on municipal services, safety and<br />

crime, and cultural and historical sites; as well as the feasibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proposed station. However, it did not address the potential economic<br />

impact on other filling stations in the area. With regard to<br />

environmental impacts it found that no plant or animal species were<br />

threatened. The geotechnical report suggested, however, that a<br />

subterranean aquifer would need protection from pollution and<br />

recommended that — if required by the Department <strong>of</strong> Water Affairs<br />

and Forestry (DWAF) — an impermeable base layer should be installed<br />

to prevent contamination, and that water quality be tested biannually.<br />

7<br />

Fuel Retailers lodged an appeal to the MEC <strong>of</strong> DACE on the basis,<br />

inter alia, that the need, desirability and sustainability <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proposed filling station had not been considered and that the<br />

geophysical report regarding prevention <strong>of</strong> fuel leaks and possible<br />

contamination <strong>of</strong> the aquifer is inadequate. The appeal was<br />

considered and dismissed. In response, the Director argued that need,<br />

desirability and sustainability need not be considered, as these<br />

factors had been considered by the local authority when it had earlier<br />

approved the rezoning <strong>of</strong> the area from ‘special’ to ‘Business 1’, 8<br />

5 GG 18261 <strong>of</strong> 5 September 1997.<br />

6 Act 73 <strong>of</strong> 1989. In terms <strong>of</strong> sec 22(1) read with sec 21(1) no activity which may<br />

have a substantial detrimental impact on the environment may be undertaken<br />

without written authorisation from the competent authority. In terms <strong>of</strong> sec 22(2)<br />

such authorisation may only be granted ‘after consideration <strong>of</strong> reports concerning<br />

the impact <strong>of</strong> the proposed activity and <strong>of</strong> alternative proposed activities on the<br />

environment’; and after the furnishing <strong>of</strong> a report concerning the impact <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proposed development on the environment.<br />

7<br />

At no point did DWAF require any preventive measures.<br />

8 As required by the relevant Ordinance 15 <strong>of</strong> 1986, which governs rezoning.


238 Sustainable development in practice<br />

which allowed for the construction <strong>of</strong> a filling station at the identified<br />

site.<br />

The applicants unsuccessfully applied to the High Court 9 and to<br />

the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal 10 to set aside the ROD in terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ECA, the common law and the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Administrative Justice<br />

Act. 11 The applicants’ arguments were based on a number <strong>of</strong> issues,<br />

but on application for leave to appeal to the Constitutional Court,<br />

only one issue was pursued, namely that the environmental<br />

authorities failed to consider the socio-economic impact <strong>of</strong><br />

constructing the proposed filling station. The applicants argued that<br />

this obligation is wider than the assessment <strong>of</strong> need and desirability<br />

considered in the rezoning process and that it required DACE to<br />

assess, amongst other things, the cumulative impact on the<br />

environment produced by the proposed filling station and all existing<br />

filling stations in close proximity to the proposed one. In sum, the<br />

proper analysis required an assessment <strong>of</strong> demand or necessity and<br />

desirability, not the feasibility, <strong>of</strong> the proposed station and its impact<br />

on the sustainability <strong>of</strong> existing filling stations. In support, the<br />

applicant relied upon the provisions <strong>of</strong> section 24(b)(iii) 12 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution, as well as sections 2(4)(a), 2(3), 2(4)(g), 2(4)(i), and 23<br />

<strong>of</strong> NEMA. 13<br />

9 2005 JDR 0915 (T).<br />

10<br />

2007 2 SA 163 (SCA).<br />

11 Act 3 <strong>of</strong> 2000.<br />

12 It provides: ‘Everyone has the right ... to have the environment protected, for<br />

the benefit <strong>of</strong> present and future generations, through reasonable legislative and<br />

other measures that ... secure ecologically sustainable development and use <strong>of</strong><br />

natural resources while promoting justifiable economic and social development’.<br />

13<br />

2(4)(a): Sustainable development requires the consideration <strong>of</strong> all relevant<br />

factors including the following:<br />

(i) That the disturbance <strong>of</strong> ecosystems and loss <strong>of</strong> biological diversity are<br />

avoided, or, where they cannot be altogether avoided, are minimised and<br />

remedied;<br />

(ii) that pollution and degradation <strong>of</strong> the environment are avoided, or, where<br />

they cannot be altogether avoided, are minimised and remedied;<br />

(iii) that the disturbance <strong>of</strong> landscapes and sites that constitute the nation's<br />

cultural heritage is avoided, or where it cannot be altogether avoided, is<br />

minimised and remedied;<br />

(iv) that waste is avoided, or where it cannot be altogether avoided,<br />

minimised and re-used or recycled where possible and otherwise disposed <strong>of</strong> in<br />

a responsible manner;<br />

(v) that the use and exploitation <strong>of</strong> non-renewable natural resources is<br />

responsible and equitable, and takes into account the consequences <strong>of</strong> the<br />

depletion <strong>of</strong> the resource;<br />

(vi) that the development, use and exploitation <strong>of</strong> renewable resources and<br />

the ecosystems <strong>of</strong> which they are part do not exceed the level beyond which<br />

their integrity is jeopardised;<br />

(vii) that a risk-averse and cautious approach is applied, which takes into<br />

account the limits <strong>of</strong> current knowledge about the consequences <strong>of</strong> decisions<br />

and actions; and<br />

(viii)that negative impacts on the environment and on people's environmental<br />

rights be anticipated and prevented, and where they cannot be altogether<br />

prevented, are minimised and remedied.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 239<br />

The environmental authorities accepted that the socio-economic<br />

impact <strong>of</strong> the proposed filling station had to be considered, but<br />

argued that they were not required to consider need, desirability and<br />

sustainability <strong>of</strong> the proposed filling station as it was taken into<br />

account by the local authority during the rezoning <strong>of</strong> the property and<br />

that ‘rezoning forms part and parcel <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> an application<br />

for authorisation in terms <strong>of</strong> section 22 <strong>of</strong> ECA’. 14 The applicant, in<br />

turn, argued that the two processes are distinct and separate. The<br />

local authority considers a rezoning application from a town-planning<br />

perspective and focuses on what land uses it would allow, whilst the<br />

environmental authorities are required to consider the impacts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proposed development on the environment and on socio-economic<br />

conditions. 15 The applicant also noted that the rezoning had taken<br />

place approximately eight years prior to the approval <strong>of</strong> the<br />

application for authorisation in terms <strong>of</strong> the ECA and that significant<br />

environmental changes had occurred in the area since then. 16<br />

13 2(3): Development must be socially, environmentally and economically<br />

sustainable.<br />

2(4)(g): Decisions must take into account the interests, needs and values <strong>of</strong> all<br />

interested and affected parties, and this includes recognising all forms <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge, including traditional and ordinary knowledge.<br />

2(4)(i): The social, economic and environmental impacts <strong>of</strong> activities,<br />

including disadvantages and benefits, must be considered, assessed and<br />

evaluated, and decisions must be appropriate in the light <strong>of</strong> such<br />

consideration and assessment.<br />

23: The purpose <strong>of</strong> this Chapter is to promote the application <strong>of</strong> appropriate<br />

environmental management tools in order to ensure the integrated<br />

environmental management <strong>of</strong> activities.<br />

(2) The general objective <strong>of</strong> integrated environmental management is to —<br />

(a) promote the integration <strong>of</strong> the principles <strong>of</strong> environmental management<br />

set out in section 2 into the making <strong>of</strong> all decisions which may have a<br />

significant effect on the environment;<br />

(b) identify, predict and evaluate the actual and potential impact on the<br />

environment, socio-economic conditions and cultural heritage, the risks and<br />

consequences and alternatives and options for mitigation <strong>of</strong> activities, with a<br />

view to minimising negative impacts, maximising benefits, and promoting<br />

compliance with the principles <strong>of</strong> environmental management set out in<br />

section 2;<br />

(c) ensure that the effects <strong>of</strong> activities on the environment receive adequate<br />

consideration before actions are taken in connection with them;<br />

(d) ensure adequate and appropriate opportunity for public participation in<br />

decisions that may affect the environment;<br />

(e) ensure the consideration <strong>of</strong> environmental attributes in management and<br />

decision-making which may have a significant effect on the environment; and<br />

(f) identify and employ the modes <strong>of</strong> environmental management best suited<br />

to ensuring that a particular activity is pursued in accordance with the<br />

principles <strong>of</strong> environmental management set out in section 2.<br />

(3) The Director-General must coordinate the activities <strong>of</strong> organs <strong>of</strong> state<br />

referred to in section 24(1) and assist them in giving effect to the objectives<br />

<strong>of</strong> this section and such assistance may include training, the publication <strong>of</strong><br />

manuals and guidelines and the co-ordination <strong>of</strong> procedures.<br />

14 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 31.<br />

15<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 32.<br />

16 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 33.


240 Sustainable development in practice<br />

3 The judgment<br />

The cause <strong>of</strong> action for judicial review centred on whether or not the<br />

environmental authorities had failed to take into consideration<br />

matters that they were required to consider before granting the<br />

authorisation under section 22(1) <strong>of</strong> the ECA. 17 Ngcobo J framed the<br />

issue as one that concerns the ‘nature and scope <strong>of</strong> the obligations <strong>of</strong><br />

environmental authorities when they make decisions that may have a<br />

substantial detrimental impact on the environment’; and, in<br />

particular, ‘the interaction between social and economic<br />

development and the protection <strong>of</strong> the environment’. 18 It is this<br />

latter aspect — that is, the interaction between social and economic<br />

development and environmental protection — that provides the<br />

impetus for the lengthy interrogation <strong>of</strong> sustainable development by<br />

the court. 19<br />

3.1 Sustainable development<br />

Ngcobo J’s departure point is the inherent challenge that gave rise to<br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> sustainable development: namely that the promotion<br />

<strong>of</strong> development requires protection <strong>of</strong> the environment, whilst the<br />

environment cannot be protected if development does not pay<br />

attention to the costs <strong>of</strong> environmental destruction.<br />

This challenge has long been recognised and the Court details how<br />

this challenge gave rise internationally to the development <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development and it traces this development to important<br />

events such as the Brundtland Report, 20 the 1972 United Nations<br />

Conference on the Human Environment or so-called ‘Stockholm<br />

Conference’ 21 (which stressed the relationship between development<br />

and the protection <strong>of</strong> the environment), the 1992 United Nations<br />

Conference on Environment and Development or so-called ‘Rio<br />

Conference’ (which generated principles on sustainable development<br />

and provided a framework for the development <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development) 22 and, finally, the 2002 Johannesburg<br />

17 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 39.<br />

18 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 1.<br />

19<br />

In Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 40 Ngcobo J confirms that in light <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dictates <strong>of</strong> sec 24 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, the case does, indeed, raise a<br />

constitutional issue. What is disconcerting though is the way in which he frames<br />

sec 24. He states that sec 24 ‘guarantees to everyone the right to a healthy<br />

environment’. This is a positive framing <strong>of</strong> the right, whilst the right is in fact<br />

negatively framed, thus lessening the impact and extent <strong>of</strong> the right. One can<br />

only hope that this careless use <strong>of</strong> language was a mere oversight on the side <strong>of</strong><br />

the Court.<br />

20 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 44.<br />

21<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 46.<br />

22 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 49-50.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 241<br />

World Summit on Sustainable Development (WSSD) which, according<br />

to the Court ‘reaffirm[ed] that sustainable development is a world<br />

priority’. 23<br />

In delineating the concept the Court refers to the Brundtland<br />

Commission’s definition <strong>of</strong> sustainable development as ‘development<br />

that meets the needs <strong>of</strong> the present without compromising the ability<br />

<strong>of</strong> future generations to meet their own needs,’ 24 but noted that<br />

recent commentators have refrained from defining sustainable<br />

development and have instead chosen to identify ‘the evolving<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> sustainable development’. These include:<br />

the integration <strong>of</strong> environmental protection and economic development<br />

(the principle <strong>of</strong> integration); sustainable utilisation <strong>of</strong> natural resources<br />

(the principle <strong>of</strong> sustainable use and exploitation <strong>of</strong> natural resources);<br />

the right to development; the pursuit <strong>of</strong> equity in the use and allocation<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural resources (the principle <strong>of</strong> intra-generational equity); the<br />

need to preserve natural resources for the benefit <strong>of</strong> present and future<br />

generations (the principle <strong>of</strong> inter-generational and intra-generational<br />

equity); and the need to interpret and apply rules <strong>of</strong> international law in<br />

an integrated systematic manner. 25<br />

In highlighting the first principle — that <strong>of</strong> integration as fundamental<br />

to the concept <strong>of</strong> sustainable development — the Court notes that the<br />

formal application there<strong>of</strong> ‘requires the collection and dissemination<br />

<strong>of</strong> environmental information, and the conduct <strong>of</strong> environmental<br />

impact assessments’ and argues that the ‘practical significance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

integration <strong>of</strong> the environmental and developmental considerations is<br />

that environmental considerations will now increasingly be a feature<br />

<strong>of</strong> economic and development policy’. 26<br />

With regard to South African law, the Court is <strong>of</strong> the opinion that<br />

sustainable development <strong>of</strong>fers a principle for the resolution <strong>of</strong><br />

tensions between ‘the need to protect the environment on the one<br />

hand, and the need for socio-economic development on the other<br />

hand’. The concept thus, according to the Court, provides a<br />

framework for reconciling socio-economic development and<br />

environmental protection. 27 Ngcobo J states: ‘sustainable<br />

development does not require the cessation <strong>of</strong> socio-economic<br />

development but seeks to regulate the manner in which it takes<br />

place’. 28 According to the Court the National Environmental<br />

Management Act (NEMA), which was enacted to give effect to section<br />

23 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 46.<br />

24<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 47.<br />

25 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 51.<br />

26 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 52 (references omitted).<br />

27<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 57.<br />

28 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 58.


242 Sustainable development in practice<br />

24 <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, defines sustainable development as being the<br />

‘integration <strong>of</strong> social, economic and environmental factors into<br />

planning, implementation and decision-making for the benefit <strong>of</strong><br />

present and future generations’. 29 Ngcobo J argues that ‘whenever a<br />

development which may have a significant impact on the environment<br />

is planned, it envisages that there will always be a need to weigh<br />

considerations <strong>of</strong> development’, with these considerations being<br />

‘underpinned by the right to socio-economic development’, against<br />

‘environmental considerations, as underpinned by the right to<br />

environmental protection. In this sense it contemplates that<br />

environmental decisions will achieve a balance between environmental<br />

and socio-economic developmental considerations through<br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> sustainable development’. 30<br />

3.2 Sustainable development and the EIA process<br />

The Court argues that the<br />

nature and scope <strong>of</strong> the obligation to consider the impact <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proposed development on socio-economic conditions must be<br />

determined in the light <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> sustainable development and<br />

the principle <strong>of</strong> integration <strong>of</strong> socio-economic development and the<br />

protection <strong>of</strong> the environment. 31<br />

If this relationship is accepted, so Ngcobo J argues, it follows that<br />

socio-economic conditions have an impact on the environment. He<br />

illustrates this point by stating that the proposed filling station may<br />

have implications for the job security <strong>of</strong> existing filling stations, but<br />

may equally have environmental consequences, such as that if<br />

existing stations close down that will require rehabilitation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

environment after closure. 32<br />

He furthermore cautions that the proliferation <strong>of</strong> filling stations<br />

close to each other may increase the likelihood <strong>of</strong> adverse impacts on<br />

the environment. In this respect the Court reminds us that NEMA<br />

‘requires that the cumulative impact <strong>of</strong> a proposed development,<br />

together with the existing developments on the environment, socioeconomic<br />

conditions and cultural heritage must be assessed’. As such<br />

‘a consideration <strong>of</strong> socio-economic conditions ... includes the<br />

consideration <strong>of</strong> the impact <strong>of</strong> the proposed development not only in<br />

29 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 59. The reference indicated is sec 1(1)(xxix). It<br />

should be noted, however, that this section does not exist and this ‘definition’ is<br />

30<br />

31<br />

32<br />

in fact from the preamble to NEMA.<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 61.<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 71.<br />

As above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 243<br />

combination with the existing developments, but also its impact on<br />

existing ones’. 33<br />

With respect to the EIA process, the Court notes that NEMA<br />

requires the consideration, assessment and evaluation <strong>of</strong> the social,<br />

economic and environmental impact <strong>of</strong> proposed activities and this<br />

‘enjoins the environmental authorities to consider and assess the<br />

impact <strong>of</strong> a proposed activity on existing socio-economic conditions,<br />

which must <strong>of</strong> necessity include existing developments’. 34 The Court<br />

explains that the objective <strong>of</strong> this exercise is not to stamp out<br />

competition or protect existing developments at the expense <strong>of</strong><br />

future developments. Rather it requires a risk-averse and cautious<br />

approach when decisions are made. 35 It concludes that what was<br />

demanded <strong>of</strong> the environmental authorities was to consider ‘the<br />

impact on the environment <strong>of</strong> the proliferation <strong>of</strong> filling stations as<br />

well as the impact <strong>of</strong> the proposed filling station on existing ones’, an<br />

obligation which is ‘wider than the requirement to assess need and<br />

desirability under the Ordinance’. 36<br />

It was common cause that this assessment never happened. The<br />

Court, however, contends that this duty fell on environmental<br />

authorities because the two organs <strong>of</strong> state have different roles and<br />

functions. Local authorities have a town planning role and as such a<br />

proposed development may satisfy the need and desirability criteria<br />

from a town-planning perspective, given that the local authority is not<br />

required to consider the social, economic and environmental impact<br />

<strong>of</strong> a proposed development. Environmental authorities, however, are<br />

required to do so by the provisions <strong>of</strong> NEMA. 37 The assumption that<br />

the duty under the Ordinance to consider need and desirability<br />

imposed the same obligation as is required by the duty under NEMA to<br />

consider the social, economic and environmental impacts <strong>of</strong> a<br />

proposed development, is therefore wrong. 38<br />

The Court, as a result sets aside the decision <strong>of</strong> the environmental<br />

authorities on a number <strong>of</strong> bases:<br />

(i) They misconstrued the nature <strong>of</strong> their obligations under NEMA and<br />

consequently failed to apply their minds to the socio-economic impacts<br />

<strong>of</strong> the proposed filling station in the instant case. 39<br />

33 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 72. See also para 74.<br />

34 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 77.<br />

35<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) paras 78-81.<br />

36 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 82.<br />

37 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 85.<br />

38<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 86.<br />

39 As above.


244 Sustainable development in practice<br />

(ii) They left the consideration <strong>of</strong> need and desirability to the local<br />

authority and consequently failed to properly discharge <strong>of</strong> their<br />

statutory duty. 40<br />

(iii) They failed to take into account socio-economic conditions as<br />

required by NEMA and as such they did not comply with a mandatory and<br />

material condition set by NEMA. 41<br />

(iv) Given the lack <strong>of</strong> consideration to the social and economic impact <strong>of</strong><br />

the proposed filling station, including its cumulative impact on the<br />

environment, the environmental authorities failed to apply their minds<br />

to the matter. 42<br />

4 Discussion<br />

4.1 Sustainable development through the cases<br />

As mentioned above Fuel Retailers focuses on the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development and more specifically how it is to be<br />

interpreted, contextualised and applied in South African law. The<br />

Court thoroughly interrogated the concept’s history and status in<br />

international law and concluded that it is now an established concept<br />

in international law. With regard to South African law the concept is<br />

still in its infancy. 43 A number <strong>of</strong> cases have, however, addressed<br />

sustainable development and over the last four years a South African<br />

jurisprudence has begun to see the light.<br />

The first case to explore this concept was one very similar to Fuel<br />

Retailers: Sasol Oil (Pty) Ltd & another v Metcalf. 44 The applicants<br />

40 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) paras 87-88.<br />

41<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 89.<br />

42 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 90–97. The Court emphasises the fact that the<br />

rezoning decision by the local authorities, on which the environmental authorities<br />

relied, had probably occurred in 1995, some eight years prior to the decision by<br />

the environmental authorities. This was done prior to the coming into effect <strong>of</strong><br />

NEMA and it argues that it was necessary for the environmental authorities to<br />

consider the matter afresh in the light <strong>of</strong> the provisions <strong>of</strong> NEMA, given that a<br />

significant change in the environment could have taken place in the intervening<br />

period.<br />

43<br />

Note, however, that as early as 1971 our neighbouring (then) Rhodesian court<br />

recognised that the principle <strong>of</strong> inter-generational equity can have the effect <strong>of</strong><br />

limiting other rights, such as property rights. Thus in King v Dykes 1971 3 SA 540<br />

(RA) 545G-H MacDonald ACJ stated: ‘The idea which prevailed in the past that<br />

ownership <strong>of</strong> land conferred the right on the owner to use his land as he pleased<br />

is rapidly giving way in the modern world to the more responsible conception that<br />

an owner must not use his land in a way which may prejudice his neighbours or<br />

the community in which he lives, and that he holds his land in trust for future<br />

generations. Legislation dealing with such matters as town and country planning,<br />

the conservation <strong>of</strong> natural resources, and the prevention <strong>of</strong> pollution, and<br />

regulations designed to ensure that proper farming practices are followed, all<br />

bear eloquent testimony <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> this more civilised and enlightened<br />

attitude towards the rights conferred by ownership <strong>of</strong> land.’<br />

44 Sasol (n 3 above).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 245<br />

sought the respondent’s, the Gauteng Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture,<br />

Conservation, Environment and Land Affairs’, authorisation in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> section 22 <strong>of</strong> the ECA for the construction <strong>of</strong> a filling station and<br />

convenience store. This authorisation was refused and in its refusal<br />

GDACE was guided by departmental guidelines that it had developed<br />

to assist in decision-making. The guidelines stipulated that<br />

development must be socially, environmentally and economically<br />

sustainable and required that filling stations in an urban, residential<br />

or built-up area should not be situated within three kilometres <strong>of</strong> an<br />

existing filling station. The applicants thus approached the High Court<br />

for a declaration that certain sections <strong>of</strong> these guidelines issued by<br />

the respondent were ultra vires the ECA and were, therefore, invalid<br />

and unenforceable. They furthermore argued that whilst GDACE had<br />

the power to authorise the construction <strong>of</strong> structures for the storage<br />

and handling <strong>of</strong> hazardous substances at filling stations, this power<br />

did not include the erection <strong>of</strong> filling stations itself. As such the<br />

guidelines did not apply. Finally they argued that even if the power<br />

did include the erection <strong>of</strong> filing stations, GDACE was not entitled to<br />

apply the guidelines as they were predominantly based on socioeconomic<br />

as opposed to environmental considerations. The High Court<br />

dismissed the ultra vires argument, but upheld the applicants’<br />

argument that GDACE did not have the power to require authorisation<br />

for the construction <strong>of</strong> filing stations per se. 45 It furthermore held<br />

that the sustainable development principles contained in section 2 <strong>of</strong><br />

the NEMA did not extend the mandate <strong>of</strong> GDACE to take socioeconomic<br />

(and not just environmental) factors into account. 46<br />

This decision was a set-back for sustainable development<br />

jurisprudence. It ignored the core element <strong>of</strong> integration as part <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development. 47 The Brundtland Report, referred to by<br />

Ngcobo J in Fuel Retailers, contextualises the principle <strong>of</strong> integration<br />

and explains that sustainable development not only prioritises the<br />

needs <strong>of</strong> the poor, but that it also captures the limitations to<br />

development imposed by the present state <strong>of</strong> technology and social<br />

organisation on the environment’s ability to meet present and future<br />

needs. 48 The Report suggests an inherent link between social and<br />

environmental needs and the need for technological advancement<br />

and development. An imbalance amongst these elements, where<br />

global patterns <strong>of</strong> development put the environment under pressure,<br />

places the earth in crisis. This principle <strong>of</strong> integration between three<br />

pillars — environmental protection, economic development and social<br />

45<br />

46<br />

47<br />

Sasol (n 3 above) 170A-E.<br />

Sasol (n 3 above) 171E-172B.<br />

For a more in-depth critique <strong>of</strong> this case see Patterson A ‘Fuelling the sustainable<br />

48<br />

development debate in South Africa’ (2006) 1 South African Law Journal 53.<br />

Report <strong>of</strong> the World Commission on Environment and Development: Our Common<br />

Future (1987).


246 Sustainable development in practice<br />

needs — is thus widely recognised as a core element <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development. 49<br />

This decision was eventually overturned by the SCA. 50 The SCA’s<br />

reversal was, some ways, due to a conflicting judgement by the same<br />

court in yet another filling station case, BP Southern Africa (Pty) Ltd<br />

v MEC for Agriculture, Conservation, Environment and Land Affairs. 51<br />

The applicant in this case sought the review and setting aside <strong>of</strong> a<br />

decision by the Gauteng Provincial Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture,<br />

Conservation, Environment and Land Affairs (GDACE) to refuse its<br />

application in terms <strong>of</strong> section 22(1) <strong>of</strong> the ECA for authorisation to<br />

develop a filling station on one <strong>of</strong> its properties. The Department<br />

based its refusal, inter alia, on environmental concerns. The<br />

applicant contended, however, that its application was refused not<br />

because the new filling station itself posed a danger to the<br />

environment, but rather, because <strong>of</strong> the fact that there were already<br />

two other filling stations within three kilometres <strong>of</strong> applicant's site<br />

and the Department regarded it as unacceptable to allow<br />

proliferation <strong>of</strong> filling stations where existing filling stations were<br />

economically vulnerable to more competition. It argued that under<br />

the guise <strong>of</strong> ‘environmental concerns’, the department was instead<br />

seeking to regulate the economy on the basis <strong>of</strong> what were essentially<br />

economic considerations unrelated to the environment.<br />

The court explored the concept <strong>of</strong> sustainable development in<br />

somewhat more detail than in Sasol and in so doing considered the<br />

wide definition <strong>of</strong> ‘environment’ employed by ECA which defines it in<br />

section 1 as: ‘the aggregate <strong>of</strong> surrounding objects, conditions and<br />

influences that influence the life and habits <strong>of</strong> man or any other<br />

organism or collection <strong>of</strong> organisms’. According to the court the broad<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> ‘environment’ would include all conditions and<br />

influences affecting the life and habits <strong>of</strong> man, which would also<br />

include socio-economic conditions and influences. 52 With reference<br />

to the state’s obligation under section 24(b) with regard to<br />

sustainable development, the Court held that ecologically sustainable<br />

development and the use <strong>of</strong> natural resources must be promoted<br />

jointly with justifiable economic and social development. 53 It stated<br />

that:<br />

49<br />

See for example P Sands Principles <strong>of</strong> international law (2003) 153. See also D<br />

Tladi Sustainable development in international law: An analysis <strong>of</strong> key enviro-<br />

50<br />

economic instruments (2007) 58.<br />

MEC for Agriculture, Conservation, Environment and Land Affairs (Pty) Ltd &<br />

51<br />

52<br />

53<br />

another (n 3 above).<br />

2004 5 SA 124 (W).<br />

BP (n 3 above) 145E.<br />

BP (n 3 above) 143C-D.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 247<br />

... sustainable development constitutes an integral part <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

international law and will balance the competing demands <strong>of</strong><br />

development and environmental protection. The concept <strong>of</strong> ‘sustainable<br />

development’ is the fundamental building block around which<br />

environmental legal norms have been fashioned, both internationally<br />

and in South Africa ... pure economic principles will no longer<br />

determine, in an unbridled fashion, whether a development is<br />

acceptable. Development, which may be regarded as economically and<br />

financially sound, will, in future, be balanced by its environmental<br />

impact, taking coherent cognisance <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> intergenerational<br />

equity and sustainable use <strong>of</strong> resources in order to arrive at<br />

an integrated management <strong>of</strong> the environment, sustainable<br />

development and socio-economic concerns. By elevating the environment<br />

to a fundamental justiciable human right, South Africa has<br />

irreversibly embarked on a road, which will lead to the goal <strong>of</strong> attaining<br />

a protected environment by an integrated approach, which takes into<br />

consideration, inter alia, socio-economic concerns and principles. 54<br />

The court thus concluded that the department was obliged to develop<br />

an integrated environmental management programme, which took<br />

cognisance <strong>of</strong> a wide spectrum <strong>of</strong> considerations, including<br />

international conventions and approaches as a result <strong>of</strong> the broad and<br />

extensive definition <strong>of</strong> ‘environment’ in ECA and the principles <strong>of</strong><br />

NEMA which, inter alia, include the consideration <strong>of</strong> socio-economic<br />

conditions. 55<br />

With the more detailed attention to sustainable development<br />

provided by the Constitutional Court in Fuel Retailers we now have<br />

significant judicial guidance on interpreting and implementing<br />

sustainable development. In essence we now know that sustainable<br />

development is central to the environmental right and to environmental<br />

regulation. We also know that our jurisprudence<br />

acknowledges the inter-connected nature <strong>of</strong> environmental, social<br />

and economic considerations <strong>of</strong> sustainable development and that the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> sustainable development aims (albeit, as argued further<br />

on, mostly unsuccessfully) to serve the purpose <strong>of</strong> facilitating the<br />

achievement <strong>of</strong> this balance. One could, therefore argue, that a<br />

central tenet <strong>of</strong> a ‘South African jurisprudence’ on sustainable<br />

development is the principle <strong>of</strong> integration.<br />

4.2 Sustainable development applied<br />

As noted by Ngcobo J in Fuel Retailers, the overarching definition <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development is the one as espoused by the Brundtland<br />

Report: ‘development which meets the needs <strong>of</strong> the present<br />

54<br />

BP (n 3 above) 144A-144D.<br />

55 BP (n 3 above) 150D-E.


248 Sustainable development in practice<br />

generation without compromising the ability <strong>of</strong> future generations to<br />

meet their own needs’. 56 In attempting to find the practical<br />

application <strong>of</strong> sustainable development it may be helpful to view this<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> the Brundlandt Report as the aim <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development — that is, that which we want to achieve. This aim<br />

operates in acknowledgment <strong>of</strong> the fact that whilst human beings are<br />

driven by their developmental needs to use, exploit and even exhaust<br />

natural resources, this can and may not happen in a limitless way.<br />

Thus, as noted by Field, sustainable development could be described<br />

as the ‘conceptual vehicle chosen by a diverse range <strong>of</strong> actors to<br />

negotiate the tensions arising from the need for social and economic<br />

development on a planet with finite resources’. 57<br />

This earlier definition has been elaborated upon by more recent<br />

authors through the identification <strong>of</strong> ‘the evolving elements <strong>of</strong> the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> sustainable development’. 58 I would suggest that these<br />

elements can, in turn, be viewed as the ‘means to achieve the aim’.<br />

These means would therefore include: sustainable utilisation <strong>of</strong><br />

natural resources, the pursuit <strong>of</strong> equity in the use and allocation <strong>of</strong><br />

natural resources, and the integration <strong>of</strong> environmental protection<br />

and economic development. 59 These elements attempt to give<br />

concrete existence to a concept that may be viewed as elusive and<br />

impractical, largely because the concept involves competing<br />

considerations or normative tensions.<br />

Out <strong>of</strong> the three elements, the integration principle has been<br />

identified as the key principle. 60 It is also the element that the Court<br />

focused on when it suggested that sustainable development requires<br />

integrating the <strong>of</strong>ten contesting demands <strong>of</strong> economic development,<br />

social development and environmental protection. This element<br />

remains, however, open to criticism. It has been suggested, not<br />

without justification, that its contents remain rather opaque. 61<br />

What, for example does ‘integration’ really mean and how is it<br />

practically achieved? If a waste site is situated close to a residential<br />

area, where that site generates an income not only for the managing<br />

company, but also for the residents that live nearby, should that site<br />

56 Report <strong>of</strong> the World Commission on Environment and Development: Our Common<br />

57<br />

Future (1987) 8.<br />

Field T ‘Sustainable development versus environmentalism: Competing paradigms<br />

58<br />

59<br />

for the South African EIA regime’ (2006) 123 South African Law Journal 409 411.<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 51.<br />

See Sands P Principles <strong>of</strong> international environmental law (2003) 253. Ngcobo<br />

refers to these elements, but also includes a wider range <strong>of</strong> elements (para 51).<br />

These three elements are, however, the most widely recognised elements <strong>of</strong><br />

60<br />

sustainable development.<br />

D Tladi Sustainable development in international law: An analysis <strong>of</strong> key enviro-<br />

61<br />

economic instruments (2007) 58.<br />

Tladi (n 60 above) 75.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 249<br />

be closed down so as accommodate environmental health<br />

considerations? Or should it be allowed to remain open in order to<br />

accommodate social and economic considerations? How does one<br />

integrate, if at all, these three contesting considerations? One could<br />

argue that integration is the ‘happy medium’ where one tightly<br />

regulates the operations <strong>of</strong> the waste site so as to minimise the<br />

exposure <strong>of</strong> the nearby residents, while still ensuring that the site<br />

contribute to the economy and provides a source <strong>of</strong> income for its<br />

workers. In reality this happy medium is a value choice. In this<br />

instance the decision-making is primarily driven by socio-economic<br />

considerations. Requiring strict operating conditions, however, means<br />

that the third pillar, the environment, remains part <strong>of</strong> the overall<br />

decision-making process.<br />

The practical and normative application <strong>of</strong> integration was only<br />

marginally addressed by the Court in Fuel Retailers as the ‘collection<br />

and dissemination <strong>of</strong> environmental information’, the ‘conduct <strong>of</strong><br />

environmental impact assessments’ and the fact that environmental<br />

considerations ‘will now increasingly be a feature <strong>of</strong> economic and<br />

development policy’. 62 While EIAs and policy tools may be useful in<br />

the practical application <strong>of</strong> the integration element <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development, they clearly do not address other forms <strong>of</strong> decisionmaking,<br />

such as decisions regarding activities where no EIAs were<br />

conducted, nor do they explain how these decisions are to be made<br />

even when there is an EIA.<br />

A current burning issue for example is that <strong>of</strong> land restitution and<br />

its relationship vis-à-vis sustainable development. 63 A number <strong>of</strong><br />

current land claims include claims to land that have been declared<br />

protected areas. This includes both private and state-owned land,<br />

including for example claims in the Kruger National Park. In making a<br />

decision on whether to award such claims decision-makers would have<br />

to take into account the possibility that claimants may not utilise the<br />

land for conservation purposes, but rather to engage in other<br />

commercial ventures such as farming. This would clearly promote an<br />

economic and social goal as opposed to an environmental goal.<br />

However, whilst the environmental aim <strong>of</strong> preserving our natural<br />

heritage may weigh very heavy, equally so the would the idea <strong>of</strong><br />

restoring land to people who were unjustly deprived there<strong>of</strong> in the<br />

past.<br />

The judgment also does not address the notion that the<br />

integration principle could be used equally effectively by diverse<br />

62 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 52.<br />

63 For a more detailed discussion see A Du Plessis ‘Land restitution through the lens<br />

<strong>of</strong> environmental law: Some comments on the South African vista’ (2006) 1<br />

Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal 1 1.


250 Sustainable development in practice<br />

groups with conflicting aims, such as environmentalists versus those<br />

pursuing economic development aims. 64 Tladi argues that sustainable<br />

development is inherently a flexible concept, which would have the<br />

effect that for those advocating economic growth, the emphasis<br />

would fall on the economic growth value <strong>of</strong> sustainable development.<br />

As such sustainable development could mean ‘lasting economic<br />

growth’, with the aim being to sustain economic growth. 65 Such an<br />

understanding effectively dilutes and detracts from the original aim<br />

<strong>of</strong> sustainable development. The other two elements, sustainable use<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural resources and equitable utilisation <strong>of</strong> natural resources,<br />

attempt to safeguard the environment against unbridled economic<br />

development.<br />

Decisions motivated by socio-economic considerations can<br />

therefore potentially be disguised as decisions prompted by<br />

environmental concerns. This was, in fact, the argument made by the<br />

applicants in BP, namely that the decision to refuse authorisation for<br />

the proposed activity was motivated not by environmental<br />

considerations, but rather by the socio-economic considerations as<br />

set out in the province’s guidelines on EIAs.<br />

True integration is <strong>of</strong>ten depicted as three circles that intersect<br />

with sustainable development situated in the intersection <strong>of</strong> these<br />

circles as shown in the diagram below.<br />

However, whilst the diagram suggests optimal overlap it is always<br />

possible that reality indicates otherwise and there may be cases<br />

where there is very little overlap and where the greater part is in one<br />

64<br />

As above.<br />

65 As above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 251<br />

<strong>of</strong> the circles. In other words, the three elements, environmental<br />

sustainability, economic sustainability and social sustainability do not<br />

always carry equal weight in decision-making. When a decisionmaker,<br />

whether it is an administrative <strong>of</strong>ficial or a judicial <strong>of</strong>ficer,<br />

takes into account sustainable development in the decision-making<br />

process, he or she makes a value-based judgement. This judgment is<br />

informed by the values <strong>of</strong> environmental sustainability, and economic<br />

sustainability as part <strong>of</strong> the integration process. However, one (or<br />

sometimes two) <strong>of</strong> these values may inevitably triumph.<br />

Tladi therefore suggests a more nuanced approach in the<br />

application <strong>of</strong> sustainable development, one that provides three<br />

variations <strong>of</strong> integration based on the value that is the preferred one<br />

in cases <strong>of</strong> conflict. In the economic growth-centred variation,<br />

economic growth takes centre stage, whilst in the environmentcentred<br />

variation, the natural environment triumphs. Finally in the<br />

human needs-centred (or social needs centred) variation the social<br />

needs <strong>of</strong> humans are placed at the forefront. 66 He argues that such a<br />

variation approach allows decision-makers to decide which variation<br />

best serves the aims <strong>of</strong> sustainable development. 67 In essence his<br />

analysis suggests that sustainable development decisions are<br />

inevitably value driven. It means that decision-makers decide in<br />

advance which <strong>of</strong> the values they prefer to advance, and whilst still<br />

taking into account the other two values, base the decision on the<br />

preferred value.<br />

If we then apply this ‘variation approach’ to integration, it would<br />

lead us to the conclusion that the decision in Fuel Retailers may fall<br />

within the economic growth or human centred (or a combination <strong>of</strong><br />

both) variation since the Court has emphasised the failure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

environmental authorities to take socio-economic considerations into<br />

account? I would suggest not. Whilst the integration process is a valuedriven<br />

process, the preferred value cannot be without a legitimate<br />

basis. In other words, a decision maker’s decision should be grounded<br />

in law and there should be some justifiable base in law for the<br />

preferred value. Such a basis may be found in a legal or policy<br />

instrument and may provide an indication <strong>of</strong> the preferred variation<br />

<strong>of</strong> sustainable development.<br />

In this respect Sachs J’s dissent is instructive. In essence he<br />

provides us with the application <strong>of</strong> this ‘variation’ approach to the<br />

integration element <strong>of</strong> sustainable development and takes NEMA as<br />

his ‘legitimising base’. With regard to the application <strong>of</strong> the preamble<br />

and principles <strong>of</strong> NEMA, he notes that ‘economic sustainability is not<br />

66 Tladi (n 60 above) 80. His idea is not that placing one value centre stage would<br />

obliterate the other, but rather that it would re-enforce the other two.<br />

67 Tladi (n 60 above) 82.


252 Sustainable development in practice<br />

treated as an independent factor to be evaluated as a discrete<br />

element in its own terms’, but rather that the focus is on the interrelationship<br />

between economic sustainability and environmental<br />

protection. 68 Accordingly, he argues, NEMA does not envisage that<br />

social, environment and economic sustainability should proceed along<br />

separate tracks, with each being assessed separately and only<br />

considered together at the end <strong>of</strong> the decision-making process. It is<br />

his contention that economic sustainability takes on significance only<br />

to the extent that it implicates the environment. As such, it is only<br />

‘when economic development potentially threatens the environment<br />

that it becomes relevant to NEMA’ and it is only at this point that it<br />

should be considered within the context <strong>of</strong> the sustainable<br />

development requirements <strong>of</strong> NEMA. 69 Sachs bases this conclusion on<br />

the thesis that ‘all environmental controls were in place and that any<br />

potential deleterious effect <strong>of</strong> over-trading was speculative and<br />

remote’. 70<br />

Sachs situates his position within the dictates <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development as required by NEMA. The overall aim <strong>of</strong> NEMA is to first<br />

and foremost ensure environmental protection. NEMA thus grants<br />

priority to the environment-centred variation <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development. In situations <strong>of</strong> conflict between economic, social and<br />

environmental considerations, the latter must be preferred. Given<br />

that NEMA operates within this model Sachs’s argument that social<br />

and economic considerations are only ‘triggered’ once the<br />

environment is implicated makes sense.<br />

Sachs could equally have used section 24 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution as his<br />

‘legitimising base’. Section 24(b)(iii) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution refers to the<br />

need to ‘secure ecologically sustainable development’. [own<br />

emphasis]. It can be argued that ‘ecologically’ qualifies the type <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development that is envisioned by the Constitution. It<br />

therefore clearly places an emphasis on environmental considerations<br />

and as such it places the environmental value centre-stage. Section<br />

24 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution therefore mandates the environment-centred<br />

variation <strong>of</strong> sustainable development. Any decision-making regarding<br />

sustainable development that is mandated by section 24 should,<br />

therefore, be situated within this model.<br />

The Sachs approach could be seen as ‘applied variation’ as it gives<br />

us some guidance on how to interpret instruments such as legislation<br />

and policy that requires sustainable development. In applying the<br />

model not only to the decision in the Fuel Retailers case but also the<br />

decision in the BP case, it exposes both for their inadequate and<br />

68 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 113.<br />

69<br />

As above.<br />

70 Fuel Retailers (n 1 above) para 112.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 253<br />

ultimately unsatisfying application <strong>of</strong> sustainable development.<br />

Whilst both decisions were at first glance ‘good for the environment’,<br />

they were really motivated by socio-economic considerations, as such<br />

applying economic centred variations <strong>of</strong> integration when the<br />

Constitution and NEMA really required environment centred<br />

variations. If the latter were applied, different outcomes would have<br />

followed in both cases.<br />

5 Conclusion<br />

Fuel Retailers may have been hailed as a victory for the environment<br />

and for environmental rights, but was it the correct decision from a<br />

normative point <strong>of</strong> view? Sustainable development is a truly laudable<br />

concept, but as pointed out it raises a number <strong>of</strong> challenges in<br />

negotiating the increasingly contested demands <strong>of</strong> development and<br />

environmental protection. It embodies competing values and requires<br />

other conceptual and normative framework to address these tensions<br />

and to provide practical solutions. On its own, the concept fails to<br />

address practical and normative considerations.<br />

We therefore need a more principled, value-based approach to<br />

sustainable development that identifies the value that is being<br />

prioritised in particular circumstances. The variation approach to<br />

integration takes into account that certain norms and values will most<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten be paramount in sustainable development decision-making.<br />

Whilst Fuel Retailers has highlighted the ongoing debate on<br />

sustainable development in the South African context, it ought not<br />

have been the final word. The majority judgement failed to<br />

interrogate the normative nature <strong>of</strong> sustainable development<br />

comprehensively and in the process provided us with an inherently<br />

flawed and incomplete application <strong>of</strong> the concept. Sachs’ dissent<br />

provides an alternative, and more nuanced perspective on this<br />

complex norm.


1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

*<br />

FUEL RETAILERS, SUSTAINABLE<br />

DEVELOPMENT & INTEGRATION:<br />

A RESPONSE TO FERIS<br />

Legal Counsellor to the South African Permanent Mission to the United Nations in<br />

New York. Extraordinary Pr<strong>of</strong>essor in the Department <strong>of</strong> Public Law at the<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Stellenbosch.<br />

255<br />

Dire Tladi *<br />

Fuel Retailers is, without question, a most interesting and significant<br />

decision: (1) Interesting because the decision tackles head on the<br />

difficult task <strong>of</strong> balancing apparently conflicting interests — the right<br />

to a healthy environment and economic imperatives <strong>of</strong> development;<br />

(2) Significant because, as the first decision in which the<br />

Constitutional Court gives content to section 24 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution,<br />

one expects the decision to play a major role in the development <strong>of</strong><br />

environmental law and sustainable development.<br />

Loretta Feris’ comment 1 provides a fairly detailed (and accurate)<br />

overview <strong>of</strong> Fuel Retailers. 2 The exploration <strong>of</strong> the nuances <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development in Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Feris’ contribution, rooted as it<br />

is in pragmatism, makes the contribution particularly useful to<br />

practitioners — especially those who evaluate applications for<br />

approval for activities with a potential impact on the environment.<br />

As someone concerned more with the theoretical and normative<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> sustainable development, I thought the paper important<br />

for engaging the complexity <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> integration in<br />

sustainable development discourse — a complexity that is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

1 L Feris ‘Sustainable development in practice: Fuel Retailers Associatioin <strong>of</strong><br />

Southern Africa v Director-General Environmental Management, Department <strong>of</strong><br />

Agriculture, Conservation and Environment, Mpumalanga Province’ (2008) 1<br />

Constitutional Court Review 235.<br />

2 Fuel Retailers Association <strong>of</strong> Southern Africa v Director-General Environmental<br />

Management, Department <strong>of</strong> Agriculture, Conservation and Environment,<br />

Mpumalanga Province, and Others 2007 6 SA 4 (CC).


256 A response to Feris<br />

missed because <strong>of</strong> our collective reverence for the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development. 3 Feris and I are in accord over a large range<br />

<strong>of</strong> issues, in particular the view that Sachs J’s dissent provides the<br />

most ‘conceptually sound analysis <strong>of</strong> sustainable development’. 4 Our<br />

common ground established, I would now like to <strong>of</strong>fer my slightly<br />

different take on what the Fuel Retailers Court misses.<br />

2 The Court’s treatment <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development<br />

Feris states upfront that she will avoid a ‘comprehensive analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

the historical development <strong>of</strong> the concept or the normative content’<br />

<strong>of</strong> sustainable development. 5 For me, the historical development <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept is critical for understanding the normative content,<br />

which, in turn, influences its practical application. Ngcobo J’s<br />

majority judgment does, in fact, survey the historical evolution <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development — he traces it back to the 1972 Stockholm<br />

Conference on the Human Environment. 6 The historical exposition <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development by the Court suffers from the same ailment<br />

as many similar expositions. First, the Court erroneously states that<br />

the term sustainable development was ‘coined’ by the Brundtland<br />

Commission in 1987. 7 Second, the Court does not explain how this<br />

evolution influences the conceptualisation that follows in the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

the judgement. The Court <strong>of</strong>fers, so to speak, a recollection <strong>of</strong> history<br />

for history’s sake. While time and space do not allow for a discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> how the historical evolution <strong>of</strong> sustainable development ought to<br />

influence its conceptualisation, the Court’s history is notably flawed<br />

in this regard. 8<br />

The problem with the Court’s analysis, in my view, begins when<br />

the Court, in connection with section 24 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, makes<br />

reference to the ‘explicit recognition <strong>of</strong> the obligation to promote<br />

justifiable “economic and social development”’ and links this notion<br />

with the ‘well-being <strong>of</strong> human beings’ and ‘socio-economic rights’. 9<br />

Precisely what that link is, the Court never explains or explores. But<br />

the result <strong>of</strong> this linkage is that, throughout the judgement, the terms<br />

3<br />

4<br />

Someone, I cannot recall who or in what context, once remarked that sustainable<br />

development, like human rights, is a concept that is not to be questioned in<br />

polite company.<br />

Feris (n 1 above) 236.<br />

5 Feris (n 1 above) 236.<br />

6 Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) para 46.<br />

7<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) para 47. Already in 1980, the IUCN World Conservation<br />

Strategy contained several references to sustainable development.<br />

8 For my views, see D Tladi Sustainable development and international law: An<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> key enviro-economic instruments (2007) 34 et seq.<br />

9 Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) para 44.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 257<br />

‘socio-economic rights’, ‘development’ and ‘economic development’<br />

are used interchangeably as the values that most <strong>of</strong>ten oppose the<br />

right to a clean and a healthy environment. 10 At one point the Court,<br />

for example, refers to the integration <strong>of</strong> environmental protection<br />

and economic development. 11 Elsewhere, the Court states that as a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> sustainable development ‘environmental considerations will<br />

now increasingly be a feature <strong>of</strong> economic and development policy’. 12<br />

Further on, the Court states that ‘economic development, social<br />

development and the protection <strong>of</strong> the environment’ are considered<br />

to be the three pillars <strong>of</strong> sustainable development. 13 Finally, the<br />

Court asserts that sustainable development ‘provides a framework for<br />

reconciling socio-economic development and environmental<br />

protection’. 14<br />

By lumping these concepts together the Court misses an<br />

opportunity to develop a sound understanding <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development. The result <strong>of</strong> treating these concepts as<br />

interchangeable is that the Court never stops to ask whether the<br />

factors that the Fuel Retailers Association requested that the<br />

environmental authorities consider are socio-economic or purely<br />

economic. To use language from the common definition <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development, the Court does not ask whether these factors are social<br />

or economic. The Court’s judgment implies — incorrectly — that<br />

economic considerations are the same as social considerations.<br />

A similar conflation <strong>of</strong> these concepts is evident in Feris’ analysis.<br />

After applying the model <strong>of</strong> three variations <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development that I have proposed, she asks whether Fuel Retailers<br />

would ‘fall within the economic growth or human-centred (or a<br />

combination <strong>of</strong> both) variation’ <strong>of</strong> sustainable development because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the failure <strong>of</strong> the authorities to consider ‘socio-economic<br />

considerations’. 15 Although Feris answers the question in the<br />

negative, it is the manner in which she treats economic growth<br />

centred variation and human well-being centred variation as similar<br />

that is <strong>of</strong> some concern.<br />

One can readily understand the intuitive lumping together <strong>of</strong><br />

these two variations <strong>of</strong> sustainable development (and the values they<br />

represent). After all, at the centre <strong>of</strong> both <strong>of</strong> these variations are<br />

human-related concerns, namely economic concerns and social<br />

concerns. However, in my view these variations (and their values)<br />

tend to pull in different directions. Factors relevant for economic<br />

10 Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) paras 51, 52, 53 & 55.<br />

11<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) para 51.<br />

12 Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) para 52.<br />

13 Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) para 53.<br />

14<br />

Fuel Retailers (n 2 above) para 55.<br />

15 Feris (n 1 above) 249.


258 A response to Feris<br />

growth variation are, for example, trade related concerns. Access to<br />

clean drinking water and food reflect a human well-being variation <strong>of</strong><br />

sustainable development. They are not the same. 16 The approach <strong>of</strong><br />

the Court in this instance — and reflected in some <strong>of</strong> Feris’ comments<br />

— takes us back in time to the old definition <strong>of</strong> sustainable<br />

development. On this outré account, sustainable development<br />

balanced environmental needs and development needs — the latter<br />

notion represented both social and economic concerns.<br />

Sustainable development — and this is where a proper historical<br />

sketch is important — was born out <strong>of</strong> a realisation that the existing<br />

paradigm (in which economic concerns trumped all other concerns<br />

(social and environment) — could not continue. By blurring the<br />

distinction between social and economic concerns, our jurisprudence<br />

flirts with the undesirable outcome <strong>of</strong> preserving the status quo:<br />

namely, paying lip service to sustainable development and<br />

integration. The failure to distinguish more carefully between these<br />

values facilitates the instrumentalisation <strong>of</strong> sustainable development<br />

for economic ends. Fuel Retailers is a case in point.<br />

3 Concluding remarks<br />

The treatment <strong>of</strong> sustainable development by the Constitutional<br />

Court was long overdue. For that reason alone Fuel Retailers is a<br />

welcome addition to South African jurisprudence. Given the<br />

shortcomings <strong>of</strong> the judgment delineated in Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Feris’ comment<br />

and my reply, we can only hope that the Court will, over time,<br />

develop a more nuanced approach to sustainable development that<br />

does justice to its history, makes subtle but important distinctions<br />

between economic concerns and social concerns, and does not allow<br />

this concept to be captured by those parties with purely pecuniary<br />

motives.<br />

16<br />

For an in-depth discussion <strong>of</strong> how these variations and their factors, see Tladi (n 8<br />

above) 81-90.


1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

CULTURAL AND RELIGIOUS<br />

ACCOMMODATIONS TO SCHOOL<br />

UNIFORM REGULATIONS<br />

* MA LLB (Natal) PhD (Cantab). Senior Lecturer, School <strong>of</strong> Philosophy and Ethics,<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> KwaZulu-Natal.<br />

1 Church <strong>of</strong> Lukumi Babalu Aye Inc v City <strong>of</strong> Hialeah 508 US 520 (1993).<br />

2 Section 15(1) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa, 1996 (‘the<br />

Constitution’) provides that ‘everyone has the right to freedom <strong>of</strong> conscience,<br />

religion, thought, belief and opinion’.<br />

259<br />

Patrick Lenta *<br />

Laws and regulations in modern liberal democracies rarely<br />

discriminate deliberately against members <strong>of</strong> religious and cultural<br />

groups or target religious and cultural practices. In one relatively<br />

recent example, Church <strong>of</strong> Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc v City <strong>of</strong> Hialeah<br />

(Church <strong>of</strong> Lukumi Babalu Aye), the US Supreme Court invalidated<br />

municipal ordinances adopted by the city <strong>of</strong> Hialeah for the specific<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> proscribing animal sacrifice practised by the Santeria<br />

religion. 1 Since these ordinances did not constitute a neutral law <strong>of</strong><br />

general applicability, but deliberately targeted a religious practice,<br />

the Supreme Court determined that they were invalid unless they<br />

served a compelling state interest. Since the state could not show<br />

such an interest, the ordinances were declared, relatively<br />

uncontroversially, to be in violation <strong>of</strong> the Free Exercise clause (the<br />

US equivalent <strong>of</strong> South Africa’s right to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion and<br />

conscience) 2 and so invalid.<br />

Laws and regulations that are facially neutral in the sense that<br />

they do not deliberately target members <strong>of</strong> particular cultural or<br />

religious groups are more common than those which are overtly<br />

discriminatory. In some instances, however, these facially neutral<br />

laws may have non-neutral effects and impose disparate burdens on<br />

group members. These individuals sometimes claim from the courts


260 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

exemptions to generally applicable laws and regulations on the<br />

grounds that particular laws or regulations impose burdens on them<br />

that are not imposed on others. For example, Muslim female pupils<br />

may seek exemptions from school uniform regulations that forbid the<br />

wearing <strong>of</strong> headscarves on the grounds that their religious beliefs<br />

obligate them to wear a headscarf or that wearing a headscarf is a<br />

genuine expression <strong>of</strong> their faith.<br />

Should Muslim girls be required to relinquish this cherished<br />

religious practice as a condition <strong>of</strong> availing themselves <strong>of</strong> the<br />

opportunity <strong>of</strong> education, or are schools obligated to meet their<br />

demands for accommodation? The most compelling argument that<br />

claims for exemptions in such cases should be granted begins with the<br />

claim that cultural group membership (including membership <strong>of</strong><br />

religious groups) is intrinsically valuable for individual group<br />

members. Will Kymlicka argues that cultural membership is<br />

the context within which we choose our ends, and come to see their<br />

value, and this is a precondition for self-respect, <strong>of</strong> the sense that one’s<br />

ends are worth pursuing. 3<br />

Membership <strong>of</strong> groups provides individuals with personal and social<br />

identities, on which their dignity and prosperity may depend. 4<br />

3 W Kymlicka Liberalism, community and culture (1989) 193.<br />

4 For other accounts <strong>of</strong> the significance <strong>of</strong> group membership, see J Raz<br />

‘Multiculturalism: a liberal perspective’ in his Ethics in the public domain (1994),<br />

B Parekh Rethinking multiculturalism (2000), J Tully Strange multiplicity (1995)<br />

and C Taylor Multiculturalism and the politics <strong>of</strong> recognition (1992). For a recent<br />

acknowledgment by the Constitutional Court concerning the value <strong>of</strong> group<br />

membership to members, see Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs & Another v Fourie &<br />

Another 2006 1 SA 524 para 89. The existence <strong>of</strong> cultural groups has social<br />

benefits too. Characterising religious groups in the United States as a source <strong>of</strong><br />

‘social capital’, R Putnam Bowling alone: The collapse and revival <strong>of</strong> the<br />

American community (2000) 79, has observed that ‘faith-based organisations<br />

serve civic life both directly, by providing social support to their members, and<br />

indirectly, by nurturing civic skills, inculcating moral values [and] encouraging<br />

altruism’. It is not fanciful to imagine that the moral values to which Putnam<br />

refers could potentially provide a counterweight to what B Barry Why social<br />

justice matters (2005) 236, calls ‘the recrudescent ideology <strong>of</strong> individualism,<br />

with its concomitant implications that members <strong>of</strong> society are nothing to one<br />

another’, in contemporary capitalist society. Also important are the ‘benefits to<br />

society <strong>of</strong> having religious groups operating as vital associations intermediate<br />

between individuals and government and creating a barrier to government<br />

domination <strong>of</strong> social life’ (K Greenawalt Religion and the constitution (2006)<br />

439). The Constitutional Court recognised certain <strong>of</strong> the benefits <strong>of</strong> religion to<br />

society in Fourie (above) para 90. It must nevertheless be conceded that ‘there is<br />

nothing automatically good about religion, which can after all lead to war,<br />

insanity, mutilation, suicide, soul-murder’. (JB White ‘Talking about religion in<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> the law: Impossible but necessary’ (1999) 81 Marquette Law<br />

Review 177 193).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 261<br />

The argument that Muslim headscarves should be accommodated<br />

by school authorities proceeds as follows. 5 According to the liberal<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity, individuals with differing aims<br />

should be afforded an equal chance to realise their ambitions and the<br />

costs that people should have to bear to do so should be, as far as<br />

possible, equal. But since cultural membership is bound up with<br />

individual autonomy, dignity, prosperity and self-respect (all <strong>of</strong> which<br />

liberals have a reason to value), in assessing whether people have<br />

equal opportunities, their cultural and religious commitments must<br />

be taken into account. A prospect only represents an opportunity for<br />

an individual if she can avail herself <strong>of</strong> it without incurring excessive<br />

costs. But in the case <strong>of</strong> a Muslim pupil, the cost <strong>of</strong> complying with the<br />

school uniform regulation may be sufficiently high that the<br />

opportunity is effectively removed. Genuine equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity,<br />

on the liberal multiculturalist conception, requires an exemption to<br />

permit Muslim female pupils to wear headscarves in school to<br />

eliminate the excessive costs attached to compliance with the<br />

uniform regulations.<br />

A common response to the contention that granting an exemption<br />

in such cases would amount to unfairly preferential treatment <strong>of</strong><br />

members <strong>of</strong> the particular group — one that recommended itself to<br />

the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa in MEC for Education,<br />

KwaZulu-Natal and Others v Pillay (Pillay), 6 the most recent occasion<br />

on which it was confronted with a claim for an accommodation 7 — is<br />

that when a cultural or religious group constitutes a minority, and so<br />

is less powerful than majority groups, as Muslims are in South Africa,<br />

then its members are disadvantaged compared to members <strong>of</strong><br />

majority (or more powerful) groups. Laws and regulations are <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

framed in a way that is consistent with the beliefs and values <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dominant, mainstream cultural groups, but not with those <strong>of</strong><br />

vulnerable, minority groups. As a result, members <strong>of</strong> minority groups<br />

bear costs in pursuing opportunities with which members <strong>of</strong><br />

mainstream and more powerful groups are not confronted. Since on<br />

this argument membership <strong>of</strong> a cultural or religious group is like a<br />

physical handicap, inasmuch as it is usually an unchosen feature <strong>of</strong><br />

individuals which is in certain respects disadvantaging, exemptions<br />

5 I have presented this argument in greater detail in P Lenta ‘Muslim headscarves in<br />

schools and in the workplace’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 296 298-299.<br />

6<br />

2008 1 SA 474 (CC) (Pillay).<br />

7 See (n 6 above) paras 44 (‘The norm embodied by the Code is not neutral, but<br />

enforces mainstream and historically privileged forms <strong>of</strong> adornment, such as ear<br />

studs, which also involve the piercing <strong>of</strong> a body part, at the expense <strong>of</strong> minority<br />

and historically excluded forms’), and para 83 (‘many individual communities still<br />

retain historically unequal power relations or historically skewed population<br />

groups which may make it more likely that local decisions will infringe on the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> disfavoured groups’).


262 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

should be granted to create equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity for all persons<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> power and influence. 8<br />

In this paper, I shall comment on Pillay, which concerns the duty<br />

<strong>of</strong> school authorities to accommodate religiously and culturally<br />

expressive clothing and accoutrements — in this case, a nose stud,<br />

which, it was claimed, expressed the pupil’s Hindu faith and South<br />

Indian culture, but which contravened school uniform regulations. 9<br />

The issue <strong>of</strong> whether a pupil should be permitted to wear a tiny nose<br />

stud might seem trivial. In fact, however, the politics <strong>of</strong> dress in<br />

schools is highly emotive, both in South Africa and elsewhere, because<br />

items <strong>of</strong> clothing and adornment <strong>of</strong>ten serve as visible markers <strong>of</strong><br />

religious and cultural identity. 10<br />

It might be imagined that this issue could easily be disposed <strong>of</strong><br />

with reference to the question <strong>of</strong> whether exemptions should be<br />

granted to accommodate Muslim headscarves. I have argued<br />

elsewhere that exemptions from school uniforms should be granted to<br />

permit Muslim pupils to wear headscarves: in some cases, Muslim<br />

pupils may sincerely believe that they are under a religious obligation<br />

8 A version <strong>of</strong> this argument is made in C Eisgruber & L Sager ‘Equal Regard’ in S<br />

Feldman (ed) Law and religion (2000) 200. For a similar argument in support <strong>of</strong><br />

religious exemptions, according to which, since members <strong>of</strong> a majority religion<br />

will usually protect their own religious practices when enacting laws, but ignore,<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten unintentionally, the burden that otherwise valid laws impose on minority<br />

religions, exemptions are justified in order to remedy this flaw in the political<br />

process, see D Laycock ‘Formal, substantive, and disaggregated neutrality toward<br />

religion’ (1990) 39 DePaul Law Review 993 1014; M McConnell ‘Free exercise<br />

revisionism and the Smith decision’ (1990) 57 <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Chicago Law Review<br />

1109 1130-36 and M Nussbaum Liberty <strong>of</strong> conscience: In defense <strong>of</strong> America’s<br />

tradition <strong>of</strong> religious equality (2008) 20-21 116-119. In Pillay, Langa CJ drew an<br />

analogy between membership <strong>of</strong> a minority religious or cultural group and<br />

disability (n 6 above, 74).<br />

9 For useful discussions <strong>of</strong> the right to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion and the ways in which it<br />

has been applied in South Africa, see P Farlam ‘Freedom <strong>of</strong> religion, conscience,<br />

thought and belief’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa<br />

(2nd Edition, OS, 2003) ch 41, S Woolman ‘Community rights: Language, culture<br />

and religion’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd<br />

Edition, OS, 2003) ch 58, D Meyerson ‘Religion and the South African constitution’<br />

in P Radan, D Meyerson & R Croucher (eds) Law and religion (2005) ch 5, G J<br />

Pienaar ‘The effect <strong>of</strong> equality and human dignity on the right to religious<br />

freedom’ (2003) 66 Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 579, I Currie<br />

& J de Waal The bill <strong>of</strong> rights handbook (5th ed 2005) ch 15, N Smith ‘Freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

religion: The right to manifest our beliefs’ (2002) 119 South African Law Journal<br />

690. Discussions <strong>of</strong> cultural expression are few, but see, for example, Woolman<br />

(above), especially at 31-43, S Woolman ‘Defending discrimination: On the<br />

constitutionality <strong>of</strong> independent schools that promote a particular, if not<br />

comprehensive, vision <strong>of</strong> the good life’ (2007) 22 Stellenbosch Law Review 31, B<br />

Fleisch & S Woolman ‘On the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> single-medium public schools’ 23<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 34 and I Currie & J de Waal The bill <strong>of</strong><br />

rights handbook (5th ed 2005) ch 28.<br />

10 As Frantz Fanon observes, ‘immense cultural regions can be grouped together on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> original, specific techniques <strong>of</strong> men’s and women’s dress ... [t]he fact<br />

<strong>of</strong> belonging to a given cultural group is usually revealed by clothing traditions’ (F<br />

Fanon, ‘Algeria unveiled’ in Studies in a dying colonialism (1962) 35).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 263<br />

to wear a headscarf and the objectives furthered by having uniforms<br />

may not be significantly undermined by granting this exemption. 11<br />

But if headscarves should be exempted, then so too, one might think,<br />

should Hindu nose studs.<br />

My purpose in this essay is to show that, although South African<br />

Hindus <strong>of</strong> South Indian extraction are, like Muslims, a minority group,<br />

the facts <strong>of</strong> Pillay are not as closely analogous as they might first<br />

appear to the case <strong>of</strong> a Muslim pupil who seeks an accommodation to<br />

permit her to wear a headscarf which she sincerely believes to be a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> religious obligation. Furthermore, the ways in which these<br />

cases differ provide grounds for concern about the Constitutional<br />

Court’s decision to accommodate nose studs in Pillay. I shall begin by<br />

providing, as background, an account <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s<br />

jurisprudence in the two cases in which it has previously considered<br />

claims for accommodations. I shall then focus on the Constitutional<br />

Court’s reasoning in Pillay. Throughout, I shall contrast the approach<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court to claims for accommodation with similar<br />

claims that have been adjudicated by courts <strong>of</strong> ultimate jurisdiction<br />

in three other jurisdictions: the United States, the United Kingdom<br />

and Canada.<br />

2 Corporal punishment and cannabis<br />

In Christian Education South Africa v Minister <strong>of</strong> Justice (Christian<br />

Education), 12 the first occasion on which the Constitutional Court was<br />

confronted with a claim for an accommodation, it unanimously<br />

affirmed that accommodations are, in principle, justifiable. Sachs J<br />

aligned the Court with liberal multiculturalist proponents <strong>of</strong><br />

exemptions by stating that the granting <strong>of</strong> religious exemptions<br />

‘would not be unfair to anyone else who did not hold those views’ 13<br />

and that<br />

the State should, wherever reasonably possible, seek to avoid putting<br />

believers to extremely painful and intensely burdensome choices <strong>of</strong><br />

either being true to their faith or else respectful <strong>of</strong> the law 14<br />

provided that religious practices do not violate the rights included in<br />

11 This is the argument <strong>of</strong> Lenta (n 5 above).<br />

12 2000 4 SA 757 (CC).<br />

13<br />

Christian Education (n 12 above) para 42.<br />

14 Christian Education (n 12 above) para 35.


264 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. 15<br />

The Constitutional Court nevertheless declined to grant an<br />

exemption to legislation proscribing corporal punishment in schools to<br />

permit teachers to inflict corporal punishment in Christian schools.<br />

The exemption was sought on the grounds that verses in chapters 9,<br />

22 and 23 <strong>of</strong> the Book <strong>of</strong> Proverbs command the corporal punishment<br />

<strong>of</strong> children at school. Sachs J argued that the right to dignity, coupled<br />

with the right not to be subjected to cruel and unusual, inhuman or<br />

degrading punishment, placed a duty on the state to ‘reduce violence<br />

in public and private life’, 16 particularly in view <strong>of</strong> the state’s resort<br />

to violence to counter protests by children during apartheid and the<br />

high incidence <strong>of</strong> child abuse in contemporary South Africa.<br />

The Constitutional Court’s decision in Christian Education is, I<br />

think, correct. 17 In a liberal democracy, the state is the ultimate<br />

guardian and arbiter <strong>of</strong> children’s interests; it has a duty to protect<br />

15 The granting <strong>of</strong> religious accommodations is, <strong>of</strong> course, far from uncontroversial.<br />

J Locke argues forcefully in favour <strong>of</strong> state neutrality, inasmuch as the state must<br />

not prefer particular religions over others, yet he does not endorse the practice<br />

<strong>of</strong> granting exemptions, insisting instead that ‘the private judgement <strong>of</strong> any<br />

person conceiving a law enacted in political matters, for the public good, does<br />

not take away the obligation <strong>of</strong> that law, nor deserve a dispensation’ (J Locke ‘A<br />

letter concerning toleration’ in I Shapiro (ed) Two treatises <strong>of</strong> government and a<br />

letter concerning toleration (2003) [1689] 243). Locke’s position is that all<br />

people, regardless <strong>of</strong> their affiliations, must comply with generally applicable<br />

laws. If individuals’ religious beliefs require them to disobey the law, they should<br />

accept the punishment prescribed by law. Thus, for Locke, if generally applicable<br />

laws are neutral in the sense that they do not deliberately target religion, or a<br />

particular religion, they should be construed as fair. Nowadays, the principal<br />

objection to granting religious exemptions is that to do so is unfair to those who<br />

might also wish to be excused from otherwise legitimate laws that burden<br />

practices motivated by secular moral beliefs. See, for example, FM Gedicks ‘An<br />

unfirm foundation: The regrettable indefensibility <strong>of</strong> religious exemptions’ (1998)<br />

20 <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Arkansas Little Rock Law Journal 555. Some defenders <strong>of</strong> the<br />

approach taken in J Rawls Political liberalism (1993) may be tempted to argue<br />

that the principle <strong>of</strong> state neutrality, according to which the state should not<br />

prefer one religious viewpoint over another, nor religious beliefs over secular<br />

beliefs, renders the granting <strong>of</strong> religious exemptions unjustifiable. On this view,<br />

exempting religious believers immunises religion in a way that advances it in<br />

comparison to equally heartfelt secular reasons for claiming exemptions.<br />

Accommodations for religious beliefs, some Rawlsians may argue, amount to<br />

favourable treatment to which religious believers are not entitled. A common<br />

response to this objection to mandatory accommodations — one that is implicit in<br />

Sachs J’s judgment — is that, if a generally applicable law puts members <strong>of</strong> a<br />

religious or cultural group (especially a minority group) at a disadvantage relative<br />

to others, refusing the exemption cannot be justified on the basis that the law<br />

provides formal equality: justice requires that exemptions be granted in<br />

appropriate cases to eliminate or reduce the burden as far as possible.<br />

16 Christian Education (n 12 above) para 47.<br />

17<br />

For a more detailed commentary, see P Lenta ‘Religious liberty and cultural<br />

accommodation’ (2005) 122 South African Law Journal 352 363-371.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 265<br />

children against what it deems to be abusive practices. 18 One <strong>of</strong> the<br />

most fundamental liberal rights is to be free from physical assault.<br />

Most people think that children have this right. 19 Since there is<br />

considerable evidence that corporal punishment is psychologically<br />

harmful to pupils, then, even though there may be countervailing<br />

evidence indicating that mild and infrequent corporal punishment has<br />

an improving effect on children, the state is entitled to proscribe it in<br />

schools. Once it does so, there is no room for an exemption for<br />

Christian schools, since corporal punishment inflicted at these schools<br />

will not be rendered non-abusive because it is a practice underpinned<br />

by religious beliefs. To grant an exemption would be to frustrate the<br />

purpose behind the legislation, which is not to reduce the incidence<br />

<strong>of</strong> corporal punishment in school, but to prevent every instance <strong>of</strong> an<br />

abusive practice.<br />

The Court’s decision in Christian Education is consistent with that<br />

<strong>of</strong> the UK House <strong>of</strong> Lords in R (Williamson) v Secretary <strong>of</strong> State for<br />

Education and Employment (Williamson), 20 the facts <strong>of</strong> which were<br />

virtually identical, except that whereas Sachs J emphasised the duty<br />

on the state to reduce the incidence <strong>of</strong> physical violence because <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa’s circumstances, Lord Nicholls <strong>of</strong> Birkenhead took the<br />

view that deference to parliament on an issue <strong>of</strong> ‘broad social policy’<br />

was appropriate. 21 Baroness Hale <strong>of</strong> Richmond agreed in substance<br />

with Lord Nicholls, adding that to ban only corporal punishment that<br />

infringed against children’s right not to suffer abusive punishment<br />

would present ‘difficult problems <strong>of</strong> definition, demarcation and<br />

enforcement’. 22<br />

18 Although there is a presumption in favour <strong>of</strong> permitting parents to raise their<br />

children in accordance with their religious beliefs, the ultimate responsibility <strong>of</strong><br />

the state for the welfare <strong>of</strong> children may require it to overrule the religious<br />

beliefs <strong>of</strong> parents. See, for example, Hay v B & Others 2003 3 SA 492 (WLD), in<br />

which parents <strong>of</strong> a minor opposed a doctor’s application to conduct an emergency<br />

blood transfusion to save the life <strong>of</strong> their child principally on the grounds that<br />

receipt <strong>of</strong> a blood transfusion was contrary to their religious beliefs. Jajbhay J<br />

held that the parents could not insist that their child should be denied a blood<br />

transfusion if the child’s survival, in the opinion <strong>of</strong> a doctor, depended on it.<br />

Jajbhay J is absolutely correct: adults may reject life-saving medical treatment<br />

for themselves, but they may not condemn their children to death on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

their religious beliefs. A similar position was adopted in the UK in Re O (A Minor)<br />

(Medical Treatment) (1993) 2 FLR 149; Re R (A Minor) (Blood Transfusion) (1993) 2<br />

FLR 757. The Canadian Supreme Court arrived at this conclusion in B(R) v<br />

Children’s Aid Society <strong>of</strong> Metropolitan Toronto (1995) 122 DLR (4th) 1 (SCC), in<br />

which it upheld a lower court order to remove a baby from the custody <strong>of</strong> its<br />

Jehovah’s Witness parents temporarily so that it could receive life-saving medical<br />

treatment, including a blood transfusion. In the US, judges have readily ordered<br />

treatment over the parents’ wishes. See Matter <strong>of</strong> Hamilton, 657 SW 425, 429<br />

(Tenn Ct App 1983); Custody <strong>of</strong> a Minor, 393 NE2d 836 (Mass 1979).<br />

19 See C McKinnon Toleration: A critical introduction (2006) 107.<br />

20 2005 2 AC 246 (HL).<br />

21<br />

n 20 above, para 51.<br />

22 n 20 above, para 86.


266 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

In Prince v President <strong>of</strong> the Law Society <strong>of</strong> the Cape <strong>of</strong> Good Hope<br />

(Prince), 23 a narrow majority <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court refused to<br />

grant to Rastafarians an exemption from legislation forbidding the<br />

possession and use <strong>of</strong> cannabis, despite an existing permit system for<br />

administering medical exemptions. The majority denied the claim<br />

principally on the grounds <strong>of</strong> the practical difficulty <strong>of</strong> policing the<br />

exemption, and because South Africa’s obligations under<br />

international law required a ban to be uniformly enforced. 24<br />

The applicant, a Rastafarian attorney, applied for an exemption<br />

to statutes which proscribe the possession and use <strong>of</strong> cannabis, on the<br />

grounds that these Acts prevent an activity central to the sacramental<br />

activities <strong>of</strong> his religion. The majority <strong>of</strong> the Court decided that<br />

although medical exemptions from the Act could be effectively<br />

controlled and administered, the same would not be true <strong>of</strong> a<br />

religious exemption for Rastafarians. Since Rastafarian use <strong>of</strong><br />

cannabis was not restricted to small quantities at religious<br />

ceremonies, but was consumed at home and on social occasions, there<br />

would be no way for enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficials to distinguish between<br />

authentic religious consumption and consumption for recreational<br />

reasons. Moreover, the majority decided, South Africa’s blanket ban<br />

on the use and possession <strong>of</strong> cannabis was intended to meet its<br />

obligations under international law. There would, in addition, be<br />

financial and administrative difficulties in establishing a permit<br />

system and this coupled with the fact that the Rastafarian religious<br />

community is not easily delineated, since its structures are informal,<br />

would render a permit system incapable <strong>of</strong> preventing cannabis being<br />

distributed to non-Rastafarians. The majority, despite aligning itself<br />

with the approach <strong>of</strong> the minority <strong>of</strong> the US Supreme Court in<br />

Employment Division v Smith (Smith), 25 according to whom religious<br />

practices could only be subordinated to a general governmental<br />

interest if the state could show a ‘compelling state interest’ and that<br />

the law was the ‘least restrictive means’ <strong>of</strong> serving that interest, 26<br />

held that a uniform ban on a drug such a cannabis, which is widely<br />

used for recreational purposes and in which there is significant trade,<br />

was justified.<br />

The dissenting judgements <strong>of</strong> Ngcobo and Sachs JJ took the view<br />

that a partial rather than full exemption (as sought by the applicant)<br />

should be granted to enable Rastafarians to use small quantities <strong>of</strong><br />

cannabis for sacramental purposes on religious occasions. A limited<br />

exemption, Sachs J held, would secure for the Rastafari ‘a modest but<br />

23<br />

24<br />

25<br />

2002 2 SA 794 (CC).<br />

For a more detailed analysis, see Lenta (n 17 above) 371-375.<br />

Employment Division, Department <strong>of</strong> Human Resources <strong>of</strong> Oregon v Smith 494 US<br />

26<br />

872 (1990).<br />

Prince (n 23 above) para 122.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 267<br />

meaningful measure <strong>of</strong> dignity and recognition’ and was required<br />

because ‘the Constitution requires the state to walk the extra mile’. 27<br />

Against the majority, Ngcobo and Sachs JJ contended that a permit<br />

system, coupled with administrative guidelines, could be instituted to<br />

ensure that the terms <strong>of</strong> a limited exemption would be effectively<br />

enforced. Ngcobo J argued that an exemption would not violate South<br />

Africa’s obligations under international law since provisions to the<br />

effect that such measures were subject to each party’s constitutional<br />

principles and limitations were included in international protocols and<br />

conventions binding on South Africa. If the South African Constitution<br />

is interpreted by the Court as requiring an exemption, it would not fall<br />

foul <strong>of</strong> international conventions. Sachs J similarly claimed that South<br />

Africa’s international obligations do not rule out an exemption for<br />

religious purposes. 28<br />

The majority’s failure to take seriously a limited exemption for an<br />

act <strong>of</strong> worship central to faith that would use administrative<br />

procedures similar to medical exemptions is, I think, regrettable. The<br />

burden imposed by the relevant legislation on Rastafarians is severe:<br />

sacramental and liturgical practices are at the core <strong>of</strong> religion and<br />

forbidding these practices forces Rastafarians either to violate the<br />

tenets <strong>of</strong> their religion or become outlaws. This appears<br />

discriminatory since it is unthinkable that major faiths should have to<br />

face this choice. The use <strong>of</strong> wine in the Catholic Mass is unlikely ever<br />

to be forbidden.<br />

On the issue <strong>of</strong> enforcement, screening devices might have been<br />

employed to separate genuine Rastafarians wishing to use cannabis<br />

for purposes <strong>of</strong> worship from others seeking to smoke cannabis for<br />

recreational purposes. The terms <strong>of</strong> the exemption proposed by the<br />

minority were consistent with dispensing cannabis in small quantities<br />

directly to Rastafarian priests for distribution restricted to individuals<br />

participating in church services, the whole to be overseen by state<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials. 29 People masquerading as Rastafarian worshippers would<br />

have to go to great lengths to pass themselves <strong>of</strong>f as believers before<br />

other believers and state <strong>of</strong>ficials. They would be required, at<br />

considerable inconvenience to themselves — which would in most<br />

cases, one imagines, outweigh the pleasure they would otherwise<br />

derive from smoking — to participate in the ceremony. It is<br />

implausible to think that a limited exemption such as this would<br />

promote the illegal trafficking <strong>of</strong> drugs any more than would a<br />

medical exemption. I concede, however, that justifying the limited<br />

27<br />

Prince (n 23 above) paras 148-9.<br />

28 Prince (n 23 above) para 164.<br />

29 The granting <strong>of</strong> this limited exemption might have had an economic cost. It might<br />

have been appropriate to ask Rastafarian worshippers to bear at least part <strong>of</strong> this<br />

cost.


268 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

exemption might depend on the plausibility <strong>of</strong> the majority’s<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> South Africa’s obligations under international<br />

conventions.<br />

By aligning itself with the ‘compelling interest test’ established by<br />

the US Supreme Court in Sherbert v Verner 30 and Wisconsin v Yoder<br />

(Yoder), 31 the Constitutional Court affirmed its willingness to grant<br />

exemptions in principle. 32 In doing so, it <strong>of</strong>fered greater protection<br />

for religious liberty than US Supreme Court did in Smith, in which the<br />

majority refused to grant an exemption from a criminal prohibition to<br />

permit Native American Indians to ingest as an element <strong>of</strong> their<br />

worship, peyote, a psychotropic drug. The majority in Smith,<br />

abandoning the ‘compelling interest’ standard (except for<br />

unemployment compensation cases and ‘hybrid’ cases involving two<br />

constitutional rights), held that if a law is generally valid, the<br />

government may apply it against religious claimants without having to<br />

show more than that the law has a rational basis. Provided the state<br />

can show this, there is no constitutional requirement to grant<br />

religious groups exemptions from facially neutral laws which do not<br />

have the purpose (though they may have the incidental effect) <strong>of</strong><br />

burdening the practice <strong>of</strong> religion. As Scalia J put it, the right to<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> religion ‘does not relieve an individual <strong>of</strong> the obligation to<br />

comply with a “valid and neutral law <strong>of</strong> general applicability”’. 33<br />

In response to Smith, the US Congress, at the instigation <strong>of</strong> a large<br />

number <strong>of</strong> religious groups, enacted the Religious Freedom<br />

Restoration Act (‘RFRA’). The RFRA was intended to restore the<br />

position prior to Smith relating to the granting <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

exemptions, according to which, as the Act states<br />

Government may not substantially burden a person’s exercise <strong>of</strong> religion<br />

even if the burden results from a rule <strong>of</strong> general applicability … [unless]<br />

it demonstrates that the application <strong>of</strong> the burden to the person (1) is in<br />

furtherance <strong>of</strong> a compelling government interest; and (2) is the least<br />

restrictive means <strong>of</strong> furthering that ... interest. 34<br />

In City <strong>of</strong> Boerne v Flores, Archbishop <strong>of</strong> San Antonio et al, 35 the US<br />

Supreme Court declared the RFRA invalid as it applies to states and<br />

30 374 US 398 (1963).<br />

31<br />

406 US 205 (1972).<br />

32 Prince (n 23 above) para 128.<br />

33 Smith (n 25 above) p 879.<br />

34<br />

Religious Freedom Restoration Act, 42 USC §§ 2000bb-1-2000bb-4 (2004).<br />

35 521 US 507 (1997).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 269<br />

localities, but not as it applies to the federal government, for which<br />

purposes it remains valid. 36<br />

In a recent US Supreme Court decision, Gonzalez, Attorney<br />

General et al v O Centro Espírita Beneficente União Do Vegetal et al<br />

(Gonzalez), 37 members <strong>of</strong> a church, the Christian Spiritists, wished to<br />

import hoasca, a tea containing a federally proscribed hallucinogen,<br />

which, it claimed, facilitated communion. The Supreme Court<br />

dismissed the Government’s submission that it had a compelling<br />

interest in the uniform application <strong>of</strong> the law to the extent that no<br />

exemption could be granted to accommodate the sect’s sacramental<br />

use <strong>of</strong> hoasca. The Court held that the government’s failure to grant<br />

an exemption to the claimants was inconsistent with their rights<br />

under the RFRA.<br />

Although the Supreme Court in Gonzalez adopted an approach<br />

similar to that employed in Prince, there are two important respects<br />

in which the approaches <strong>of</strong> the two courts differ. 38 First, the majority<br />

in Prince gave greater weight to a need for uniform enforcement if<br />

the ban on the use and possession was to be effectively policed.<br />

Second, the US Supreme Court ruled that the fact that hoasca was<br />

covered by the Convention on Psychotropic Substances, did ‘not<br />

automatically mean’ that the federal law furthered a compelling<br />

interest that outweighed the claim for an exemption under the RFRA.<br />

Despite acknowledging the importance <strong>of</strong> ‘honouring international<br />

obligations and <strong>of</strong> maintaining the leadership position <strong>of</strong> the United<br />

States in the war on drugs’, the invocation <strong>of</strong> these general interests<br />

alone, the Supreme Court decided, was ‘not enough’ in the absence<br />

<strong>of</strong> evidence addressing the international consequences <strong>of</strong> granting an<br />

exemption. 39 By contrast, the majority <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court<br />

attached greater significance to South Africa’s obligations under<br />

international law, holding that ‘[t]he use made <strong>of</strong> cannabis by<br />

Rastafari cannot in the circumstances be sanctioned without<br />

36 The American Indian Religious Freedom Act Amendments were enacted by the US<br />

Congress in 1994 to permit peyote use by Native Americans for the purposes <strong>of</strong><br />

religious worship and many states enacted legislation to exempt Native American<br />

Indians from existing prohibitions against drug use. This legislation does not<br />

protect the sacramental use <strong>of</strong> cannabis by Rastafarians, however, raising the<br />

issue <strong>of</strong> whether the 1994 Amendments constitute unfair discrimination. This<br />

issue arose in the Kansas Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals in State v McBride 955 P2d 133 (Kan Ct<br />

App 1998), in which the court distinguished between the religious use <strong>of</strong> the two<br />

substances on the following grounds: peyote is used in small quantities and is<br />

restricted to religious ceremonies by Native American Indians; recreational use<br />

and abuse <strong>of</strong> peyote is rarer than is the case with cannabis, and the state in the<br />

US has a special duty to respect the political and cultural integrity <strong>of</strong> Native<br />

Americans. See B Taylor ‘Kansas denies religion-based defense to Rastafarians on<br />

marijuana charges’ (1998) 38 Washburn Law Journal 307.<br />

37 No 04-1084 (2006).<br />

38 See P Edge ‘Religious drug use in England, South Africa and the United States <strong>of</strong><br />

America’ (2006) 1 Religion and Human Rights 165 176.<br />

39 Gonzalez (n 37 above) 17-18.


270 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

impairing the state’s ability ... to honour its international obligation<br />

to do so’. 40<br />

Do these differences in approach indicate that the US Supreme<br />

Court in Gonzalez provided greater protection to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion<br />

than the Constitutional Court did in Prince? Before concluding that it<br />

did, it is important to recognise that the facts <strong>of</strong> the two cases are<br />

different. Gonzalez deals with a drug that is not widely used: the<br />

market for hoasca is small and there had not in the past been practical<br />

difficulties in policing the ban on recreational use <strong>of</strong> hoasca. By<br />

contrast, as the majority in Prince noted, ‘cannabis, unlike peyote, is<br />

a drug in which there is substantial illicit trade’. 41 Unlike hoasca,<br />

cannabis is widely used beyond the confines <strong>of</strong> religious worship for<br />

recreational purposes. For these reasons, an approach such as that<br />

employed in Gonzalez may well have denied an exemption for<br />

religious use <strong>of</strong> cannabis, just as Blackmun J in his dissenting<br />

judgement in Smith held that although an exemption should be<br />

granted in the case <strong>of</strong> peyote, the state could legitimately deny<br />

claims for religious exemptions involving drugs such as marijuana and<br />

heroin, the use <strong>of</strong> which is not restricted to a ceremonial context and<br />

in which there is ‘significant illegal trade’. 42 Would the majority’s<br />

approach in Prince commit it to denying an exemption in a case in<br />

material respects the same as Gonzalez? Few <strong>of</strong> the difficulties <strong>of</strong><br />

policing and administering an exemption for cannabis are likely to<br />

occur in the case <strong>of</strong> an exemption for hoasca. Nevertheless, if the<br />

Constitutional Court determined that South Africa’s obligations under<br />

international law required a ban to be uniformly enforced, the view<br />

<strong>of</strong> the majority in Prince suggests that the Court might reject a claim<br />

for an exemption for hoasca too.<br />

The refusal <strong>of</strong> the majority <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court in Prince<br />

to grant an exemption to enable Rastafarians to use cannabis on the<br />

grounds <strong>of</strong> international law obligations is consistent with the<br />

approach <strong>of</strong> the UK judiciary. In Taylor, 43 later endorsed in<br />

Andrews, 44 a Rastafarian had been observed by police <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

approaching a Rastafarian temple. On being searched, he was found<br />

to be in possession <strong>of</strong> cannabis, in violation <strong>of</strong> a criminal prohibition.<br />

The Rastafarian’s defence consisted in the contention that the<br />

cannabis was intended to be consumed as part <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> worship at<br />

the temple. Accordingly his possession was a manifestation <strong>of</strong> his<br />

religion, protected under the right to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion (Article 9 <strong>of</strong><br />

the European Convention on Human Rights). The Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal held,<br />

40<br />

Prince (n 23 above) para 139.<br />

41 n 23 above, para 129.<br />

42 Gonzalez (n 37 above) 917-8.<br />

43<br />

[2001] EWCA Crim 2263; [2002] 1 Cr App R 37.<br />

44 [2004] EWCA Crim 947.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 271<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> several international conventions whose purpose was<br />

to restrict the use, possession and trafficking <strong>of</strong> psychotropic<br />

narcotics, that whatever the interference with the Rastafarian’s<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> religion, it was justified in order to prevent public health<br />

and safety dangers arising from cannabis use, possession and supply.<br />

3 Nose studs, headscarves and daggers<br />

Pillay concerned a claim by the parent <strong>of</strong> a Hindu pupil at a state<br />

school that the failure <strong>of</strong> the school’s authorities to grant her<br />

daughter an exemption from the school’s Code <strong>of</strong> Conduct to permit<br />

her to wear a nose stud constituted unfair discrimination on the<br />

grounds <strong>of</strong> religion and culture. The claim was brought under the<br />

Promotion <strong>of</strong> Equality and Unfair Discrimination Act, 45 which prohibits<br />

unfair discrimination on the grounds <strong>of</strong> religion and culture. Although<br />

the claim was not brought under the rights to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion and<br />

culture, the Court held that there may be, as in this case, an<br />

overlap [between the Promotion <strong>of</strong> Equality and Unfair Discrimination<br />

Act and the rights to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion, belief and opinion and to<br />

participate in cultural life 46 ] … where the discrimination in question<br />

flows from an interference with a person’s religious or cultural<br />

practices’. 47<br />

Pillay clearly represents a development <strong>of</strong> the Court’s jurisprudence<br />

on religious liberty and cultural accommodation.<br />

The Court ruled that the school’s failure to grant the exemption<br />

was unfairly discriminatory and that the school was required to<br />

exempt the pupil concerned, Langa CJ, on behalf <strong>of</strong> the majority,<br />

deciding that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud represents an expression <strong>of</strong><br />

the Hindu religion and <strong>of</strong> South Indian Tamil culture. The majority<br />

found that the failure <strong>of</strong> the school to grant the accommodation was<br />

unfairly discriminatory against the pupil concerned relative to other<br />

pupils whose religious beliefs and cultural practices did not bring<br />

them into conflict with the Code. Langa CJ stated that although the<br />

school uniform served ‘admirable purposes,’ these objectives would<br />

not be undermined by granting religious and cultural exemptions. 48<br />

In a separate judgement in which she agreed with the majority’s<br />

finding <strong>of</strong> unfair discrimination, but disagreed in part with its<br />

45<br />

46<br />

Act 4 <strong>of</strong> 2000 (‘the Equality Act’).<br />

Section 30 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution reads: ‘Everyone has the right to use the language<br />

and participate in the cultural life <strong>of</strong> their choice, but no one exercising these<br />

47<br />

48<br />

rights may do so in a manner inconsistent with any provision <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights.’<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 46.<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 101.


272 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

reasoning, O’Regan J found that there is no evidence that the wearing<br />

<strong>of</strong> a nose stud has religious significance for the claimant, although she<br />

accepted that it is a form <strong>of</strong> cultural expression. She agreed with the<br />

majority that the failure <strong>of</strong> the school to grant an exemption was<br />

unfairly discriminatory, but for a different reason: the applicant was<br />

discriminated against, not relative to those pupils on whom the Code<br />

imposed no burden <strong>of</strong> religious or cultural denial, but relative to other<br />

pupils whom the school had in the past exempted: Hindu pupils had<br />

been permitted to wear ‘Lakshmi strings’ in honour <strong>of</strong> the Goddess<br />

Lakshmi and other pupils had been allowed to wear hide bracelets as<br />

a mark <strong>of</strong> respect on the death <strong>of</strong> a relative. 49<br />

Both Langa CJ and O’Regan J recognised that exemptions should<br />

not be made in response to every claim. Claims for exemptions call<br />

for a proportionality exercise. The strength <strong>of</strong> the claim must be<br />

determined. This involves an enquiry into whether, if a religious<br />

belief is relied upon, it is genuinely a religious belief, or, in the case<br />

<strong>of</strong> a cultural practice, that it is genuinely a cultural practice; the<br />

sincerity <strong>of</strong> the claimant, and the nature and severity <strong>of</strong> the burden<br />

on religious exercise. The strength <strong>of</strong> the competing interest <strong>of</strong> the<br />

state or other relevant institution in the uniform application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rule must equally be considered. In cases where the law in question<br />

protects fundamental rights <strong>of</strong> individuals, or serves a compelling<br />

state objective that would be significantly frustrated by granting an<br />

exemption, or where the exemption would present insurmountable<br />

practical difficulties such that it could not be administered<br />

effectively, it may be that an exemption is ruled out. In the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

this section, I consider the way in which the Constitutional Court<br />

negotiated each step in this enquiry.<br />

3.1 Religious belief or cultural practice?<br />

The claimant was required to show that the practice for which the<br />

accommodation is claimed is cultural in nature or that it is motivated<br />

by religious beliefs. The task <strong>of</strong> determining what beliefs and<br />

practices are religious — as opposed to secular, moral or personal — is<br />

a difficult matter, since religion is a highly complex concept. By what<br />

criteria can religion be defined and the distinction between it and the<br />

non-religious drawn, given the ineffable nature <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

experience and the fact that individuals have shifting relationships<br />

with religious communities which may themselves be riven with<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ound theological differences? Defining culture, to the extent that<br />

49 Pillay (n 6 above) para 130.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 273<br />

it differs from religion, is no easier, since ‘cultural forms possess<br />

inherent indeterminacy’. 50<br />

On the issue <strong>of</strong> the cultural significance <strong>of</strong> the nose stud, Langa<br />

CJ asserted two claims. First, ‘cultural convictions or practices may<br />

be as strongly held and as important to those who hold them as<br />

religious beliefs are [for religious believers]’ since individual identity<br />

and dignity is bound up with culture. Second, cultural practices ‘will<br />

differ from person to person within a culture’, since ‘[c]ultures are<br />

living and contested formations’. 51 Noting the regrettable absence <strong>of</strong><br />

testimony from the pupil herself, Langa CJ found that an admission by<br />

the school authorities that the nose stud has ‘cultural significance’ 52<br />

for the pupil was dispositive <strong>of</strong> the question <strong>of</strong> whether the practice<br />

should be considered to be a cultural practice.<br />

On the issue <strong>of</strong> whether the nose stud has religious significance,<br />

Langa CJ referred to the testimony <strong>of</strong> Dr Rambilass, an expert on the<br />

Hindu religion, who had given evidence on behalf <strong>of</strong> the school. Dr<br />

Rambilass had conceded that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud is a cultural<br />

practice, but denied that the nose stud has independent religious<br />

significance, being ‘part <strong>of</strong> the Shringaar which is concerned with<br />

love, beauty and adornment’. 53 Langa CJ contested this expert<br />

witness’s conclusion that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud is devoid <strong>of</strong><br />

religious significance on three grounds. First, he argued that it is<br />

difficult to separate Hindu culture and Hindu religion. Secondly,<br />

‘there are many different sects <strong>of</strong> Hinduism with different beliefs and<br />

practices’. 54 Thirdly, Dr Rambillas’s testimony<br />

self-consciously focused on defining Hindu religion according to the<br />

specific wording <strong>of</strong> the Vedic texts rather than on a broader view <strong>of</strong><br />

religion as being informed and even defined by culture, tradition and<br />

practice. 55<br />

On the grounds that ‘the borders between culture and religion are<br />

malleable and that religious belief informs cultural practice and<br />

cultural practice attains religious significance’, Langa CJ concluded<br />

that Sunali’s (the pupil in question’s) wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud was ‘an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> both culture and religion’. 56<br />

Langa CJ’s reasoning in determining that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose<br />

stud has religious significance may be questioned from several<br />

50<br />

L Rosen, quoted in W Fallers Sullivan ‘Judging religion' (1998) 81 Marquette Law<br />

51<br />

52<br />

53<br />

54<br />

55<br />

56<br />

Review 441 456.<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) paras 53-54.<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 58.<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 59.<br />

As above.<br />

As above.<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 60.


274 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

perspectives. There was no evidence to suggest that it bore religious<br />

significance for Sunali beyond the claimant’s assertion that it did.<br />

Expert testimony indicated otherwise, and Langa CJ’s rejection <strong>of</strong> Dr<br />

Rambilass’ testimony concerning the content <strong>of</strong> the Hindu religion,<br />

about which he and not Langa CJ is an expert, is illegitimate. As for<br />

Langa CJ’s contention that it is <strong>of</strong>ten difficult to distinguish between<br />

culture and religion, it is one thing to say that many religious<br />

practices are in some sense cultural and that many cultural practices<br />

are religious — both <strong>of</strong> which propositions are true, since culture and<br />

religion are inter-imbricated. It is quite another thing to aver that all<br />

cultural practices are religious, which is false. There is a subset <strong>of</strong><br />

cultural practices that do not carry religious significance, which the<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> Dr Rambilass indicated included the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose<br />

stud.<br />

That the borders <strong>of</strong> religion and culture are porous and that<br />

cultural practices may attain religious significance does not, contra<br />

Langa CJ, constitute evidence that the nose stud has religious<br />

significance. It would do so only if all cultural practices had religious<br />

significance, which is surely not the case. Langa CJ failed to cite<br />

credible evidence for thinking that nose studs have religious<br />

significance. Accordingly, O’Regan J’s assessment is more plausible:<br />

Although the applicant argues that the nose stud was part <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

practice, it is clear that its primary significance to her family arises from<br />

its associative meaning as part <strong>of</strong> their cultural identity, rather than<br />

personal religious beliefs. This is consistent with Dr Rambilass’s evidence<br />

that wearing a nose-stud is not part <strong>of</strong> Hindu religion’. 57<br />

O’Regan J’s approach to determining whether a practice is cultural is<br />

to be preferred to Langa CJ’s. She contended that since cultural<br />

practices are associative and that the right to cultural life is to be<br />

practiced as a member <strong>of</strong> a community and not primarily a question<br />

<strong>of</strong> sincere, but personal belief, Langa CJ’s ‘individualised and<br />

subjective approach to what constitutes culture is faulty’. Rather ‘in<br />

probing whether a particular practice is a cultural practice, some<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> what the cultural community considers to be a<br />

cultural practice is important’. 58 O’Regan J elaborated:<br />

57 Pillay (n 6 above) para 62. O’Regan J’s conclusion — ‘that the applicant has<br />

established that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud is a matter <strong>of</strong> associative cultural<br />

significance, which was a matter <strong>of</strong> personal choice at least for the learner in this<br />

case, but that it is not part <strong>of</strong> a religious or personal belief <strong>of</strong> the applicant that<br />

it is necessary to wear the stud as part <strong>of</strong> her religious beliefs’ — is open to the<br />

interpretation that she accepted that the practice has non-mandatory religious<br />

significance for Sunali. But this would be inconsistent with O’Regan J’s failure to<br />

challenge, and apparent acceptance <strong>of</strong>, Dr Rambilass’s statement that wearing a<br />

nose stud is not a religious practice.<br />

58 Pillay (n 6 above) para 154.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 275<br />

It will not ordinarily be sufficient for a person who needs to establish<br />

that he or she has been discriminated against on the grounds <strong>of</strong> culture<br />

to establish that it is his or her sincerely held belief that it is a cultural<br />

practice, or that his or her family has a tradition <strong>of</strong> pursuing this<br />

practice. The person will need to show that the practice that has been<br />

affected relates to a practice that is shared in a broader community <strong>of</strong><br />

which he or she is a member and from which he or she draws meaning. 59<br />

O’Regan J’s distinction between religion and culture has merit.<br />

Although most religions are also cultures, a religion may be<br />

constituted by the beliefs and practices <strong>of</strong> a single individual. A<br />

religion need not be constituted by shared practices and beliefs (even<br />

though it will usually be). By contrast, culture signifies the range <strong>of</strong><br />

beliefs and assumptions held in common by members <strong>of</strong> a group, as<br />

well as the ensemble <strong>of</strong> customs and practices (fluid and mobile to be<br />

sure) that reflect the way members do things in common: modes <strong>of</strong><br />

dress and decoration, types <strong>of</strong> circulation and social activity, ways <strong>of</strong><br />

working and so on. Thus, where it is claimed that a practice is a<br />

cultural practice, we can examine the culture concerned to<br />

determine whether members engage in it in common with other<br />

members. We are not necessarily in a position to do this when it is<br />

claimed that a particular practice is religious in nature, since the<br />

beliefs and practices <strong>of</strong> a single individual may be sufficient to<br />

constitute a religion.<br />

O’Regan J noted that there are a number <strong>of</strong> women <strong>of</strong> South<br />

Indian heritage who wear a nose stud because it identifies them as<br />

members <strong>of</strong> that community and connects them with their community<br />

and with former generations. She rightly considered this sufficient<br />

evidence to conclude that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud by women <strong>of</strong><br />

South Indian extraction is a matter <strong>of</strong> ‘associative cultural<br />

significance’. 60 She nevertheless noted, again correctly, that the<br />

practice is optional (that there is no cultural norm or obligation<br />

putting pressure on Sunali to wear a nose stud is evidenced by the fact<br />

that her sisters opted not to do so).<br />

No evidence was adduced by the applicant to show that the<br />

wearing <strong>of</strong> the nose stud by her daughter was religious; indeed, it is<br />

clear that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud is, for Hindu women, an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> cultural identity that is entirely optional and is not a<br />

religious practice. Nevertheless, that the practice has cultural<br />

significance is sufficient to bring it within the ambit <strong>of</strong> the Equality<br />

Act.<br />

59<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 159.<br />

60 Pillay (n 6 above) para 162.


276 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

3.2 Sincerity<br />

In order to be successful, the claimant must be sincere in her<br />

assertion that her opposition to conforming to the standard<br />

requirements rests on religious or cultural grounds: she must<br />

demonstrate that her beliefs are sincerely held (‘neither fictitious,<br />

nor capricious ... [nor] an artifice’) 61 or that she is sincerely<br />

expressing her cultural identity. Although the enquiry into sincerity<br />

precludes determining the truth or legitimacy <strong>of</strong> religious claims, it is<br />

important because charlatans may be tempted, for tactical purposes,<br />

to misrepresent as religiously or culturally motivated their insistence<br />

on acting contrary to the rules. The sincerity enquiry<br />

attempts to ensure that exemptions are not granted to individuals who<br />

frame their opposition ... in religious [or cultural] terms in order to be<br />

afforded the legal remedy desired when in fact the religious beliefs are<br />

not sincerely held because the opposition stems from secular<br />

convictions. 62<br />

A claimant is not acting on sincerely held religious beliefs or<br />

expressing her cultural identity simply because she says she is. The<br />

claimant must demonstrate to the satisfaction <strong>of</strong> the court that the<br />

asserted beliefs are sincerely held or that the practice in question is<br />

an expression <strong>of</strong> cultural identity. For Langa CJ, the fact that Sunali<br />

refused to remove the nose stud after initially agreeing to do so —<br />

equivocation that is most plausibly explained, he stated, ‘as a young<br />

woman uncertain about the consequences <strong>of</strong> standing up against the<br />

imposing authority <strong>of</strong> the School’s headmistress’ — ‘points to the<br />

conclusion that Sunali held a sincere belief that the nose stud was part<br />

<strong>of</strong> her religion and culture’. 63 In fact, however, Sunali’s conduct was<br />

also consistent with the actions <strong>of</strong> a pupil who was initially prepared<br />

to forgo wearing the nose stud, but whose parent resolved to defy the<br />

school’s authorities in order that her daughter could continue to<br />

engage in a practice expressive <strong>of</strong> cultural identity only. The sincerity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the claimant’s averment that the practice has religious significance<br />

is questionable, particularly in view <strong>of</strong> Dr Rambilass’s evidence that<br />

Hindu women do not regard it as a religiously significant practice.<br />

Even allowing that different believers within the same faith may hold<br />

different beliefs and attach different significance to the same<br />

61 Iacobucci J in Syndicat Northcrest v Amselem (2004) 2 SCR 551 para 52<br />

(Amselem).<br />

62 C Kraus ‘Religious exemptions — applicability to vegetarian beliefs’ (2001) 30<br />

H<strong>of</strong>stra Law Review 197 215. As the US District Court observed in US v Kuch 288 F<br />

Supp 439 443 claimants ‘must not be permitted the special freedoms this<br />

sanctuary may provide merely by adopting religious nomenclature and cynically<br />

using it as a shield to protect them when participating in antisocial conduct that<br />

otherwise stands condemned’.<br />

63 Pillay (n 6 above) para 58.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 277<br />

practice, the applicant provided no convincing evidence that Sunali’s<br />

wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud was motivated by sincerely held religious<br />

belief. In the absence <strong>of</strong> any evidence that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud<br />

is motivated by a religious belief (such as the scriptural evidence<br />

provided by the claimants in Christian Education or the verses <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Quran referred to by Muslim women claiming exemptions to permit<br />

them to wear headscarves) the impression that remains is that<br />

Sunali’s wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud only masqueraded as a religious<br />

practice for the purposes <strong>of</strong> securing an exemption.<br />

This is not to insist on the semiotic neutrality <strong>of</strong> a nose stud for a<br />

pupil <strong>of</strong> South Indian descent, nor is it to dispute the sincerity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

claimant’s assertion that Sunali wished to wear the nose stud to<br />

express her South Indian culture. Far from it: as both Langa CJ and<br />

O’Regan J rightly observed, it is a practice that is clearly invested<br />

with cultural significance: an expression <strong>of</strong> the pupil’s cultural<br />

identity. Although the nose stud is an adornment worn by women out<br />

<strong>of</strong> personal choice within South Indian culture, there is no reason to<br />

doubt that Sunali wore it as a fashion accessory that expressed her<br />

cultural identity.<br />

3.3 Claimant’s burden versus state interest<br />

Langa CJ observed that the constitution places a duty <strong>of</strong> ‘reasonable<br />

accommodation’ on the institution from which an exemption is<br />

claimed. How should reasonableness be construed in this context?<br />

According to Langa CJ, the institution must make more than mere<br />

negligible effort ‘to enable those outside the “mainstream” to swim<br />

freely in its waters’, but determining the extent <strong>of</strong> the hardship it<br />

must suffer to do so will involve a ‘contextual’ determination, ‘an<br />

exercise in proportionality that will depend intimately on the facts’. 64<br />

In practice, courts must assess the burden imposed on the claimant’s<br />

religious freedom or cultural practice and whatever interest is served<br />

by refusing the exemption, and strike an appropriate balance<br />

between the two. The claimant should only succeed if she suffers a<br />

substantial burden on the exercise <strong>of</strong> her religion or culture and if the<br />

state or institution’s interest in denying her an exemption is not<br />

strong. Even if the burden on the claimant is substantial, the claim<br />

should not succeed if the government’s interest in denying the<br />

exemption is strong: human sacrifice may be central to a claimant’s<br />

religion, but it should not be accepted as a defence against a charge<br />

64 Pillay (n 6 above) para 76.


278 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

<strong>of</strong> murder. Likewise the claim should fail if it affects religious or<br />

cultural activities only marginally. 65<br />

The claimant was required to show that, as a result <strong>of</strong> the<br />

school’s code, Sunali was placed under a substantial burden. A<br />

showing <strong>of</strong> this kind is easier where the religious or cultural practice<br />

for which the claimant is seeking protection is mandatory rather than<br />

optional: where there is ‘a Hobson’s choice between observance <strong>of</strong><br />

their faith and adherence to the law’ 66 as there was in Christian<br />

Education. In Pillay, by contrast, the applicant conceded that her<br />

wearing a nose stud was not required by the tenets <strong>of</strong> her faith, but<br />

was instead a voluntary practice. The Constitutional Court held —<br />

consistently with the Canadian Supreme Court’s ruling in Amselem 67<br />

(affirmed, though the Constitutional Court does not say so, by the<br />

House <strong>of</strong> Lords in Williamson 68 ) — that it is not essential to the success<br />

<strong>of</strong> a claim for a religious exemption that the religious practice be<br />

required by the claimant’s religious or cultural beliefs, but only that<br />

it be an expression <strong>of</strong> those beliefs. That is so, stated Langa CJ,<br />

because the Constitution is committed to ‘affirming diversity’ and<br />

‘differentiating between mandatory and voluntary practices does not<br />

celebrate or affirm diversity but merely tolerates it’. 69<br />

The Constitutional Court is clearly correct that in order to be<br />

afforded protection under the right to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion the belief<br />

or practice need not be mandatory, although this has nothing to do<br />

with celebrating rather than tolerating diversity. To be successful,<br />

the claimant must demonstrate not that the practice for which she<br />

seeks protection is compelled by her religion, but that the regulation<br />

imposes a substantial burden on the practice <strong>of</strong> her religion. A trivial<br />

impact imposed by a law on an individual would not be sufficient to<br />

qualify for an exemption. Even if religious practices are not<br />

mandatory, being prevented from engaging in such practices may be<br />

substantially burdensome. Kent Greenawalt illustrates this point with<br />

an example: individual A might not consider wearing a cross to be<br />

mandatory, yet could regard wearing a cross as ‘an important symbol<br />

<strong>of</strong> witness and commitment and a great aid to devotion’. 70 Were a<br />

school to forbid all jewellery, including crosses, A’s convictions should<br />

65 See Lyng v Northwest Indian Cemetery Protection Association 374 US 398 (1963)<br />

at 475, in which Brennan J, dissenting, argued that a trivial interference with<br />

religious practice was insufficient; the claimants were required to show the<br />

‘centrality’ <strong>of</strong> the affected practices and the presence <strong>of</strong> a ‘substantial and<br />

realistic threat <strong>of</strong> frustrating their religious practice’.<br />

66<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 62.<br />

67 n 61 above, paras 67-8.<br />

68 n 20 above, para 33.<br />

69<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 65.<br />

70 Greenawalt (n 4 above) 210.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 279<br />

be sufficient to vault her over the threshold <strong>of</strong> substantial burden. 71<br />

Of course, not all voluntary practices are similarly justifiable.<br />

Consider individual B, who wears a cross without attaching great<br />

religious significance to it, though aware that it represents for<br />

Christians the crucifixion <strong>of</strong> Christ. A rule forbidding B from wearing<br />

jewellery would not constitute a substantial burden.<br />

Even allowing that proscribing voluntary practices may be<br />

burdensome, interfering with obligatory practices is likely to be more<br />

burdensome. That is so, because forgoing a practice mandated by the<br />

tenets <strong>of</strong> religion (as wearing a headscarf is for some Muslim women)<br />

will be intensely injurious to them, because what is being demanded<br />

<strong>of</strong> them is that they violate transcendental religious commands, on<br />

which the favour <strong>of</strong> their deity or sanctions, salvation or damnation,<br />

may depend. A clash between religious commandments and civil laws<br />

or regulations situates believers between competing sources <strong>of</strong><br />

authority, a predicament particularly grave given ‘the widespread<br />

sense that one’s religious obligations are more ultimate than those <strong>of</strong><br />

the social order and should take priority if the two come into<br />

conflict’. 72 Voluntary practices, precisely because they are not<br />

commanded, are less damagingly relinquished, even if forbidding such<br />

obstacles may be substantially burdensome.<br />

Langa CJ appeared not to appreciate this when he asserted, ‘that<br />

we choose voluntarily rather than through a feeling <strong>of</strong> obligation only<br />

enhances the significance <strong>of</strong> a practice to our autonomy, our identity<br />

and our dignity,’ to which he added that ‘it may be even more vital<br />

to protect non-obligatory cultural practices’. 73 But this obscures the<br />

fact that the costs to a believer <strong>of</strong> forgoing an optional practice will<br />

almost always be lower than the costs that a believer pays in deciding<br />

not to engage in a practice that the tenets <strong>of</strong> his faith mandates,<br />

because in the case <strong>of</strong> an optional practice, the individual is not<br />

required to make the agonising choice between competing sources <strong>of</strong><br />

authority.<br />

71<br />

See, by way <strong>of</strong> illustration, Sasnett v Sullivan 908 F Supp 1429 (WD Wis 1995),<br />

aff’d, 91 F 3d 1018 (7th Cir 1996), vacated and remanded, 521 US 1114 (1997), in<br />

which a prisoner challenged under the RFRA regulations limiting the wearing <strong>of</strong> all<br />

religious jewellery except wedding bands. Prison <strong>of</strong>ficials argued that the<br />

exercise <strong>of</strong> a prisoner’s religion was substantially burdened only if the practice<br />

was required by their religion, which the wearing <strong>of</strong> crucifixes was not. Posner J<br />

held that the question was whether the burdened practice was motivated by a<br />

sincere religious belief, not whether it was ecclesiastically mandated. He found<br />

that the regulation forbidding the wearing <strong>of</strong> crosses substantially burdened the<br />

plaintiff’s religious liberty. Winnifred Fallers Sullivan quotes one <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs:<br />

‘There’s nothing saying you have to wear a cross, but it brings a person closer to<br />

God’ (Sullivan (n 50 above) 451).<br />

72<br />

Greenawalt (n 4 above) 439.<br />

73 Pillay (n 6 above) paras 64 & 66.


280 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

How should the magnitude <strong>of</strong> the burden imposed on the claimant<br />

be measured? Langa CJ decided that the failure <strong>of</strong> the school to grant<br />

an exemption constituted a ‘significant infringement’ <strong>of</strong> the<br />

claimant’s religious and cultural identity on the basis <strong>of</strong> what he<br />

referred to as a ‘subjective investigation’. 74 The issue, he stated, is<br />

whether the pupil considered the nose stud central to her religion or<br />

cultural identity, not whether other members <strong>of</strong> the South Indian<br />

Tamil Hindu community do so (since the status <strong>of</strong> a practice within a<br />

particular group may be disputed). Langa CJ acknowledged that ‘the<br />

Court can properly look at a range <strong>of</strong> evidence including evidence <strong>of</strong><br />

the objective centrality <strong>of</strong> the practice to the community at large’. 75<br />

Yet it is striking that he, unlike O’Regan J, did not consider the way<br />

in which the practice is viewed by other members <strong>of</strong> the South Indian<br />

Hindu community. Instead he considered the pupil’s beliefs and<br />

attitudes concerning the practice, which he inferred from her<br />

conduct. Where Langa CJ’s reasoning went awry was in assuming that<br />

behaviour is an accurate indicator <strong>of</strong> beliefs. In fact, conduct is not<br />

reliable evidence <strong>of</strong> beliefs: it is usually the case that multiple beliefs<br />

and motivations are consistent with any individual’s activity.<br />

Langa CJ appears to have accepted uncritically the applicant’s<br />

assertion that she was placed under a substantial burden and refers<br />

to the pupil’s insistence on wearing the nose stud under the pressure<br />

<strong>of</strong> threatened disciplinary action as evidence <strong>of</strong> this. 76 But in fact, all<br />

that the pupil’s conduct evidences is a strong commitment to wearing<br />

the nose stud, which could reflect a substantial burden but could<br />

equally be motivated by her obedience to her mother, who appears to<br />

have engaged in a power struggle with the school authorities. The<br />

difficulty with Langa CJ’s enquiry into burden is that he seemed to<br />

treat the conclusory allegation on the part <strong>of</strong> the claimant regarding<br />

burden as dispositive. He was too ready to interpret the pupil’s<br />

conduct as indicative <strong>of</strong> the strength <strong>of</strong> her religious and cultural<br />

commitment to the practice, without allowing that a strong<br />

commitment to persisting with the practice is not necessarily<br />

generated by a substantial burden.<br />

The school claimed that the burden, if any, was slight since the<br />

pupil could wear the nose stud out <strong>of</strong> school hours. Langa J rejected<br />

this claim on the grounds that ‘[t]he practice to which Sunali adheres<br />

is that once she inserts the nose stud, she must never remove it’. 77<br />

However, he referred to no evidence in support <strong>of</strong> the claim that the<br />

practice <strong>of</strong> wearing a nose stud adopted by certain members <strong>of</strong> the<br />

74 Pillay (n 6 above) paras 85 & 88.<br />

75 Pillay (n 6 above) para 88.<br />

76<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 90.<br />

77 Pillay (n 6 above) para 85.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 281<br />

South Indian community obliges them to wear the nose stud at all<br />

times.<br />

The school claimed that the burden placed on the pupil was slight<br />

for the additional reason that she could have transferred to another<br />

school that would have allowed her to wear a nose stud. Langa CJ<br />

rejected this argument on the grounds that ‘permitting it only when<br />

no other option remains’ 78 was inconsistent with South Africa’s<br />

‘constitutional project which not only affirms diversity, but promotes<br />

and celebrates it’. The effect <strong>of</strong> requiring the pupil to relocate to<br />

another school to express her cultural identity, Langa CJ asserted,<br />

‘would be to marginalise religions and cultures’. 79<br />

If in Pillay the burden on the pupil did not, contra Langa CJ,<br />

appear to be particularly substantial, neither was the school’s<br />

interest in enforcing the school uniform without exception strong. It<br />

is <strong>of</strong>ten argued that uniforms promote crucial educational interests:<br />

minimising external differences between pupils <strong>of</strong> different social<br />

classes; discouraging competitive fashions; promoting school spirit<br />

and encouraging discipline. 80 At issue was the empirical question <strong>of</strong><br />

whether the accommodation sought by the claimant would<br />

significantly impair the achievement <strong>of</strong> these educational objectives.<br />

The school did not <strong>of</strong>fer evidence on this point and it is difficult to see<br />

how it could have done so. In fact, as Langa CJ noted, it is difficult to<br />

see how granting an exemption to permit the wearing <strong>of</strong> a nose stud<br />

would interfere substantially with the effective running <strong>of</strong> a school<br />

and with the purposes the school uniform was designed to further. 81<br />

This conclusion is consistent with that <strong>of</strong> the UK House <strong>of</strong> Lords in<br />

Mandla v Dowell Lee, 82 decided under the Race Relations Act <strong>of</strong> 1976,<br />

in which a headmaster had refused to admit a Sikh pupil to a private<br />

school on the grounds that the pupil insisted on wearing a turban,<br />

mandated by his faith, in violation <strong>of</strong> the school uniform. Lord Fraser<br />

78 Pillay (n 6 above) para 65.<br />

79 Pillay (n 6 above) para 92.<br />

80<br />

There is some debate about whether school uniforms are successful in fostering<br />

these educational objectives, although (contested) studies conducted by<br />

American researchers have found school uniforms increase discipline, foster<br />

school morale, reduce unhealthy competition amongst pupils and so forth. For a<br />

critical review <strong>of</strong> the literature, see D Brunsma School uniforms: A critical review<br />

<strong>of</strong> the literature (2002). The United States Department <strong>of</strong> Education’s Manual on<br />

school uniforms, (http://www.ed.gov/updates/uniforms.html (accessed: 6 June<br />

2007)) begins with the sentence, ‘A safe and disciplined learning environment is<br />

the first requirement <strong>of</strong> a good school’ and under the heading ‘Treat school<br />

uniforms as part <strong>of</strong> an overall safety program’ the Manual states as follows:<br />

‘Uniforms by themselves cannot solve all <strong>of</strong> the problems <strong>of</strong> school discipline, but<br />

they can be one positive contributing factor to discipline and safety’.<br />

81<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 101.<br />

82 [1983] 2 AC 548.


282 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

likewise dismissed the headmaster’s argument that an exemption<br />

would frustrate the objectives furthered by the uniform.<br />

In Pillay, the available evidence suggested that the burden<br />

imposed on the pupil and the interest <strong>of</strong> the school in denying her an<br />

exemption were roughly in equipoise. The political philosophy<br />

underlying the Court’s holding that the severity <strong>of</strong> the burden placed<br />

on the pupil outweighed the burden placed on the school is revealed<br />

in its commitment not only to tolerating difference but to ‘affirm[ing]<br />

it as one <strong>of</strong> the primary treasures <strong>of</strong> our nation’. 83 The Court appears<br />

to be committed to a ‘politics <strong>of</strong> difference’ that in certain respects<br />

resembles that outlined by Iris Marion Young in Justice and the<br />

Politics <strong>of</strong> Difference. 84<br />

Young’s contrast between what she considers the traditional<br />

liberal approach and the politics <strong>of</strong> difference is instructive:<br />

The vision <strong>of</strong> liberalism as the transcendence <strong>of</strong> group difference seeks<br />

to abolish the public and political significance <strong>of</strong> group difference,<br />

while retaining and promoting both individual and group diversity in<br />

private, or nonpolitical, social contexts. 85<br />

For Young, ‘[g]roups cannot be socially equal unless their specific<br />

experience, culture and social contributions are publicly affirmed and<br />

recognised’. 86 She deprecates the ‘the typical liberal approach ...<br />

which tolerates any behaviour so long as it is kept in private’, 87<br />

arguing that ‘the private, as traditionally conceived, is what should be<br />

83<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 92.<br />

84 IM Young Justice and the politics <strong>of</strong> difference (1990). It may be useful to deal<br />

briefly with the change in the way in which the idea <strong>of</strong> respect for difference has<br />

been viewed in South Africa. In a perversion <strong>of</strong> the contemporary politics <strong>of</strong><br />

difference, the apartheid government justified its policy <strong>of</strong> creating ‘homelands’,<br />

an order <strong>of</strong> ‘plural nations’ in semi-autonomous polities with no economic<br />

viability, with reference to something like a multicultural respect for difference.<br />

As a result, opponents <strong>of</strong> apartheid became suspicious <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> respect for<br />

difference. As R Nixon Homelands, Harlem and Hollywood: South African culture<br />

and the world beyond (1994) 206 asserts, ‘Since the late 1950s, difference (as<br />

opposed to unity) has been perceived — for sound historical reasons — as a<br />

government term. This is so because the South African brand <strong>of</strong> racial supremacy<br />

has been couched as a form <strong>of</strong> sensitivity to the special needs and cultural<br />

particularities <strong>of</strong> diverse “peoples”. Attentiveness to difference is thus perceived<br />

as “apartheid” business, a way <strong>of</strong> coating state racism with a democratic gloss’.<br />

Nevertheless, as John and Jean Comar<strong>of</strong>f ‘Criminal justice, cultural justice: The<br />

limits <strong>of</strong> liberalism and the pragmatics <strong>of</strong> difference in the new South Africa’<br />

(1994) 31 American Ethnologist 188 195 observe, there has been in South Africa ‘a<br />

growing recognition <strong>of</strong> the gravitas <strong>of</strong> difference’. In the jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court, attentiveness to difference has emerged, particularly in its<br />

jurisprudence dealing with sexual orientation and religious and cultural<br />

accommodation, as an integral part <strong>of</strong> constitutional justice.<br />

85 n 84 above, 168 (emphasis added).<br />

86<br />

n 84 above, 174 (emphasis added).<br />

87 Young (n 84 above) 161 (emphasis added).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 283<br />

hidden from view, or what cannot be brought out to view. It is<br />

connected with shame and incompleteness’. 88<br />

The refusal to permit members <strong>of</strong> cultural groups to manifest<br />

their culture publicly is considered by Young and the Constitutional<br />

Court to devalue members by relegating cultural practices to the<br />

private sphere. It is from this perspective that we should understand<br />

Langa CJ’s assertion that ‘the symbolic effect <strong>of</strong> denying her the right<br />

to wear it ... sends a message that Sunali, her religion and her culture<br />

are not welcome’. 89 From the perspective <strong>of</strong> the politics <strong>of</strong><br />

difference, the school’s refusal to permit Sunali to express her<br />

cultural identity at school (that is, in public) constitutes an injury to<br />

her. Young’s depreciation <strong>of</strong> liberal toleration chimes with O’Regan<br />

J’s statement that ‘treating people as worthy <strong>of</strong> equal respect in<br />

relation to their cultural practices requires more than mere<br />

tolerance’. 90<br />

3.4 Discrimination, neutrality and fairness<br />

Under the Equality Act, the claimant was required to show that the<br />

school’s Code unfairly discriminated against her on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

religion or culture. The school argued that in this case there was no<br />

comparator, no group relative to which Sunali received inferior<br />

treatment. The location <strong>of</strong> the appropriate comparator was the<br />

subject <strong>of</strong> disagreement between the judgements <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ and<br />

O’Regan J. Langa CJ identified the appropriate comparator as ‘those<br />

learners whose sincere religious or cultural beliefs or practices are not<br />

compromised by the Code, as compared to those whose beliefs are<br />

uncompromised’. He found that ‘the Code has a disparate impact’ 91<br />

on certain religions and cultures, the members <strong>of</strong> which are<br />

disproportionately burdened or incommoded relative to others who<br />

are not members. He took to view that the school’s Code<br />

is not neutral, but enforces mainstream and historically privileged forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> adornment, such as ear studs which also involve the piercing <strong>of</strong> a body<br />

part, at the expense <strong>of</strong> minority and historically excluded forms. 92<br />

This again is consistent with Young’s ‘politics <strong>of</strong> difference’,<br />

according to which<br />

88 Young (n 84 above) 119.<br />

89<br />

Prince (n 6 above) para 85. Langa CJ here paraphrases the Canadian Supreme<br />

Court in Multani v Commission Scolaire Marguerite-Bourgeoys [2006] SCC 6 para<br />

79 (Multani): ‘A total prohibition against wearing a kirpan to school undermines<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> this religious symbol and sends students the message that some<br />

religious practices do not merit the same protection as others’.<br />

90 n 84 above, 156.<br />

91<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 44.<br />

92 As above.


284 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

blindness to difference disadvantages groups whose experience, culture<br />

and socialised capacities differ from those <strong>of</strong> privileged groups [who] ...<br />

implicitly define the standards according to which all will be measured.<br />

Because their privilege involves not recognising those standards as<br />

culturally and experientially specific, the ideal <strong>of</strong> common humanity in<br />

which all can participate without regard to race, gender, religion or<br />

sexuality poses as neutral and universal. 93<br />

For O’Regan J, by contrast,<br />

the correct comparator is those learners who have been afforded an<br />

exemption to allow them to pursue their cultural or religious practices,<br />

as against those learners who are denied exemption, like the learner in<br />

this case. 94<br />

As indicated above, the school had in the past granted exemptions to<br />

permit the wearing <strong>of</strong> red ‘Lakshmi strings’ and <strong>of</strong> hide bracelets to<br />

mark respect after a funeral, 95 both <strong>of</strong> which were ‘associative<br />

cultural or religious practices’. According to O’Regan J, the unfairness<br />

lay in the school’s inconsistency in exempting certain practices but<br />

not others without adequate justification <strong>of</strong> the differential<br />

treatment. Whereas Langa CJ asserted that the Code was nonneutral,<br />

O’Regan J appears to have accepted that the Code was<br />

neutral: she stated that ‘the Code is entitled to establish neutral rules<br />

to govern the school uniform’. 96<br />

Which group is the correct comparator? The answer, I think, is<br />

that both groups are. Langa CJ was certainly correct that the<br />

unfairness that justifies the granting <strong>of</strong> an exemption is present when<br />

a rule imposes a burden on members <strong>of</strong> a minority or vulnerable<br />

cultural or religious group to which others are not subject. On the<br />

other hand, O’Regan J is right that the granting <strong>of</strong> exemptions to<br />

permit certain religious and cultural practices allows those who have<br />

been denied exemptions to claim that they have been unfairly<br />

treated. Since both judges found that there had been discrimination,<br />

does it matter which comparator is to be considered the appropriate<br />

one? It does: on O’Regan J’s approach, had the school refused to grant<br />

any exemptions there would have been no discrimination and the<br />

claim would have failed. By contrast, Langa CJ would have still found<br />

the rule to be discriminatory and the claim would still have been<br />

successful. The correct approach would be to hold that both groups<br />

are appropriate comparators and both can give rise to claims for<br />

exemptions.<br />

93 n 84 above, 164.<br />

94 Pillay (n 6 above) para 164.<br />

95<br />

Pillay (n 6 above) para 170.<br />

96 Pillay (n 6 above) para 165.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 285<br />

Given the disagreement between Langa CJ and O’Regan J about<br />

whether the Code is neutral, who is right? Langa CJ’s determination<br />

that the code is non-neutral is preferable, comporting as it<br />

substantially does with the approach <strong>of</strong> the minority <strong>of</strong> the US<br />

Supreme Court in Goldman v Weinberger (Goldman). 97 In that case,<br />

an orthodox Jewish rabbi serving as a psychologist in the military<br />

claimed an exemption from an air force regulation that proscribed the<br />

wearing <strong>of</strong> headgear indoors. The military’s uniform dress regulation<br />

permitted the wearing <strong>of</strong> rings and the wearing <strong>of</strong> religious symbols<br />

underneath military uniforms. This allowed latitude for Christians to<br />

wear articles with religious significance. The minority in Goldman<br />

were prepared to grant the exemption in part because ‘the<br />

accommodation <strong>of</strong> items Christians were likely to wear contrasted<br />

disturbingly with the rigidity <strong>of</strong> the rule that disfavoured Orthodox<br />

Jews and other minorities’. 98<br />

The School argued that if an exemption were to be granted, then<br />

‘some <strong>of</strong> the girls might feel that it is unfair’. 99 Langa CJ, with whom<br />

O’Regan J agreed on this point, determined, correctly and<br />

consistently with the Canadian Supreme Court in its recent Multani<br />

decision, 100 that once the rule is found to be discriminatory the<br />

appropriate response to complaints from those not covered by the<br />

exemption is to explain to them that the Code does not impose a<br />

burden <strong>of</strong> cultural denial that is comparable to the burden imposed<br />

on them in requiring them to forgo a fashion item. 101<br />

3.5 Deference<br />

The school raised the argument that deference should be accorded to<br />

the pr<strong>of</strong>essional judgements <strong>of</strong> the school authorities regarding school<br />

uniforms. Langa CJ responded by conceding that ‘the Court must give<br />

due weight to the opinion <strong>of</strong> experts, including school authorities,<br />

who are particularly knowledgeable in their area’. He insisted,<br />

however, that courts ‘are best qualified and constitutionally<br />

mandated’ to answer the question ‘whether the fundamental right to<br />

equality has been violated, which in turn requires the Court to<br />

determine what obligations the school bears to accommodate<br />

diversity reasonably’. 102 ‘The Court cannot abdicate its duty by<br />

deferring to the school’s view on the requirements <strong>of</strong> fairness’ since<br />

97 475 US 503 (1986).<br />

98 Greenawalt (n 4 above) 165.<br />

99 Pillay (n 6 above) para 103.<br />

100 n 89 above, para 104.<br />

101 As O’Regan J observed, ‘A school is an ideal place to educate other learners about<br />

the difference between fashion and cultural practices, and should an exemption<br />

for nose-studs be granted, a school would be obliged to furnish such education to<br />

its learners’ (Pillay (n 6 above) para 172).<br />

102 Pillay (n 6 above) para 81.


286 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

to do so would be to make the school a judge in its own case. 103 Langa<br />

CJ referred approvingly to the fact that the Code had been ‘devised<br />

after extensive consultation with parents, educators, staff and<br />

learners’, but decided that the fact <strong>of</strong> consultation ‘does not<br />

immunise the resultant decisions ... from constitutional scrutiny and<br />

review’ since<br />

many individual communities still retain historically unequal power<br />

relations or historically skewed population groups which may make it<br />

more likely that local decisions will infringe on the rights <strong>of</strong> disfavoured<br />

groups. 104<br />

Langa CJ’s view <strong>of</strong> judicial deference is correct. 105 A moderate<br />

degree <strong>of</strong> deference should be accorded school authorities because<br />

they possess specialist expertise. The Court should allow ample scope<br />

for the development <strong>of</strong> policy and the promulgation <strong>of</strong> regulations by<br />

the school administration, recognising that rights can sometimes<br />

properly give way to contrary public needs, such as the creation <strong>of</strong><br />

conditions for effective education. Yet the Court, as ultimate<br />

authority on questions <strong>of</strong> right, should arrive at its own independent<br />

evaluation, rather than accepting the view <strong>of</strong> the school authorities.<br />

Brennan J took this view in Goldman, criticising the majority for<br />

deferring unduly to the judgement <strong>of</strong> the military. 106<br />

3.6 A slippery slope? The end <strong>of</strong> school uniforms?<br />

Langa CJ rejected an objection that to grant an exemption in this case<br />

would result in a ‘slippery slope scenario’, an opening <strong>of</strong> the<br />

floodgates to endless claims for accommodation for, amongst other<br />

things ‘dreadlocks, body piercings, tattoos and loincloths’. 107 On this<br />

objection, once nose studs have been accommodated, fairness<br />

requires that other claims for exemptions be granted, resulting in the<br />

erosion <strong>of</strong> the uniformity <strong>of</strong> school uniforms to the point that there<br />

would be a uniform in name only. This argument has no merit, Langa<br />

CJ claimed, since, first, exemptions must only be considered for<br />

‘bona fide religious and cultural practices’. 108 Second, claims for<br />

exemptions may be refused on the grounds that ‘a practice may be so<br />

insignificant to the person concerned that it does not require a<br />

departure from the ordinary uniform’. 109 Third, schools could refuse<br />

103 Pillay (n 6 above) para 81.<br />

104 Pillay (n 6 above) para 83.<br />

105 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> what constitutes appropriate deference in the context <strong>of</strong><br />

rights adjudication, see P Lenta ‘Judicial deference and rights’ (2006) Tydskrif vir<br />

Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 456.<br />

106 n 97 above, 515.<br />

107 Pillay (n 6 above) para 107.<br />

108 As above.<br />

109 Pillay (n 6 above) para 114.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 287<br />

to accommodate a particular practice ‘if accommodating [it] would<br />

impose an unreasonable burden on the School’: 110 if the practice will<br />

‘create a real possibility <strong>of</strong> disruption ... threaten[ing] academic<br />

standards or discipline’. 111 Finally, as to the extent that other<br />

cultural and religious practices are exempted from the Code, ‘that is<br />

something to be celebrated, not feared’ since ‘the display <strong>of</strong> religion<br />

and public is ... a pageant <strong>of</strong> diversity which will enrich our schools<br />

and in turn our country’. 112<br />

Langa CJ’s response accords with that <strong>of</strong> Brennan J in Goldman.<br />

Brennan J stated that each claim would have to be evaluated against<br />

the reasons for refusing it. He added that the court could defer to<br />

‘dress and grooming rules that have a reasoned basis in, for example,<br />

functional utility, health and safety considerations and the goal <strong>of</strong><br />

polished, pr<strong>of</strong>essional appearance’. 113 Claims for accommodation<br />

could justifiably be refused in the case <strong>of</strong> departures from the<br />

uniform that infringed these requirements.<br />

Despite the US Supreme Court’s recent characterisation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

‘slippery slope’ argument as ‘the classic rejoinder <strong>of</strong> bureaucrats<br />

throughout history’, 114 the raising <strong>of</strong> this concern is not always an<br />

indication <strong>of</strong> bad faith. It may instead reflect ‘the reasonable belief<br />

that the proliferating recognition <strong>of</strong> difference might itself generate<br />

an accelerating and potentially destabilising realignment <strong>of</strong><br />

institutional practices’. 115 Langa CJ was adamant that the decision in<br />

Pillay ‘does not abolish school uniforms’. 116 Yet, given the broadness<br />

<strong>of</strong> culture, or as O’Regan J put it, the fact that ‘all human beings have<br />

a culture’, 117 the potential number <strong>of</strong> claims for accommodation that<br />

may have to be granted consistently with the jurisprudence in Pillay<br />

may be high. Langa J mentions turbans, yarmulkes and<br />

headscarves, 118 all <strong>of</strong> which schools would have to accommodate.<br />

What about dreadlocks? Provided they were tied up, they may have to<br />

be accommodated as an expression <strong>of</strong> Rastafarian culture or religion.<br />

Body piercings and tattoos? Perhaps: tattoos, for example, may<br />

express not only the faith <strong>of</strong> Coptic Christians but also Maori culture.<br />

110 Pillay (n 6 above) para 107.<br />

111 Pillay (n 6 above) para 114.<br />

112 Pillay (n 6 above) para 107.<br />

113 Goldman (n 97 above) 519.<br />

114 Gonzalez (n 37 above) 15.<br />

115 A Sarat & R Berkowitz ‘Disorderly differences: Recognition, accommodation, and<br />

American law’ (1994) 6 Yale Journal <strong>of</strong> Law and the Humanities 285 288.<br />

116 Pillay (n 6 above) para 114.<br />

117 Pillay (n 6 above) para 150.<br />

118 Pillay (n 6 above) para 106.


288 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

Kilts? A pupil <strong>of</strong> Scottish extraction may insist on wearing a kilt at<br />

school and it is not clear, on the approach outlined in Pillay, that<br />

schools could refuse to grant this exemption. 119 It is difficult to<br />

predict how many claims for religious and cultural accommodation<br />

are likely to be pressed, 120 but were all the claims that are required<br />

to be accommodated in accordance with the approach in Pillay to be<br />

brought, school uniforms, although they might not be abolished,<br />

would be far less uniform. In that case, the educational objectives<br />

promoted by uniforms may be to some extent undermined. This is the<br />

price that may have to be paid for extending the obligation to<br />

accommodate to include optional cultural practices.<br />

A claim that could be refused on the grounds <strong>of</strong> the approach in<br />

Pillay is a claim for an exemption to permit a pupil to carry a weapon.<br />

In Multani, the Canadian Supreme Court — adopting an approach to<br />

religious exemptions strongly resembling the approach <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court in Pillay to religious and cultural exemptions —<br />

decided that the ‘duty to make reasonable accommodation’ 121<br />

obliged a school to accommodate a Sikh pupil’s demand for an<br />

exemption to permit him to wear a kirpan, a metal dagger, which Sikh<br />

men believe themselves to be religiously obligated to wear at all<br />

times. Despite accepting that a kirpan is a bladed weapon, the<br />

Supreme Court held that the increased risk <strong>of</strong> violence introduced by<br />

granting the exemption to the school’s code de vie was acceptably<br />

low, provided the pupil wore the kirpan sealed and sewn inside his<br />

clothing. To refuse an accommodation in this case, the Court<br />

(consistently with the view <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court in Pillay)<br />

added, would be to ‘stifle the promotion <strong>of</strong> values such as<br />

multiculturalism, diversity and the development <strong>of</strong> an educational<br />

culture respectful <strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong> others’. 122<br />

The Constitutional Court would be unlikely to grant an exemption<br />

for a kirpan (and mistaken were it to do so), since South Africa is ‘an<br />

119<br />

It might be contended in response that South Indian/Hindu culture is a more<br />

authentically South African culture than Scots Presbyterian culture, but that<br />

would be mistaken. While Hindu South Indians arrived in South Africa as<br />

indentured labourers from the 1860s onwards, the Scots began to arrive before<br />

that. Two aspects <strong>of</strong> Scots culture are relevant here. First, it is strongly religious.<br />

During the mid nineteenth century, a group <strong>of</strong> Scots who were ministers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Presbyterian Church <strong>of</strong> Scotland helped to revitalise the Dutch Reformed Church.<br />

Secondly, it is difficult to imagine a more forceful and nationalistic assertion <strong>of</strong><br />

culture than that characteristic <strong>of</strong> the Scots.<br />

120<br />

The granting <strong>of</strong> an exemption by the US Supreme Court in Yoder did not result in<br />

an avalanche <strong>of</strong> claims. See W Galston Liberal pluralism (2002) 121: ‘The limited<br />

public education accommodation for the Old Order Amish endorsed by the<br />

Supreme Court in Wisconsin v Yoder a quarter <strong>of</strong> a century ago has not lead to an<br />

escalation <strong>of</strong> faith-based demands. Indeed few other groups have sought similar<br />

treatment for themselves’.<br />

121<br />

Multani (n 89 above) para 53.<br />

122 Multani (n 89 above) para 78.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 289<br />

exceptionally, possibly uniquely, violent society’, 123 whereas Canada<br />

is one <strong>of</strong> the least violent countries in the world. Yet its probable<br />

refusal to do so would not necessarily reflect a difference in approach<br />

between the Constitutional Court and the Canadian Supreme Court:<br />

the social contexts <strong>of</strong> Canada and South Africa are sufficiently<br />

different as to result in the same approach to accommodations<br />

leading in the case <strong>of</strong> weapons to different outcomes.<br />

4 Accommodating dress and adornment: A<br />

comparative analysis<br />

The jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> the UK House <strong>of</strong> Lords indicates that it may be<br />

prepared, in certain circumstances, to grant an exemption to permit<br />

the wearing <strong>of</strong> religious clothing and adornments, although its<br />

approach suggests that it is less solicitous towards claims for<br />

exemptions to school uniforms for religious dress than its South<br />

African and Canadian counterparts. In Begum, 124 the House <strong>of</strong> Lords<br />

rejected a claim for a religious exemption from a Muslim pupil, who<br />

wished to wear not only a headscarf (hijab), but also a jilbab, a long<br />

garment the purpose <strong>of</strong> which is to hide the contours <strong>of</strong> the female<br />

body. Despite accepting that the application was motivated by a<br />

sincere belief on the part <strong>of</strong> the pupil that she was under a religious<br />

obligation to wear a jilbab, the Court denied the claim, for the<br />

following reasons: first, the current school uniform’s dispensation for<br />

Muslim pupils was designed in consultation with Muslim authorities to<br />

meet their religious requirements; second, the pupil could have<br />

transferred to another school in the area that permitted the wearing<br />

<strong>of</strong> a jilbab; 125 third, deference — a ‘margin <strong>of</strong> appreciation’ 126 —<br />

should be accorded to the decision <strong>of</strong> Parliament to allow schools to<br />

make their own decisions about uniforms 127 and, fourth, to grant this<br />

exemption might encourage undesirable religious extremism and<br />

might place undue pressure on Muslim female pupils who did not wish<br />

to wear the jilbab to do so. 128<br />

Faced with a case with similar facts to those in Begum, the<br />

jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court would seem to commit it to<br />

123 A Altbeker A country at war with itself: South Africa’s crisis <strong>of</strong> crime (2007) 12.<br />

124 R (on the application <strong>of</strong> Begum) v Headteacher and Governors <strong>of</strong> Denbigh High<br />

School [2006] UKHL 15 (Begum).<br />

125 Begum (n 124 above) paras 25 & 89.<br />

126 Begum (n 124 above) para 62.<br />

127 Begum (n 124 above) para 34.<br />

128 Begum (n 124 above) para 65.


290 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

granting an exemption to permit the pupil to wear a jilbab. 129 Langa<br />

CJ rejected the argument that the Court should substantially defer to<br />

the judgement <strong>of</strong> the school authorities about whether an exemption<br />

would interfere with the effective running <strong>of</strong> the school. He also<br />

disputed the contention that the pupil could have relocated to<br />

another school that permitted the practice, since this would fail to<br />

celebrate diversity, and ‘would be to marginalise religions and<br />

cultures’. 130 The Constitutional Court is likely to take the view, as far<br />

as claims for accommodation are concerned, that there is only one<br />

sensible stopping point: the point at which religious and cultural<br />

practices violate the rights <strong>of</strong> others or interfere with the business <strong>of</strong><br />

the school. So, for example, the Constitutional Court should not only<br />

refuse to accommodate weapons in schools; it should also agree with<br />

Silber J in Headteachers and Governors <strong>of</strong> Y School 131 that it is not<br />

reasonable to expect a school to accommodate a niqab, a veil which<br />

covers the entire face and head save for the eyes, which would<br />

frustrate educational objectives by impeding identification <strong>of</strong> and<br />

communication with pupils. 132<br />

129 Begum was followed in Playfoot (a minor), R (on the application <strong>of</strong>) v Millais<br />

School [2007] EWHC 1698 (Admin) (16 July 2007), in which the High Court refused<br />

to grant an exemption to permit a female pupil to wear a silver ring that<br />

expressed her commitment, as a Christian, to remaining sexually abstinent prior<br />

to marriage. The Court rejected the claim primarily on the grounds that the<br />

wearing <strong>of</strong> the ring at school was not required by her religion unlike other<br />

practices that the school had accommodated, such as the wearing <strong>of</strong> headscarves<br />

by Muslim pupils and the wearing <strong>of</strong> Kara bangles by Sikh girls. Since the<br />

Constitutional Court has emphasised that the duty <strong>of</strong> reasonable accommodation<br />

includes optional as well as mandatory practices, it may well be that it would<br />

grant an exemption in these circumstances. The reasoning in Playfoot is anyway<br />

inconsistent with that <strong>of</strong> the House <strong>of</strong> Lords in Williamson, in which it was stated<br />

that a perceived obligation is not a ‘prerequisite to manifestation <strong>of</strong> a belief in<br />

practice’ (n 20 above, para 33).<br />

130 Pillay (n 6 above) para 92.<br />

131 R (on the application <strong>of</strong> X) v Headteachers and Governors <strong>of</strong> Y School [2007]<br />

EWCH 298 (Admin); [2007] HRLR 20 (QBD (Admin)).<br />

132 Two points about this. First, although the Court would probably agree with Silber<br />

J’s conclusion, it would decline to follow the reasoning <strong>of</strong> Silber J, who, adopting<br />

the approach <strong>of</strong> the House <strong>of</strong> Lords in Begum, declined to grant the exemption on<br />

the grounds that deference is due to school authorities and because the pupil<br />

concerned could have transferred to another school which permits the wearing <strong>of</strong><br />

a niqab. Secondly, if the school is acting reasonably by declining a pupil’s request<br />

that she be permitted to wear a niqab, a school’s decision to refuse to permit a<br />

teacher to wear a niqab is equally reasonable, since a teacher’s obscuring <strong>of</strong> her<br />

face and mouth makes non-verbal communication more difficult and, as a result,<br />

may impede effective communication between the teacher and pupils. The UK<br />

Employment Appeal Tribunal took this view in Azmi v Kirklees Metropolitan<br />

Borough Council [2007] UKEAT/0009/07 (30 March 2007). Of course, non-verbal<br />

communication might be less important with older learners. See, for example,<br />

Nussbaum (n 8 above) 350.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 291<br />

The US Supreme Court has yet to be confronted with a claim for<br />

an exemption from school uniform regulations. Would it be likely to<br />

grant a claim for an exemption to permit religious clothing and<br />

adornments? 133 In Smith, 134 the US Supreme Court held that, other<br />

than in exceptional circumstances, there is no constitutional<br />

requirement to grant religious exemptions from facially neutral laws<br />

which do not have the purpose, but may have the incidental effect,<br />

<strong>of</strong> burdening the practice <strong>of</strong> religion. Post-Smith, a facially neutral<br />

school uniform policy, if fairly administered, would be<br />

constitutionally valid. Nevertheless, as the Supreme Court stated in a<br />

subsequent decision, Church <strong>of</strong> Lukumi Babalu Aye, 135 the regulation<br />

would have to be applied in a religiously neutral manner. If<br />

exemptions are made for some religious groups but not for others, as<br />

they were in Pillay, they may be held unconstitutional. Moreover, the<br />

regulation might be challenged, as in Pillay, under a ‘hybrid’ claim<br />

that it infringes not only religious liberty but also freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

expression. The US Supreme Court in Smith indicated that hybrid<br />

claims might be treated differently from free exercise claims standing<br />

alone. 136 The claim that the wearing <strong>of</strong> clothing and adornments<br />

constitutes expressive conduct appears strong. In Pillay, Langa J<br />

found that the ban on nose studs under the school uniform infringed<br />

the pupil’s right to freedom <strong>of</strong> expression. 137 And in her concurring<br />

judgement in Begum, Baroness Hale <strong>of</strong> Richmond contended that a<br />

woman wearing a hijab ‘may have chosen the garment as a mark <strong>of</strong><br />

her defiant political identity’ and may be engaging ‘in a highly<br />

complex autonomous act intended to use the resources <strong>of</strong> the<br />

133 See J Mikhail ‘The free exercise <strong>of</strong> religion: An American perspective’ in M<br />

Mahlman & H Rottleuthner (eds) Ein Neuer Kampf Der Religionen? Staat, Recht<br />

und Religïose Toleranz (2006) 271.<br />

134 n 25 above.<br />

135 n 1 above.<br />

136 n 25 above, 881 - 882. The category <strong>of</strong> the ‘hybrid’ claim, though difficult to<br />

interpret, has resulted in some successful claims, particularly in areas that link<br />

free speech to religious liberty. See, for example, Chalifoux v New Caney Ind<br />

School Dist, 976 F Supp 659 (SC Tex 1997).<br />

137 n 6 above, para 94.


292 Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform regulations<br />

tradition both to change and to preserve it’. 138<br />

5 Conclusion<br />

The relative levels <strong>of</strong> protection for religious liberty afforded by the<br />

South African Constitutional Court, the UK House <strong>of</strong> Lords, the<br />

Canadian Supreme Court and the US Supreme Court in response to<br />

claims for exemptions from school uniforms may now be assessed. The<br />

highest level <strong>of</strong> protection is provided by the South African<br />

Constitutional Court and the Canadian Supreme Court. These courts<br />

are most accommodating <strong>of</strong> clothing and adornment practices <strong>of</strong><br />

religious (and in the case <strong>of</strong> the South African Constitutional Court,<br />

cultural) significance, emphasising the values <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism and<br />

diversity.<br />

The UK House <strong>of</strong> Lords <strong>of</strong>fers a lower level <strong>of</strong> protection for<br />

religious claimants. It is more deferential to the legislature, on the<br />

grounds <strong>of</strong> a Dworkinian distinction between policy and principle (as<br />

in Williamson), and to school authorities, on the basis <strong>of</strong> their<br />

specialist expertise (as in Begum). It takes the view that pupils should<br />

as far as possible accommodate themselves to the relevant regulation<br />

by, for example, transferring where reasonably possible to another<br />

school that would permit the practice for which protection is being<br />

sought. By contrast, the South African Constitutional Court and the<br />

Canadian Supreme Court’s emphasis on affirming culturally and<br />

religiously differentiated identities suggests a stance in accordance<br />

with which pupils are to a lesser extent required to accommodate<br />

themselves to the regulation. The approach <strong>of</strong> the House <strong>of</strong> Lords in<br />

Begum reflects an anxiety about religious extremism which is<br />

pervasive in post 9/11 and 7/7 UK but not in the different<br />

138 n 124 above, para 94. The US Supreme Court has not yet addressed the issue <strong>of</strong><br />

whether school uniforms violate the right to freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, but lower<br />

courts have decided that school uniforms do not violate the right to free speech.<br />

The US Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals upheld the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> a mandatory public school<br />

uniform policy in a Louisiana school district (Canady v Bossier Parish School<br />

Board, 240 F 3d 437, US Ct App 6th Circuit (2001)). The court found that<br />

‘improving the educational process’ was an important and substantial<br />

government interest. In upholding the imposition <strong>of</strong> mandatory uniforms, the<br />

court noted that the school’s policy was ‘viewpoint-neutral’. Most importantly <strong>of</strong><br />

all for the present case, the Court went on to find that<br />

[t[he School Board's purpose for enacting the uniform policy is to increase<br />

test scores and reduce disciplinary problems throughout the school<br />

system. This purpose is in no way related to the suppression <strong>of</strong> student<br />

speech. Although students are restricted from wearing clothing <strong>of</strong> their<br />

choice at school, students remain free to wear what they want after<br />

school hours. Students may still express their views through other<br />

mediums during the school day. The uniform requirement does not bar<br />

the important ‘personal intercommunication among students’ necessary<br />

to an effective educational process.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 293<br />

environment <strong>of</strong> South Africa: 139 the House <strong>of</strong> Lords’s concern about<br />

the prospect <strong>of</strong> undesirable extremism and the potential for moderate<br />

Muslims to become radicalised is not even engaged with in Pillay,<br />

despite being raised in the school’s Heads <strong>of</strong> Argument. The lowest<br />

level <strong>of</strong> protection is that provided by the US Supreme Court, which<br />

will in most cases decline to grant exemptions to facially neutral state<br />

laws and local regulations, including school uniform regulations.<br />

139 JM Coetzee Diary <strong>of</strong> a bad year (2007) 122 describes South Africa as a country in<br />

which ‘Islamist extremism still takes a lowly place on the list <strong>of</strong> public concerns’.


THE CASE FOR RELIGIOUS INCLUSIVISM<br />

AND THE JUDICIAL RECOGNITION OF<br />

RELIGIOUS ASSOCIATIONAL RIGHTS:<br />

A RESPONSE TO LENTA<br />

* Barrister & Solicitor, Executive Director, Centre for Cultural Renewal (Ottawa,<br />

Canada). Research Associate, SAIFAC, Johannesburg. Research Fellow, Faculty <strong>of</strong><br />

Law, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Free State, Bloemfontein. I would like to acknowledge the<br />

contributions and suggestions made to this article from those who attended the<br />

Constitutional Court Review Symposium — sponsored by the South African<br />

Institute for Advanced Constitutional, International and Human Rights Law,<br />

Constitutional Law <strong>of</strong> South Africa and the Konrad Adenauer Stiftung — in August<br />

2008. I would be remiss if I did not single out the Executive Director <strong>of</strong> SAIFAC,<br />

Theunis Roux, for his encouragement. The expert, substantive editorial<br />

interventions <strong>of</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, and SAIFAC Senior Research<br />

Fellow, Stuart Woolman, have significantly improved this work. Justice Laurie<br />

Ackermann, as always, has been an unstinting source <strong>of</strong> support and helpful<br />

insights. In addition, I have benefited from discussions with Shaun de Freitas<br />

(Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor) Department <strong>of</strong> Constitutional Law and Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Law,<br />

Faculty <strong>of</strong> Law, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Free State: he generously shared with me his<br />

own unpublished paper on Pillay. Errors and omissions remain the author’s alone.<br />

295<br />

Iain T Benson *<br />

The idea <strong>of</strong> culture derived from anthropology, a discipline which<br />

studied the encapsulated exotic, is no longer appropriate. There are no<br />

longer (if there ever were) single cultures in any country, polity or legal<br />

system, but many. Cultures are complex conversations within any social<br />

formation. These conversations have many voices. 1<br />

1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

Patrick Lenta, in his comment on Pillay and in earlier work, 2 has done<br />

South African jurisprudence a great service by forcing us to attend to<br />

the complexity <strong>of</strong> cultures and the problems associated with the<br />

1 M Chanock ‘Human rights and cultural branding: Who speaks and how’ in A An-<br />

Na’im (ed) Cultural transformation and human rights in Africa (2002) 41. See also<br />

S Benhabib The claims <strong>of</strong> culture: Equality and diversity in the global era (2002)<br />

2<br />

3-9.<br />

See P Lenta ‘Cultural and religious accommodations to school uniform<br />

regulations’ (‘School uniforms’) (2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 259 ‘Muslim<br />

headscarves in schools and in the workplace’ (2007) 124 South African Law<br />

Journal 296 (‘Headscarves’) and ‘Religious liberty and cultural accommodation’<br />

(2005) 122 South African Law Journal 352 363-371 (‘Accommodation’).


296 A response to Lenta<br />

accommodation <strong>of</strong> religious belief and practice in constitutional<br />

democracies. The usefulness <strong>of</strong> his work extends beyond South<br />

Africa’s borders. Questions <strong>of</strong> religious (and cultural) accommodation<br />

are on the front burner in many other constitutional democracies.<br />

This reply focuses on a narrow set <strong>of</strong> questions that fall within the<br />

framework Lenta and others have constructed for discussions about<br />

the relationship between religion and the State. First, I want to<br />

suggest that: (a) commentators and courts alike reflexively invoke a<br />

rather reductive conception <strong>of</strong> ‘the secular’; (b) that this reductive<br />

conception is generally ‘anti-religious’; and (c) the South African<br />

Constitution ought to be read so as to recognise that religions and<br />

religious practice occupy an important role in the formation <strong>of</strong> public<br />

discourse and the support <strong>of</strong> public institutions. 3 Religions are not<br />

merely to be tolerated: In societies such as South Africa, they ought<br />

to be embraced. Second, I hope to demonstrate that the failure to<br />

take seriously religions and cultural communities with comprehensive<br />

understandings <strong>of</strong> the good, results in a body <strong>of</strong> jurisprudence — in<br />

South Africa and Canada — that privileges individual religious<br />

autonomy over the communal dimension <strong>of</strong> rights to religious freedom<br />

and practice.<br />

2 The problem <strong>of</strong> single cultures or<br />

‘convergence liberalism’<br />

John Gray and others have <strong>of</strong> late suggested that the concept <strong>of</strong> a<br />

‘single culture’ or a ‘one-size fits all’ conception <strong>of</strong> the public sphere<br />

hides illiberal strains <strong>of</strong> liberalism implicitly committed to an<br />

endorsement <strong>of</strong> ‘convergence’. Gray has described the two main<br />

approaches to liberalism in relation to pluralism as follows:<br />

Liberalism contains two philosophies. In one, toleration is justified as a<br />

means to truth. In this view, toleration is an instrument <strong>of</strong> rational<br />

consensus, and a diversity <strong>of</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> life is endured in the faith that it is<br />

destined to disappear. In the other, toleration is valued as a condition <strong>of</strong><br />

peace, and divergent ways <strong>of</strong> living are welcomed as marks <strong>of</strong> diversity<br />

in the good life. The first conception supports an ideal <strong>of</strong> ultimate<br />

convergence on values, the latter an ideal <strong>of</strong> modus vivendi. Liberalism's<br />

future lies in turning its face away from the ideal <strong>of</strong> rational consensus<br />

and looking instead to modus vivendi.<br />

3 These readings <strong>of</strong> ‘secularism’ may appear to some to be variant readings.<br />

However, they are consistent with the meaning <strong>of</strong> the neologism coined by<br />

George Jacob Holyoake. While others may use the term in a way that suggests<br />

that secularism is religion-friendly and consistent with the contours <strong>of</strong> every<br />

liberal democracy, I think it important to emphasise the <strong>of</strong>ten aggressive strategy<br />

<strong>of</strong> religious exclusion and marginalisation that occurs in many ‘secular’ liberal<br />

democracies (eg, France).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 297<br />

The predominant liberal view <strong>of</strong> toleration sees it as a means to a<br />

universal civilisation. If we give up this view, and welcome a world that<br />

contains many ways <strong>of</strong> life and regimes, we will have to think afresh<br />

about human rights and democratic government. We will refashion these<br />

inheritances to serve a different liberal philosophy. We will come to<br />

think <strong>of</strong> human rights as convenient articles <strong>of</strong> peace, whereby<br />

individuals and communities with conflicting values and interest may<br />

consent to coexist. 4<br />

Such a characterisation <strong>of</strong> liberalism would seem to fit Lenta’s notion<br />

that modern liberal states <strong>of</strong>ten assume or propound a false view <strong>of</strong><br />

the public sphere as a ‘neutral’ space. However, Lenta does not<br />

discuss variant interpretations <strong>of</strong> the ‘secular’. And when he tends to<br />

use the term at all, he employs it in a Rawlsian sense 5 to mean the<br />

opposite <strong>of</strong> ‘religious.’ This disjunction is odd (and flawed). For the<br />

Rawlsian characterisation 6 <strong>of</strong> the secular and the religious leads us<br />

toward religious exclusivism — a terminal point largely at odds with<br />

the religious inclusivism <strong>of</strong> Lenta’s analysis. 7<br />

In religiously exclusive liberal discourse, ‘secular’ <strong>of</strong>ten serves as<br />

a synonym for ‘non-religious’. While the two terms are commonly<br />

conflated in this manner, this terminology does not sit comfortably<br />

with Lenta’s call for inclusivity <strong>of</strong> religious believers and what he<br />

describes as a constitutional ‘presumption in favour <strong>of</strong> the<br />

government’s being required to grant an exemption [for religious<br />

belief].’ 8 Such an approach, according to Lenta, means ‘departing<br />

from the principle <strong>of</strong> uniformity.’ 9 On this matter, Lenta and I are in<br />

accord. Further evidence <strong>of</strong> a more nuanced position can be gleaned<br />

from Lenta’s work as a whole. In ‘Headscarf’, Lenta describes the<br />

differences between the French approach to laïcité and the Canadian<br />

approach to multi-cultural inclusion — and then notes that the<br />

Canadian commitment to inclusivism — even with its limitations —<br />

4 J Gray Two faces <strong>of</strong> liberalism (2000) 105. See also PD Lauwers ‘Religion and the<br />

ambiguities <strong>of</strong> liberal pluralism: A Canadian perspective’ (2007) 37 The Supreme<br />

Court Law Review 1.<br />

5 See Lenta ‘School uniforms’ (n 2 above) 264.<br />

6<br />

See J Rawls Political liberalism (1993). For a useful criticism <strong>of</strong> the approach<br />

taken by John Rawls, see PF Campos ‘Secular fundamentalism’ (1994) 94<br />

Columbia Law Review 1814 1825. Campos would have been better served had he<br />

noted that Rawls’ argument is not so much ‘secular’ as ‘secularist’. That is, a<br />

secularist is someone who advocates secularism in the construction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

political domain. See further CL Niles ‘Epistemological nonsense?: The secular/<br />

religious distinction’ (2003) 17 Notre Dame Journal <strong>of</strong> Law, Ethics & Public Policy<br />

561 575 n 50 (criticising Rawls' A theory <strong>of</strong> justice on these same grounds.)<br />

7 Religiously inclusive secularism, which we might better call a ‘religiously inclusive<br />

public sphere’, has been adopted by the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada. The Canadian<br />

jurisprudence shall be discussed in greater detail below. See Chamberlain v<br />

Surrey Sch Dist No 36, [2002] 4 SCR 710 749 (Can) (‘Chamberlain’)<br />

8<br />

Lenta ‘Headscarves’ (n 2 above) 307.<br />

9 As above.


298 A response to Lenta<br />

more closely approximates both the South African position and his<br />

preferred reading <strong>of</strong> South Africa’s basic law. 10<br />

And yet, Lenta remains committed to the proposition that the<br />

Western liberal political tradition is committed to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion<br />

largely as a response to historical religious strife. Of course, there’s<br />

more than a grain <strong>of</strong> truth to that proposition. For one can mark<br />

liberalism and constitutionalism’s true beginning with Locke’s Letter<br />

on Toleration. But if one does mark ‘religious freedom’ as beginning<br />

with this modest, but still revolutionary, tract, then, upon a closer<br />

reading, it is hard to view — from a Lockean perspective — state<br />

neutrality as liberal exclusivism regarding religion, as anything but an<br />

anti-religious ideology. 11<br />

For many liberals, the term ‘secular’ means only ‘non-religious’.<br />

But that mistakes the term’s origins — the saecularum — as a<br />

particular way <strong>of</strong> marking periods <strong>of</strong> time. It is important, therefore,<br />

to stop and to examine what we mean when we use terms such as<br />

‘secular’ or ‘secularism’. The failure to do so can lead, I contend, to<br />

fundamentally anti-religious outcomes. 12 A decision from the<br />

Canadian courts provides an illuminating and instructive account <strong>of</strong><br />

why getting this term right is <strong>of</strong> such great import.<br />

Mr Justice McKenzie, in the unanimous decision <strong>of</strong> the British<br />

Columbia Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal in Chamberlain, stated that:<br />

In my opinion, ‘strictly secular’ in the School Act can only mean pluralist<br />

in the sense that moral positions are to be accorded standing in the<br />

public square irrespective <strong>of</strong> whether the position flows out <strong>of</strong> a<br />

10 The South African approach might well be said to accept a ‘co-operation’ <strong>of</strong><br />

Church and State — rather than any American notion <strong>of</strong> ‘strict separation’. Of<br />

course, anyone au fait with recent American constitutional law knows that the US<br />

Constitution is no longer read as endorsing an absolutely strict separation <strong>of</strong><br />

Church and State. The principles <strong>of</strong> such co-operation and useful distinctions<br />

about avoidance <strong>of</strong> both atheistic and religious theocracy are neatly set out in A<br />

Sachs Protecting human rights in a new South Africa (1990) 43–49. See also S<br />

Woolman ‘Community rights: Language, culture and religion’ in S Woolman et al<br />

(eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2008) ch 58.<br />

11 Something <strong>of</strong> this sort is occurring now in Canada. A Commission made up <strong>of</strong> two<br />

academics — including noted philosopher Charles Taylor — have endorsed ‘open<br />

secularism’ and defined secularism at variance with its history. For comment, see<br />

IT Benson & TL Nguyen ‘The need to re-evaluate the language <strong>of</strong> the secular and<br />

secularism in the quest for fair treatment <strong>of</strong> minorities and belief in Quebec and<br />

Canada today’ 18 December 2007, http://www.culturalrenewal.ca/downloads/<br />

sb_culturalrenewal/BriefTaylorBouchardCommissionDecember2007Fin a.pdf<br />

12<br />

(accessed 12 September 2008).<br />

For more on the history <strong>of</strong> the terms ‘secularism’ and ‘secular’, see IT Benson<br />

‘Considering secularism’ in D Farrow (ed) Recognising religion in a secular<br />

society: Essays in pluralism, religion and public policy (2004) 83–93 and ‘Notes<br />

towards a (re)definition <strong>of</strong> the secular’ (2000) 33 <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> British Columbia<br />

Law Review 519 520–538.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 299<br />

conscience that is religiously informed or not. That meaning <strong>of</strong> strictly<br />

secular is thus pluralist or inclusive in the widest sense ...<br />

No society can be said to be truly free where only those whose morals<br />

are uninfluenced by religion are entitled to participate in deliberations<br />

related to moral issues <strong>of</strong> education in public schools. In my respectful<br />

view ‘strictly secular’ so interpreted could not survive scrutiny in light <strong>of</strong><br />

the freedom <strong>of</strong> conscience and religion guaranteed by section 2 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Charter [conscience and religion] and equality rights guaranteed by<br />

section 15. 13<br />

What is said here about moral positions applies equally to religious<br />

and cultural beliefs in a public school setting such as Pillay. Simply<br />

put, convictions emanating from religious beliefs ought to be at no<br />

disadvantage in terms <strong>of</strong> public respect by comparison to belief sets<br />

that emanate from non-religious convictions. When the case reached<br />

the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada, all nine judges agreed with the<br />

reasoning <strong>of</strong> McKenzie J. ‘Secular’ in Canadian constitutional<br />

jurisprudence embraces a religiously inclusive understanding <strong>of</strong> the<br />

term. 14<br />

Justice Gonthier provides further support for this proposition<br />

when he writes:<br />

In my view, Saunders J [the trial judge] below erred in her assumption<br />

that ‘secular’ effectively meant ‘non-religious’. This is incorrect since<br />

nothing in the Charter, political or democratic theory, or a proper<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> pluralism demands that atheistically based moral<br />

positions trump religiously based moral positions on matters <strong>of</strong> public<br />

policy. I note that the preamble to the Charter itself establishes that ‘<br />

... Canada is founded upon principles that recognise the supremacy <strong>of</strong><br />

God and the rule <strong>of</strong> law’. According to the reasoning espoused by<br />

Saunders J, if one's moral view manifests from a religiously grounded<br />

faith, it is not to be heard in the public square, but if it does not, then it<br />

is publicly acceptable. The problem with this approach is that everyone<br />

has ‘belief’ or ‘faith’ in something, be it atheistic, agnostic or religious.<br />

To construe the ‘secular’ as the realm <strong>of</strong> the ‘unbelief’ is therefore<br />

erroneous. Given this, why, then, should the religiously informed<br />

conscience be placed at a public disadvantage or disqualification? To do<br />

so would be to distort liberal principles in an illiberal fashion and would<br />

provide only a feeble notion <strong>of</strong> pluralism. The key is that people will<br />

disagree about important issues, and such disagreement, where it does<br />

13 Chamberlain v Surrey School Board (2000) 80 BCLR (3d) 181 (CA) (‘Chamberlain’)<br />

at paras 33 & 34, reversing Chamberlain v Surrey School Board (1998) 60 BCLR<br />

(3d) 311 (SC) (emphasis added). For a detailed analysis <strong>of</strong> this decision, see IT<br />

Benson & B Miller ‘Court corrects erroneous understanding <strong>of</strong> the secular and<br />

respects parental rights’ Lex View No. 40.0, available at http://<br />

www.culturalrenewal.ca/qry/page.taf?id=64 (accessed 12 December 2008).<br />

14 Chamberlain (n 7 above) 749. Madam Justice McLachlin, who wrote the decision<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Chamberlain majority, endorsed the reasoning <strong>of</strong> Justice Gonthier on the<br />

correct interpretation <strong>of</strong> ‘secular’.


300 A response to Lenta<br />

not imperil community living, must be capable <strong>of</strong> being accommodated<br />

at the core <strong>of</strong> a modern pluralism [emphasis added]. 15<br />

The approach <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada and the implicit<br />

recognition in Pillay that a public school must accommodate a variety<br />

<strong>of</strong> beliefs (religious or cultural) are at stark variance with the<br />

approaches taken by countries such as France. In France, the public<br />

sphere has generally been stripped <strong>of</strong> all religious accommodation<br />

under the mistaken belief that the removal <strong>of</strong> all religious signifiers is<br />

‘neutral.’ In Pillay, the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa arrived at<br />

a similar conclusion about the place <strong>of</strong> religion in the public sphere as<br />

the Canadian Supreme Court did in Chamberlain. (I would have<br />

preferred, however, a somewhat different characterisation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relationship between the ‘sacred’ and the ‘secular’.) In Fourie, Sachs<br />

J <strong>of</strong>fers the kind <strong>of</strong> careful and nuanced understanding <strong>of</strong> the public<br />

realm as a sphere <strong>of</strong> ‘co-existence’ that is largely on all fours with the<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> religious inclusivism defended here and set out as above in<br />

Chamberlain:<br />

In the open and democratic society contemplated by the Constitution<br />

there must be mutually respectful co-existence between the secular and<br />

the sacred. The function <strong>of</strong> the Court is to recognise the sphere which<br />

each inhabits, not to force the one into the sphere <strong>of</strong> the other ... The<br />

hallmark <strong>of</strong> an open and democratic society is its capacity to<br />

accommodate and manage difference <strong>of</strong> intensely-held world views and<br />

lifestyles in a reasonable and fair manner. The objective <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution is to allow different concepts about the nature <strong>of</strong> human<br />

existence to inhabit the same public realm, and to do so in a manner<br />

that is not mutually destructive and that at the same time enables<br />

government to function in a way that shows equal concern and respect<br />

for all ... It is clear from the above that acknowledgment by the State <strong>of</strong><br />

the right <strong>of</strong> same-sex couples to enjoy the same status, entitlements and<br />

responsibilities as marriage law accords to heterosexual couples is in no<br />

way inconsistent with the rights <strong>of</strong> religious organisations to continue to<br />

refuse to celebrate same-sex marriages. The constitutional claims <strong>of</strong><br />

same-sex couples can accordingly not be negated by invoking the rights<br />

<strong>of</strong> believers to have their religious freedom respected. The two sets <strong>of</strong><br />

interests involved do not collide; they co-exist in a constitutional realm<br />

based on accommodation <strong>of</strong> diversity. 16<br />

A more coherent and accurate way <strong>of</strong> describing what is at issue is to<br />

recognise that religious beliefs and believers are within the public<br />

sphere shared by all. Utilising the secular/sacred dichotomy confuses<br />

the principles at issue. What should be emphasised is the co-operative<br />

relationship — between politics and religion — in the same manner as<br />

15 Chamberlain (n 7 above) para 137 (emphasis added).<br />

16 Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs & Another v Fourie & (Doctors for Life Intenational &<br />

Others, amici curiae); Lesbian and Gay Equality Project & Others v Minister <strong>of</strong><br />

Home Affairs 2006 1 SA 524 (CC) paras 94–98.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 301<br />

the passage correctly notes the co-operation <strong>of</strong> the religious and the<br />

non-religious within ‘the same public realm.’ Unfortunately, the<br />

distinction between the ‘secular’ and the ‘sacred’ at the outset does<br />

little to assist what I take to be South Africa’s religiously inclusive<br />

position. For a religious citizen, the public order <strong>of</strong> the State, too, has<br />

its own sacred dimension. Why? Because everything within creation<br />

flows, in a some sense, from ‘grace’ or ‘the holy’ or ‘the divine’. The<br />

Fourie Court would have done better to describe the public realm as<br />

encompassing believers <strong>of</strong> all sorts — whether atheist, agnostic or<br />

religious — and identifying the role <strong>of</strong> the law, when certain types <strong>of</strong><br />

conflicts emerge, as ordering all relationships according to principles<br />

<strong>of</strong> justice. When most people use the term ‘secular’ they mean<br />

‘public’ — and it would clarify matters greatly if the Constitutional<br />

Court (and courts elsewhere) said so in the future.<br />

Lenta’s use <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Iris Marion Young, 17 which is critical <strong>of</strong><br />

‘the liberal tendency’ (the singular conception <strong>of</strong> ‘liberal’ here is<br />

telling) is good as far as it goes in suggesting a tendency towards the<br />

privatisation and consequent public irrelevance <strong>of</strong> religion within one<br />

strand <strong>of</strong> liberal thought. Any mon<strong>of</strong>ocal view <strong>of</strong> ‘liberal’ fails,<br />

however, to look at different conceptions <strong>of</strong> liberalism and the<br />

conceptions <strong>of</strong> ‘the secular’ themselves that play into such an implicit<br />

or explicit privatisation and marginalisation <strong>of</strong> the religious and the<br />

sacred. Secularism (as an anti-religious movement) goes unanalysed in<br />

Lenta’s work. But the same, it must said, is true <strong>of</strong> Pillay and Fourie<br />

and the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada’s reasoning in Chamberlain.<br />

In discussing Pillay, Lenta does not address how we will try to<br />

accommodate (if we should) non-religious or non-cultural claims<br />

regarding belief sets and practices. Unfair discrimination, by both the<br />

State and private parties, including on the grounds <strong>of</strong> both religion<br />

and culture, is specifically prohibited by sections 9(3) and (4) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution. Section 9(3) reads:<br />

The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against<br />

anyone on one or more grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy,<br />

marital status, ethnic or social origin, colour, sexual orientation, age,<br />

disability, religion, conscience, belief, culture, language and birth.<br />

Pillay focuses exclusively on ‘religion’ and ‘culture’ and concludes<br />

that cultural practices are entitled to the same degree <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional solicitude as religious practices. One would do well to<br />

heed without necessarily agreeing with Justice O’Regan’s concerns<br />

about the extent to which culture and religion differ in terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

17 See Lenta ‘School uniforms’ (n 2 above) 282.


302 A response to Lenta<br />

community and the individual. 18 Two important questions, raised by<br />

Pillay, but not engaged by Lenta, are: (1) can there be ‘a culture <strong>of</strong><br />

one?’ and (2) does the accommodation approach apply if the<br />

objection to wearing <strong>of</strong> a uniform is based simply on ‘belief’ or<br />

‘opinion’?<br />

3 Equating ‘culture’ with religion: Can there be<br />

a ‘religion or culture <strong>of</strong> one?’<br />

If it is true, as John Donne famously observed, that ‘no man is an<br />

island’, 19 then it might be fair to ask if one person can be a culture or<br />

one person’s beliefs a religion. What are the requirements in order for<br />

something to constitute a ‘culture’ or ‘religion’? The judgment in<br />

Pillay does not help us here. Chief Justice Langa’s judgment begins<br />

and ends its analysis with the following ‘brief introduction’:<br />

Without attempting to provide any form <strong>of</strong> definition, religion is<br />

ordinarily concerned with personal faith and belief, while culture<br />

generally relates to traditions and beliefs developed by a community.<br />

However, there will <strong>of</strong>ten be a great deal <strong>of</strong> overlap between the two;<br />

religious practices are frequently informed not only by faith but also by<br />

custom, while cultural beliefs do not develop in a vacuum and may be<br />

based on the community’s underlying religious or spiritual beliefs.<br />

Therefore, while it is possible for a belief or practice to be purely<br />

religious or purely cultural, it is equally possible for it to be both<br />

religious and cultural. 20<br />

A tension always exists between understanding religion in its personal<br />

dimensions and broader communal dimensions. Too great a focus on<br />

the individual’s belief runs the risk <strong>of</strong> trivialising the communal<br />

foundation to which any individual belief is invariably related. It is not<br />

too strong a statement to say that Pillay gets things back to front: The<br />

meaning that an individual draws from a religious belief or a religious<br />

practice is contingent upon the existence <strong>of</strong> a pre-existing religious<br />

community with well-developed tenets <strong>of</strong> belief and practice. Put<br />

differently, in a very important sense, the religious community<br />

creates and nurtures the religious believer. 21 Unfortunately, Pillay<br />

fails to recognise this relationship.<br />

18 KwaZulu-Natal MEC for Education v Pillay 2008 1 SA 474 (CC) (Pillay) paras<br />

141–148. As I expand upon below, Justice O’Regan’s reasons view religion<br />

individualistically and fail to accord religion an appropriate associational<br />

dimension.<br />

19 J Donne ‘Meditation XVII’ in MH Abrams et al (eds) The Norton anthology <strong>of</strong><br />

English literature Vol. 1 (3rd ed, 1974) 1215.<br />

20 Pillay (n 18 above) para 47.<br />

21 S Woolman ‘Freedom <strong>of</strong> association’ in Woolman et al (eds) (n 10 above) ch 44.<br />

See also M Walzer ‘On involuntary association’ in A Gutmann (ed) Freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

association (1998) 64.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 303<br />

Consider this statement from another Constitutional Court<br />

decision on religious faith and culture, a decision referred to in the<br />

most recent Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada decision touching on religious<br />

rights:<br />

For many believers, their relationship with God or creation is central to<br />

all their activities. It concerns their capacity to relate in an intensely<br />

meaningful fashion to their sense <strong>of</strong> themselves, their community and<br />

their universe. For millions in all walks <strong>of</strong> life, religion provides support<br />

and nurture and a framework for individual and social stability and<br />

growth. Religious belief has the capacity to awake concepts <strong>of</strong> selfworth<br />

and human dignity which form the cornerstone <strong>of</strong> human rights. It<br />

affects the believer’s view <strong>of</strong> society and founds the distinction between<br />

right and wrong. 22<br />

The reference both to ‘community’ and ‘social stability’ in this<br />

passage points towards a better framework for locating the right to<br />

religion (and also to culture). For it is precisely in the relationship<br />

between the person and the community that the importance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> religion is best viewed. Social stability, after all, is not<br />

something achieved by the individual. Its achievement is a function <strong>of</strong><br />

the co-ordination <strong>of</strong> action between and among individuals within a<br />

community. Neither Pillay nor the Canadian Supreme Court in<br />

Amselem 23 seem comfortable with affirming this proposition.<br />

But should they be? For example, we recognise many religiously or<br />

culturally sponsored charitable endeavours as public goods. Religious<br />

institutions that promote ‘health care’ or ‘education’ are only<br />

possible because various communities commit themselves to their<br />

realisation and their ongoing maintenance.<br />

In another setting, that <strong>of</strong> whether a privilege should extend to<br />

religious communications in the criminal law area, two justices <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada recognised the wider context and referred<br />

to the following passage with approval:<br />

In a very real sense, then, the value <strong>of</strong> religious confidentiality is the value<br />

to society <strong>of</strong> religion and religious organisations generally. Even from a<br />

purely utilitarian perspective, that value cannot be overstated. Religious<br />

organisations based on claims to unchanging truths are a stabilising<br />

influence in an increasingly fast-paced and atomised society where bonds<br />

<strong>of</strong> community are scarce and worth preserving. Moreover, many provide<br />

22<br />

Christian Education South Africa v Minister <strong>of</strong> Education 2000 4 SA 757 (CC) para<br />

36. See, generally, I Currie & J de Waal The Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights handbook (5th ed 2005)<br />

336–357; P Farlam ‘Freedom <strong>of</strong> religion’ in Woolman et al (eds) (n 10 above) ch<br />

41. See further Bruker v Marcovitz 2007 SCC 54; K Boonstra & IT Benson ‘When<br />

should the courts enforce religious obligations?’ Lex View No 63 (2008), available<br />

at http://www.culturalrenewal.ca/qry/page.taf?id=150 (accessed December 12,<br />

2008).<br />

23 Syndicat Northcrest v Amselem 2004 SCC 47. See discussion in n 28 below.


304 A response to Lenta<br />

needed social services that government is unwilling or unable to provide in<br />

a cost-efficient and humane manner. 24<br />

Religious organisations and their special character (including their<br />

internal rules, employment contracts etc.) would be ignored or<br />

threatened were religious or cultural accommodation limited to the<br />

protection <strong>of</strong> only individual practices or belief sets or if courts adopt<br />

too ready a willingness to scrutinise internal arrangements. Moreover,<br />

the undeniable public benefits <strong>of</strong> these privately funded institutions<br />

are what make these projects <strong>of</strong> interest to the ‘public’. 25 Yet what<br />

is clearly understood in charities law gets overlooked all too<br />

frequently in constitutional dicta. Consider the errant approach <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada in the following passage:<br />

While some provisions in the Constitution involve groups, such as section<br />

93 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution Act 1867 protecting denominational schools and<br />

section 25 <strong>of</strong> the Charter referring to existing aboriginal rights, the<br />

remaining rights and freedoms are individual rights; they are not<br />

concerned with the group as distinct from its members. The group or<br />

organisation is simply a device adopted by individuals to achieve a fuller<br />

realisation <strong>of</strong> individual rights and aspirations. People by merely<br />

combining together, cannot create an entity which has greater<br />

constitutional rights and freedoms than they, as individuals, possess. 26<br />

This position — a standard liberal individualistic approach to<br />

communities — is both epistemologically incorrect and politically<br />

unsound: it gets the ontological priority <strong>of</strong> meaning back to front.<br />

Individuals only come to participate in these institutions because a<br />

community has — in most instances — already produced them and the<br />

meaning that flows from their ongoing reproduction. It is because<br />

communities exist that individuals have anything to choose at all.<br />

Indeed, sections 15, 30 and 31 <strong>of</strong> the South African Constitution<br />

expressly recognise the communal nature <strong>of</strong> these religious and<br />

cultural institutions. When the Constitutional Court is ultimately<br />

faced, again, with questions <strong>of</strong> religious and cultural accommodation<br />

it would do well to recall that these charitable institutions are not run<br />

by an individual but built and supported over time by identifiable<br />

communities. The express legal recognition <strong>of</strong> the ‘public benefits’ <strong>of</strong><br />

many religious and cultural charities points us in the right direction.<br />

A real danger — and not a mere oversight — exists when the<br />

‘individualising tendency’ <strong>of</strong> one strand <strong>of</strong> liberalism is ascendant.<br />

24 R v Gruenke [1991] 3 SCR 263 299-300 per L’Heureux-Dubé J for herself and<br />

Gonthier J concurring with the majority (emphasis added).<br />

25 On the ‘public benefit’ <strong>of</strong> religious charities, see H Picard (ed) The law and<br />

practice relating to charities (3rd ed 1999) 84-116; J Warburton (ed) Tudor on<br />

charities (9th ed 2003) 78-81 and DWM Waters (ed) Waters' law <strong>of</strong> trusts in<br />

Canada (3d ed 2005) 716-745.<br />

26 Public Service Employee Relations Act (Alberta) Ref [1987] 1 SCR 313.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 305<br />

The individualising tendency, I would argue, poses a genuine threat to<br />

the proper recognition <strong>of</strong> religious liberties. Holding the individual<br />

and communitarian dimensions together in theory and in practice is<br />

essential for the very social stability that the Constitutional Court in<br />

Christian Education refers to above. As William Galston notes:<br />

In some measure, religion and liberal policies need each other. Religion<br />

can undergird key liberal values and practices; liberal politics can<br />

protect — and substantially accommodate — the free exercise <strong>of</strong><br />

religion. But this relationship <strong>of</strong> mutual support dissolves if the<br />

respective proponents lose touch with what unites them. Pushed to the<br />

limit, the juridical principles and practices <strong>of</strong> a liberal society tend<br />

inevitably to corrode moralities that rest either on traditional forms <strong>of</strong><br />

social organisation or on the stern requirements <strong>of</strong> revealed religion ...<br />

[L]iberal theorists (and activists) who deny the very existence <strong>of</strong><br />

legitimate public involvement in matters such as family stability, moral<br />

education, and religion are unwittingly undermining the values and<br />

institutions they seek to support. 27<br />

Yet once one recognises the importance religious and cultural rights<br />

have for a society, we still need to define what count as religions and<br />

cultures and ask what are the rules or requirements <strong>of</strong> entrance, exit<br />

and membership (to name but three) for a ‘culture?’ 28 Is something<br />

worthy <strong>of</strong> constitutional protection simply because I say or believe it<br />

is? If, like religion, protection and recognition extend to those things<br />

that are voluntarily chosen as well as obligatory (and what would be<br />

the obligatory aspect <strong>of</strong> ‘a culture <strong>of</strong> one’ except mere assertion <strong>of</strong><br />

the will?), should we be concerned that the important category <strong>of</strong><br />

culture could be thinned out to nothingness, deflated to the point <strong>of</strong><br />

implosion, by lack <strong>of</strong> meaningful definition? If this concern is<br />

accurate, as I think it is, then too broad a conception <strong>of</strong> culture can<br />

have the paradoxical result that in trying to give content to the<br />

27 W Galston Liberal purposes: Goods, virtues, and diversity in the liberal state<br />

(1991) 279.<br />

28 On entrance, membership and exit see Woolman ‘Freedom <strong>of</strong> association’ (note<br />

21 above). See also A Hischmann Exit, voice and loyalty (1970); E Brody<br />

‘Entrance, voice and exit: The constitutional bounds <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> association’<br />

(2002) 35 UC Davis Law Review 821. Though not dealing with associational rights<br />

and focused more on some <strong>of</strong> the other tensions common to Pillay and Amselem,<br />

see a helpful exchange between two Canadian scholars: R Moon ‘Religious<br />

identity and commitment: Syndicat Northcrest v Amselem’ (2005) 29 Supreme<br />

Court Law Review (2d) 201 and DM Brown ‘Neutrality or privilege?: A comment on<br />

religious freedom’ (2005) 29 Supreme Court Law Review (2d) 221.


306 A response to Lenta<br />

concept we actually denude it. 29<br />

I have already contended that turning ‘religion’ into a merely<br />

individually assessed matter can have the damaging effect <strong>of</strong> reducing<br />

and weakening the category. Benjamin Berger has observed that one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the most pr<strong>of</strong>ound implications <strong>of</strong> the relationship between<br />

religious commitment and assessing a contemporary liberal order is<br />

that:<br />

... there is a fundamental, though eminently explicable, shortfall at the<br />

core <strong>of</strong> liberal legal discourse about religious liberties. Religion is not<br />

only what law imagines it to be. Law is blind to critical aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

religion as culture. That being so, even if successful at accommodating<br />

or tolerating what it understands to be religion, aspects <strong>of</strong> religion as<br />

culture remain entirely unattended to and, therefore, unresolved in<br />

their tension with the constitutional rule <strong>of</strong> law. And with this insight we<br />

come to one important part <strong>of</strong> the explanation for why the story we tell<br />

about law and religion has proven so unsatisfactory: law — in whose<br />

29 Thus Pillay could be said to give either insufficient attention to the relationship<br />

between religion and culture and communities (Chief Justice Langa’s judgment)<br />

or too much attention to religion and culture as individual practices (as in Justice<br />

O’Regan’s reasons). A richer examination <strong>of</strong> the communal prerequisites for<br />

religious practice can be found in Taylor v Kurtstag No and Others 2005 1 SA 362<br />

(W). Here, in Judge Malan’s reasons for his judgment, the rules <strong>of</strong> entrance,<br />

membership, exit and excommunication in the context <strong>of</strong> Orthodox Judaism are<br />

taken seriously by the Court. The Canadian Supreme Court has, to date, focused<br />

more on the individual side <strong>of</strong> the religious rights ledger. See Amselem (n 23<br />

above). In this case the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada’s majority stated that religion is<br />

about ‘self-definition and spiritual fulfillment’ (para 39). Amselem collapses the<br />

individual and communitarian dimensions <strong>of</strong> religious practice. Amselem focused<br />

on what might be termed a ‘fringe religious belief’ and held expressly that it was<br />

not necessary to show the practice in question was required by the religion. A<br />

more nuanced reading <strong>of</strong> the judgement, however, shows that since the concern<br />

about delving too far into religious beliefs would involve the courts in an<br />

assessment <strong>of</strong> ‘dogma’ and that would constitute ‘unwarranted intrusions into the<br />

religious affairs <strong>of</strong> the synagogues, churches, mosques, temples and religious<br />

facilities <strong>of</strong> the nation with value-judgment indictments <strong>of</strong> those beliefs that may<br />

be unconventional or not mainstream’ (para 55) the court, as in Pillay, gave<br />

respect to the communitarian dimension but in a round-about and implicit<br />

manner which should have been addressed expressly.. So while the<br />

communitarian aspects <strong>of</strong> Charter protection were insufficiently elucidated, they<br />

clearly informed the decision. See also K Boonstra & I Benson ‘Religion is in the<br />

eye <strong>of</strong> the beholder’ Lex View No 64 [comment on Amselem] available at http://<br />

www.culturalrenewal.ca/qry/page.taf?id=166 (accessed February 23, 2009).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 307<br />

capacity to tolerate, accommodate, and ‘make space’ for cultural<br />

claims we place so much faith — fails to appreciate religion as culture. 30<br />

Pillay and Amselem underscore the need for courts to make express<br />

the proposition that religion acquires meaning through communities<br />

and that religion matters to individuals precisely because they are<br />

(usually) born into communities that give their (religious) lives<br />

meaning. Belief, in the context <strong>of</strong> religion, cannot be rightly<br />

understood as an individual dispositional state. The communal<br />

character <strong>of</strong> religious believers poses strong, but not ultimately<br />

incompatible, challenges to liberal theories grounded in predominantly<br />

individualistic notions <strong>of</strong> autonomy. Liberal judges ought,<br />

in fact, to recognise that communal religious freedom is what enables<br />

many individuals in our society — religious and not — to flourish.<br />

4 Are belief and opinion to be analysed in the<br />

same way as religion and culture?<br />

What becomes <strong>of</strong> the analysis <strong>of</strong> accommodation if a student’s<br />

objection to wearing a uniform or part <strong>of</strong> a uniform is based on<br />

conscience, belief or opinion simpliciter? Since a term such as ‘belief’<br />

is also a protected category, what analytical tools are we to bring to<br />

bear on assessing the importance and bona fides <strong>of</strong> a belief claim that<br />

some aspect <strong>of</strong> uniform wearing is <strong>of</strong>fensive to a student? Are religious<br />

or cultural beliefs elevated forms <strong>of</strong> belief in terms <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

protection? Should religion and culture be considered more weighty<br />

rights than idiosyncratic or individualistic personal beliefs? Given<br />

what I and others have argued about the ‘public benefits’ <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

charities and projects generally, the answer should be ‘yes.’<br />

Lenta mentions the Scottishness <strong>of</strong> kilt wearing as a cultural<br />

practice that might have to be accommodated in light <strong>of</strong> the<br />

reasoning in Pillay. One wonders how and whether a belief sheltered<br />

by, say, iconoclastic or eccentric expressions <strong>of</strong> individual will, but<br />

nonetheless a ‘belief’, would be analysed? What weight is placed on<br />

30 B Berger ‘Law’s religion: Rendering culture’ in R Moon (ed) Law and religious<br />

pluralism in Canada (2008) 264 288 available in an earlier version <strong>of</strong> the article at<br />

http://ohlj.ca/english/documents/45-2_02_Berger_postFR2_July10.pdf (accessed<br />

20 September 2008). David Brown’s critique <strong>of</strong> a certain overly expansive view <strong>of</strong> law,<br />

see n 28, above, at 230 - 233 would apply to Berger’s concept that law somehow<br />

constitutes a ‘culture’ rather than, as another view would have it, a set <strong>of</strong> rules that<br />

must order relationships between cultures. Law understood as a ‘culture’ or<br />

‘community’ in its own right would seem to call into question the ability <strong>of</strong> the law to<br />

adjudicate in a neutral fashion between competing claims amongst sub-cultures and<br />

communities. The laws are the equal property <strong>of</strong> all and owned especially by none; if<br />

this is so then it is probably wiser to avoid understanding constitutional law as<br />

constituting a ‘culture’ or a ‘community’ given how important constitutional<br />

principles are to citizenship shared by all.


308 A response to Lenta<br />

the balancing scales where uniforms are weighed not against religious<br />

or cultural beliefs and membership (which the cases show can marshal<br />

significant social arguments for their respect) but against what may<br />

seem merely idiosyncratic whims or expressions <strong>of</strong> pique, adolescent<br />

rebellion or ego? Say, a clerk at the Constitutional Court who sports a<br />

Mohawk and goes barefoot with or without wearing a kilt. If the test<br />

here is largely subjective (as it would appear to be with both religion<br />

and now culture after Pillay), why should we treat the non-religious,<br />

non-cultural individual claim for respect differently than claims that<br />

are at bottom communal, but which the Court treats as individual<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> expressive conduct? Examining the associational dimension<br />

and the goods consequent upon such associations might provide some<br />

way around this difficulty.<br />

Courts — and commentators — have tried to avoid rank-ordering<br />

rights. 31 Is this agnosticism about which rights are more weighty than<br />

others sustainable? In the most recent decision from the Canadian<br />

Supreme Court touching upon the freedom <strong>of</strong> religion in relation to<br />

civil laws, the majority judgment began by affirming that multiculturalism<br />

and pluralism must be protected, but then goes on to<br />

employ a fact-specific application <strong>of</strong> Canadian Charter rights that<br />

denies ‘bright-line application but does employ rank-ordered choosing<br />

without naming it as such’:<br />

Canada rightly prides itself on its evolutionary tolerance for diversity<br />

and pluralism. This journey has included a growing appreciation for<br />

multiculturalism, including the recognition that ethnic, religious or<br />

cultural differences will be acknowledged and respected. Endorsed in<br />

legal instruments ranging from the statutory protections found in human<br />

rights codes to their constitutional enshrinement in the Canadian<br />

Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms, the right to integrate into Canada’s<br />

mainstream based on and notwithstanding these differences has become<br />

a defining part <strong>of</strong> our national character. The right to have differences<br />

protected, however, does not mean that those differences are always<br />

hegemonic. Not all differences are compatible with Canada’s<br />

31 Dagenais v Canadian Broadcasting Corp [1994] 3 SCR 835 para 72. Chief Justice<br />

Lamer stated that ‘[w]hen the protected rights <strong>of</strong> two individuals come into<br />

conflict ... Charter principles require a balance to be achieved that fully respects<br />

the importance <strong>of</strong> both sets <strong>of</strong> rights.’ See also Trinity Western <strong>University</strong> v<br />

British Columbia College <strong>of</strong> Teachers [2001] 1 SCR 772 para 29. Justice Iacobbucci<br />

wrote that ‘[n]either freedom <strong>of</strong> religion nor the guarantee against discrimination<br />

based on sexual orientation is absolute.’ For a useful critique <strong>of</strong> balancing in hard<br />

cases and where matters <strong>of</strong> principle are at stake, see S Woolman & H Botha<br />

‘Limitations’ in Woolman et al (eds) (n 10 above) ch 34 citing New Jersey v TLO<br />

(1985) 469 US 325 369 (Brennan J describes balancing as ‘doctrinally destructive<br />

nihilism’). See also the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada’s decision allowing a student to<br />

wear a kirpan (Sikh ceremonial dagger worn for religious reasons) in a public<br />

school as long as it was sealed within his clothing; Multani v Commission Scolaire<br />

Marguerite Bourgois [2006] 1 S.C.R. 256 and case comment P Lauwers and IT<br />

Benson ‘Allowing Kirpans in Public Schools’ Lex View No. 57 http://<br />

www.culturalrenewal.ca/qry/page.taf?id=119 (last accessed February 20, 2009).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 309<br />

fundamental values and, accordingly, not all barriers to their expression<br />

are arbitrary. Determining when the assertion <strong>of</strong> a right based on<br />

difference must yield to a more pressing public interest is a complex,<br />

nuanced, fact-specific exercise that defies bright-line application. It is,<br />

at the same time, a delicate necessity for protecting the evolutionary<br />

integrity <strong>of</strong> both multi-culturalism and public confidence in its<br />

importance. 32<br />

The French administrative court’s decision that the wearing <strong>of</strong> a niqab<br />

(concealing the face <strong>of</strong> an individual except for the eyes) is a ground<br />

for denial <strong>of</strong> citizenship is, itself, grounded in the underlying notion<br />

that such concealment is ‘inconsistent with Republican values’.<br />

Perhaps that is true for France. 33 But what should religiously inclusive<br />

jurisdictions such as South Africa and Canada do in the face <strong>of</strong> such a<br />

dispute and what are the grounds for deciding matters differently?<br />

The relatively empty appeal to ‘balancing’ articulated above is <strong>of</strong><br />

little assistance here.<br />

In his earlier writings, Lenta hints, without giving a definitive<br />

viewpoint on the matter, that a niqab might be distinguished from a<br />

headscarf on the basis that in certain contexts facial covering could<br />

lead to ‘making identification and communication difficult’. He<br />

thereby avoids the religiously inclusive requirement to accommodate<br />

such a face-covering in public settings where such identification is<br />

essential or important. 34 I think Lenta is correct — if I have understood<br />

him properly — and look forward to his further analysis on this point.<br />

The debate in Canada regarding whether Muslim women should be<br />

allowed to vote while wearing face-coverings suggests that the issue<br />

may find practical means <strong>of</strong> resolution which allow for<br />

accommodation. 35<br />

To what extent headscarves or face-coverings should or should not<br />

be accommodated in public settings such as public school classrooms<br />

32 Bruker v Marcovitz 2007 SCC 54 paras 1-2 per Abella J.<br />

33<br />

K Bennhold ‘A veil closes France’s door to citizenship’ The New York Times 19 July<br />

2008 available at http://www.nytimes.com/2008/07/19/world/europe/19france.<br />

html?_r=1&pagewanted=1&ei=5070&en=2b01d3cac5c8b204&ex=1217304000&emc<br />

=eta1&oref=slogin (accessed 22 July 2008).<br />

34 See Lenta ‘Headscarves’ (n 2 above) 319.<br />

35 A Canadian report has noted that there are very few women who wear full head<br />

coverings that obscure the face. One estimate puts the number in Quebec at 50<br />

Muslim women out <strong>of</strong> a total number <strong>of</strong> around 200 000. According to this report,<br />

Muslim women in Canada are used to showing their faces for identification<br />

purposes at banks, airports and at the United States border. There has been some<br />

debate around the question <strong>of</strong> whether full facial coverings should be allowed at<br />

election booths and how identity can be assured. One commonly suggested<br />

solution has been for election <strong>of</strong>ficials to make provision for Muslim women to<br />

uncover to women election <strong>of</strong>ficers for the purpose <strong>of</strong> establishing identity.<br />

Another solution is to bring with them an adult who can swear to their identity.<br />

See http://www.cbc.ca/canada/story/2007/09/09/harper-veil.html (accessed 19<br />

November 2008).


310 A response to Lenta<br />

or government <strong>of</strong>fices must be based upon nuanced and careful linedrawing.<br />

I do not believe that in a Canadian or South African context<br />

a blanket gendered approach or ‘Republican values’ conclusion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sort that the French have embraced is likely to be the path ahead. A<br />

proper understanding <strong>of</strong> the principles <strong>of</strong> accommodation and the<br />

religiously inclusive public sphere <strong>of</strong> the kind adopted by the Canadian<br />

Supreme Court in Chamberlain and implicitly endorsed in Pillay and<br />

Fourie, suggests that civil function issues (such as voting<br />

identification) may be creatively accommodated.<br />

What is certain, however, is that the courts have yet to address<br />

sufficiently the communal nature <strong>of</strong> religious belief and the<br />

importance that this communal nature (legally comprehended as<br />

associational rights) plays in serving the goods that religious beliefs<br />

can <strong>of</strong>fer to free and democratic societies. An individualistic rights<br />

approach will tend to dissolve this good for the public and, ironically,<br />

for individuals as well. 36<br />

36 Thus D Schneiderman ‘Associational rights, religion and the Charter’ in R Moon<br />

(ed) (n 30 above) 65 notes that: ‘ ... pluralists will call upon state actors to take<br />

care that they do not impair associational rights more than is necessary. Courts<br />

have <strong>of</strong>ten not been so careful. They have assumed a unity <strong>of</strong> purpose between<br />

state and society that should not so readily be presumed’ (80). Compare in the<br />

same volume (239) L Weinrib ‘Ontario’s Sharia law debate: Law and politics under<br />

the Charter’, who focuses on the individual aspect <strong>of</strong> rights and asserts: ‘These<br />

[Charter] provisions make clear that the relationship between the individual and<br />

the state is primary and direct: that is, undiminished by personal characteristics<br />

and unmediated by given or chosen social affiliations’ (247) (emphasis added). To<br />

argue, as does Weinrib, that relationships between the individual and his or her<br />

association (church, organisation etc) are not or cannot be, in constitutionally<br />

significant ways, ‘mediated’ by what a person has chosen (ie contractually<br />

agreeing to Membership Rules or a Code <strong>of</strong> Conduct etc) overstates the<br />

importance that individual rights may have in a constitutional order and<br />

contributes to the sort <strong>of</strong> threats to associational rights I have criticised<br />

throughout this article. The volume in which these papers appears shows this<br />

tension between approaches and the emerging awareness <strong>of</strong> associational rights<br />

as against what might be termed the earlier but incomplete focus upon more<br />

individualistic approaches. It seems clear the law can and should move towards<br />

greater associational rights recognition.


1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

MEDIA FREEDOM AND THE LAW OF<br />

PRIVACY: NM AND OTHERS V SMITH AND<br />

OTHERS (FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION<br />

INSTITUTE AS AMICUS CURIAE)<br />

2007 (5) SA 250 (CC)<br />

* Directors, Webber Wentzel; Lecturers, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Witwatersrand School <strong>of</strong><br />

Law.<br />

1 C Smith Patricia de Lille (2002).<br />

2 The clinical trial was conducted by the head <strong>of</strong> the Immunology Clinic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Medical Faculty <strong>of</strong> the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong>, and was aimed at determining the<br />

efficacy <strong>of</strong> a combination <strong>of</strong> drugs on patients’ HIV levels.<br />

311<br />

Glenn Penfold & Dario Milo*<br />

Patricia de Lille, a biography <strong>of</strong> the well-known Member <strong>of</strong><br />

Parliament, was published in March 2002. 1 The book included a<br />

chapter on Ms De Lille’s work in campaigning for the rights <strong>of</strong> persons<br />

living with HIV/AIDS. In a chapter recounting Ms De Lille’s involvement<br />

in a dispute relating to a controversial HIV drugs trial at Kalafong<br />

Hospital, 2 the names <strong>of</strong> three trial participants, and their HIV-positive<br />

status, were published without their consent. After the reference to<br />

their names was drawn to their attention, the three women instituted<br />

action against the author (Charlene Smith), Ms De Lille and the<br />

publisher for breach <strong>of</strong> their rights to privacy, dignity and<br />

psychological integrity. The plaintiffs alleged that the defendants<br />

intentionally published their HIV status without the plaintiffs’<br />

consent or, alternatively, that they acted negligently in doing so.<br />

While the former did not require an extension <strong>of</strong> the actio injuriarum<br />

(the delictual action for infringement <strong>of</strong> personality rights), the latter<br />

did.<br />

The defendants argued that the women’s HIV status was not<br />

private at the time <strong>of</strong> the book’s publication, in that their status had<br />

been placed in the public domain. They also denied that the<br />

publication was either intentional or negligent.


312 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

After a trial that lasted eight days in the High Court, Schwartzman<br />

J held that the defendants lacked both intention and negligence in<br />

respect <strong>of</strong> the publication <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs’ HIV status. 3 With regard<br />

to the latter, Schwartzman J found that the defendants reasonably<br />

believed, at the time <strong>of</strong> publication, that the plaintiffs had consented<br />

to the disclosure <strong>of</strong> their HIV status. 4 The High Court, however, held<br />

the publisher liable for continuing to distribute copies <strong>of</strong> the book<br />

after it became aware that the women had not in fact consented to<br />

the general disclosure <strong>of</strong> their HIV status. 5 As a result, the publisher<br />

was ordered to pay R15 000 in damages to each plaintiff. The<br />

plaintiffs appealed against the High Court’s exoneration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

defendants in respect <strong>of</strong> the initial publication <strong>of</strong> the book.<br />

After the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal denied leave to appeal, the<br />

matter came before the Constitutional Court, which (by nine judges<br />

to one) held the defendants liable for the initial publication <strong>of</strong> the<br />

plaintiffs’ HIV status. 6 The judges were further divided as to how they<br />

came to this finding. The majority, in a judgment penned by Madala<br />

J, 7 did not deviate from the conventional approach to the actio<br />

injuriarum, holding that, contrary to the factual finding <strong>of</strong> the High<br />

Court, the defendants intentionally violated the plaintiffs’ privacy.<br />

Madala J was satisfied that the defendants ‘were certainly aware that<br />

the [plaintiffs] had not given their consent or at least foresaw the<br />

possibility that the consent had not been given to the disclosure’. 8<br />

This rendered it unnecessary for the majority to consider whether the<br />

actio injuriarum should be extended to cover harm brought about by<br />

negligence (as opposed to the traditional mental element <strong>of</strong><br />

intention). 9<br />

The remaining three judges, in separate judgments, took the legal<br />

road less travelled, effectively holding that liability for breach <strong>of</strong><br />

privacy should be extended to include liability for media defendants<br />

based on negligence. On the facts, Langa CJ and Sachs J found that<br />

the ‘media defendants’ (ie the author and the publisher) fell short <strong>of</strong><br />

3 NM and Others v Smith and Others [2005] 3 All SA 457 (W) (NM High Court) paras<br />

40-41.<br />

4 The principal reasons for this were that the women had been identified by name<br />

as being HIV-positive in a report on various allegations relating to the manner in<br />

which the clinical trials were conducted, prepared by an outside expert, Pr<strong>of</strong> SA<br />

Strauss, for the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong> (‘The Strauss Report’) (para 40 <strong>of</strong> the High<br />

Court judgment). The Strauss Report did not suggest that the contents <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Report were confidential (para 40.2).<br />

5 Para 44.2 <strong>of</strong> the High Court judgment.<br />

6 NM and Others v Smith and Others (Freedom <strong>of</strong> Expression Institute as Amicus<br />

Curiae) 2007 5 SA 250 (CC) (NM or NM v Smith).<br />

7 In which six judges, Moseneke DCJ, Mokgoro, Nkabinde, Skweyiya, Van der<br />

Westhuizen and Yacoob JJ, concurred.<br />

8<br />

NM (n 6 above) para 64.<br />

9 NM (n 6 above) para 57.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 313<br />

the standard <strong>of</strong> negligence (or reasonableness), 10 while O’Regan J<br />

held that they did not. 11<br />

Against the background <strong>of</strong> this variety <strong>of</strong> factual findings by the<br />

Court, and to some extent because <strong>of</strong> them, the judgment in NM v<br />

Smith raises various issues <strong>of</strong> significant interest, some <strong>of</strong> which are<br />

discussed in this note. 12 The first issue that interests us is the<br />

majority’s cursory treatment <strong>of</strong> the ‘constitutional matter’<br />

requirement (the threshold requirement for the Constitutional<br />

Court’s jurisdiction) in a judgment that proceeds to decide the factual<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> intention for purposes <strong>of</strong> the actio<br />

injuriarum. This is a ‘garden-variety judicial task’ 13 that one would<br />

expect ordinary appellate courts to undertake, but which is not<br />

generally the domain <strong>of</strong> a specialist court whose jurisdiction is<br />

confined to ‘constitutional matters’. The second, related issue that<br />

we briefly deal with is the questionable merits <strong>of</strong> the majority’s<br />

factual finding that the defendants acted intentionally. This is<br />

followed by a discussion <strong>of</strong> the most significant legal development<br />

that arises from this case: the approach <strong>of</strong> the minority judgments to<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> negligence and unreasonableness in an action for breach<br />

<strong>of</strong> privacy. The issues that arise in this context include the distinction<br />

between media and non-media defendants, the transferability <strong>of</strong> the<br />

negligence standard that applies in defamation law to privacy law,<br />

and the application <strong>of</strong> the negligence test endorsed by the minority<br />

judges to the facts <strong>of</strong> the case.<br />

2 The ‘constitutional matter’ requirement<br />

The Constitutional Court is a specialist court that does not have<br />

unlimited jurisdiction. While section 167(3)(a) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

proclaims that the Constitutional Court is the highest court on all<br />

‘constitutional matters’, the next paragraph stipulates that the Court<br />

‘may decide only constitutional matters, and issues connected with<br />

10<br />

NM (n 6 above) paras 111 & 207. Although Sachs J relies on a case dealing with<br />

media liability (the decision <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal in National Media<br />

Limited and Others v Bogoshi 1998 4 SA 1196 (SCA) (Bogoshi)) for this approach, it<br />

is unclear whether he limits liability based on reasonableness to the media<br />

defendants. For example, he states that he supports the ‘reasons and<br />

conclusions’ in Madala J’s judgment and finds that Ms De Lille (who, on the<br />

approach <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ and O’Regan J, is not a media defendant) did not meet the<br />

standard <strong>of</strong> reasonableness (paras 202 & 207).<br />

11 NM (n 6 above) para 189.<br />

12<br />

Other issues that the case addresses but which are outside <strong>of</strong> the scope <strong>of</strong> this<br />

note include the Court's approach to the privacy <strong>of</strong> a person's HIV/AIDS status, the<br />

relevance <strong>of</strong> dignity and reputation claims in this context (especially given the<br />

stigma attached to HIV/AIDS in society) and the proper approach to the issue <strong>of</strong><br />

costs.<br />

13 This phrase is taken from FI Michelman ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law, legality and the<br />

supremacy <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) (Michelman ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law’) 11-10.


314 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

decisions on constitutional matters’. 14 The threshold <strong>of</strong> a<br />

‘constitutional matter’ (and connected issues) thus determines the<br />

line beyond which the Constitutional Court’s authority does not<br />

extend. While the Constitutional Court is the highest court on<br />

constitutional matters, the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal has the last word<br />

on non-constitutional matters. 15<br />

A ‘constitutional matter’ is defined in section 167(7) as including<br />

‘any issue involving the interpretation, protection or enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitution’. The Constitutional Court has clarified this<br />

definition by identifying certain categories <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

matters. 16 The category that most commonly applies when one is<br />

dealing with the common law (like the actio injuriarum) is the<br />

obligation, under section 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, to develop the<br />

common law in light <strong>of</strong> the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights. 17 Nevertheless, much uncertainty remains as to the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> a ‘constitutional matter’. 18<br />

Given the fact that classification <strong>of</strong> an issue as a ‘constitutional<br />

matter’ determines whether the Constitutional Court is lawfully<br />

empowered to deal with it, and given the lack <strong>of</strong> clarity as to the<br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> this requirement, it is both surprising and disappointing<br />

14<br />

15<br />

16<br />

Sec 167(3)(b).<br />

Sec 168(3).<br />

Frazer v ABSA Bank Limited (National Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions as amicus<br />

curiae) 2007 3 484 (CC) (Frazer v ABSA) para 38; Boesak v S 2001 1 SA 912 (CC)<br />

17<br />

(Boesak) para 14. See also Michelman ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law’ (n 13 above) 11-7 - 11-8.<br />

See, for example, Khumalo and others v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 (CC) (Khumalo v<br />

Holomisa); Carmichele v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security and Another (Centre for<br />

Applied Legal Studies intervening) 2001 4 SA 938 (CC); and K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety<br />

18<br />

and Security 2005 6 SA 419 (CC) (K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security).<br />

Part <strong>of</strong> the reason for this uncertainty is the breadth <strong>of</strong> our Constitution. As Van<br />

der Westhuizen J remarked in Frazer v ABSA (n 16 above) para 36:<br />

‘[p]hilosophically and conceptually it is difficult to conceive <strong>of</strong> any legal issue<br />

that it not a constitutional matter within a system <strong>of</strong> constitutional supremacy’.<br />

See also Ngcobo J in Van der Walt v Metcash Trading Limited 2002 4 SA 317 (CC)<br />

(Metcash) para 32; and C Lewis ‘Reaching the pinnacle: principle, policies and<br />

people for a single apex Court in South Africa’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on<br />

Human Rights 509 519. Michelman ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law’ (n 13 above) 11.2(b) suggests<br />

that the Constitutional Court’s acceptance <strong>of</strong> the legality principle (ie the<br />

exercise <strong>of</strong> all public power must be in accordance with law) logically means that<br />

all appeals are constitutional matters. This is because, as Michelman points out, a<br />

court’s decision amounts to the exercise <strong>of</strong> public power and must therefore be<br />

correct as a matter <strong>of</strong> law. Michelman notes that this is apparently in conflict<br />

with the Court’s endorsement <strong>of</strong> its ‘less-than-plenary subject-matter<br />

competence’ (11-12). Although engagement with Michelman’s thought-provoking<br />

analysis falls beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this case note, we note that it may be based on<br />

an overly broad conception <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> legality (an argument that is<br />

apparently acknowledged by Michelman at 11-14). In any event, this is not the<br />

approach taken by the Constitutional Court, which has remarked that ‘[a]<br />

contention that a lower Court reached an incorrect decision is not, without more,<br />

a constitutional matter’ (Frazer v ABSA (n 16 above) para 40). See also the cases<br />

cited below at ns 24, 26 & 27.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 315<br />

that the majority’s judgment in NM v Smith contains only three short<br />

paragraphs under the heading ‘Is this a constitutional issue?’:<br />

The applicants approached this Court with a view to vindicate their<br />

constitutional rights to privacy, dignity and psychological integrity<br />

which, they allege, have been violated by the respondents. Their claim<br />

is, however, based on the actio iniuriarum and, therefore, falls to be<br />

determined in terms <strong>of</strong> the actio iniuriarum.<br />

It is important to recognise that even if a case does raise a constitutional<br />

matter, the assessment <strong>of</strong> whether the case should be heard by this<br />

Court rests instead on the additional requirement that access to this<br />

Court must be in the interests <strong>of</strong> justice and not every matter will raise<br />

a constitutional issue worthy <strong>of</strong> attention.<br />

The dispute before us is clearly worthy <strong>of</strong> constitutional adjudication<br />

and it is in the interests <strong>of</strong> justice that the matter be heard by this Court<br />

since it involves a nuanced and sensitive approach to balancing the<br />

interest <strong>of</strong> the media, in advocating freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, privacy and<br />

dignity <strong>of</strong> the applicants irrespective <strong>of</strong> whether it is based on the<br />

constitutional law or the common law. The Court is in any event<br />

mandated to develop and interpret the common law if necessary. 19<br />

It is apparent that only the first paragraph quoted above deals with<br />

the mandatory requirement <strong>of</strong> a constitutional matter. The remaining<br />

paragraphs deal with whether granting leave to appeal is ‘in the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> justice’. 20 All that one gleans from this first paragraph is<br />

that the aim <strong>of</strong> the plaintiffs was to vindicate their constitutional<br />

rights through the actio injuriarum. Nevertheless, as Woolman points<br />

out, the desire <strong>of</strong> litigants cannot be decisive <strong>of</strong> whether a<br />

constitutional matter arises. 21 The third paragraph perhaps provides<br />

an indication <strong>of</strong> the majority’s thinking on this issue, stating that the<br />

case ‘involves a nuanced and sensitive approach to balancing the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> the media, in advocating freedom <strong>of</strong> expression, privacy<br />

and dignity <strong>of</strong> the applicants’. While this may be true <strong>of</strong> other<br />

portions <strong>of</strong> the judgment, 22 it is difficult to envisage how this<br />

balancing comes into play in the most significant aspect <strong>of</strong> the<br />

19 NM (n 6 above) paras 29-31.<br />

20 While the existence <strong>of</strong> a constitutional matter is a necessary requirement for the<br />

Constitutional Court to entertain a matter, it is not in itself sufficient. The Court<br />

has a discretion as to whether or not to hear a particular constitutional matter.<br />

This discretion is exercised on the basis <strong>of</strong> the ‘interests <strong>of</strong> justice’, taking into<br />

account a range <strong>of</strong> factors. See, for example, Boesak (n 16 above) para 12. In<br />

relation to direct appeals to the Constitutional Court, the ‘interests <strong>of</strong> justice’<br />

test is expressly included in sec 167(6) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.<br />

21<br />

S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law<br />

Journal 762 782. See also Frazer v ABSA (n 16 above) para 40.<br />

22 For example, the majority’s reasoning on the quantum <strong>of</strong> damages (which<br />

balances various constitutional rights and values) or, more clearly, the minority’s<br />

extension <strong>of</strong> the actio injuriarum to negligence in relation to media defendants.<br />

The latter is a clear constitutional matter, in that the judges sought to develop<br />

the common law in light <strong>of</strong> the values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution (as contemplated in sec<br />

39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution).


316 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

majority’s judgment, namely, the assessment <strong>of</strong> intention. This is a<br />

subjective assessment <strong>of</strong> the question whether the defendants knew<br />

that they were disclosing private information without the plaintiffs’<br />

consent or actually foresaw that this may be the case and proceeded<br />

recklessly to disclose the information. It seems to us that this is purely<br />

a factual enquiry which leaves no room for balancing <strong>of</strong> interests.<br />

The paucity <strong>of</strong> the majority’s explanation as to why the issues in<br />

its judgment amount to ‘constitutional matters’ is even more<br />

surprising given the fact that, irrespective <strong>of</strong> whether it was right or<br />

wrong to exercise jurisdiction on this matter, it is difficult to<br />

reconcile the Court’s consideration <strong>of</strong> this matter with its previous<br />

jurisprudence on the meaning <strong>of</strong> ‘constitutional matters’.<br />

Earlier decisions <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court emphasise that, while<br />

the jurisdiction <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court is extensive and the term<br />

‘constitutional matter’ should be given a wide meaning, 23 it is not allembracing<br />

and some proper meaning must be given to it. 24 Most<br />

strikingly for our purposes, some <strong>of</strong> the Court’s decisions prior to NM<br />

v Smith indicate that purely factual disputes do not amount to<br />

constitutional matters. 25 We briefly discuss two <strong>of</strong> them.<br />

The first is Boesak, in which the applicant alleged that his<br />

constitutional rights to be presumed innocent and to freedom and<br />

security had been infringed by a decision <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong><br />

Appeal upholding fraud and theft convictions against him. According<br />

to the applicant, the Court erred in finding him guilty beyond<br />

reasonable doubt. During the course <strong>of</strong> his judgment, on behalf <strong>of</strong> a<br />

unanimous Constitutional Court, Langa DP identified certain broad<br />

principles that apply to the classification <strong>of</strong> criminal cases, including<br />

that a challenge to a decision <strong>of</strong> the SCA on the basis only that it is<br />

wrong on the facts is not a constitutional matter; and ‘[u]nless there<br />

is some separate constitutional issue ... no constitutional right is<br />

engaged when an applicant merely disputes the findings <strong>of</strong> fact made<br />

23 S v Basson 2005 1 SA 171 (CC) (Basson) para 90-1; and Boesak (n 16 above) para<br />

14. See also the later decision <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court in Frazer v ABSA (n 16<br />

above) para 37 & 39.<br />

24 See Basson (n 23 above) para 91; Metcash (n 18 above) para 32; and Dikoko v<br />

Mokhatla 2006 6 SA 235 (CC) para 123. Van der Westhuizen J, on behalf <strong>of</strong> a<br />

unanimous Court in the more recent decision in Frazer v ABSA (n 16 above) para<br />

39 stated as follows: ‘While the conception <strong>of</strong> a constitutional matter is broad,<br />

the term is <strong>of</strong> course not completely open. The fact that sec 167(3)(b) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution limits this Court’s jurisdiction to constitutional matters presupposes<br />

that a meaningful line must be drawn between constitutional and nonconstitutional<br />

matters and it is the responsibility <strong>of</strong> this Court to do so’. See also<br />

Wary Holdings (Pty) Ltd v Stalwo (Pty) Ltd and another, Trustees <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Hoogekraal Highlands and another v Minister <strong>of</strong> Agriculture and Land Affairs<br />

25<br />

[2008] ZACC 12 para 39.<br />

I Currie & J De Waal The Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights handbook (5th ed, 2005) 104 state that:<br />

‘[m]atters that turn purely on questions <strong>of</strong> fact are not constitutional matters’.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 317<br />

by the SCA’. 26 The second decision is Phoebus Apollo Aviation CC v<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security, 27 in which the Court held that it did<br />

not have jurisdiction in relation to a dispute about whether the State<br />

should, on the facts <strong>of</strong> the particular case, be held vicariously liable<br />

for the dishonest acts <strong>of</strong> three <strong>of</strong>f-duty police <strong>of</strong>ficers. Kriegler J<br />

stated as follows:<br />

It is not suggested that in determining the question <strong>of</strong> vicarious liability<br />

the SCA applied any principle which is inconsistent with the<br />

Constitution. Nor is there any suggestion that any such principle needs to<br />

be adapted or evolved to bring it into harmony with the spirit, purport or<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. On the contrary, counsel for the appellant<br />

expressly conceded that the common-law test for vicarious liability, as it<br />

stands, is consistent with the Constitution. It has long been accepted<br />

that the application <strong>of</strong> this test to the facts <strong>of</strong> a particular case is not a<br />

question <strong>of</strong> law but one <strong>of</strong> fact, pure and simple. The thrust <strong>of</strong> the<br />

argument presented on behalf <strong>of</strong> the appellant was essentially that<br />

though the SCA has set the correct test, it had applied that test<br />

incorrectly — which is <strong>of</strong> course not ordinarily a constitutional issue. 28<br />

It may be that these cases are not, on a proper reading, authority for<br />

a general principle that a dispute <strong>of</strong> fact can never be a constitutional<br />

matter, particularly if one has regard to the fact that in both cases<br />

the Court found that no constitutional matter arose only after stating<br />

that no fundamental right was implicated by the factual dispute. In<br />

Boesak, for example, Langa DP remarked that upholding a conviction<br />

when the SCA ought to have had reasonable doubt as to the<br />

applicant’s guilt ‘is no violation <strong>of</strong> the applicant’s right to be<br />

presumed innocent’ before he stated that the appeal did not involve<br />

a constitutional matter. 29 Similarly, in Phoebus Apollo the Court<br />

found that the right to property clearly did not apply, before stating<br />

that no constitutional matter arose. 30<br />

These cases may therefore leave room for an argument that a<br />

dispute <strong>of</strong> fact can amount to a constitutional matter where a<br />

plausible argument can be made that the matter is relevant to the<br />

26<br />

Boesak (n 16 above) para 15(a).<br />

27 2003 1 BCLR 14 (CC) (Phoebus Apollo).<br />

28 Phoebus Apollo (n 27 above) para 9.<br />

29<br />

n 16 above, para 16. See also para 35. This approach is consistent with the<br />

decisions <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court to the effect that an incorrect decision by a<br />

court does not infringe a constitutional right. While one has the right to a fair<br />

trial (s 35(3) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution) or a fair public hearing (s 34), one does not have<br />

a right to the correct outcome in judicial proceedings. See Lane and Fey NNO v<br />

Dabelstein and others 2001 2 SA 1187 (CC) para 4; Metcash (n 18 above) paras 14<br />

& 19; and Basson (n 23 above) paras 91, 94 & 99.<br />

30 n 27 above, paras 4-6 & 9. See also Metcash (n 18 above) para 14.


318 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

vindication <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right (whether directly or indirectly). 31<br />

This reading <strong>of</strong> Boesak and Phoebus Apollo finds some support in the<br />

following dictum <strong>of</strong> Chaskalson CJ in Basson:<br />

Where no constitutional right is engaged, a challenge to a decision <strong>of</strong><br />

the SCA or any other court, on the basis only that it is wrong on the<br />

facts, is not a constitutional matter. And a dispute that does not impact<br />

upon or give effect to an entrenched right or other constitutional<br />

provision, will not ordinarily be a constitutional matter. 32<br />

There may thus have been scope for distinguishing Boesak and<br />

Phoebus Apollo, and arguing that because the claim in NM Smith was<br />

a plausible one that was clearly aimed at indirectly vindicating<br />

constitutional rights, any factual dispute that is relevant to<br />

vindicating those rights (including one as to intention on the part <strong>of</strong><br />

the defendants) amounts to a constitutional matter. However, the<br />

difficulty which such an argument would face is the unanimous<br />

decision <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court in K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and<br />

Security. This case involved a claim based on vicarious liability for<br />

rape committed by uniformed, on-duty police <strong>of</strong>ficers. The claim<br />

sought to vindicate a number <strong>of</strong> the victim’s constitutional rights,<br />

including her rights to freedom and security <strong>of</strong> the person and dignity.<br />

The Court, in assessing whether a constitutional matter arose,<br />

considered the meaning <strong>of</strong> the ‘development’ <strong>of</strong> the common law for<br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> section 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. O’Regan J, writing for a<br />

unanimous Court, noted that the common law is most clearly<br />

developed when a common law rule is changed or a new rule is<br />

introduced. 33 She pointed out, however, that courts more commonly<br />

decide cases within the framework <strong>of</strong> an existing rule. O’Regan J<br />

identified two types <strong>of</strong> cases where this occurs. The first is where a<br />

court merely applies the rule to ‘a set <strong>of</strong> facts which it is clear fall<br />

within the terms <strong>of</strong> the rule or existing authority’, in which case the<br />

rule is not developed. 34 The second instance is where a court<br />

determines ‘whether a new set <strong>of</strong> facts falls within or beyond the<br />

31<br />

Michelman ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law’ (n 13 above) 11-10 puts it as follows: ‘what the<br />

[Constitutional Court] is really telling us in Pheobus Apollo Aviation is that it<br />

sometimes will decline to hear argument on a claim <strong>of</strong> unconstitutionality<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the extreme prima facie implausibility <strong>of</strong> the claim ...’. An example <strong>of</strong><br />

the indirect vindication <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right would be an action, such as that<br />

in NM, for breach <strong>of</strong> privacy (a constitutional right entrenched in sec14 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution) through the actio iniuriarum.<br />

32 n 23 above, para 91, emphasis added. See also Rail Commuters Action Group and<br />

others v Transnet Limited t/a Metrorail and others 2005 2 SA 359 (CC) (Rail<br />

Commuters) para 52, where O’Regan J, after quoting from Boesak, stated as<br />

follows: ‘This reasoning does not imply that disputes <strong>of</strong> fact may not be resolved<br />

by this Court. It states merely that where the only issue in a criminal appeal is<br />

dissatisfaction with the factual findings made by the SCA, and no other<br />

constitutional issue is raised, no constitutional right is engaged by such a<br />

challenge’.<br />

33<br />

n 17 above, para 16.<br />

34 As above.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 319<br />

scope <strong>of</strong> an existing rule’ so that the ‘precise ambit <strong>of</strong> each rule is ...<br />

clarified in relation to each new set <strong>of</strong> facts’. 35 This falls within the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> the common law contemplated in<br />

section 39(2), which is aimed at ensuring ‘that our common law is<br />

infused with the values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’. 36<br />

Turning to NM v Smith, it seems to us that a finding as to whether<br />

the defendants, as a matter <strong>of</strong> fact, knew that the information was<br />

private or that the plaintiffs had not consented to its disclosure or<br />

that the defendants actually foresaw that possibility, does not<br />

amount to the development <strong>of</strong> the common law in the manner<br />

contemplated in K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security. It is difficult to<br />

see in what way the values <strong>of</strong> the Constitution are relevant to this<br />

enquiry. 37 Moreover, if this does amount to the development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law, it is difficult to reconcile this with the approach <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court in Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security v Luiters, 38<br />

which was argued after, and decided before, NM v Smith. In this case,<br />

dealing with vicarious liability in respect <strong>of</strong> the actions <strong>of</strong> an <strong>of</strong>f-duty<br />

police <strong>of</strong>ficer who allegedly placed himself on duty, the Court<br />

unanimously held (with reliance on K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and<br />

Security) that the question as to whether the <strong>of</strong>ficer subjectively<br />

intended to act within the course and scope <strong>of</strong> his employment was<br />

not a constitutional matter. Langa CJ remarked as follows:<br />

The Minister queried the finding <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal that<br />

Constable Siljeur subjectively intended to act as a policeman at the time<br />

<strong>of</strong> the shooting. A number <strong>of</strong> reasons were given in support <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Minister’s criticism <strong>of</strong> this finding by the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal. The<br />

thrust <strong>of</strong> the Minister’s submission, however, was to urge this Court to<br />

reconsider the facts as found by the High Court and the Supreme Court<br />

<strong>of</strong> Appeal. This submission does not raise a constitutional issue for, as it<br />

was made clear in K, the question whether a police <strong>of</strong>ficer has<br />

subjectively acted as a police <strong>of</strong>ficer is purely factual.<br />

35<br />

As above.<br />

36 K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security (n 17 above) para 17. O’Regan J referred to<br />

this as ‘the incremental development <strong>of</strong> the rule’ in light <strong>of</strong> the normative<br />

framework <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.<br />

37 As Woolman (n 21 above) 783 comments: ‘the majority in NM acts as a trier <strong>of</strong><br />

fact in a run-<strong>of</strong>-the-mill actio iniuriarum matter’. It may be suggested that the<br />

approach <strong>of</strong> the majority in NM falls within the second instance in K v Minister <strong>of</strong><br />

Safety and Security, ie determining whether a particular set <strong>of</strong> facts falls within<br />

or beyond the ambit <strong>of</strong> an existing rule, in that the majority determined that the<br />

facts fell within the ambit <strong>of</strong> dolus eventualis in circumstances which would, in<br />

the absence <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, amount only to negligence. For a variation on<br />

this argument, see FI Michelman ‘On the uses <strong>of</strong> interpretive ‘charity’: Some<br />

notes on application, avoidance, equality, and objective unconstitutionality from<br />

the 2007 term <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa’ (2008) 1 Constitutional<br />

Court Review (Michelman ‘Interpretive charity’) 30 - 32. For the reasons set out<br />

in this article, we do not find this argument persuasive.<br />

38 2007 2 SA 106 (CC) (Luiters).


320 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

The Constitutional Court’s own case law therefore suggests that a<br />

good argument can be made that the factual question as to the<br />

defendants’ state <strong>of</strong> mind in NM v Smith was not a constitutional<br />

matter, notwithstanding the fact that the plaintiffs were seeking to<br />

vindicate their constitutional rights.<br />

Elsewhere in this volume, Michelman, adopting what he describes<br />

as a ‘charitable’ reading <strong>of</strong> the majority judgment in NM v Smith,<br />

suggests that the majority may have developed the common law ‘in<br />

response to constitutional pressure’ and that all <strong>of</strong> the issues in this<br />

case<br />

stood to be decided in the shadow <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights and <strong>of</strong> the<br />

looming possibility that the common law might, depending on how they<br />

were to be decided, have to be developed under the mandate <strong>of</strong> section<br />

39(2). 39<br />

Michelman goes on to assert that the majority, in finding that the<br />

conduct <strong>of</strong> the defendants amounted to intention, may be said to<br />

have been considering whether the common law rule applies to the<br />

new factual situation as envisaged in K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and<br />

Security. 40 While Michelman’s thoughtful argument merits a more<br />

detailed response than this case note permits, it seems to us that<br />

there are at least three possible responses. The first is that one<br />

cannot get away from the fact that a finding <strong>of</strong> intention (dolus)<br />

involves a finding <strong>of</strong> subjective state <strong>of</strong> mind (ie actual knowledge or<br />

foresight) on the part <strong>of</strong> the defendant. This is a purely factual finding<br />

which, it seems to us, leaves no space for a consideration <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional rights or values. Second, if the majority intended, in<br />

light <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, to extend the scope <strong>of</strong> dolus eventualis to<br />

conduct which would otherwise not have constituted this form <strong>of</strong><br />

intention, one would expect them to have said so expressly. On the<br />

contrary, the approach <strong>of</strong> the majority was simply to apply the dolus<br />

eventualis test to the facts <strong>of</strong> the case before them. 41 Third, even if<br />

one is able to bring the majority’s approach within the wording <strong>of</strong><br />

O’Regan J’s judgment in K v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security, it seems<br />

to us more difficult to do so in relation to Luiters.<br />

Irrespective <strong>of</strong> whether or not the majority was correct in holding<br />

that the defendants’ intention (or lack there<strong>of</strong>) properly fell within<br />

the Court’s jurisdiction, our primary difficulty with the judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

39 Michelman ‘Interpretive charity’ (n 37 above) 20; see also 21 and 28.<br />

40 Michelman ‘Interpretive charity’ (n 37 above) 28.<br />

41<br />

As Michelman ‘Interpretive charity’ (n 37 above) points out at 19, Madala J<br />

expressly states that, in light <strong>of</strong> the fact that his judgment ‘is not extending the<br />

common-law definition <strong>of</strong> intention to include negligence in relation to the<br />

publication <strong>of</strong> private medical facts, there will be no “chilling effect” on freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> expression in South Africa ...’ (para 69).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 321<br />

the majority in NM v Smith is that none <strong>of</strong> these issues were canvassed<br />

in the judgment and no attempt was made to reconcile the majority’s<br />

approach with the previous case law. The Court thus dealt with a<br />

matter that could conceivably fall beyond its jurisdiction — an<br />

outcome that would have serious implications for the rule <strong>of</strong> law —<br />

without providing a meaningful explanation <strong>of</strong> its reasons for doing so.<br />

Moreover, if the majority’s reason for regarding the defendants’<br />

intention as a constitutional matter is that it was an issue that needed<br />

to be decided in order to determine whether the plaintiffs’<br />

constitutional rights should be vindicated, the effect <strong>of</strong> this is that a<br />

wide range <strong>of</strong> ordinary factual disputes may well occupy the Court’s<br />

resources in the future. 42 These matters could, for example, include<br />

an extensive factual dispute as to whether an allegation in a<br />

defamation action is true (which implicates the right to dignity) or a<br />

dispute as to whether a person who caused physical harm to another<br />

did so with intention or negligence (which implicates the right to<br />

security <strong>of</strong> the person and bodily integrity).<br />

Finally on this issue, we reiterate that the Constitution provides<br />

that the Constitutional Court’s jurisdiction extends to ‘issues<br />

connected with decisions on constitutional matters’. The Court has<br />

held that this phrase should be given a wide interpretation so as to<br />

extend the Court’s jurisdiction to matters that ‘stand in a logical<br />

relationship’ to constitutional matters. 43 It includes ‘any anterior<br />

matter [that], logically or otherwise, is capable <strong>of</strong> throwing light on<br />

or affecting the decision by this Court on the primary constitutional<br />

matter’. 44 It is unfortunate that the Court did not consider whether<br />

the question as to the defendants’ intention fell within the scope <strong>of</strong><br />

this concept. 45<br />

42 Subject to the ‘interests <strong>of</strong> justice’ filter discussed above.<br />

43 Alexcor Limited and another v Richtersveld Community and others 2003 12 BCLR<br />

1301 (CC) para 30.<br />

44 As above. The Court went on to state it more formally: ‘when any factum<br />

probandum <strong>of</strong> a disputed issue is a constitutional matter, then any factum<br />

probans, bearing logically on the existence or otherwise <strong>of</strong> such factum<br />

probandum, is itself an issue “connected with a decision on a constitutional<br />

matter”.’ See also Rail Commuters (n 32 above) para 52; and Basson (n 23 above)<br />

para 22.<br />

45 The judgment in Luiters (n 38 above) suggests that this may well be the case: ‘[i]t<br />

was argued on behalf <strong>of</strong> the Minister that once the Court assumes jurisdiction on<br />

one basis, it has the power to alter the findings <strong>of</strong> both the High Court and the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal on factual issues even if we do not find it necessary to<br />

change the test. It may well be that the factual issues are issues that are<br />

connected to a decision on a constitutional matter in such circumstances’ (para<br />

29).


322 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

3 The majority’s finding <strong>of</strong> intention<br />

The most extraordinary aspect <strong>of</strong> the judgment in NM v Smith is the<br />

extent to which the Court was divided on the factual question as to<br />

the defendants’ state <strong>of</strong> mind. 46 The majority held that the<br />

defendants had intended wrongfully to infringe the plaintiffs’ privacy,<br />

finding that they ‘knew well <strong>of</strong> the wrongfulness <strong>of</strong> their conduct and<br />

that the disclosure <strong>of</strong> private facts was likely to invade the privacy<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> the applicants’. 47 The majority’s criticism <strong>of</strong> the defendants<br />

is, at times, strident, stating at one point that Ms Smith<br />

did a half-hearted check [for the consents] but soon became tired <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exercise and so decided to go ahead and produce the book without<br />

having obtained the consents <strong>of</strong> the applicants. 48<br />

These are very serious findings for the majority <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional<br />

Court to make in relation to persons (the defendants) who had<br />

testified that they honestly assumed that suitable consents had been<br />

given and did not consider the possibility that this was not the case, 49<br />

and in circumstances where the Court states, ‘[t]hat they are good<br />

activists in the field <strong>of</strong> HIV/AIDS admits <strong>of</strong> no doubt’. 50<br />

Not only are the findings <strong>of</strong> the majority severe, they are also at<br />

odds with the decision <strong>of</strong> Schwartzman J in the trial court who, having<br />

heard several days <strong>of</strong> evidence at the trial, held that the defendants<br />

had lacked both intention and negligence. In relation to the former,<br />

he stated that Ms Smith and Ms De Lille had<br />

by their long standing involvement with people infected with HIV,<br />

demonstrated that they are two <strong>of</strong> the most unlikely people to<br />

intentionally invade the privacy <strong>of</strong> a person infected with HIV. 51<br />

The findings <strong>of</strong> the majority are also dramatically at odds with<br />

O’Regan J’s dissenting judgment. It is remarkable that the majority<br />

finds that the defendants knew that the plaintiffs had not consented<br />

46 See also Woolman (n 21 above) 781; and J Steinberg ‘Generous judgment instills<br />

stigma’ in Notes from a fractured country (2007) 221.<br />

47 NM (n 6 above) para 64.<br />

48 NM (n 6 above) para 88.<br />

49<br />

NM (n 6 above) paras 159-168.<br />

50 NM (n 6 above) para 59.<br />

51 NM High Court (n 3 above) para 40. Michelman ‘Interpretive charity’ (n 37 above)<br />

states that the majority's refusal to defer to the High Court's finding on the facts<br />

is explicable if it viewed the High Court's application <strong>of</strong> the common law rule <strong>of</strong><br />

intention as not being compliant with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights (at current page 37:<br />

Editors to insert new page number). The difficulty we have with this approach is<br />

that it assumes that the majority’s discussion <strong>of</strong> whether intentional conduct was<br />

present on the facts, constitutes a constitutional matter with which the Court<br />

ought to have concerned itself. We have argued above that the Court itself does<br />

not identify this as a constitutional matter raised by the case.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 323<br />

to the disclosure <strong>of</strong> their HIV status (or had actually foreseen this<br />

possibility and recklessly disregarded it) where O’Regan J finds, on<br />

considering the same record, that the reasonable journalist would not<br />

have been obliged to make further enquiries in this regard. 52<br />

Given this context, one would expect that the majority would<br />

have been careful to set out their reasons for differing so dramatically<br />

from the factual findings <strong>of</strong> the trial court and O’Regan J. We agree<br />

with Langa CJ that, in light <strong>of</strong> the defendants’ heartfelt denials <strong>of</strong><br />

intention, the Court ‘would need a great deal <strong>of</strong> evidence to find that<br />

these activists would intentionally infringe the rights <strong>of</strong> the very<br />

people whom they are committed to protect’. 53<br />

The reasons that the majority advances in this regard are, with<br />

respect, not convincing. While we do not intend to engage in a<br />

detailed factual analysis for purposes <strong>of</strong> this note, we mention two<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> concern. The first is that the majority did not engage in any<br />

detail with the reasons <strong>of</strong>fered by O’Regan J as to why she found that<br />

the defendants did not act with intention or negligence. The second<br />

is that a number <strong>of</strong> the majority’s statements in the portion <strong>of</strong> its<br />

judgment dealing with intention indicate that the defendants did not<br />

have intention and were, at best for the plaintiffs, negligent. For<br />

example, Madala J states that: ‘[b]oth respondents assumed, without<br />

any enquiry, that the information contained in the Strauss Report was<br />

not confidential’ and ‘[Ms Smith] assumed that the applicants had<br />

consented to the public disclosure <strong>of</strong> their names and HIV status<br />

because the source <strong>of</strong> the publication came from a reputable<br />

institution’. 54 The Court also notes that ‘[Ms De Lille] failed to take<br />

sufficient steps to ascertain whether the [plaintiffs] had in fact given<br />

unlimited consent’. 55 It is difficult to reconcile these statements,<br />

which suggest that the defendants actually made certain (incorrect)<br />

assumptions, and ought to have made further investigations, with a<br />

finding <strong>of</strong> intention, even in the form <strong>of</strong> dolus eventualis. 56<br />

52<br />

NM (n 6 above) paras 185-187.<br />

53 NM (n 6 above) para 93.<br />

54 NM (n 6 above) paras 60-61, emphasis added.<br />

55<br />

NM (n 6 above) para 60.<br />

56 Michelman ‘Interpretative charity’ (n 37 above) suggests that the fact that the<br />

inclusion <strong>of</strong> the names <strong>of</strong> the three plaintiffs in the book could add no value to<br />

the publication (and in particular, despite protestations by Ms Smith to the<br />

contrary, certainly was not required to give authenticity to the publication) ‘may<br />

have been instrumental in leading Madala J's majority to its conclusion that<br />

Smith's choice was “intentional” in the pertinent, legal sense’ (at current page<br />

43: editors to insert new page no). We submit, however, that the utility <strong>of</strong><br />

including the plaintiffs' names in the book can at most be a factor to consider in<br />

determining whether the state <strong>of</strong> mind <strong>of</strong> Ms Smith was such that she acted with<br />

intention (either in the sense that she knew that she was acting unlawfully or<br />

foresaw that she may be doing so and acted in reckless disregard <strong>of</strong> that<br />

foresight). This factor cannot elevate otherwise negligent but non-intentional<br />

conduct to the status <strong>of</strong> dolus.


324 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

4 The Court's approach to the development <strong>of</strong><br />

the common law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

The law <strong>of</strong> defamation underwent radical reform with regard to media<br />

defendants in the Bogoshi case. 57 Although the decision has been<br />

rightly criticised for blurring the doctrinal boundaries between fault<br />

and unlawfulness in the law <strong>of</strong> delict, 58 it now appears to be generally<br />

accepted by our courts that the effect <strong>of</strong> Bogoshi is that media<br />

defendants sued for liability in defamation will be entitled to rebut<br />

the presumption <strong>of</strong> unlawfulness by proving that their conduct was in<br />

all the circumstances objectively reasonable (a position that is<br />

favourable to the media relative to non-media defendants). In<br />

addition, if the defence <strong>of</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> unlawfulnness,<br />

and hence lack <strong>of</strong> fault, is pursued by a media defendant, the media<br />

defendant must establish that it was not negligent in this regard (in<br />

this respect, the media is in a less favourable position relative to nonmedia<br />

defendants). 59<br />

Despite these developments in the law <strong>of</strong> defamation, until the<br />

NM v Smith decision, the common law principles that governed the<br />

57<br />

n 10 above. The reform in fact started at the High Court level with the decision <strong>of</strong><br />

Cameron J (as he then was) in Holomisa v Argus Newspapers Ltd 1996 2 SA 588<br />

(W) (Holomisa v Argus Newspapers).<br />

58<br />

The Court's discussion <strong>of</strong> lawfulness in the form <strong>of</strong> reasonable publication<br />

overlaps significantly with its discussion <strong>of</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> fault in the form <strong>of</strong> a<br />

reasonable belief that the publication was lawful. For instance, Hefer JA at 1214<br />

stated that ‘the indicated approach is intended to cater for ignorance and<br />

mistake at the level <strong>of</strong> lawfulness; and in a given case negligence on the<br />

defendant's part may well be determinative <strong>of</strong> the legality <strong>of</strong> the publication’.<br />

For discussion <strong>of</strong> the blurring between the elements <strong>of</strong> fault and unlawfulness by<br />

the Court, see J Burchell Personality rights and freedom <strong>of</strong> expression: The<br />

modern actio injuriarum (1998) 226; JR Midgley ‘Media liability for defamation’<br />

(1999) 116 South African Law Journal 211; D Milo ‘The cabinet minister, the Mail<br />

& Guardian, and the report card: The Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal's decision in the<br />

Mthembi-Mahanyele case’ (2005) 122 South African Law Journal 28 38-39; J<br />

Neethling ‘The protection <strong>of</strong> false defamatory publications by the mass media:<br />

Recent developments in South Africa against the background <strong>of</strong> Australian, New<br />

Zealand and English law’ (2007) 40 Comparative and International Law Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa 103 123-124. For further discussion on how courts in the area <strong>of</strong><br />

delict continue to grapple with the distinction between fault and unlawfulness,<br />

see eg A Fagan ‘Rethinking wrongfulness in the law <strong>of</strong> delict’ (2005) 122 South<br />

African Law Journal 90; J Neethling ‘The conflation <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness and<br />

negligence: is it always a bad thing for the law <strong>of</strong> delict?’ (2006) 123 South<br />

African Law Journal 204; RW Nugent ‘Yes, it is always a bad thing for the law — a<br />

reply to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Neethling’ (2006) 123 South African Law Journal 557; J<br />

Neethling & JM Potgieter ‘Wrongfulness and negligence in the law <strong>of</strong> delict: A<br />

Babylonian confusion?’ (2007) 70 Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse<br />

Reg 120; FDJ Brand ‘Reflections on wrongfulness in the law <strong>of</strong> delict’ (2007) 124<br />

South African Law Journal 74; A Fagan ‘Blind Faith: A Response to Pr<strong>of</strong>essors<br />

Neethling and Potgieter’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 285.<br />

59 The leading judicial recognition <strong>of</strong> these principles is the Constitutional Court's<br />

unanimous decision in Khumalo v Holomisa (n 17 above) paras 19-20. See also<br />

Mthembi-Mahanyele v Mail & Guardian Ltd and Another 2004 6 SA 329 (SCA)<br />

(Mthembi-Mahanyele) paras 45-46.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 325<br />

law <strong>of</strong> privacy — more particularly liability based on intention — had<br />

not been challenged under the Constitution. 60 The facts <strong>of</strong> NM v Smith<br />

raised squarely the issue <strong>of</strong> the fault element <strong>of</strong> liability in privacy<br />

cases: assuming that Ms Smith, Ms De Lille and the publisher held the<br />

view that consent had been provided to reveal the plaintiffs’<br />

identities and that this view was mistaken, was it necessary for them<br />

to prove that such a mistake was reasonable? As stated, the majority<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Court did not reach this issue; it found that the defendants<br />

published with knowledge that the plaintiffs had not provided the<br />

requisite consent (or at least with reckless disregard as to whether<br />

consent had been granted). 61 On the other hand, the minority judges<br />

grappled with the issue at some length. Their judgments raise a<br />

number <strong>of</strong> issues <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound significance to media liability in privacy<br />

cases, and we deal with each in turn: the distinction between media<br />

and non-media defendants for purposes <strong>of</strong> privacy (and defamation)<br />

liability and the desirability <strong>of</strong> a negligence test in this context; and<br />

how negligence on the part <strong>of</strong> media defendants should be assessed<br />

where journalists rely on <strong>of</strong>ficial reports.<br />

5 The distinction between media and non-media<br />

defendants and the negligence test<br />

In Bogoshi, the Court expressly perpetuated the distinction between<br />

media and non-media defendants that was created in Suid-Afrikaanse<br />

Uitsaaikorporasie v O'Malley, 62 where the Appellate Division opined<br />

that strict liability applied in defamation cases to members <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mass media. 63 Although the Court in Bogoshi rightly jettisoned the<br />

restrictive principle <strong>of</strong> strict liability, it held that it would not be just<br />

to allow media defendants to escape liability on the same basis as<br />

non-media defendants, that is, by relying on the absence <strong>of</strong> animus<br />

injuriandi. 64 Hefer JA relied for this distinction on the Australian High<br />

Court's judgment in Lange v Australian Broadcasting Corporation: 65<br />

'the damage that can be done when there are thousands <strong>of</strong> recipients<br />

<strong>of</strong> a communication is obviously greater than when there are a few<br />

60<br />

A number <strong>of</strong> academic commentators had, however, expressed the view (albeit<br />

without much analysis) that the developments in defamation law had the effect<br />

that equivalent principles now applied in the law <strong>of</strong> privacy. See eg D McQuoid-<br />

Mason ‘Privacy’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd<br />

Edition, OS, 2003) 38-19; Burchell (n 58 above) at 429.<br />

61 See text accompanying n 8 & 9 above. Madala J, for the majority, stated at para<br />

57 that this was not an appropriate case to depart from ‘the age-old approach to<br />

the actio injuriarum. I do not, by any means, wish to be understood to say the<br />

common law should or could never be developed in this regard’.<br />

62<br />

1977 3 SA 394 (A).<br />

63 O’Malley (n 62 above) 403. This was confirmed by the Appellate Division in<br />

Pakendorf en Andere v De Flamingh 1982 3 SA 146 (A).<br />

64<br />

Bogoshi (n 10 above) 1214.<br />

65 (1997) 189 CLR 520 (Lange).


326 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

recipients'; 66 this made the 'additional burden' <strong>of</strong> proving lack <strong>of</strong><br />

negligence 'entirely reasonable'. 67<br />

These principles were developed by the minority in NM v Smith in<br />

judgments that are now the leading discussions in South African law<br />

with respect to the question <strong>of</strong> how to distinguish between media and<br />

non-media defendants, and why such a distinction is necessary. All<br />

the minority judges were clear that, as in defamation law, a higher<br />

level <strong>of</strong> care is required in privacy law for media defendants as<br />

opposed to non-media defendants. As O'Regan J stated:<br />

For purposes <strong>of</strong> this case, I accept that the legal principles developed in<br />

Bogoshi should apply not only in the law <strong>of</strong> defamation but also to the<br />

infringement <strong>of</strong> privacy rights by the media ... Modern electronic, print<br />

and broadcast media are immensely, and indeed, increasingly powerful.<br />

Publications <strong>of</strong>ten reach hundreds <strong>of</strong> thousands <strong>of</strong> readers, viewers and<br />

listeners. It is accordingly appropriate, given the scale <strong>of</strong> damage to an<br />

individual that can be caused by such widespread publication, to confer<br />

special obligations upon the media in respect <strong>of</strong> publication. In so doing,<br />

we recognise that the media are not only bearers <strong>of</strong> rights under our<br />

constitutional order, but also bearers <strong>of</strong> obligations. 68<br />

Given the immense power wielded by the media, 69 we submit that, while<br />

a negligence test for breaches <strong>of</strong> privacy by the media clearly limits their<br />

rights to media freedom, such a limitation is justifiable. We agree with<br />

Sachs J in this context that ‘the principles developed in [the Bogoshi] case<br />

are eminently transportable to the law <strong>of</strong> privacy’, 70 at least in the<br />

66<br />

Lange (n 65 above) 572.<br />

67 Bogoshi (n 10 above) 1214.<br />

68<br />

NM (n 6 above) para 177. See also Langa CJ at para 94: 'It is ... constitutionally<br />

appropriate that the media should be held to a higher standard than the average<br />

person'.<br />

69<br />

For foreign studies in this regard, see generally J Curran & J Seaton Power<br />

without responsibility: The press, broadcasting, and new media in Britain (6th ed, 2003). For an interesting South African perspective, see R Calland Anatomy <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa: Who holds the power? (2006) 194-204.<br />

70 NM (n 6 above) para 203. See also J Neethling ‘The right to privacy, HIV/AIDS and<br />

media defendants’ (2008) 125 South African Law Journal 36 45. For a different<br />

view, see H Scott 'Liability for the mass publication <strong>of</strong> private information in<br />

South African law: NM v Smith (Freedom <strong>of</strong> Expression Institute as Amicus<br />

Curiae)' (2007) 18 Stellenbosch Law Review 387 396-398. Scott argues that the<br />

analogy between privacy and defamation law in this context is flawed, amongst<br />

other things, because in Bogoshi the result was to extend much greater<br />

protection to the media than was previously thought to be the case, whereas the<br />

impact in relation to breach <strong>of</strong> privacy is to significantly limit freedom <strong>of</strong> the<br />

media (398). However, we submit that this was only the case because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unconstitutional imposition <strong>of</strong> strict liability on the media; the point is that media<br />

defendants, post-Bogoshi, are not treated as generously as non-media defendants<br />

in the law <strong>of</strong> defamation. We consider that there is no principled objection to<br />

utilising defences that have developed in defamation law in the privacy context,<br />

in clearly analogous contexts, as the common law <strong>of</strong> privacy itself recognises. See<br />

eg Jansen van Vuuren and another NNO v Kruger 1993 4 SA 842 (A) 850.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 327<br />

context <strong>of</strong> fault liability. 71 The Constitutional Court in Khumalo v<br />

Holomisa stated that the defence <strong>of</strong> reasonable publication — which is in<br />

many respects akin to a negligence test — strikes the correct balance<br />

between freedom <strong>of</strong> expression and reputation and thus limits each right<br />

as little as possible. O'Regan J stated in that case for a unanimous court: 72<br />

The defence <strong>of</strong> reasonable publication avoids ... a winner-takes-all<br />

result and establishes a proper balance between freedom <strong>of</strong> expression<br />

and the value <strong>of</strong> human dignity. Moreover, the defence <strong>of</strong> reasonable<br />

publication will encourage editors and journalists to act with due care<br />

and respect for the individual interest in human dignity prior to<br />

publishing defamatory material, without precluding them from<br />

publishing such material when it is reasonable to do so. 73<br />

We submit that, in principle, assessing the media’s conduct through<br />

the prism <strong>of</strong> a negligence test achieves a reasonable balance between<br />

the competing considerations <strong>of</strong> privacy and dignity on the one hand,<br />

and freedom <strong>of</strong> the media on the other. On this approach, unless a<br />

defence negating unlawfulness (such as consent) applies, the media<br />

would have to establish lack <strong>of</strong> negligence in order to escape liability,<br />

such as, on the facts <strong>of</strong> NM v Smith, that its mistake as to the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> consent was not negligent. 74 Requiring the media to<br />

establish lack <strong>of</strong> negligence does not in our view constitute a<br />

disproportionate restriction on media freedom; indeed, the standards<br />

expected <strong>of</strong> reasonable journalists are <strong>of</strong>ten reflected in codes <strong>of</strong><br />

conduct, such as the Press Council’s Code, which media houses<br />

71 Another respect in which the Bogoshi principles seem to us to be capable <strong>of</strong><br />

application in privacy actions is in the context <strong>of</strong> the defence <strong>of</strong> truth and public<br />

interest. While the ‘truth’ aspect <strong>of</strong> this defence is seldom in issue in privacy<br />

cases (which typically turn on information that is true but invasive: see eg E<br />

Barendt ‘Privacy and the press’ 1995 Yearbook <strong>of</strong> Media and Entertainment Law<br />

22 26), the truth <strong>of</strong> an allegation that implicates the privacy <strong>of</strong> the plaintiff may<br />

nevertheless need to be established by the media in order to rely upon the<br />

defence <strong>of</strong> public interest (see also Tshabalala-Msimang and others v Makhanya<br />

and others [2008] 1 All SA 509 (W) para 48). Thus a plaintiff is entitled in principle<br />

to vindicate her right to privacy and dignity where false but non-defamatory facts<br />

are published, where the matter ‘is by its nature such as to attract the law <strong>of</strong><br />

[privacy]’: Ash v McKennitt and others [2007] 3 WLR 194 (CA) para 80. We submit<br />

that the application <strong>of</strong> Bogoshi to the law <strong>of</strong> privacy in this context has the result<br />

that facts which may not be true but which have been published reasonably,<br />

should also benefit from the defence <strong>of</strong> public interest. See also the approach to<br />

defences to breach <strong>of</strong> confidence actions in England: Attorney-General v<br />

Guardian Newspapers Ltd (No 2) [1990] 1 AC 109 at 283. See also the decision <strong>of</strong><br />

the English High Court in Mosley v News Group Newspapers Ltd [2008] EWHC 1777<br />

(QB) para 143 and what follows (testing the invasion <strong>of</strong> privacy in issue against<br />

the test <strong>of</strong> whether the journalist acted responsibly based on information then<br />

available to him).<br />

72 Khumalo v Holomisa (n 17 above) para 43.<br />

73<br />

Compare also the decision <strong>of</strong> Cameron J in Holomisa v Argus Newspapers (n 57<br />

above) 617.<br />

74 We submit that there is also no reason in principle why the qualification that a<br />

mistake need be reasonable should not extend to mistakes about other elements<br />

<strong>of</strong> the delict, such as whether the information constituted a private fact.


328 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

themselves espouse, 75 and negligence is a concept with which our law<br />

is familiar. 76 Moreover, a negligence standard represents a<br />

reasonable compromise between the extremes <strong>of</strong> strict liability, on<br />

the one hand, and a purely subjective test <strong>of</strong> intention, on the other.<br />

While the former provides no protection to media freedom, the latter<br />

may have the deleterious result that privacy concerns are effectively<br />

eviscerated. 77 A standard based on negligence also finds support in<br />

the analogous context <strong>of</strong> defamation law in such jurisdictions as<br />

England 78 and Australia, 79 and in the jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> the Privy<br />

Council 80 and the European Court <strong>of</strong> Human Rights. 81<br />

Accepting that negligence should apply to ‘media defendants’,<br />

the difficulty that remains is a definitional one: how should the line<br />

be drawn between media and non-media defendants? While<br />

traditional print and electronic media entities are easily recognisable,<br />

the digital revolution has the result that ‘[l]ines between different<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> media are blurring, making it difficult to apply mediumspecific<br />

definitions’. 82 O’Regan J’s guidance in NM v Smith in regard<br />

to the definitional category <strong>of</strong> media defendants is instructive:<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essional and commercial purveyors <strong>of</strong> information are well placed to<br />

ensure that appropriate systems prevent the unreasonable disclosure <strong>of</strong><br />

private facts and the negligent disclosure <strong>of</strong> those facts. This is not the<br />

case for ordinary citizens. Moreover, generally, disclosure by ordinary<br />

75 As Lord H<strong>of</strong><strong>fm</strong>ann recently stated in an English defamation case, ‘the standard <strong>of</strong><br />

responsible journalism is made more specific by the Code <strong>of</strong> Practice which has<br />

been adopted by the newspapers and ratified by the Press Complaints<br />

Commission’ (Jameel v Wall Street Journal Europe Sprl [2007] 1 AC 359 (HL)<br />

(Jameel) para 55). Expert evidence as to reasonable conduct on the part <strong>of</strong><br />

journalists could also be led, as it was in the NM, where Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Anton Harber<br />

led evidence as to what is expected <strong>of</strong> a journalist reporting the identity <strong>of</strong><br />

persons living with HIV/AIDS.<br />

76 See Sachs J in NM (n 6 above) para 204.<br />

77 We submit that the experience <strong>of</strong> the US courts with the actual malice standard<br />

that applies in defamation and false light privacy cases is instructive in this<br />

regard. This rule — first articulated by the US Supreme Court in New York Times v<br />

Sullivan 376 US 254 (1964) — has had a disproportionate impact on the rights <strong>of</strong><br />

the plaintiff and has also adversely affected the quality <strong>of</strong> public discourse. See<br />

generally D Milo Defamation and freedom <strong>of</strong> speech (2008) 203-206. This was,<br />

however, not the outcome on the approach <strong>of</strong> the majority in NM v Smith, who<br />

found intention on the part <strong>of</strong> the defendants.<br />

78 See Reynolds v Times Newspapers Ltd [2001] 2 AC 127 (HL) at 202, 205. See also<br />

Jameel (n 75 above) paras 32, 55, 149.<br />

79 Lange (n 65 above) 573.<br />

80 See eg Bonnick v Morris [2003] 1 AC 300 (PC) paras 22, 23.<br />

81<br />

See eg Bladet Tromso and Stensaas v Norway (2000) 29 EHRR 125 (Bladet) para<br />

65. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the respects in which these jurisdictions articulate a<br />

negligence test for media liability, see Milo Defamation and freedom <strong>of</strong> speech (n<br />

77 above) 188-99.<br />

82 DA Anderson ‘Freedom <strong>of</strong> the press’ (2002) 80 Texas Law Review 429 438.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 329<br />

citizens will not be as widespread as disclosure by those involved in<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>essional or commercial dissemination <strong>of</strong> information. 83<br />

On the basis <strong>of</strong> this test, the minority judges rightly regarded the<br />

publisher and Ms Smith as media defendants, but viewed Ms De Lille<br />

as a non-media defendant. 84 As we have discussed, our courts in<br />

defamation cases have adopted the proposition that the primary<br />

rationale for imposing a negligence standard on the media is the<br />

increased capacity to cause harm inter alia because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

widespread manner in which allegations may be published. We note<br />

that it is not only the traditional media that has the capacity to cause<br />

severe harm to a person’s reputation and privacy because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

extent <strong>of</strong> the publication; the wide circulation <strong>of</strong> a leaflet containing<br />

private information may also have this effect. 85 It remains an open<br />

question whether the negligence standard should apply beyond the<br />

traditional media categories, as is the case in Australian law. 86 This<br />

will require an assessment <strong>of</strong> various factors, including the capacity<br />

to cause harm; the resources available to the publisher to guard<br />

against such harm occurring; 87 whether pr<strong>of</strong>essional codes <strong>of</strong> conduct<br />

— such as the Press Council's Code and the Broadcasting Complaints<br />

Commission Code — govern the publishers; 88 the credibility attached<br />

to the medium <strong>of</strong> communication in issue; 89 and the commercial<br />

motive <strong>of</strong> the publication. 90 We caution that the imposition <strong>of</strong> a<br />

negligence standard on publishers other than the traditional media<br />

83 NM (n 6 above) para 181. See also Langa CJ at para 94: ‘It makes sense that media<br />

defendants, who are experts in the field and who routinely distribute facts to vast<br />

numbers <strong>of</strong> people, with a particular air <strong>of</strong> authority and for commercial gain,<br />

should be held liable for disclosures which they should reasonably have foreseen<br />

would cause harm’.<br />

84 NM (n 6 above) per Langa CJ paras 98-9; O’Regan J para 182. It is more difficult to<br />

understand Sachs J's decision in this regard. Sachs J concludes that all three<br />

defendants ‘did not meet the standard <strong>of</strong> reasonableness’, albeit that he<br />

accepted that the Bogoshi test applied to media defendants. It is not clear<br />

whether Sachs J regards Ms De Lille as a media defendant, thus attracting the<br />

higher standard <strong>of</strong> care, or whether he means to impose the higher standard <strong>of</strong><br />

care beyond the traditional categories <strong>of</strong> media defendants.<br />

85 In one High Court case, Marais v Groenewald en ’n ander 2001 1 SA 634 (T), it was<br />

precisely such reasoning that led to the Court imposing defamation liability based<br />

on gross negligence on the defendant, who had widely disseminated a letter to<br />

various political party structures. Van Dijkhorst J held that ‘[s]kriftelike laster<br />

kan anders as deur die media — soos hier deur partystrukture — tog ook wyd<br />

versprei word en ’n goeie naam skaad. Publikasie kan soveel wyer wees as in ’n<br />

plaaslike koerantjie’ (646). See further our comments in the text in regard to<br />

imposing negligence liability on non-media defendants.<br />

86 See also Lange (n 65 above) 572. O’Regan J in NM (n 6 above) para 181 left open<br />

the issue <strong>of</strong> whether harmful targeted disclosure <strong>of</strong> information, e.g. to a small<br />

community, should also trigger a negligence standard <strong>of</strong> fault.<br />

87 See also O'Regan J in NM (n 6 above) para 181.<br />

88 See the dictum <strong>of</strong> Lord H<strong>of</strong><strong>fm</strong>ann in Jameel (n 75 above).<br />

89<br />

See Bogoshi (n 10 above) 1213.<br />

90 See NM (n 6 above) para 98 (Langa CJ) & para 181 (O’Regan J).


330 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

should be carefully considered on a case-by-case basis, in view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

serious consequences for freedom <strong>of</strong> expression that are involved. 91<br />

6 The negligence test and reliance on <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

reports<br />

The final aspect <strong>of</strong> NM v Smith that we address in this note is the<br />

application by the minority judges <strong>of</strong> the negligence standard to the<br />

facts. It is here that O’Regan J parts ways with Langa CJ and Sachs J;<br />

while O’Regan J held that the media defendants did not act<br />

negligently, Langa CJ and Sachs J reached the opposite conclusion.<br />

The crisp issue for resolution was whether a reasonable journalist and<br />

publisher would have assumed from the Strauss Report that the<br />

plaintiffs had consented to their identities and HIV-status being<br />

revealed.<br />

Langa CJ held that the Strauss Report was not a public document<br />

and was not widely distributed; in these circumstances:<br />

The reasonable media defendant would ... not have relied on the Strauss<br />

Report as a document that removed their duty to ensure informed<br />

consent had been obtained ...<br />

The inescapable conclusion is that a reasonable journalist or a<br />

reasonable publisher would have foreseen the possibility that there was<br />

not consent. Because the possible harm was great, the effort necessary<br />

to avoid the harm minimal and the benefit <strong>of</strong> publishing the names<br />

negligible, a reasonable journalist or publisher would have taken steps<br />

to avoid that harm. 92<br />

A diametrically opposed factual conclusion was reached by O’Regan<br />

J, who would have exonerated Ms Smith and the publisher from any<br />

negligence liability. 93 The interesting aspect <strong>of</strong> O’Regan J’s judgment<br />

91<br />

As Langa CJ stated in NM (n 6 above) para 94: ‘However, to extend that standard<br />

to ordinary people, and thus to everyday relationships, would be to extend the<br />

law too far into intensely personal space ... [This] is not a matter that is<br />

appropriate for the law to regulate’.<br />

92 NM (n 6 above) paras 110-111. Langa CJ also attached significance to the expert<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Harber, that a journalist cannot assume that consent has<br />

been given in relation to HIV/AIDS reporting. Compare Sachs J at para 205, who<br />

held that Ms Smith ‘should have left no stone unturned in her pursuit <strong>of</strong><br />

verification’. We submit that this dictum, which Langa CJ also adopted (para 111)<br />

sets the bar too high for media defendants. Even allowing for the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

private information in issue, it is, we submit, not correct as a matter <strong>of</strong> principle<br />

to postulate that reasonableness required that every possible step available to<br />

verify whether consent had been given, should have been followed. Rather, what<br />

is required <strong>of</strong> Ms Smith is that, within the context <strong>of</strong> a book publication (as<br />

opposed to, for instance, the reportage <strong>of</strong> breaking news in a daily newspaper),<br />

she ought to have taken reasonable steps to verify the issue <strong>of</strong> consent.<br />

93 A conclusion also reached by the High Court (NM High Court (n 3 above) para 41).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 331<br />

for media freedom is her treatment <strong>of</strong> whether a reasonable<br />

journalist and publisher would be entitled to rely on the contents <strong>of</strong><br />

the Strauss Report, which had disclosed the identities <strong>of</strong> the<br />

plaintiffs. O’Regan J reasoned as follows:<br />

To hold that in the circumstances … [Ms Smith and the publisher] were<br />

under a further duty to contact either the <strong>University</strong> [<strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong>] or the<br />

[plaintiffs] to ensure that they had in fact consented to publication <strong>of</strong><br />

their names would impose a significant burden on freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

expression. The result <strong>of</strong> such a finding would be that where personal<br />

private facts have been published already by a reputable organisation,<br />

another organisation may not rely on that publication as having been<br />

done lawfully and without infringement <strong>of</strong> privacy. 94<br />

While we agree with much <strong>of</strong> O’Regan J’s reasoning, it is difficult to<br />

fault Langa CJ’s analysis on the facts. We consider that it may well be<br />

that O’Regan J did not attach enough significance to the expert<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Anton Harber and the nature <strong>of</strong> the privacy<br />

interests at stake, which would seem to us to require that a<br />

reasonable author and publisher <strong>of</strong> a book — presumably not under<br />

significant time pressures <strong>of</strong> the kind experienced by daily<br />

newspapers and broadcasters where breaking news is reported —<br />

ought to have taken additional steps to ascertain whether consent had<br />

been given for widespread disclosure to the public at large. 95 This is<br />

more particularly so given that the inclusion <strong>of</strong> the names <strong>of</strong> the<br />

plaintiffs could not, in the circumstances, have added much <strong>of</strong> value<br />

to the discussion in the biography <strong>of</strong> Ms De Lille's role in the saga. 96<br />

What is ground-breaking about O’Regan J’s judgment from the<br />

perspective <strong>of</strong> media freedom is her view that, as a general rule, a<br />

reasonable journalist is entitled to rely on the contents <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

documents:<br />

Journalists must be entitled to publish information provided to them by<br />

reliable sources without rechecking in each case whether the publication<br />

was lawful, unless there is some material basis upon which to conclude<br />

that there is a risk that the original publication was not lawful. If there<br />

is a reasonable basis for suspecting that the publication <strong>of</strong> private<br />

information was without consent, a journalist will, <strong>of</strong> course, bear an<br />

94<br />

NM (n 6 above) para 185.<br />

95 Langa CJ in NM (n 6 above) para 111 suggests that the steps that a reasonable<br />

journalist would have taken on the facts included finding the annexures to the<br />

Strauss Report containing the terms <strong>of</strong> the consent by the plaintiffs or contacting<br />

the plaintiffs directly.<br />

96 Michelman ‘Interpretive charity’ (n 37 above) [current page 45 <strong>of</strong> article; editors<br />

to insert] <strong>of</strong> this volume.] attaches great significance to this point in rejecting<br />

O'Regan J's analysis on the facts.


332 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

obligation to check. If there are no grounds for such suspicion, it cannot<br />

be said that a journalist acts negligently in not checking. 97<br />

This observation takes our reasonable publication law a significant<br />

step further than the Bogoshi progeny to date. In Bogoshi, Hefer JA<br />

set out a number <strong>of</strong> relevant factors to determine reasonableness <strong>of</strong><br />

media conduct, including the ‘character and known provenance’ <strong>of</strong><br />

the information, ‘the nature, extent and tone <strong>of</strong> the allegations’, ‘the<br />

reliability <strong>of</strong> their source as well as the steps taken to verify the<br />

information’, and ‘the opportunity given to the person concerned to<br />

respond, and the need to publish before establishing the truth in a<br />

positive manner’. 98 However, it has been disappointing that, in the<br />

ten years since Bogoshi was handed down, very little guidance has<br />

emerged from the Courts as to how the reasonable publication test<br />

should be applied in a concrete set <strong>of</strong> circumstances. 99 The leading<br />

decision on the application <strong>of</strong> the Bogoshi case, Mthembi-Mahanyele<br />

v Mail & Guardian Ltd, 100 muddied the waters, with the Supreme<br />

Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal split evenly on the issue <strong>of</strong> whether the newspaper<br />

could benefit from a reasonable publication defence. Whereas Lewis<br />

JA — with whom Howie P concurred — regarded the journalists'<br />

conduct as reasonable, inter alia on the basis that the tone <strong>of</strong> the<br />

article was irreverent and that the newspapers had relied on<br />

information in the public domain, 101 Mthiyane JA — with whom Mpati<br />

DP concurred — ruled that none <strong>of</strong> the guidelines suggested in Bogoshi<br />

was followed by the newspaper. 102 Mthembi-Mahanyele did little to<br />

illustrate how to concretise some <strong>of</strong> factors that Hefer JA had<br />

enunciated in the Bogoshi case.<br />

O’Regan J’s approach in NM v Smith that a journalist is, all things<br />

being equal, entitled to publish information derived from a reliable<br />

source, and particularly to repeat allegations made by a reputable<br />

organisation, therefore represents a desirable development in our<br />

jurisprudence in favour <strong>of</strong> media freedom. We submit that O’Regan J<br />

97 NM (n 6 above) para 187. Langa CJ endorsed this suggestion; he held that<br />

‘journalists should not be forced to verify disclosures made by reputable<br />

organisations’, but this would depend on ‘the nature <strong>of</strong> the document, the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> the institution that produced the document, the importance <strong>of</strong> the interests<br />

involved and the relevant circumstances <strong>of</strong> the case’ (para 102).<br />

98 Bogoshi (n 10 above) 1212-1213.<br />

99 There have been only a handful <strong>of</strong> reported decisions applying Bogoshi, and not<br />

much clarity as to its application has emerged. For instance, in Sayed v Editor,<br />

Cape Times 2004 1 SA 58 (C), Davis J held that the defence was available for a<br />

story that had been produced with ‘considerable care’, whereas the defence<br />

failed in Lady Agasim-Pereira v Johnnic Publishing Eastern Cape (Pty) Ltd [2003]<br />

2 All SA 416 (SE), inter alia on the basis that obvious sources had not been<br />

contacted to verify the allegations.<br />

100 n 59 above.<br />

101 Mthembi-Mahanyele (n 59 above) 74.<br />

102 Mthembi-Mahanyele (n 59 above) para 110. The fifth judge, Ponnan AJA, held<br />

that the publication was not defamatory to begin with; he therefore did not need<br />

to address defences available to the media (para 85).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 333<br />

is correct to observe that, in general, it would set the standard <strong>of</strong><br />

reasonableness too high to require journalists to verify the contents<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial reports or documents, and that to require this would have<br />

a chilling effect on freedom <strong>of</strong> the media. This position is in harmony<br />

with the developing reasonable publication jurisprudence in England<br />

and in the European Court <strong>of</strong> Human Rights.<br />

In England, the responsible publication defence has been held to<br />

entitle publishers to argue that their reporting <strong>of</strong> an important issue<br />

<strong>of</strong> public interest qualifies for protection under the ‘neutral<br />

reportage’ doctrine. In one leading case, Charman v Orion Group<br />

Publishing Group Ltd and others, 103 the Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal confirmed<br />

that a responsible publication defence will be available where<br />

'judging the thrust <strong>of</strong> the report as a whole, the effect <strong>of</strong> the report<br />

is not to adopt the truth <strong>of</strong> what is being said, but to record the fact<br />

that the statements which were defamatory were made'. 104 In such<br />

cases, journalists will not be required to verify the truth <strong>of</strong> the<br />

underlying allegations. 105<br />

The European Court <strong>of</strong> Human Rights has expressly adopted the<br />

proposition contended for by O’Regan J. In Bladet Troms and Stensaas<br />

v Norway, 106 the facts were that defamation proceedings were<br />

brought against a newspaper and its editor in relation to an article<br />

alleging breaches <strong>of</strong> seal hunting regulations. The Court held that an<br />

interference with the article 10 rights 107 <strong>of</strong> the press was not<br />

justifiable. The newspaper had relied on the <strong>of</strong>ficial report prepared<br />

by a seal hunting inspector for the Ministry <strong>of</strong> Fisheries. The Court<br />

held as follows:<br />

In the view <strong>of</strong> the Court, the press should normally be entitled, when<br />

contributing to public debate on matters <strong>of</strong> legitimate concern, to rely<br />

on the contents <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial reports without having to undertake<br />

independent research. Otherwise, the vital public-watchdog role <strong>of</strong> the<br />

press may be undermined ...<br />

[T]he Court considers that the paper could reasonably rely on the <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

... report, without being required to carry out its own research into the<br />

accuracy <strong>of</strong> the facts reported. It sees no reason to doubt that the<br />

newspaper acted in good faith in this respect. 108<br />

The sanctioning in this jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> reliance on <strong>of</strong>ficial reports<br />

and other documents <strong>of</strong> solid providence has the potential to grant<br />

103 [2008] 1 All ER 750 (CA) (Charman).<br />

104 Charman (n 103 above) para 48.<br />

105 See also Roberts v Gable [2008] 2 WLR 129 (CA) para 53.<br />

106 n 81 above.<br />

107 Article 10 <strong>of</strong> the European Convention on Human Rights protects freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

expression.<br />

108 Bladet (n 81 above) paras 68, 72.


334 Media freedom and the law <strong>of</strong> privacy<br />

the media significant breathing space to pursue important stories on<br />

matters <strong>of</strong> public interest. For instance, where a media publisher<br />

repeats allegations made in an <strong>of</strong>ficial report, it should not be<br />

required <strong>of</strong> the media publisher to take extensive steps to verify the<br />

contents <strong>of</strong> the report (although the subject <strong>of</strong> the allegation should<br />

generally be provided with a right <strong>of</strong> reply). Stated differently, the<br />

media defendant's conduct in not verifying the truth <strong>of</strong> the allegations<br />

emanating from such a source should not count against it when<br />

assessing its conduct, both for purposes <strong>of</strong> the reasonableness<br />

defence (which negates unlawfulness) and for the defence <strong>of</strong> lack <strong>of</strong><br />

negligence (which negates fault).<br />

7 Conclusion<br />

NM v Smith is a fascinating — and disappointing — decision <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court on many levels. We have discussed some aspects<br />

<strong>of</strong> the decision in this note. From the perspective <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

jurisprudence, it is unfortunate that the majority <strong>of</strong> the Court treated<br />

the factual enquiry as to whether the defendants acted with intention<br />

in publishing the plaintiffs’ identities as a constitutional matter,<br />

without undertaking any substantive analysis <strong>of</strong> this difficult issue.<br />

This is particularly the case where the majority’s approach is difficult<br />

to reconcile with previous decisions <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court on<br />

what is and what is not a ‘constitutional matter’. The majority <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Court in our view also appeared to reach the incorrect conclusion on<br />

the facts, finding that the defendants had intentionally violated the<br />

plaintiffs’ privacy. We prefer the judgments <strong>of</strong> the minority judges,<br />

who reached a conclusion on the major constitutional issue involved<br />

in the case — that the media need to establish absence <strong>of</strong> negligence<br />

in publishing private information. The decision <strong>of</strong> Langa CJ on the<br />

facts — visiting negligence liability on the media defendants —<br />

appears to us to be defensible. Further, O’Regan J’s endorsement <strong>of</strong><br />

a general rule that journalists are entitled to rely on reliable sources<br />

and information from reputable organisations, represents a<br />

significant advance in our media freedom jurisprudence.


WANTED: A PRINCIPLED APPROACH TO<br />

THE BALANCING OF PUBLIC POLICY<br />

CONSIDERATIONS. STEENKAMP NO V<br />

PROVINCIAL TENDER BOARD,<br />

EASTERN CAPE<br />

It matters how judges decide cases 1<br />

1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

*<br />

Senior Lecturer, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Witwatersrand. BA, LLB (Cape) LLM (Wits). I wish to<br />

thank the editors <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court Review for inviting me to be a<br />

contributor to the inaugural edition and for affording me the opportunity to<br />

present an earlier version <strong>of</strong> this note at the Constitutional Court Review<br />

Conference in Somerset West. I am thankful for the comments and questions<br />

raised by the participants at the conference, particularly those <strong>of</strong> Cora Hoexter. I<br />

would especially like to thank Stu Woolman for his editorial input, as well as for<br />

his continuing support, encouragement and patience. In the spirit <strong>of</strong> Harambee, I<br />

must express my heartfelt thanks to Mtendeweka Mhango for his insightful<br />

comments and valuable engagement with an earlier version <strong>of</strong> this paper. Finally,<br />

I must convey my thanks to Jonathan Klaaren for his critical and insightful<br />

comments. Any mistakes or omissions remain my own.<br />

1<br />

See R Dworkin Law’s empire (1986) 1.<br />

2 2007 3 BCLR 300 (CC).<br />

335<br />

Sanele Sibanda*<br />

Steenkamp NO v Provincial Tender Board, Eastern Cape 2 is unlikely to<br />

generate too much controversy in academic circles or in the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ession. The majority decision entrenches the status quo in so far<br />

as the delictual liability <strong>of</strong> tender boards is concerned. And apart from<br />

the majority judgment’s rather confounding comments that appeared<br />

to conceive the subject <strong>of</strong> remedies in rather rigid and dichotomous<br />

terms, nothing in the written text appears outwardly contentious.<br />

Even the disagreement between the majority and the minority<br />

concerns a point <strong>of</strong> law upon which reasonable people could disagree.<br />

However, that is not to say that the judgment does not raise any<br />

issues <strong>of</strong> interest and concern. My aim in this note is to reflect upon,<br />

and where appropriate critique, the manner in which the majority and<br />

minority arrived at their respective positions with respect to the


336 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness. In particular, I will consider the<br />

manner in which the both judgments dealt with the balancing <strong>of</strong> the<br />

public policy considerations raised. I critique the rather thinly<br />

substantiated, individualised and subjectivised approach <strong>of</strong> the<br />

majority to the balancing <strong>of</strong> the policy considerations. In particular, I<br />

take issue with the fact that the majority’s approach is focused on<br />

justifying the outcome <strong>of</strong> the matter as and between the parties, thus<br />

missing an important opportunity to guide us on how matters involving<br />

similar considerations should be approached in future. I then contrast<br />

this approach with the minority’s clearer identification <strong>of</strong> the values<br />

and interests represented by the policy considerations raised.<br />

The minority’s approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> policy considerations<br />

— grounded in the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality — is to be preferred.<br />

Proportionality doe not simply require that courts clearly identify the<br />

competing values or interests at stake in a dispute. Properly<br />

conceived, proportionality demands that courts elaborate in some<br />

detail the reasons that support their conclusions.<br />

2 Background and facts<br />

Although judgment in Steenkamp was handed down in 2006 and<br />

reported in 2007, the facts giving rise to this matter preceded the<br />

Constitutional Court’s decision by over a decade. The matter has its<br />

origins in disputed tender proceedings in the Eastern Cape. In 1996,<br />

Balraz Technologies (Pty) Ltd (‘Balraz’) was awarded a tender by the<br />

provincial tender board. However, that award was subsequently set<br />

aside in review proceedings instituted by one <strong>of</strong> the unsuccessful<br />

tenderers, Cash Paymaster Services (Pty) Ltd. 3 In Cash Paymaster<br />

Services (Pty) Ltd v Eastern Cape Province, the court held that given<br />

the irregularities in the tender adjudication process, the tender board<br />

had acted in an administratively unfair manner.<br />

Unfortunately, Balraz did not survive to tender another day. It was<br />

placed under final liquidation before it could retender. As a result, all<br />

future claims relating to the original tender were instituted by<br />

Balraz’s liquidator. At the trial court, the applicant, Balraz’s<br />

liquidator, was unsuccessful in its claim for the recovery <strong>of</strong> out-<strong>of</strong>pocket<br />

expenses incurred as a result <strong>of</strong> its having commenced to<br />

deliver services as per the contract arising out <strong>of</strong> the original tender<br />

award. The court held that the applicant’s status as an unregistered<br />

entity at the time <strong>of</strong> submitting its tender documentation rendered<br />

the tender award void. No relationship giving rise to a duty <strong>of</strong> care<br />

could have arisen as and between itself and the tender board. Put<br />

3<br />

For the review decision, see Cash Paymaster Services (Pty) Ltd v Eastern Cape<br />

Province 1999 1 SA 324 (Ck).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 337<br />

differently, the conduct <strong>of</strong> the tender board vis-à-vis the applicant<br />

could not be properly conceived as being wrongful.<br />

Undeterred by this outcome, the applicant appealed to the<br />

Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal. That appeal was dismissed. The Supreme<br />

Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal’s decision focused on the delictual liability <strong>of</strong> the<br />

tender board as a public body. It held, on grounds <strong>of</strong> public policy,<br />

that neither statute nor common law ought to be extended to cover<br />

alleged delictual damages caused by the tender board (to the<br />

applicant) that were <strong>of</strong> a purely economic nature. The Supreme Court<br />

<strong>of</strong> Appeal held so despite the fact that it had found that the tender<br />

board had acted negligently (albeit in good faith).<br />

3 The majority decision 4<br />

In the Constitutional Court, the issue was crystallised as follows: Can<br />

a once successful tenderer recover its out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket expenses<br />

incurred after the contract was awarded, but before the said award<br />

was set aside on review? 5 The majority judgment, delivered by<br />

Moseneke DCJ, turned on whether or not the respondent’s decision to<br />

award the tender to the applicant, whilst in breach <strong>of</strong> its<br />

constitutional and statutory mandate to exercise its powers in an<br />

administratively fair manner, was wrongful in a delictual sense. 6 The<br />

respondent had conceded that it had acted in an administratively<br />

unfair manner, albeit in good faith, when it assessed and awarded the<br />

tender to Balraz. 7<br />

In considering the import <strong>of</strong> the tender board’s failure to uphold<br />

the principles <strong>of</strong> administrative justice, the majority rejected the<br />

idea that the breach <strong>of</strong> a constitutional or a statutory duty should as<br />

a matter <strong>of</strong> course be regarded as being delictually wrongful.<br />

According to the majority, the determination <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness giving<br />

rise to the recognition <strong>of</strong> a duty <strong>of</strong> care and liability on the part <strong>of</strong> a<br />

defendant could not be made without having regard to public policy<br />

considerations <strong>of</strong> what was fair and reasonable in the particular<br />

circumstances. 8<br />

4 I do not consider the concurring decision delivered by Sachs J because the issues<br />

raised therein are not germane to those presently under consideration.<br />

5<br />

Two other issues were raised in the Constitutional Court: firstly, whether or not<br />

there was a constitutional issue raised; and secondly, whether or not it was in the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> justice to consider the matter. These issues will not be discussed in<br />

this note. For present purposes it suffices to say that in both instances the<br />

decision <strong>of</strong> the court was in the affirmative.<br />

6 See sec 187 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa, Act 200 <strong>of</strong> 1993<br />

(Interim Constitution) and sec 217(1) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South<br />

Africa, 1996 (‘Final’ Constitution); and the State Tender Board Act 2 <strong>of</strong> 1994<br />

(Repealed by Provincial Tender Board Repeal Act (Eastern Cape) 6 <strong>of</strong> 2004).<br />

7<br />

Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 36.<br />

8 Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 37.


338 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

In holding that the applicant’s claim must fail, the majority held<br />

that the applicable constitutional and statutory provisions in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

which the tender board acted did not envision a tenderer in the<br />

position <strong>of</strong> Balraz having a claim to damages. 9 Instead the majority<br />

took the view that had Balraz been prudent in the circumstances, it<br />

would have utilised other avenues <strong>of</strong> redress available to it to<br />

mitigate its risk <strong>of</strong> loss. 10 For example, according to the majority,<br />

Balraz could have tendered again after the adverse outcome <strong>of</strong> the<br />

review proceedings. 11 Alternatively it could have negotiated for a<br />

right to reimbursement for out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket expenses at the time <strong>of</strong><br />

contracting in order to safeguard it from loss in the event <strong>of</strong> the<br />

tender award being overturned on review. 12<br />

In concluding that Balraz was not owed a duty <strong>of</strong> care by the<br />

tender board, the majority held that no rights or values in the<br />

Constitution would justify an extension <strong>of</strong> the ambit <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong><br />

delict in the manner sought. In reaching this conclusion, the majority<br />

found that compelling public policy considerations required that it<br />

provide some level <strong>of</strong> immunity to tender boards that made innocent<br />

but negligent decisions. 13 One such policy consideration that weighed<br />

heavily on the majority was a deep-seated concern that an extension<br />

<strong>of</strong> liability in the manner sought would open the floodgates <strong>of</strong><br />

litigation by unsuccessful tenderers. This prospect, the majority<br />

feared, would have the undesirable consequence <strong>of</strong> eroding the<br />

efficacy <strong>of</strong> the tendering process and tarnishing the image <strong>of</strong> tender<br />

boards in the public’s eyes. 14 Given that the majority had disposed <strong>of</strong><br />

the matter on the basis <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness, the majority declined to<br />

answer questions relating to the validity <strong>of</strong> Balraz’s tender or the<br />

tender board’s negligence. 15<br />

4 The minority decision<br />

Langa CJ and O’Regan J, in delivering the dissenting minority<br />

judgment, identified one especially critical ground upon which they<br />

9 Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 47.<br />

10<br />

Moseneke DCJ, clearly unmoved by the applicant’s contentions, makes this point<br />

when he writes that ‘[o]n the facts, Balraz wasted no moment to accept the<br />

tender award. But once the order to supply goods and services was made by the<br />

department, Balraz should have curbed its commercial enthusiasm as it was well<br />

within its right to require that its initial expense not lead to its financial ruin<br />

should the award be nullified. Balraz unnecessarily chose the more hazardous<br />

course which is to incur mainly salary expenses <strong>of</strong> directors without fashioning<br />

out an appropriate safeguard. Its loss could have been easily curbed by prudent<br />

conduct and precaution.’ Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 52.<br />

11<br />

Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 49.<br />

12 Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 50.<br />

13 Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 55(a).<br />

14<br />

Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 55(b).<br />

15 Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 61.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 339<br />

differed with the majority, namely the determination <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness<br />

on the part <strong>of</strong> the tender board. Langa CJ and O’Regan J deemed it<br />

important to characterise the applicant’s claim as one <strong>of</strong> pure<br />

economic loss. Such a characterisation had historically played a part<br />

in the courts’ disinclination to recognise a duty <strong>of</strong> care. 16<br />

According to the minority, the nature <strong>of</strong> the wrongfulness inquiry<br />

in the post 1994-era must, in essence, accord with the norms and the<br />

values <strong>of</strong> Constitution. In a matter such as the one before the Court,<br />

the minority held that the following norms or principles had to be<br />

taken into account when determining wrongfulness:<br />

(1) The need to guarantee that successful tenderers have an enduring<br />

faith in the tender process and the resultant contracts. Such a guarantee<br />

ensures that tenderers commence to deliver on their contracts timeously<br />

without having to labour under the fear <strong>of</strong> facing financial ruin in the<br />

event that a tender is subsequently set aside through no fault <strong>of</strong> their<br />

own. Further, a failure to provide such a guarantee posed a greater risk<br />

<strong>of</strong> financial ruin to smaller or new business enterprises that government<br />

procurement policies sought to promote. 17<br />

(2) The need to properly differentiate between claims for damages<br />

arising out <strong>of</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it instituted by an unsuccessful tenderer on the<br />

one hand; and damages resulting from out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket expenditure<br />

incurred by an initially successful tenderer who had commenced to<br />

deliver services in accordance with its contractual obligations. The<br />

former would constitute a windfall claim and the latter a claim for<br />

reimbursement for services rendered. 18<br />

(3) The need to promote accountability in the entire tender process in<br />

order to ensure that that once successful tenderers who incur out-<strong>of</strong>pocket<br />

expenditure spent in the good faith fulfilment <strong>of</strong> a tender<br />

contract were not unduly burdened with unrecoverable expenditure.<br />

Such a burden would inevitably have a detrimental impact on the future<br />

delivery <strong>of</strong> tender obligations.<br />

Having considered the factors set out above, the minority concluded<br />

that in the circumstances <strong>of</strong> the case, the tender board acted<br />

wrongfully, owed the applicant a duty <strong>of</strong> care, and thus created the<br />

basis for a claim for delictual damages.<br />

16 Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 67.<br />

17<br />

Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 82.<br />

18 Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 83.


340 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

5 Comparing the approach <strong>of</strong> the majority and<br />

the minority to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy<br />

considerations<br />

My focus in this section will be on what I take to be the main point <strong>of</strong><br />

disagreement between the two opinions: namely the approach to the<br />

balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations. I will not, therefore,<br />

concern myself with the actual decision reached on the nonconstitutional<br />

point <strong>of</strong> delictual wrongfulness. For purposes <strong>of</strong> this<br />

note I am satisfied that the Court could conceivably have gone either<br />

way.<br />

5.1 Wrongfulness as a requirement for delictual liability<br />

Before I turn squarely to the central concern <strong>of</strong> this note, namely the<br />

balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations I want to consider briefly the<br />

requirement <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness as an element <strong>of</strong> delictual liability. The<br />

requirement <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness is a sine qua non for the attachment <strong>of</strong><br />

delictual liability. Wrongfulness, in a delictual sense, is said to exist<br />

where particular conduct either infringes upon a person’s legally<br />

recognised right or where it results in the breach <strong>of</strong> a legal duty owed<br />

to a person by another. 19 According to Neethling et al, whether<br />

particular conduct is in fact wrongful is determined with reference to<br />

the legal convictions <strong>of</strong> the community or the community’s boni<br />

mores. This inquiry, according to the authors, entails an objective<br />

test based on the criterion <strong>of</strong> reasonableness. The pertinent question<br />

to ask is whether or not the conduct in question was justifiable or<br />

unjustifiable. 20<br />

In the context <strong>of</strong> the wrongfulness inquiry, the determination <strong>of</strong><br />

reasonableness requires (a) that a court must take into consideration<br />

all the circumstances <strong>of</strong> the matter pertaining to the parties and (b)<br />

that a court must consider issues <strong>of</strong> public and legal policy in making<br />

a value judgment as to how the alleged wrongdoer’s conduct should<br />

be viewed by society. 21 The second proviso requires that the<br />

19 JR Midgley & JC Van der Walt ‘Delict’ LAWSA (2nd ed, 2005) Volume 8(1) para 60.<br />

See also J Neethling et al Law <strong>of</strong> delict transl & ed J Knobel (5th ed, 2005) 31.<br />

20 Neethling et al (n 19 above) 34.<br />

21<br />

See Olitzki Property Holdings v State Tender Board and Another 2001 8 BCLR 779<br />

(SCA) para 12 (Cameron JA commenting on how reasonableness is determined<br />

puts it as follows: ‘The determination <strong>of</strong> reasonableness here in turn depends on<br />

whether affording the plaintiff a remedy is congruent with the court’s<br />

appreciation <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> justice <strong>of</strong> the community. This appreciation must<br />

unavoidably include the application <strong>of</strong> broad considerations <strong>of</strong> public policy<br />

determined also in the light <strong>of</strong> the Constitution and the impact upon them that<br />

the grant or refusal <strong>of</strong> the remedy the plaintiff seeks will entail.’ (footnotes<br />

omitted).) See also Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security v Van Duivenboden 2002 6 SA


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 341<br />

reasonableness <strong>of</strong> particular conduct be determined in terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

legal convictions <strong>of</strong> the community. 22 Historically, the test for<br />

reasonableness in this context has been described as being openended<br />

and flexible. It necessarily takes cognisance <strong>of</strong> the everevolving<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the legal convictions <strong>of</strong> the community. 23<br />

5.2 The important role <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations in<br />

determining wrongfulness in novel situations<br />

The role played by public policy considerations in the determination<br />

<strong>of</strong> reasonableness in areas where liability has not previously been<br />

established cannot be overstated. 24 Van Aswegen, writing in the preconstitutional<br />

era, pointed out that the most important role played by<br />

policy considerations has been in ‘the new developments, expansions<br />

and adaptations to the settled body <strong>of</strong> delict law.’ 25 The overriding<br />

utility <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations is that they afford the court an<br />

opportunity to consider novel problems for which there is no<br />

precedent or authority. In other words, despite the clearly openended<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> ‘public policy’, the concept, at the<br />

very least, requires judges to provide some level <strong>of</strong> principled<br />

reasoning grounded in social policy for the decisions that they make.<br />

The importance <strong>of</strong> public policy has been entrenched further in<br />

the current constitutional dispensation. Significant developments<br />

have occurred in extending the limits <strong>of</strong> delictual liability through the<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> new duties <strong>of</strong> care. These new duties have <strong>of</strong>ten been<br />

21 431 (SCA) para 16; Premier <strong>of</strong> the Province <strong>of</strong> the Western Cape v Fair Cape<br />

Property Developers (Pty) Ltd [2003] 2 All SA 465 (SCA) para 41.<br />

22<br />

Neethling et al (n 19 above) 34. See also A Fagan ‘Rethinking wrongfulness in the<br />

law <strong>of</strong> delict’ (2005) 122 South African Law Journal 90 93-94. Although, strictly<br />

speaking, it is outside the scope <strong>of</strong> this paper, it is worth mentioning that the<br />

Fagan’s robust analysis <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness as an element <strong>of</strong> delict in the<br />

aforementioned article has ignited a debate with respect to the manner in which<br />

our courts engage in the wrongfulness inquiry (and its relationship to negligence).<br />

See J Neethling ‘The conflation <strong>of</strong> wrongflness and negligence: Is it always such a<br />

bad thing for the law <strong>of</strong> delict’ (2006) 123 South African Law Journal 204; RW<br />

Nugent ‘Yes, it is always a bad thing for the law: A reply to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Neethling’<br />

(2006) 123 South African Law Journal 557; J Neethling & JM Potgieter<br />

‘Wrongfulness and negligence in the law <strong>of</strong> delict: A Babylonian confusion?’<br />

(2007) 70 Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg (2007) 120; J<br />

Neethling & JM Potgieter ‘In (self)defence <strong>of</strong> the distinction between<br />

wrongfulness and negligence’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 280; and A<br />

Fagan ‘Blind Faith: A response to Pr<strong>of</strong>essors Neethling and Potgieter’ (2007) 124<br />

South African Law Journal 285.<br />

23 See Midgley et al (n 19) para 60. See also Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Fund<br />

(Commission for Gender Equality Intervening) 1999 2 All SA (SCA) para 23.<br />

24<br />

MM Corbett ‘Aspects <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> policy in the evolution <strong>of</strong> our common law’<br />

(1987) 104 South African Law Journal 67.<br />

25 A van Aswegen ‘Policy considerations in the law <strong>of</strong> delict’ 1993 (56) Tydskrif vir<br />

Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 171; See also Midgley et al (n 19 above)<br />

para 60.


342 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

rooted in the ‘constitutionalisation’ <strong>of</strong> public policy. In Carmichele, 26<br />

the Constitutional Court recognised that in making the type <strong>of</strong> value<br />

judgments required in order to determine wrongfulness in novel<br />

situations, the constitutional injunction contained in s 39(2) requires<br />

all courts to promote the spirit, object and purport <strong>of</strong> the bill <strong>of</strong><br />

rights. 27 In deciding to extend the delictual liability <strong>of</strong> police <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

and prosecutors to instances wherein the wrongful conduct<br />

constituted an actionable omission, the Carmichele Court accepted<br />

that the determination <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness demands that some regard be<br />

paid to public policy considerations. Ackermann J and Goldstone J<br />

wrote:<br />

Before the advent <strong>of</strong> the [Interim Constitution], the refashioning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law in this area entailed ‘policy decisions and value judgments’<br />

which had to ‘reflect the wishes <strong>of</strong>ten unspoken, and the perceptions,<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten dimly discerned, <strong>of</strong> the people’. A balance had to be struck<br />

between the interests <strong>of</strong> the parties and the conflicting interests <strong>of</strong> the<br />

community according to what ‘the (c)ourt conceives to be society’s<br />

notions <strong>of</strong> what justice demands’. Under s 39(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

concepts such as policy decisions and value judgments reflecting ‘the<br />

wishes ... and the perceptions ... <strong>of</strong> the people’ and ‘society’s notions <strong>of</strong><br />

what justice demands’ might well have to be replaced, or supplemented<br />

and enriched by the appropriate norms <strong>of</strong> the objective value system<br />

embodied in the Constitution. 28 (emphasis added)<br />

The Court’s acknowledgment <strong>of</strong> the fact that the advent <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution has established ‘an objective normative value system’<br />

has influenced the development <strong>of</strong> notions <strong>of</strong> public policy and,<br />

concomitantly, the understanding <strong>of</strong> what constitutes the legal<br />

convictions <strong>of</strong> the community. 29 The influence <strong>of</strong> this ‘phrase’ has led<br />

26 See Carmichele v Minister <strong>of</strong> Safety and Security 2001 4 SA 938 (CC) (hailed as a<br />

groundbreaking judgment that saw the extension <strong>of</strong> the delictual liability for<br />

omissions to instances in which the police and public prosecutors failed to act in<br />

circumstances where they could have prevented the plaintiff from being raped).<br />

Section 39 (2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution reads as follows: ‘When interpreting any<br />

legislation, and when developing the common law or customary law, every court,<br />

tribunal or forum must promote the spirit, purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights’.<br />

27 Woolman has made the point that the effect <strong>of</strong> sec 39(2) is to place a mandatory<br />

injunction on all courts to interpret all laws in a way that promotes the spirit,<br />

purport and objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. Put differently, sec 39(2) establishes an<br />

interpretive canon that dispels any notions <strong>of</strong> judicial discretion. In accordance<br />

with this view, a failure by the lower courts to fulfil the obligation imposed by sec<br />

39(2) renders their decisions susceptible to constitutional review by the<br />

Constitutional Court. See S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al (eds)<br />

Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) ch 31. See also F<br />

Michelman ‘The rule <strong>of</strong> law, legality and the supremacy <strong>of</strong> the Constitution’ in<br />

Woolman et al (eds) (above) ch 11.<br />

28 Carmichele (n 26 above) para 56 (footnotes omitted).<br />

29 See Woolman ‘Application’ in Woolman et al (eds) (n 27 above) 31-93, for a<br />

discussion on the origins, application and problems with use <strong>of</strong> the phrase ‘an<br />

objective normative value system’ in South African constitutional jurisprudence.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 343<br />

to positive developments in the lower courts. Olitzki, 30 Premier,<br />

Western Cape v Fair Cape Property Developers, 31 and the Supreme<br />

Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal decision <strong>of</strong> Steenkamp 32 all turn on the grounding <strong>of</strong><br />

fairness and reasonableness in terms <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights and<br />

constitutional norms. 33<br />

However, in spite <strong>of</strong> these positive developments, a couple <strong>of</strong><br />

important questions are left unanswered. How does a court determine<br />

what public policy considerations to take into account when engaging<br />

with the wrongfulness inquiry in a novel situation? And further, is<br />

there a principled basis upon which courts go about balancing public<br />

policy considerations; or is it a purely a matter <strong>of</strong> judicial discretion?<br />

In fact, what becomes evident from a review <strong>of</strong> the South African<br />

academic literature and case law is that although the determination<br />

<strong>of</strong> wrongfulness is ultimately a legal question, no explicit legal rules<br />

or principles guide the selection or the deployment <strong>of</strong> public policy<br />

considerations. 34<br />

So despite the apparent mandatory injunction <strong>of</strong> s 39(2), the<br />

courts enjoy and exercise a wide discretion with regard to the type <strong>of</strong><br />

public policy considerations that they deem appropriate and relevant<br />

in any particular situation. At a minimum, the litigants’ pleadings will<br />

influence the choice <strong>of</strong> policy considerations. However the courts, as<br />

was demonstrated in Carmichele, must consider, mero motu, other<br />

relevant policy considerations including those that flow from our basic<br />

law. While sound reasons exist for this type <strong>of</strong> judicial discretion —<br />

the inevitability <strong>of</strong> novel disputes — the same considerations do not<br />

30 Olitzki (n 21 above) para 31.<br />

31 Premier <strong>of</strong> the Province <strong>of</strong> the Western Cape v Fair Cape Property Developers<br />

(Pty) Ltd [2003] 2 All SA 465 (SCA) para 33.<br />

32<br />

Steenkamp NO v Provincial Tender Board, Eastern Cape [2006] 1 All SA 478 (SCA)<br />

para 25 (Steenkamp (SCA)).<br />

33 See Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association <strong>of</strong> South Africa: In re Ex parte<br />

President <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa 2000 2 SA 674 (CC) para 44. In this<br />

matter, Chaskalson CJ emphatically pronounced that ‘there is only one system <strong>of</strong><br />

law. It is shaped by the Constitution which is the supreme law, and all law,<br />

including the common law, derives its force from the Constitution and is subject<br />

to constitutional control.’ Although the context and issues under consideration<br />

when Chaskalson CJ made this pronouncement were quite different from the<br />

issues under consideration presently, the potency <strong>of</strong> this holding can equally be<br />

extended to the present context. This is to say that the courts have, in my<br />

opinion, correctly recognised the overarching influence <strong>of</strong> the Constitution such<br />

that even in the determination <strong>of</strong> matters <strong>of</strong> public policy, such determination<br />

must be made within the rubric <strong>of</strong> constitutional norms and principles. See also B<br />

Leinius & JR Midgley ‘The impact <strong>of</strong> the Constitution on the law <strong>of</strong> delict’ (2002)<br />

119 South African Law Journal 20; Neethling et al (n 19 above) 36.<br />

34 See van Aswegen (n 25 above) 174. She considers the philosophical underpinnings<br />

<strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> policy considerations and whether or not they can appropriately<br />

be considered to constitute legal rules when applied in judicial decision-making.<br />

Although Van Aswegen argues convincingly that policy considerations when<br />

invoked by judges are equally part <strong>of</strong> the law as are other legal sources, she does<br />

not deal with the question as to how judges should decide on what these<br />

considerations are to be, nor how they should be applied in a particular instance.


344 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

come into play when it comes to the determination <strong>of</strong> how competing<br />

public policy considerations should be assessed and reconciled.<br />

5.3 A comparative evaluation <strong>of</strong> the approach taken by the<br />

majority and the minority to the balancing <strong>of</strong> policy<br />

considerations<br />

In Steenkamp, both the majority and minority judgments took into<br />

account similar policy considerations with respect to the impact that<br />

an extension <strong>of</strong> delictual liability would have on the functioning <strong>of</strong><br />

tender boards. 35 However, the two judgments came to vastly<br />

different conclusions as far as the weight to be attached to these<br />

considerations is concerned and whether the tender board acted<br />

wrongfully. The majority was clearly moved by arguments advanced<br />

against the extension <strong>of</strong> liability, whilst the minority was less<br />

persuaded. The arrival at different conclusions is not something that<br />

in itself is notable. Different judges will disagree regarding the<br />

construction <strong>of</strong> the facts and proper application <strong>of</strong> the law. I would<br />

even go so far as to contend that such differences <strong>of</strong> opinion amongst<br />

judges are a desirable feature <strong>of</strong> any legal system that is attuned to<br />

the contested views <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> law from different sectors <strong>of</strong> a<br />

heterogeneous polity. However, for present purposes my concern is<br />

not with the different conclusions reached by judges <strong>of</strong> the majority<br />

and the minority. It remains, rather simply, focused on the manner in<br />

which they engage competing policy considerations.<br />

One major problem with the majority’s approach to wrongfulness<br />

is that it reveals a decidedly individualised inquiry that places undue<br />

emphasis on Balraz’s particular circumstances and fails to focus on<br />

the public policy considerations underlying its claim. 36 It would<br />

appear from the majority decision that although the majority does<br />

take cognisance <strong>of</strong> the public policy grounds raised by the plaintiff, it<br />

did not seriously engage them. 37 By way <strong>of</strong> contrast, the<br />

considerations <strong>of</strong> public policy in support <strong>of</strong> not extending liability to<br />

35 See Steenkamp (n 2 above) paras 49-50 & 55 (majority judgment) and paras 87-92<br />

(minority judgment).<br />

36 See Steenkamp (n 2 above) paras 43-46 (majority judgment).<br />

37 In fact Moseneke DCJ, Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 47, states: ‘I must at the<br />

outset say that the submissions <strong>of</strong> the applicant are attractive but not<br />

sustainable’.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 345<br />

tender boards, although also not engaged with at great length, 38 are<br />

considered in a decidedly more objective fashion that clearly<br />

identifies the public interests that they seek to promote without<br />

subjectivising the inquiry to focus on the conduct <strong>of</strong> this particular<br />

tender board. Ultimately, the competing public policy considerations<br />

pit the individualised considerations <strong>of</strong> the applicant against the<br />

potentially negative social consequences and public interest concerns<br />

that militate against the extension <strong>of</strong> delictually liability to tender<br />

boards. The entire exercise ineluctably results in the emasculation <strong>of</strong><br />

the applicant’s claim. This diminishment <strong>of</strong> the applicant’s (public<br />

policy) interests not only creates an extra hurdle for the applicant,<br />

but unjustifiably shifts the focus away from the open and candid<br />

consideration <strong>of</strong> competing interests that a proportionality exercise<br />

demands when determining the question <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness.<br />

Put somewhat differently, the primary problem with the approach<br />

taken by the majority is its failure to identify and elaborate upon the<br />

values and interests underlying the applicant’s claim for a delictual<br />

remedy and properly weighing them up against the competing values<br />

and interests <strong>of</strong> the tender board as a public body. The applicant had<br />

an underlying right to administrative justice 39 and a right to<br />

appropriate relief. 40 And yet neither the right nor the desired remedy<br />

is engaged by the majority’s opinion. Instead the majority’s reasoning<br />

is predicated on the belief that the applicant should have shown that<br />

it had done everything within its power to mitigate its loss before it<br />

could allege wrongfulness.<br />

The minority opinion takes a markedly different approach to the<br />

identification, elaboration and assessment <strong>of</strong> competing policy<br />

considerations when determining the question <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness. The<br />

minority’s approach, although also clearly grounded in the factual<br />

matrix <strong>of</strong> the matter before the court, is more deliberate in the<br />

manner in which it engages with these competing considerations. By<br />

this I simply mean that the minority’s approach displays a more<br />

deliberate effort to identify the societal and public interests that<br />

38<br />

See Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 55: Moseneke DCJ holds that the majority concur<br />

with the ‘significant findings and conclusions’ <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal. It<br />

is interesting to note that Moseneke DCJ finds it adequate to concur in this<br />

fashion and simply leave the matter there. What makes this fact all the more<br />

peculiar is the fact that earlier on in the decision the Deputy Chief Justice goes to<br />

some length to justify the constitutional importance <strong>of</strong> the matter at hand; and<br />

its potential to influence the future development <strong>of</strong> the law in respect <strong>of</strong> appeals<br />

to private law remedies in matters that are clearly founded in public law. See<br />

Steenkamp (n 2 above) paras 17-23.<br />

39<br />

See sec 33(1) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution: ‘Everyone has the right to for the right to<br />

administrative action that is lawful, reasonable and procedurally fair.’<br />

40 Section 38 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution affords a person a right to approach a court seeking<br />

‘appropriate relief’ where that person alleges that their rights have been<br />

infringed.


346 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

underpinned the applicant’s claim. 41 Although not expressly<br />

articulated in these terms, the minority approach to the assessment<br />

<strong>of</strong> public policy considerations would appear to be grounded in the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality. 42<br />

41 The best way to illustrate this point is by way <strong>of</strong> example. The approach <strong>of</strong> the<br />

majority and that <strong>of</strong> the minority differ on the point <strong>of</strong> whether or not the law<br />

should be developed to accommodate a claim for out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket expenses<br />

instituted by a once successful tenderer. The majority position on this point is set<br />

out as follows:<br />

The residual question is whether there is justification to develop the<br />

common law to embrace this narrow claim for damages based on out-<strong>of</strong>pocket<br />

expenses in favour <strong>of</strong> an initially successful tenderer where the<br />

award is subsequently set aside by the court and the tenderer retains the<br />

right to participate in the subsequent tender process. I think not. First,<br />

there is no magic in characterising financial loss as out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket. If<br />

public policy is slow to recompense financial loss <strong>of</strong> disappointed<br />

tenderers it should not change simply because <strong>of</strong> the name the financial<br />

loss bears. Second, even if there may not be a public law remedy such as<br />

an interdict, review or appeal this is no reason for resorting to damages<br />

as a remedy for out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket loss. This is so because first, as I found<br />

earlier, the loss may be avoided and second it is not justified to<br />

discriminate between tenderers only on the basis that they are either<br />

disappointed tenderers or initially successful tenderers. To do so is to<br />

allot different legal rights to parties to the same tender process. There is<br />

no justification for this distinction particularly because ordinarily both<br />

classes <strong>of</strong> tenderers are free to tender again should the initial tender be<br />

set aside. Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 54.<br />

The minority position on this point is set out as follows:<br />

A claim for out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket expenses, however, is a far more modest claim.<br />

Moreover, the inability to recover out-<strong>of</strong>-pocket expenses may well<br />

render smaller and less financially viable tenderers at risk <strong>of</strong> liquidation.<br />

Indeed, such was the case here. In our country, government procurement<br />

is one <strong>of</strong> the key mechanisms for ensuring that those previously locked<br />

out <strong>of</strong> economic opportunity by the policies <strong>of</strong> apartheid, are given an<br />

opportunity to participate. By definition such companies and individuals<br />

are <strong>of</strong>ten new, small and not financially robust. In our view, this is an<br />

additional and important factor which supports our conclusion that both<br />

Moseneke DCJ and the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal are incorrect to conclude<br />

that aquilian liability cannot arise on the circumstances <strong>of</strong> this case.<br />

Steenkamp (note 2 above) para 80.<br />

42 See Steenkamp (n 2 above) para 69. Although Langa CJ and O’Regan make no<br />

direct reference to the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality, it is, in my view, implicit in<br />

their approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> policy considerations: ‘Determining whether<br />

conduct is wrongful or unlawful for the purposes <strong>of</strong> aquilian liability, as has been<br />

stated on many occasions, essentially involves a question <strong>of</strong> legal policy which<br />

must be answered in the light <strong>of</strong> the norms and values <strong>of</strong> our society and, since<br />

1994, in the light <strong>of</strong> the norms <strong>of</strong> our Constitution. Even though the question is a<br />

normative one, it is not to be answered on the basis <strong>of</strong> 'an intuitive reaction to a<br />

collection <strong>of</strong> arbitrary factors', but instead requires an identification <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relevant norms followed by an analysis and, if necessary, balancing <strong>of</strong> those<br />

norms to determine the outcome.’ (parqa 70) (emphasis mine and footnotes<br />

omitted.)


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 347<br />

6 The prinicple <strong>of</strong> proportionalty: A possible<br />

basis upon which the balancing <strong>of</strong> public<br />

policy considerations should be performed?<br />

The principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality is firmly established in South African<br />

constitutional law. The invocation <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality<br />

has been experienced mainly within the context <strong>of</strong> limitations<br />

analysis. 43 The most fundamental idea underlying the principle <strong>of</strong><br />

proportionality is that courts will candidly assess the competing<br />

rights, values and interests reflected in both the asserted<br />

constitutional norm and in the existing law that allegedly impairs that<br />

norm. 44 In other words, the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality requires more<br />

than a mechanical exercise <strong>of</strong> summing up on some imagined scale the<br />

respective virtues <strong>of</strong> the two sides to the disputes. Chaskalson P, in S<br />

v Makwanyane, <strong>of</strong>fers up a lucid exposition <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality and what it entails:<br />

The limitation <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights for a purpose that is reasonable<br />

and necessary in democratic society involves the weighing up <strong>of</strong><br />

competing values, and ultimately an assessment based on<br />

proportionality. This is implicit in the provisions <strong>of</strong> section 33 (1). The<br />

fact that different rights have different implications for democracy, and<br />

in the case <strong>of</strong> our Constitution, for an ‘open and democratic society<br />

based on freedom and equality’, means there is no absolute standard<br />

which can be laid down for determining reasonableness and necessity.<br />

Principles can be established, but the application <strong>of</strong> those principles to<br />

particular circumstances can only be done on a case by case basis. This<br />

is inherent in the requirement <strong>of</strong> proportionality, which calls for the<br />

balancing <strong>of</strong> different interests. 45<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality would appear to be most<br />

apparent in those areas or instances where the courts must address<br />

rather novel issues, where no clear legal rule or precedent exists and<br />

where important matters <strong>of</strong> principle are at stake. 46 In such instances<br />

the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality will require a court deciding upon such<br />

43<br />

Section 36 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution provides the test for the limitation <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional rights.<br />

44 See S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations’ in Woolman et al (eds) (n 27 above) ch 34;<br />

I Currie & J de Waal The Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights handbook (5th ed, 2005) 172-8; G Erasmus<br />

‘Limitation and suspension’ in D van Wyk et al (eds) Rights and constitutionalism:<br />

The new South African legal order (1994) 629.<br />

45<br />

1995 3 SA 391 (CC) para 104. This dictum has been cited with approval in many<br />

subsequent cases. See, eg, National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v<br />

Minister <strong>of</strong> Justice and Others 1999 1 SA 6 (CC) para 33.<br />

46<br />

An obvious example <strong>of</strong> such an issue is where a law is being challenged for<br />

violating the rights protected in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights. In most instances there will be<br />

some right demand — fundamental and therefore worthy <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

protection — being pitted against some law that will <strong>of</strong>ten seek to attain some<br />

important societal purpose.


348 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

an issue to make explicit, at least, the following: the exact nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the conflict; what the competing or conflicting values or interests are<br />

and the importance <strong>of</strong> these; and the substantive reasons for choosing<br />

one set <strong>of</strong> values or interests over the other. In other words, the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality demands that where the courts are<br />

required to engage in the exercise <strong>of</strong> balancing they should do so in a<br />

manner that clearly identifies all the pertinent competing values or<br />

interests, before weighing these up and providing fully substantiated<br />

conclusions. This type <strong>of</strong> application <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong><br />

proportionality is one that we have become accustomed to seeing at<br />

work in our bill <strong>of</strong> rights jurisprudence.<br />

The application <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality or at the very<br />

least an approach that is closely akin to it is nothing novel in delict.<br />

Courts have <strong>of</strong>ten had to consider whether or not to extend liability.<br />

In Carmichele, Judges Ackermann and Goldstone allude to the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> [the principle <strong>of</strong>] proportionality: 47<br />

... in determining whether there was a legal duty on the police <strong>of</strong>ficer to<br />

act, Hefer JA in Minister <strong>of</strong> Law and Order v Kadir referred to weighing<br />

and striking a balance between the interests <strong>of</strong> the parties and the<br />

conflicting interests <strong>of</strong> the community. This is a proportionality exercise<br />

with liability depending upon the interplay <strong>of</strong> various factors.<br />

Proportionality is consistent with the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, but that exercise<br />

must now be carried out in accordance with the ‘spirit, purport and<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights’ and the relevant factors must be weighed in<br />

the context <strong>of</strong> [a] constitutional State founded on dignity, equality and<br />

freedom and in which government has positive duties to promote and<br />

uphold such values. (emphasis added)<br />

The core <strong>of</strong> the idea underlying the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality and<br />

how it can add an important dimension to public policy considerations<br />

in the determination <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness was powerfully captured by<br />

Nugent JA in Van Duivenboden:<br />

When determining whether the law should recognise the existence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

legal duty in any particular circumstances what is called for is not an<br />

intuitive reaction to a collection <strong>of</strong> arbitrary factors, but rather a<br />

balancing against one another <strong>of</strong> identifiable norms. 48 (emphasis added)<br />

A similar approach to rethinking public policy considerations grounded<br />

in an application <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality was also followed<br />

in Steenkamp (SCA). 49 The Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal’s judgment —<br />

like the minority’s opinion in the Constitutional Court — illustrates<br />

how the principle <strong>of</strong> proportionality can be applied in the<br />

47 Carmichele (n 26 above) para 43.<br />

48<br />

Van Duivenboden (n 26 above) para 21.<br />

49 Steenkamp (SCA) (n 32 above).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 349<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> wrongfulness. The SCA’s decision accomplishes this<br />

task by meticulously identifying and engaging with the public policy<br />

considerations it deemed relevant to the determination <strong>of</strong><br />

wrongfulness. 50 The SCA focused on the public and societal interests<br />

that underlay both the appellant’s claim for a remedy and the<br />

respondent’s denial <strong>of</strong> liability. Although the final decision with<br />

respect to wrongfulness in the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal accords with<br />

that <strong>of</strong> the majority <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court, it is certainly more<br />

palatable. It gives due consideration to the competing rights and<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> both the applicant and the respondent in an objective and<br />

judicious manner. In short, the conclusion reached as to the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> wrongfulness in the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal decision is more<br />

transparently reasoned and does not leave one with an uneasy sense<br />

that the exercise <strong>of</strong> balancing masks the subjective whims <strong>of</strong><br />

judges. 51<br />

7 Conclusion<br />

Again. My discomfort with the Constitutional Court’s majority<br />

decision in Steenkamp is not with its conclusion that the conduct <strong>of</strong><br />

the tender board was not wrongful. The matter really could have gone<br />

either way. However, my main concern and the reason for writing this<br />

note is to take issue with the unsatisfactory and somewhat opaque<br />

manner in which the majority reached its conclusion. The most<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ound shortcoming <strong>of</strong> this decision is that it leaves the<br />

Constitutional Court vulnerable to the critique that the ultimate<br />

conclusion as to wrongfulness reflects a mere subjective preference<br />

rather than a decision grounded in principle. That some may consider<br />

this charge to be unfair criticism is undoubted. However, as long as<br />

courts continue to engage in an amorphous balancing exercise,<br />

critiques such as mine will be difficult to rebut. A failure to develop<br />

a principled framework will always leave those who are sitting on the<br />

wrong side <strong>of</strong> a decision in which public policy considerations were<br />

considered with reason to be sceptical about what actually animated<br />

50<br />

See Steenkamp (SCA) (n 32 above) paras 29-44<br />

51 See Woolman & Botha (n 44 above) 34-93 to 34-104 9: The authors provide a<br />

sustained critique <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> balancing and its relationship with<br />

proportionality; in particular, the inappropriateness <strong>of</strong> the balancing metaphor in<br />

constitutional adjudication.


350 Wanted: A principled approach to the balancing <strong>of</strong> public policy considerations<br />

a court’s decision. 52<br />

Steenkamp has given us an opportunity to consider how the<br />

exercise <strong>of</strong> balancing policy considerations might be pr<strong>of</strong>itably<br />

supplanted by a more principled framework. The principle <strong>of</strong><br />

proportionality is a useful departure point in the creation <strong>of</strong> such a<br />

framework. The appeal <strong>of</strong> this principle, to my mind, is that it is<br />

already established in our law, and more importantly, that it accords<br />

with the unarticulated practices that have already taken hold in our<br />

courts under the new constitutional dispensation.<br />

52 In a recent article Stuart Woolman has raised similar concerns about the<br />

Constitutional Court’s thin reasoning. Woolman objects to this minimalist mode <strong>of</strong><br />

adjudicative reasoning by the Constitutional Court for several reasons, not least<br />

<strong>of</strong> which is that he considers it to be tantamount to abdication by the<br />

Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> its responsibility to develop clearly articulated rules and<br />

to provide clearly substantiated reasons for its decisions. These clearly<br />

articulated rules and substantiated reasons are, according to Woolman, essential<br />

for purposes <strong>of</strong> developing a coherent constitutional jurisprudence that informs<br />

political discourse, as well as serving to guide the lower courts and the other<br />

coordinate branches <strong>of</strong> government. S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing Bill <strong>of</strong><br />

Rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 762 784-787. See also F Michelman<br />

‘On the uses <strong>of</strong> “interpretive charity”’: Some notes on application, avoidance,<br />

equality and objective unconstitutionality from the 2007 term <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitutional Court <strong>of</strong> South Africa’ (2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 1<br />

(Contends that while the judgments in question are thinly reasoned, they can, if<br />

patiently (and charitably) assessed, and if given sufficient expiation by<br />

commentators, be reconstructed so as to avoid some <strong>of</strong> the alleged problems with<br />

both their form and substance.)


1 <strong>Intro</strong>duction<br />

SEVERING THE UMBILICAL CORD: A<br />

SUBTLE JURISPRUDENTIAL SHIFT<br />

REGARDING CHILDREN AND THEIR<br />

PRIMARY CAREGIVERS<br />

351<br />

Ann Skelton<br />

In S v M (Centre for Child Law as Amicus Curiae) 1 the Constitutional<br />

Court overturned a High Court judgment in which a primary caregiver<br />

<strong>of</strong> children had been sentenced to correctional supervision, including<br />

a brief period <strong>of</strong> imprisonment. The appellant had been convicted on<br />

multiple counts <strong>of</strong> fraud in the Regional Court. The sentence handed<br />

down by the High Court on appeal required her to undergo<br />

imprisonment prior to possible release on correctional supervision.<br />

Her further appeal to the Constitutional Court focused on the duties<br />

<strong>of</strong> a court when sentencing a primary caregiver, given the<br />

constitutional injunction that a child’s best interests are <strong>of</strong><br />

paramount importance in all matters concerning the child. The<br />

Constitutional Court’s judgment subtly adjusts the balancing exercise<br />

at sentencing, as governed by the so-called ‘triad <strong>of</strong> Zinn’ principles.<br />

The judgment also provides an endorsement <strong>of</strong> the usefulness <strong>of</strong><br />

correctional supervision, one <strong>of</strong> the benefits <strong>of</strong> which is the scope that<br />

it allows for the application <strong>of</strong> restorative justice.<br />

The more pr<strong>of</strong>ound aspect <strong>of</strong> the judgment in S v M, however, lies<br />

in its development <strong>of</strong> child law, and in particular in what the<br />

Constitutional Court adds to its previous pronouncements on section<br />

28 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution 2 — that the section is a statement <strong>of</strong> realisable<br />

and enforceable rights. In S v M, the Court pays more detailed<br />

attention than previously to the ‘best interests <strong>of</strong> the child’ principle.<br />

The Court also expands for the first time on what the Constitution<br />

means when it says that the best interests <strong>of</strong> the child are <strong>of</strong><br />

paramount importance in all matters concerning the child. This case<br />

note examines the focus in the judgment on the child’s rights as<br />

1<br />

2008 3 SA 232; 2007 12 BCLR 1312 (CC); 2007 2 SACR 539 (CC) (S v M).<br />

2 Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa, 1996 (the Constitution).


352 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

distinct from the rights <strong>of</strong> their caregivers. It is argued that this<br />

distinction presents a new development in the Court’s child rights<br />

jurisprudence, and that some <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Court’s earlier<br />

pronouncements on children in relation to their caregivers should be<br />

re-examined in the light <strong>of</strong> S v M.<br />

What are the duties <strong>of</strong> a sentencing court in the light <strong>of</strong> section<br />

28(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution when the person being sentenced is the<br />

primary caregiver <strong>of</strong> minor children? This question was the central<br />

pivot <strong>of</strong> the arguments and judgment in S v M. The case wound its way<br />

up to the Constitutional Court by means <strong>of</strong> a long journey that began<br />

in the Wynberg Regional Court. The applicant in the case was M, 3 the<br />

mother <strong>of</strong> three minor children. She was the sole caregiver <strong>of</strong> the<br />

children, and was also the main provider <strong>of</strong> financial support for their<br />

care. She had raised a bond on a modest home in which the family<br />

lived on the income she derived from two small businesses. She was<br />

convicted on various counts <strong>of</strong> fraud and theft and was sentenced<br />

initially by the Regional Court to four years imprisonment. 4 On<br />

appeal, the High Court confirmed her conviction on 38 counts <strong>of</strong> fraud<br />

and three <strong>of</strong> theft amounting to a total value <strong>of</strong> just over R19 000. The<br />

High Court set aside her sentence and replaced it with a sentence <strong>of</strong><br />

four years in terms <strong>of</strong> section 276(1)(i) <strong>of</strong> the Criminal Procedure Act<br />

51 <strong>of</strong> 1977, a sentence which incorporates correctional supervision,<br />

subject to an initial portion <strong>of</strong> the sentence being served in prison.<br />

The High Court refused the applicant leave to appeal to the Supreme<br />

Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal, and that Court itself turned down a petition for leave<br />

to appeal. 5<br />

The effect <strong>of</strong> the High Court sentence was that the applicant<br />

would have had to serve no less than a total <strong>of</strong> eight months<br />

imprisonment before the Commissioner <strong>of</strong> Correctional Services could<br />

have considered releasing her on correctional supervision. When the<br />

applicant noted an appeal in the Regional Court against her sentence,<br />

that court denied her bail pending the determination <strong>of</strong> her appeal.<br />

Consequently, the applicant began serving her sentence on 29 May<br />

2003. The High Court granted the applicant appeal bail on 25 July<br />

2003, after she had served just under two months <strong>of</strong> her sentence. She<br />

remained on bail at the time when the matter was heard in the<br />

Constitutional Court. The fact that she had served two months in 2003<br />

meant that she was in effect facing a period <strong>of</strong> no less than six months<br />

<strong>of</strong> further imprisonment in terms <strong>of</strong> the sentence imposed by the High<br />

Court.<br />

3<br />

The Constitutional Court issued an order on the day <strong>of</strong> hearing that the citation <strong>of</strong><br />

the case name should include only the initial <strong>of</strong> the applicant’s surname, in order<br />

to protect the identity <strong>of</strong> her children.<br />

4<br />

S v M (n 1 above) para 3.<br />

5 S v M (n 1 above) para 4.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 353<br />

The Constitutional Court decided to enrol her application for<br />

leave to appeal. The Chief Justice issued directions in which he posed<br />

three questions, 6 and required that the parties should confine the<br />

scope <strong>of</strong> their submissions to answering these. In addition to the<br />

central question <strong>of</strong> defining the role <strong>of</strong> a sentencing court when<br />

sentencing a primary caregiver <strong>of</strong> minor children, the Chief Justice<br />

also directed that once the duties had been identified, there should<br />

be consideration <strong>of</strong> whether the duties were observed in this case.<br />

The final question posed was that if the Court were to find that the<br />

duties were not observed, what order (if any) should the Court make?<br />

The Court had asked the Cape Bar to appoint a curator ad litem<br />

for the children, and the curator compiled a comprehensive report for<br />

the Court, in addition to making oral submissions. The Centre for Child<br />

Law, which had been granted leave to enter the case as amicus<br />

curiae, also presented ‘wide ranging written and oral submissions on<br />

the constitutional, statutory and social context in which the matter<br />

fell to be decided’. 7<br />

The applicant, the curator and the amicus all contended that the<br />

sentencing court had a duty to give specific and independent<br />

consideration to the effect that sentencing a caregiver to<br />

imprisonment would have on minor children. 8 It was conceded that<br />

there would be cases where the best interests <strong>of</strong> the child would be<br />

outweighed by the imperative to sentence a caregiver to<br />

imprisonment where considerations <strong>of</strong> proportionality required that.<br />

On the facts <strong>of</strong> M’s case, however, it was argued that due<br />

consideration <strong>of</strong> the best interests <strong>of</strong> the children led to the<br />

conclusion that the appropriate sentence would be one that did not<br />

require M to spend any further time in prison. It was proposed that<br />

conditions could be added to the sentence <strong>of</strong> correctional supervision<br />

to redress the impact <strong>of</strong> the crime on the victims and to recognise the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

6 S v M (n 1 above) para 5.<br />

7 S v M (n 1 above) para 6.<br />

8<br />

S v M was not the first case to find that a sentencing court had such a duty. In S v<br />

Kika 1998 2 SACR 428 (W) the High Court set aside a sentence <strong>of</strong> a fine which<br />

resulted in imprisonment <strong>of</strong> a primary caregiver, finding that the magistrate had<br />

not considered the impact that the sentence might have on the children. The<br />

judge caused the circumstances to be investigated, and sent the matter back to<br />

the court a quo for the setting <strong>of</strong> a fresh sentence, pointing out a court must,<br />

when sentencing a primary caregiver, be satisfied that the welfare needs <strong>of</strong> the<br />

children will be met. The direct link with section 28(1)(b) and section 28(2) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution was first articulated in S v Howells 1999 1 SACR 675 (C); 1999 2 All SA<br />

233 (C) affirmed on appeal by the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal in Howells v S 2000<br />

JOL 6577 (SCA). In that case the court considered the effect that imprisonment <strong>of</strong><br />

a primary caregiver convicted <strong>of</strong> fraud would have on the children, but<br />

nevertheless decided to set a sentence <strong>of</strong> imprisonment, whilst making ancillary<br />

orders to ensure the children would be adequately cared for.


354 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

The response <strong>of</strong> the National Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions,<br />

supported in the main by the Department <strong>of</strong> Social Development and<br />

the Department <strong>of</strong> Justice and Constitutional Development, was that<br />

the current operation <strong>of</strong> the general principles <strong>of</strong> sentencing provided<br />

sufficient room for the consideration <strong>of</strong> the best interests <strong>of</strong> the<br />

primary caregiver’s children. Their submissions were that the courts<br />

a quo in this matter had given adequate consideration to the situation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the children, and that the sentence should not be interfered with.<br />

The majority judgment <strong>of</strong> the Court was written by Sachs J.<br />

Characterised by ringing language and memorable passages, the<br />

judgment is the Court’s clearest and most detailed explanation to<br />

date <strong>of</strong> the content and scope <strong>of</strong> children’s rights as set out in section<br />

28 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution. The judgment also makes some interesting<br />

observations about recent developments in the principles <strong>of</strong><br />

sentencing, such as the growing recognition <strong>of</strong> restorative justice, 9<br />

and re-affirms the importance and usefulness <strong>of</strong> correctional<br />

supervision as a form <strong>of</strong> sentence. 10 For the sake <strong>of</strong> completeness,<br />

this case note will provide an overview <strong>of</strong> the judgment, including a<br />

brief consideration <strong>of</strong> the Court’s findings and observations on<br />

sentencing. The major part <strong>of</strong> the note will expand on the Court’s<br />

pronouncements on children’s rights, and in particular the Court’s<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> the paramount importance <strong>of</strong> the best interests <strong>of</strong><br />

the child as stated in section 28(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution.<br />

2 Overview <strong>of</strong> the judgment<br />

The majority judgment proceeds by delivering responses to the key<br />

questions that had been posed by the Court. Expounding on the duties<br />

<strong>of</strong> the sentencing court in the light <strong>of</strong> section 28(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution<br />

when the person being sentenced is the primary caregiver <strong>of</strong> minor<br />

children, the Court begins by considering the current approach to<br />

sentencing. Sachs J finds that the Zinn 11 triad still retains the status<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘sentencing north star’. 12 However, this departure point must<br />

now be considered in the light <strong>of</strong> the Constitution, which has<br />

transformed the traditional aims <strong>of</strong> sentencing. 13 In the view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

9 S v M (n 1 above) para 55.<br />

10<br />

S v M (n 1 above) para 58-59.<br />

11 In S v Zinn 1969 2 SA 537 (A) at 540G-H the appellate division described what has<br />

to be considered at sentencing as ‘the triad consisting <strong>of</strong> the crime, the <strong>of</strong>fender<br />

and the interests <strong>of</strong> society’.<br />

12 S v M (n 1 above) para 10 fn 4.<br />

13 S v M (n 1 above) para 10. The court makes reference to the case <strong>of</strong> Director <strong>of</strong><br />

Public Prosecutions, KwaZulu-Natal v P 2006 3 SA 515 (SCA); 2006 1 All SA 446<br />

(SCA); 2006 1 SACR 243 (SCA); and Brandt v S 2005 2 All SA 1 (SCA); S v B 2006 1<br />

SACR 311 (SCA). These cases deal with the way in which the Constitution has<br />

changed the approach to sentencing <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fenders who were below the age <strong>of</strong> 18<br />

years at the time <strong>of</strong> the commission <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>fence.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 355<br />

Court, the question to be asked was whether the rights <strong>of</strong> children as<br />

set out in section 28 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution ‘add an extra element’ 14 to<br />

the responsibilities <strong>of</strong> a sentencing court over and above those<br />

imposed by the Zinn triad, and if so, how are those responsibilities to<br />

be fulfilled? In order to examine this question properly, the Court<br />

turned its attention to the significance <strong>of</strong> section 28(2) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Constitution, namely the ‘best interests <strong>of</strong> the child’ provision. 15 The<br />

detail <strong>of</strong> this aspect <strong>of</strong> the judgment will be discussed below. For the<br />

moment it is sufficient to note that the Court reiterates that section<br />

28(2) is a self-standing right, as well as being a guideline for the<br />

balancing <strong>of</strong> other rights. The question is not whether section 28<br />

creates enforceable rights — which clearly it does — but rather ‘what<br />

reasonable limits can be placed on their application’? 16 In exploring<br />

this, the court tackles the issue <strong>of</strong> what is meant by ‘paramount’. The<br />

judgment strives to establish how the paramountcy principle operates<br />

in practice, particularly when the child’s rights are being weighed<br />

against other important competing rights. The weighing exercise in<br />

M’s case was that between the rights <strong>of</strong> the children not to be<br />

separated from parental or family care and to have their best<br />

interests considered, and the rights <strong>of</strong> society to be protected by the<br />

punishment <strong>of</strong> criminal misconduct.<br />

Having established the scope and significance <strong>of</strong> section 28, the<br />

inquiry shifted to what the proper approach <strong>of</strong> a sentencing court<br />

should be where the convicted person is the primary caregiver <strong>of</strong><br />

minor children. Is it enough to consider the plight <strong>of</strong> the children as<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the Zinn triad — that part <strong>of</strong> the triangle dealing with the<br />

criminal and his or her circumstances? Counsel for the Director <strong>of</strong><br />

Public Prosecutions had argued that the principles <strong>of</strong> sentencing<br />

provided sufficient scope to consider the situation <strong>of</strong> the children,<br />

and that the law needed no development. The Court took a different<br />

approach, favouring the view <strong>of</strong> the amicus that a child <strong>of</strong> a primary<br />

caregiver is not a ‘circumstance’ but an individual whose interests<br />

needed independent consideration. 17 The weight that would be<br />

accorded to those interests would depend on the facts <strong>of</strong> each case,<br />

but the Court determined that there was a duty on any court<br />

sentencing a primary caregiver to give separate and specific<br />

consideration to the impact that the intended sentence would have<br />

on the children. The Court took cognisance <strong>of</strong> information that had<br />

been placed before it about the effects on children <strong>of</strong> the<br />

imprisonment <strong>of</strong> their primary caregivers. Also considered was the<br />

international legal framework, the UN Convention on the Rights <strong>of</strong> the<br />

14<br />

15<br />

S v M (n 1 above) para 11.<br />

Section 28(2) reads as follows: ‘A child’s best interests are <strong>of</strong> paramount<br />

16<br />

17<br />

importance in every matter concerning the child’.<br />

S v M (n 1 above) para 14.<br />

S v M (n 1 above) para 30.


356 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

Child, and in particular the African Charter on the Rights and Welfare<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Child. Article 30(1) <strong>of</strong> that Charter contains a unique provision<br />

dealing expressly with ‘Children <strong>of</strong> Imprisoned Mothers’. Of particular<br />

relevance were clauses calling on states parties to ‘ensure that a noncustodial<br />

sentence will always be first considered when sentencing<br />

such mothers’; and to ‘establish and promote measures alternative to<br />

institutional confinement <strong>of</strong> such mothers’. Article 30(1) concludes by<br />

reminding the states parties that ‘the essential aim <strong>of</strong> the<br />

penitentiary system will be the reformation, the integration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mother to the family and social rehabilitation’.<br />

The Court held as follows:<br />

[F]ocused and informed attention needs to be given to the interests <strong>of</strong><br />

children at appropriate moments in the sentencing process. The<br />

objective is to ensure that the sentencing court is in a position<br />

adequately to balance all the varied interests involved, including those<br />

<strong>of</strong> the children placed at risk. This should become a standard<br />

preoccupation <strong>of</strong> all sentencing courts. 18<br />

The result <strong>of</strong> the judgment in S v M, therefore, is that in each case<br />

the sentencing court must give specific attention to the impact the<br />

sentence will have on the child or children <strong>of</strong> a primary caregiver. This<br />

does not mean that a primary caregiver will never, henceforth, be<br />

given a custodial sentence. The judgment explains quite clearly that<br />

the choice <strong>of</strong> the sentencing option least damaging to the interests <strong>of</strong><br />

the children is made ‘within the legitimate range <strong>of</strong> choices in the<br />

circumstances available to the court’. 19 In other words, if a noncustodial<br />

option is clearly appropriate, the court must impose such a<br />

sentence, bearing in mind the interests <strong>of</strong> the children. If there is a<br />

range <strong>of</strong> appropriate sentences under consideration, the likely<br />

negative impact <strong>of</strong> imprisonment on the children <strong>of</strong> the primary<br />

caregiver will generally tip the balance in favour <strong>of</strong> a communitybased<br />

sentence.<br />

If the court cannot reasonably consider a non-custodial sentence<br />

in the circumstances, the court’s responsibilities do not end there.<br />

The judgment gives step-by-step guidelines indicating that<br />

if, on the Zinn triad approach the appropriate sentence is clearly<br />

custodial and the convicted person is a primary caregiver, the court must<br />

apply its mind to whether it is necessary to take steps to ensure that the<br />

children will be adequately cared for while the caregiver is<br />

incarcerated. 20<br />

18 S v M (n 1 above) para 33.<br />

19<br />

As above.<br />

20 S v M (n 1 above) para 36.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 357<br />

Having enumerated the duties, the majority then applied them to<br />

the facts <strong>of</strong> M’s case and decided to overturn the High Court sentence.<br />

It was replaced with a sentence that allowed her to serve no further<br />

time in prison. The remainder <strong>of</strong> the sentence was suspended, on<br />

various conditions, including correctional supervision for a period <strong>of</strong><br />

three years, and repayment to the victims <strong>of</strong> the crime <strong>of</strong> the monies<br />

<strong>of</strong> which they had been defrauded. In addition to the need to protect<br />

the children’s best interests, the fact that M had not committed<br />

<strong>of</strong>fences for a long time, and had made demonstrable efforts to be a<br />

contributing member <strong>of</strong> society were strong factors influencing the<br />

choice <strong>of</strong> sentence. The Court pondered whether it should, having<br />

decided to set aside the order <strong>of</strong> the High Court, replace the sentence<br />

or refer the matter back for the court a quo to reconsider. It decided<br />

to set a new sentence itself, due to the fact that a significant amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> up-to-date and good quality information had been placed before it.<br />

The Court made several interesting observations regarding<br />

sentence. The judgment weighs up the advantages <strong>of</strong> correctional<br />

supervision versus a custodial sentence. 21 Correctional supervision is<br />

described as ‘a multifaceted approach to sentencing comprising<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> rehabilitation, reparation and restorative justice.’ 22 It is<br />

also a sentence that, if applied to those who are likely to respond<br />

positively, can protect society without the destructive impact that<br />

imprisonment can have on innocent family members. The Court<br />

remarked on prison overcrowding, pointing out that rehabilitation is<br />

difficult to achieve under such circumstances, and that therefore<br />

correctional supervision is a sentence which is more likely to result in<br />

rehabilitation. 23 The Court went on to say that ‘[a]nother advantage<br />

<strong>of</strong> correctional supervision is that it keeps open the option <strong>of</strong><br />

restorative justice in a way that imprisonment cannot do’. The court<br />

21<br />

The judgment recalls the Court’s earlier judgment in S v Williams and Others<br />

1995 3 SA (CC), per Langa J as he then was: ‘The development <strong>of</strong> this process [<strong>of</strong><br />

correctional supervision] must not be seen as a weakness, as the justice system<br />

having “gone s<strong>of</strong>t.”’<br />

22 S v M (n 1 above) para 59. The Court refers to the following judgments regarding<br />

correctional supervision: S v R 1993 1 SA 476 (A); S v Siebert 1998 1 SACR 554<br />

(SCA); S v Ingram 1995 1 SACR 1 (SCA).<br />

23 S v M (n 1 above) para 61. The Court cites S v Lebuku 2006 JOL 17622 (T) para 13<br />

– 15 with approval, where Webster J refers to the 2003/2004 Annual Report <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Inspecting Judge <strong>of</strong> Prisons in which Judge Fagan recommended the use <strong>of</strong> noncustodial<br />

sentences in appropriate cases, in order to avoid further over-crowding.


358 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

explained that central to the notion <strong>of</strong> restorative justice24 is the<br />

recognition that the community, and not the criminal justice system,<br />

that is the site <strong>of</strong> crime control. The sentence handed down by the<br />

Court demonstrates a restorative justice lens, as in addition to being<br />

confined to her home when not working, and being required to do 10<br />

hours <strong>of</strong> community service per week, M was required to pay back her<br />

victims, which she had <strong>of</strong>fered to do. With regard to this, a particular<br />

point is made:<br />

It would have special significance if she is required to make the<br />

repayments on a face-to-face basis. This could be hard for her, but<br />

restorative justice ideally requires looking the victim in the eye and<br />

acknowledging wrongdoing. 25<br />

Writing for the minority, 26 Madala J confirmed the principles decided<br />

upon by the majority. He fully agreed that the sentencing court does<br />

have a duty to consider the rights <strong>of</strong> the children when sentencing a<br />

primary caregiver. However, applying that approach, Madala J came<br />

to a different conclusion. The fact that M was a repeat <strong>of</strong>fender, and<br />

that she had committed further <strong>of</strong>fences whilst on bail were factors<br />

that, according to the minority, outweighed the children’s interests.<br />

The overall judgment is not weaker for the minority judgment. The<br />

principles are common to both, although the judges differed on the<br />

outcome after all the relevant factors had been considered.<br />

3 Development <strong>of</strong> Child Law<br />

S v M has developed child law significantly, through its detailed<br />

enunciation <strong>of</strong> the scope and application <strong>of</strong> section 28. The concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> best interests is put under the spotlight, and the Court spells out<br />

the way in which ‘paramountcy’ referred to in section 28(2) should be<br />

24<br />

The court cites the following sources on restorative justice: D Pinnock ‘What kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> justice?’ <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Cape Town, Institute <strong>of</strong> Criminology Occasional Paper<br />

Series 4-95 (1995) available at http://web.uct.ac.zadepts/sjrp/publicat/<br />

25<br />

whatkind.htm, accessed on 16 August 2007; and M Batley in Maepa (ed) Beyond<br />

retribution: Prospects for restorative justice in South Africa Institute for Security<br />

Studies, Monograph 111 ‘Restorative justice in the South African context’ 21<br />

http://www.iss.co.za/pubs/Monographs/No111/Chap2.htm (S v M (n 1 above) n<br />

67). See also A M Skelton ‘The influence <strong>of</strong> the theory and practice <strong>of</strong> restorative<br />

justice in South Africa with special reference to child justice’ unpublished LLD<br />

thesis, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Pretoria</strong>, 2005; A Skelton & M Batley ‘Charting progress,<br />

mapping the future: Restorative justice in South Africa’ Institute for Security<br />

Studies and Restorative Justice Centre (2006).<br />

In Dikoko v Mokhatla 2006 6 SA 235 (CC), in the dissenting judgment <strong>of</strong> Sachs J, at<br />

para 114, the key elements <strong>of</strong> restorative justice are listed as encounter,<br />

reparation, reintegration and participation. See also the dissenting judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

Mokgoro J, particularly at para 68. Since S v M was heard there have been three<br />

other judgments reported which expound upon restorative justice, see S v<br />

Maluleke 2008 1 SACR 49 (T); S v Shilubane 2008 1 SACR 295 (T); S v Saayman<br />

26<br />

2008 1 SACR 393 (E).<br />

Nkabinde J and Navsa AJ concurred with the dissenting judgment.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 359<br />

understood and applied. The Court acknowledges that the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

best interests is not new to South African courts, as it has long been<br />

used as the applicable standard in matters such as care, contact or<br />

maintenance. In the family law field it is everyday currency, its most<br />

common application being where adult parties are in dispute about<br />

the care <strong>of</strong> or contact with a child. In such cases, the decisions will<br />

always be guided fundamentally by what is in the child’s best<br />

interests.<br />

However, in the new constitutional order, ‘the scope <strong>of</strong> best<br />

interests has been greatly enlarged’. 27 Section 28(2) declares the best<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> the child to be <strong>of</strong> paramount importance, not just in<br />

family matters, but in all matters concerning the child. At first blush<br />

this formulation seems to have such an all-encompassing reach that<br />

questions should be asked about how it can be effectively used in<br />

practice. To illustrate this, Sachs J quoted from the judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

Jooste v Botha 28 in which Van Dijkhorst J was so concerned that<br />

section 28(2) would over-ride all other legitimate interests, that he<br />

felt constrained to interpret the provision only as a general guideline<br />

and not as a rule <strong>of</strong> law <strong>of</strong> horizontal application. Sachs J points out<br />

that Van Dijkhorst J was wrong about this. He explains that while<br />

section 28 undoubtedly serves as a general guideline to the courts, its<br />

‘normative force’ does not stop there. 29 In fact, the Constitutional<br />

Court has previously described section 28(2) as an independent, selfstanding<br />

right, 30 and as ‘an expansive guarantee’. 31 Sachs J sums up<br />

the unequivocal position <strong>of</strong> the Court: section 28 establishes a set <strong>of</strong><br />

children’s rights that courts are obliged to enforce. 32<br />

This leads to another question: If the ambit <strong>of</strong> children’s rights is<br />

so wide, in what circumstances can such rights be limited? It is a<br />

question that has been pondered by academics for a number <strong>of</strong> years.<br />

27 S v M (n 1 above) para 12.<br />

28<br />

2000 2 SA 199 (T).<br />

29 S v M (n 1 above) para 14.<br />

30 In Minister <strong>of</strong> Welfare and Population Development v Fitzpatrick and Others 2000<br />

3 SA 422 (CC); 2000 3 BCLR 713 (CC) per Goldstone J: ‘The plain meaning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

words clearly indicates that the reach <strong>of</strong> section 28(2) cannot be limited to the<br />

rights enumerated in section 28(1) and section 28(2) must be interpreted to<br />

extend beyond those provisions. It creates a right that is independent <strong>of</strong> those<br />

specified in section 28(1).’<br />

31 Sonderup v Tondelli 2001 1 SA 2001 (CC); 2001 2 BCLR 152 (CC) (Sonderup) para<br />

29.<br />

32 S v M (n 1 above) para 14.


360 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

Clark, 33 writing in 1998, took the view that children’s rights would<br />

trump opposing rights. However, her comments related to family law,<br />

where the best interests principle is considered the determining<br />

factor. Bekink and Bekink considered the matter more broadly,<br />

arguing that ‘paramount’ means that in weighing up competing<br />

interests, the scales must tip in favour <strong>of</strong> the child. 34<br />

In the case <strong>of</strong> De Reuck v Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions,<br />

Witwatersrand Local Division and Others 35 the Constitutional Court<br />

provided some clarity on the issue. In the High Court decision in the<br />

same matter, the Court had found that children’s best interests can<br />

never be trumped by the rights <strong>of</strong> others. 36 The Constitutional Court<br />

disagreed, reiterating its approach that constitutional rights are<br />

mutually interrelated and interdependent, forming a single<br />

constitutional value system. Citing its earlier judgment in Sonderup, 37<br />

the Constitutional Court held that section 28(2), like other rights<br />

enshrined in the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, is subject to limitations that are<br />

reasonable and justifiable in accordance with section 36.<br />

4 What is the meaning <strong>of</strong> ‘paramount<br />

importance’ <strong>of</strong> children’s best interests?<br />

The question that remained hovering in the air even after the<br />

Constitutional Court had ruled in De Reuck was: What is to be<br />

understood by the phrase ‘paramount importance’? Friedman and<br />

Pantazis 38 posed the question thus: ‘Indeed, if a child’s best interests<br />

are not always supreme, what is the point <strong>of</strong> section 28(2)?’<br />

The authors went on to observe that section 28(2) is highly<br />

unusual, because it is the only section in the Constitution that applies<br />

to a group <strong>of</strong> people in relation to all aspects <strong>of</strong> their lives. In their<br />

view the section appears to be aimed at creating a right for children<br />

33<br />

B Clark ‘Competing custody rights: New concepts <strong>of</strong> family and the best interests<br />

<strong>of</strong> the child’ (1998) 35 Comparative and International Law Journal <strong>of</strong> South<br />

Africa 288 290. See further J Heaton ‘Some general remarks on the concept “best<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> the child”’ (1990) 53 Tydskrif vir Hedendaagse Romeins Hollandse Reg<br />

96; B Clark ‘A golden thread? Some aspects <strong>of</strong> the application <strong>of</strong> the standards <strong>of</strong><br />

the best interests <strong>of</strong> the child in South African family law’ (2000) Stellenbosch<br />

Law Review 3; F Mahlobogwane ‘South African courts and the “best interests <strong>of</strong><br />

the child” in custody disputes’ (2005) 38 Comparative and International Law<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> South Africa 246.<br />

34<br />

B Bekink & M Bekink ‘Defining the standard <strong>of</strong> the best interest <strong>of</strong> the child:<br />

Modern South African perspectives’ (2004) 37 De Jure 21 26.<br />

35 2004 1 SA 406 (CC); 2003 12 BCLR 1333 (CC) para 55.<br />

36<br />

De Reuck v Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions, Witwatersrand Local Division 2003 3<br />

SA 389 (W) (De Reuck) para 45.<br />

37 2001 1 SA 1171 (CC); 2001 2 BCLR 152 para 27-30.<br />

38<br />

A Friedman & A Pantazis ‘Children’s rights’ in S Woolman et al (eds)<br />

Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) 47-34 - 47-35.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 361<br />

as children — addressing the vulnerability <strong>of</strong> children, and ensuring<br />

that their rights do not, as in the pre-constitutional era, frequently<br />

have to give way to the rights <strong>of</strong> others. Friedman and Pantazis<br />

concluded that section 28(2) implies that in every matter where a<br />

child’s rights are (substantially) involved, those interests must be<br />

taken into account. In addition, they said that a child’s interests have<br />

a leg up vis-à-vis other rights and values, though this does not amount<br />

to these rights necessarily acting as trumps. 39 The judgment in S v M<br />

seems to have proved them right.<br />

Sachs J states that what lies at the heart <strong>of</strong> section 28 is the right<br />

<strong>of</strong> the child to be a child and enjoy special care. In a poetic passage<br />

<strong>of</strong> the judgment, he explains what he means by this:<br />

Every child has his or her own dignity. If a child is to be constitutionally<br />

imagined as an individual with a distinctive personality, and not merely<br />

as a miniature adult waiting to reach full size, he or she cannot be<br />

treated as a mere extension <strong>of</strong> his or her parents, umbilically destined to<br />

sink or swim with them. The unusually comprehensive and emancipatory<br />

character <strong>of</strong> section 28 presupposes that in our new dispensation the sins<br />

and traumas <strong>of</strong> fathers and mothers should not be visited on their<br />

children. Individually and collectively all children have the right to<br />

express themselves as independent social beings, to have their own<br />

laughter as well as sorrow, to play, imagine and explore in their own<br />

way, to themselves get to understand their bodies, minds and emotions,<br />

and above all to learn as they grow how they should conduct themselves<br />

and make choices in the wide social and moral world <strong>of</strong> adulthood. And<br />

foundational to the enjoyment <strong>of</strong> the right to childhood is the promotion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the right as far as possible to live in a secure and nurturing<br />

environment free from violence, fear, want and avoidable trauma. 40<br />

This forms the crux <strong>of</strong> the Court’s decision that sentencing courts do<br />

have a duty to consider the rights <strong>of</strong> the children when sentencing the<br />

primary caregiver. The state’s action — imprisonment <strong>of</strong> an adult —<br />

causes the removal <strong>of</strong> the caregiver from the family home. This<br />

directly impacts on the child’s right to family and parental care. The<br />

Court went on to say that although no constitutional injunction can<br />

completely protect children from life’s hard knocks, the law can<br />

create conditions to protect them from abuse or neglect. In S v M, the<br />

Court defined the legal duty as ensuring that the best interests <strong>of</strong> the<br />

child are considered by the sentencing court wherever there is a<br />

likelihood that the primary caregiver will be removed from the family<br />

through imprisonment. The likely effect, where the range <strong>of</strong> available<br />

sentencing options permits it, is to give children’s rights ‘a leg up’ by<br />

keeping the caregiver in the family. Where a custodial option is<br />

considered by the sentencing court to be the only legitimate course,<br />

39<br />

Friedman & Pantazis (n 38 above) 47-35.<br />

40 S v M (n 1 above) para 18.


362 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

then the court must nevertheless be satisfied that the children will be<br />

properly cared for and may make orders to minimise the negative<br />

effects on the children.<br />

If children’s rights do not always win out over other rights, what<br />

is the meaning <strong>of</strong> ‘paramount importance?’ The judgment embarks on<br />

an exploration <strong>of</strong> this thorny question. Sachs J comments that the<br />

very expansiveness <strong>of</strong> the paramountcy principle appears to promise<br />

everything but deliver little in particular. 41 The best interests<br />

concept is indeterminate, resulting in differing views about its<br />

meaning by pr<strong>of</strong>essionals and judges. These problems accepted, the<br />

Court has recognised that it is precisely the contextual nature and<br />

inherent flexibility <strong>of</strong> section 28 that constitutes the source <strong>of</strong> is<br />

strength. The determination will depend on the circumstances <strong>of</strong> each<br />

case, and this is not a weakness, but a strength. A truly child-centred<br />

approach requires an in-depth consideration <strong>of</strong> the needs and rights<br />

<strong>of</strong> the particular child in the ‘precise real-life situation’ he or she is<br />

in. To apply a pre-determined formula for the sake <strong>of</strong> certainty,<br />

irrespective <strong>of</strong> the circumstances, would in fact be contrary to the<br />

best interests <strong>of</strong> the child. 42<br />

The exercise <strong>of</strong> weighing up the best interests <strong>of</strong> the child has<br />

been clearly articulated by the Court. S v M has built on the Court’s<br />

previous jurisprudence, 43 creating a nuanced model that can be<br />

applied in a range <strong>of</strong> different legal and factual contexts. A more<br />

difficult question, concedes Sachs J, is to ‘establish an operational<br />

thrust for the paramountcy principle’. S v M goes further than any<br />

previous judgment, though it still defines the principle more by<br />

stating what it is not, than by saying what it is. It is not an<br />

‘overbearing and unrealistic trump’, 44 it cannot be interpreted ‘to<br />

mean that the direct or indirect impact <strong>of</strong> a measure or action on<br />

children must in all cases oust or override all other considerations.’<br />

Sachs J concludes that ‘the fact that the best interests <strong>of</strong> the child<br />

41<br />

S v M (n 1 above) para 23. See also H Reece ‘The paramountcy principle:<br />

Consensus or construct?’ (1996) 49 Current Legal Problems 267; D Matlala ‘The<br />

law reports: Parent and child — paramountcy <strong>of</strong> a child’s best interests’ (2006)<br />

June De Rebus 41.<br />

42 The Court has re-stated this position in the subsequent judgment <strong>of</strong> AD and<br />

Another v DW and Others (Centre for Child Law as Amicus Curiae; Department<br />

for Social Development as Intervening Party) 2008 3 SA 183 (CC), per Sachs J para<br />

55: ‘Child law is an area that abhors maximalist legal propositions that preclude<br />

or diminish the possibilities <strong>of</strong> looking at and evaluating the specific<br />

circumstances <strong>of</strong> the case ... This means that each child must be looked at as an<br />

individual, not as an abstraction. It also means that unduly rigid adherence to<br />

technical matters, such as who bears the burden for pro<strong>of</strong>, should play a<br />

relatively diminished role; the courts are essentially guarding the best interests<br />

<strong>of</strong> a child, not simply settling a dispute between litigants.’<br />

43 Minister <strong>of</strong> Welfare and Population Development v Fitzpatrick and Others 2000 3<br />

SA 422 (CC); De Reuck (n 35 above); Sonderup (n 30 above).<br />

44 n 1 above, para 25.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 363<br />

are paramount does not mean that they are absolute.’ 45 To<br />

acknowledge all <strong>of</strong> these realities is important because if the best<br />

interests principle is spread ‘too thin’ it risks becoming devoid <strong>of</strong><br />

meaning, instead <strong>of</strong> promoting the rights <strong>of</strong> children as it was<br />

intended to do. 46<br />

Later in the judgment the operation <strong>of</strong> the principle is explained<br />

in a more positive manner. The judgment states that sentencing<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficers should pay appropriate attention to the children <strong>of</strong> a primary<br />

caregiver and take reasonable steps to minimise damage. It continues<br />

thus:<br />

The paramountcy principle, read with the right to family care, requires<br />

that the interests <strong>of</strong> children who stand to be affected receive due<br />

consideration. It does not necessitate overriding all other<br />

considerations. Rather, it calls for appropriate weight to be given in each<br />

case to a consideration to which the law attaches the highest value,<br />

namely the interests <strong>of</strong> children who may be concerned. 47<br />

5 The child’s rights separate from adult’s rights:<br />

a subtle shift<br />

A further important feature <strong>of</strong> the majority judgment in S v M is the<br />

fact that it carefully focuses on the best interests <strong>of</strong> the child, and<br />

does not get entangled in a debate about the issues relating to the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> the primary caregiver. The discourse centres on children’s<br />

rights to family and parental care, and their right to have their best<br />

interests given appropriate weight. Counsel for the National Director<br />

<strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions attempted to argue that if the sentencing court<br />

considers children’s rights, then primary caregivers will gain an unfair<br />

advantage in the sentencing process. The majority <strong>of</strong> the Court<br />

rejected this out <strong>of</strong> hand, saying that ‘the issue is not whether parents<br />

should be allowed to use their children as a pretext for escaping the<br />

otherwise just consequences <strong>of</strong> their own misconduct.’ 48 That, said<br />

the Court, would be a mischaracterisation <strong>of</strong> the interests at stake.<br />

The purpose <strong>of</strong> emphasising the duty <strong>of</strong> the sentencing court to<br />

consider the best interests <strong>of</strong> the child is not to allow errant parents<br />

to escape punishment, but rather to protect innocent children from<br />

avoidable harm.<br />

45 S v M (n 1 above) para 26.<br />

46 S v M (n 1 above) para 25.<br />

47<br />

S v M (n 1 above) para 42.<br />

48 S v M (n 1 above) para 35. See, however, Madala J’s dissenting judgment at para<br />

117, where he states that the Court must guard against creating a perception that<br />

encourages <strong>of</strong>fenders to use the interests <strong>of</strong> children as ‘a tool in the judicial<br />

process’.


364 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

This focus on the child’s rights separate from the rights <strong>of</strong> their<br />

caregivers heralds a subtle but significant shift in the Constitutional<br />

Court’s child rights jurisprudence. Read together with the strong<br />

statements earlier in the judgment about children being possessed <strong>of</strong><br />

their own dignity, and being separate beings who are not merely<br />

destined to sink or swim with their parents, the Court’s ‘new’<br />

enunciation <strong>of</strong> children’s rights calls for a re-examination <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong><br />

its earlier pronouncements.<br />

The High Court decision in Grootboom v Oostenberg Municipality<br />

& Others 49 concerned an application brought by a group <strong>of</strong> 390 adults<br />

and 510 children (all <strong>of</strong> whom were living with their parents) who had<br />

not been provided with adequate housing and who, at the time <strong>of</strong> the<br />

initial application, were living on a sports field, following their<br />

eviction from land destined for low-cost housing. The applicants<br />

succeeded in their argument that because children have an<br />

unqualified right to shelter in terms <strong>of</strong> section 28(1)(c), coupled with<br />

the fact that they have a right to be cared for by their families or<br />

parents, children had the right to be provided with shelter (together<br />

with their parents) until such time as their parents could provide them<br />

with shelter. Davis J was careful to point out that the children were<br />

the bearers <strong>of</strong> the right. The fact that they should not be separated<br />

from their parents in order to access their rights did not amount to a<br />

derivative right for the parents (as had been argued by the<br />

applicants), but rather that ‘an order that enforces a right to shelter<br />

should take account <strong>of</strong> the need <strong>of</strong> the child to be accompanied by his<br />

or parent’. 50<br />

The approach <strong>of</strong> the majority in S v M is reminiscent <strong>of</strong> this way<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking. The similarities are that in both cases the judgments<br />

make it clear that the rights accrue to the child, but because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

imperative to keep children in their families wherever possible, the<br />

adult caregiver might also benefit from the required order.<br />

However, the Constitutional Court did not uphold the judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

Davis J. In Government <strong>of</strong> the Republic <strong>of</strong> South Africa & Others v<br />

Grootboom & Others, 51 the Court found that section 28(1)(c) did not<br />

create any primary obligations on the State to provide shelter on<br />

demand to children and their parents, but rather that the primary<br />

obligation to care for children lay with their parents, and that the<br />

state only has the obligation in the alternative to provide shelter<br />

49 2000 3 BCLR 277 (C) (Grootboom 1).<br />

50 Grootboom 1 (n 48 above) 289D.<br />

51 2001 1 SA 46 (CC); 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC) (Grootboom 2).


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 365<br />

when, for example, children are removed from their families. 52 The<br />

Court found that responsibilities <strong>of</strong> the state to children in the care <strong>of</strong><br />

their families extended to providing the legal and administrative<br />

infrastructure to ensure that children are protected in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

section 28(1). Section 28(1)(c), although it contains no internal<br />

qualifier suggesting that it is subject to progressive realisation, does<br />

not, according to Grootboom, provide children with a direct and<br />

immediately enforceable right to housing. 53 The Court was concerned<br />

that ‘[c]hildren could become stepping stones to housing for their<br />

parents instead <strong>of</strong> being valued for who they are’. This statement jars<br />

with the fact that children in South Africa receive other poverty or<br />

care-related benefits, such as child support grants, 54 and there is no<br />

serious suggestion that this might lead to them being valued for the<br />

money that their presence brings into the household rather than for<br />

who they are. 55<br />

In S v M the majority <strong>of</strong> the Court does not get distracted by any<br />

ideas that primary caregivers might use their children as ‘stepping<br />

stones’ to avoid imprisonment, although this kind <strong>of</strong> argument was<br />

advanced by counsel for the National Director <strong>of</strong> Public Prosecutions.<br />

The minority judgment in S v M does, however, get mired in this way<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking. Although Madala J agrees with the majority on the<br />

principle that the children <strong>of</strong> primary caregivers should have their<br />

best interests considered and protected, he is concerned about<br />

children being ‘used’ by adults seeking to avoid imprisonment. He<br />

cautions that ‘[t]his Court should be wary <strong>of</strong> setting a precedent that<br />

creates a perception that courts will give primary caregivers a<br />

sentence that is disproportionate to what they deserve and which<br />

encourages them to use the interests <strong>of</strong> children as a tool in the<br />

judicial process.’ 56 These remarks, in contrast to the explanation in<br />

the majority judgment that the children are the bearers <strong>of</strong> the rights<br />

52 Grootboom 2 (n 51 above) para 77. The judgment did not state clearly that<br />

children living with their parents will not have a claim for the enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

their rights in terms <strong>of</strong> section 28(1)(c), as it uses the term ‘for example’ when<br />

referring to children removed from their primary caregivers.<br />

53 The Court came to the puzzling conclusion that there was no difference between<br />

the right to ‘adequate housing’ provided for in section 26 and ‘shelter’ in section<br />

28. Friedman & Pantazis (‘Children’s Rights’ in Woolman et al (n 37 above) 46-8)<br />

have criticised this interpretation by the court, firstly because it ignores the plain<br />

meaning in the two different phrases, and also because the Constitutional<br />

drafters’ choice <strong>of</strong> different terminology suggests different conceptual<br />

extensions.<br />

54 In the case <strong>of</strong> Khoza and Others v Minister <strong>of</strong> Social Development and Others;<br />

Mahlaule and Another v Minister <strong>of</strong> Social Development and Others 2004 6 BCLR<br />

569 (CC) the Court recognised that denial <strong>of</strong> support to South African born<br />

children <strong>of</strong> foreign permanent residents in South Africa was not only<br />

discrimination on the grounds <strong>of</strong> the parents’ nationality, but also trenches on the<br />

rights that children have under section 28(1)(c).<br />

55 Friedman & Pantazis (n 38 above) 47-6 n 2: ‘In any case, the state is committed to<br />

providing all needy children with child care grants.’<br />

56 S v M (n 1 above) para 117.


366 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

and to suggest otherwise is a mischaracterisation, strike a chord that<br />

is an echo <strong>of</strong> children being used as ‘stepping stones’.<br />

Much disappointment has been expressed with regard to the<br />

Constitutional Court’s decision in Grootboom, viewed from a<br />

children’s rights perspective. 57 However, it has also been<br />

acknowledged by several writers 58 that the effect <strong>of</strong> the decision in<br />

Grootboom — vis-à-vis children’s rights — underwent some<br />

adjustment in the case <strong>of</strong> Minister <strong>of</strong> Health & Others v Treatment<br />

Action Campaign & Others. 59 In that case, which dealt with access to<br />

treatment to avoid mother-to-child transmission <strong>of</strong> HIV/AIDS, the<br />

Court held as follows:<br />

The state is obliged to ensure that children are accorded the protection<br />

contemplated by s 28 that arises when the implementation <strong>of</strong> the right<br />

to parental or family care is lacking. Here we are concerned with<br />

children born in public hospitals and clinics to mothers who are for the<br />

most part indigent and unable to gain access to private medical<br />

treatment which is beyond their means. 60<br />

So the approach adopted in Grootboom to the effect that children<br />

living with their parents will have to look to their parents, rather than<br />

the state, for the fulfilment <strong>of</strong> their section 28(1)(c) rights was<br />

ameliorated. 61 Although the two cases are clearly distinguishable by<br />

the fact that shelter is arguably easier for parents to provide than a<br />

specialised form <strong>of</strong> health care, it was significant that the TAC Court<br />

57<br />

J Sloth-Nielsen ‘The child’s right to social services, the right to social security,<br />

and primary prevention <strong>of</strong> child abuse: Some conclusions in the aftermath <strong>of</strong><br />

Grootboom’ (2001) 17 South African Journal on Human Rights 210; E Bonthuys<br />

‘The South African bill <strong>of</strong> rights and the development <strong>of</strong> family law’ (2002) 119<br />

South African Law Journal 748; M Pieterse ‘Reconstructing the private/public<br />

dichotomy? The enforcement <strong>of</strong> children’s constitutional social rights and care<br />

entitlements’ (2003) Tydskrif vir Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 1; S Liebenberg ‘Taking<br />

stock: The jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> children’s socio-economic rights and its implications<br />

for government policy’ (2004) 5:4 ESR Review 2; and K McLean ‘Housing’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional law <strong>of</strong> South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006)<br />

55.51 – 55.54.<br />

58 J Sloth-Nielsen ‘Children’ in D Davis & H Cheadle (eds) The South African<br />

constitution: The bill <strong>of</strong> rights (2nd ed [date]) 421; Friedman & Pantazis (n 38<br />

above) 47-13; E Bonthuys ‘Children’ in I Currie & J de Waal (eds) The bill <strong>of</strong> rights<br />

handbook (5th edition [date]) 613.<br />

59<br />

2002 1 BCLR 1033 (CC) (TAC).<br />

60 TAC (n 59 above) para 79.<br />

61 S Liebenberg (‘The judicial enforcement <strong>of</strong> social security rights in South Africa’<br />

in E Riedel Social Security as a Human Right (2007) 69) points out that the Court<br />

did not conclude that children enjoyed an unqualified, direct claim to the<br />

provision <strong>of</strong> basic health care services, but rather based their finding on the fact<br />

that the government’s policy was unreasonable because it excluded a particularly<br />

vulnerable group.


(2008) 1 Constitutional Court Review 367<br />

gave clarity that section 28(1)(c) rights do not only set an obligation<br />

for the state where the child is separated from the parent. 62<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

S v M appears to herald a new era in which the fear <strong>of</strong> children being<br />

used as instruments by their parents to advance their parents’ rights<br />

have been supplanted by a clear recognition <strong>of</strong> children as rights<br />

bearers. Comparisons have been adduced in this article to show that<br />

this approach may indicate a subtle shift by the Court to see children<br />

as separate from their parents and therefore not ‘umbillically<br />

destined to sink or swim with them’.<br />

There are, <strong>of</strong> course, significant differences between cases such<br />

as Grootboom and TAC on the one hand, and S v M on the other. The<br />

first-mentioned cases deal with socio-economic rights <strong>of</strong> children.<br />

This means that the orders given in those matters potentially had<br />

significant cost implications. S v M does not create major cost<br />

implications, it requires only an investment <strong>of</strong> time and care on the<br />

part <strong>of</strong> state <strong>of</strong>ficials already employed. In such cases it is clearly<br />

easier for the Court to make the kind <strong>of</strong> pronouncements that it has<br />

made in S v M. Grootboom and TAC can themselves be separated out<br />

from one another. Health care is not something that parents can ever<br />

fully provide unless assisted either by private health care providers,<br />

or if the parents are poor, by the state. Although the judgments do<br />

not fully explain the difference, commentators have mentioned that<br />

nutrition and shelter are more likely to be within the scope <strong>of</strong> what<br />

parents can be expected to deliver, whilst health care and social<br />

services are more likely to require input by the state. 63<br />

Children <strong>of</strong> primary caregivers who are due to be sentenced pose<br />

an interesting counter-point. They are still living with their parents,<br />

but are at risk <strong>of</strong> being separated from them. S v M found that the<br />

state has a duty to create a positive legal environment, and thus<br />

sentencing courts now have clear duties that have been articulated by<br />

the Court. These arise from the rights <strong>of</strong> the children, and the<br />

majority judgment had no difficulty in dispelling any concerns about<br />

62<br />

The jurisprudence related to the socio-economic rights <strong>of</strong> children who are<br />

separated from their parents has gradually developed, with the courts finding<br />

that such children do have an immediate and directly enforceable claim against<br />

the state for the rights included in section 28(1)(h): see Centre for Child Law and<br />

Another v Minister <strong>of</strong> Home Affairs and Others 2005 6 SA 50, which dealt with the<br />

rights <strong>of</strong> unaccompanied foreign children to receive social services, and Centre<br />

for Child Law and Others v MEC for Education, Gauteng and Others 2007 1 SA 223<br />

(T), which dealt with children who had been removed from state care and placed<br />

in a school <strong>of</strong> industries where they were living in extremely poor conditions,<br />

without adequate social services.<br />

63 Friedman & Pantazis (n 38 above) 47-12; J Sloth-Nielsen (n 56 above) 225.


368 Children and their primary caregivers<br />

the primary caregivers reaping unfair advantages from the fact that<br />

they had children. The only distinction that can be made is that S v M<br />

deals with the right to family or parental care, and does not deal<br />

directly with socio-economic rights <strong>of</strong> the children.<br />

The effect <strong>of</strong> S v M is ultimately to force the state to create a legal<br />

environment to facilitate children’s rights being recognised and their<br />

best interests being met as far as possible through the orders <strong>of</strong><br />

sentencing courts. To that extent, the judgment accords with the role<br />

<strong>of</strong> the state as outlined in Grootboom, which was to create the<br />

regulatory environment for the achievement <strong>of</strong> children’s rights.<br />

However, in the way that it ‘constitutionally imagine[s]’ 64 children as<br />

separate rights bearers with separately identifiable and enforceable<br />

rights, S v M takes children’s rights a jurisprudential step forward.<br />

64 S v M (n 1 above) para 18.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!