04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

This collection of colloquies flows from<br />

the Constitutional Law of South Africa<br />

Public Lecture Series held last year.<br />

The contributors to the nine colloquies<br />

include four Constitutional Court Justices,<br />

four of the world’s leading constitutional<br />

law scholars and the best of<br />

South Africa’s own legal academy.<br />

“Each of the topics [canvassed in <strong>this</strong> work] is engaged<br />

by two commentators in dialogue form: the<br />

views of one commentator are first advanced, to<br />

which a second commentator replies. The result is<br />

a satisfying conversation that edifies the reader both<br />

in areas of well thought-out agreement and in areas<br />

of disagreement. This book thus contributes greatly<br />

to the vital debate in legal circles and civil society at<br />

large about a select number of core problems arising<br />

from our Constitution. It does so in a manner that<br />

demonstrates how to argue productively about basic<br />

questions of law and human rights. And it is full of<br />

constructive proposals that will light the way along<br />

South Africa’s new path. For that, the editors of and<br />

contributors to Constitutional Conversations can only<br />

be commended.”<br />

- Pius Langa ‘Foreword’<br />

Chief Justice of South Africa<br />

“In my view, if the debates involving judges and scholars<br />

that led to <strong>this</strong> book are anything to go by, dialogue<br />

between the judiciary and the academic world<br />

is likely to become increasingly fruitful in the years to<br />

come. US Supreme Court Justice Robert Jackson,<br />

whom I love to quote, sardonically remarked that the<br />

‘Court does not have the last word because it is infallible.<br />

It is infallible because it has the last word.’<br />

We judges have to acknowledge, however, that the<br />

last word on the infallibility of the judges themselves<br />

will lie with the academic critics. O dialogo continua!<br />

Long may the dialogue continue!”<br />

- Albie Sachs ‘A gentle provocation’<br />

Judge, Constitutional Court of South Africa<br />

Pretoria University Law Press<br />

<strong>PULP</strong><br />

ISBN:978-0-9814124-1-2<br />

CONTENTS<br />

• Foreword<br />

Chief Justice Pius Langa<br />

• Introduction: Law’s autonomy<br />

Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop<br />

• The South African Constitution as the last great<br />

modernist project<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

• Reply: A gentle provocation<br />

Justice Albie Sachs<br />

• Constitutional supremacy and appellate<br />

jurisdiction in South Africa<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

• Reply: On the reach of the Constitution and the<br />

nature of constitutional jurisdiction<br />

Justice Kate O’Regan<br />

• The principle of democracy in South African<br />

constitutional law<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

• Reply: Writing the law democratically<br />

Danie Brand<br />

• True in theory, true in practice: Why direct<br />

application still matters<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

• Reply: Summarising Proust<br />

Iain Currie<br />

• Limitations: Shared constitutional interpretation, an<br />

appropriate normative framework and hard choices<br />

Stu Woolman & Henk Botha<br />

• Reply: Sharing interpretation<br />

Johan van der Walt<br />

• The widening gyre of dignity<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

• Reply: The soul of dignity<br />

Justice Laurie Ackermann<br />

• Towards a substantive right to equality<br />

Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt<br />

• Reply: A cautionary note regarding substantive<br />

equality<br />

Karthy Govender<br />

• The ‘arbitrary deprivation’ vortex: Constitutional<br />

property law after FNB<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

• Reply: Against regulatory taking: In defence of the<br />

two-stage inquiry<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

• Socio-economic rights: Revisiting the<br />

reasonableness review/minimum core debate<br />

Sandra Liebenberg<br />

• Reply: On ‘dialogue’, ‘translation’ and ‘voice’<br />

Marius Pieterse<br />

Constitutional Conversations<br />

Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop (eds)<br />

<strong>PULP</strong><br />

Constitutional<br />

Conversations<br />

Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop (eds)


Constitutional<br />

Conversations<br />

Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop (Eds)<br />

2008


Constitutional conversations<br />

Published by:<br />

Pretoria University Law Press (<strong>PULP</strong>)<br />

The Pretoria University Law Press (<strong>PULP</strong>) is a publisher at the Faculty of Law,<br />

University of Pretoria, South Africa. <strong>PULP</strong> endeavours to publish and make<br />

available innovative, high-quality scholarly texts on law in Africa that have<br />

been peer-reviewed. <strong>PULP</strong> also publishes a series of collections of legal<br />

documents related to public law in Africa, as well as text books from African<br />

countries other than South Africa.<br />

For more information on <strong>PULP</strong>, see www.pulp.up.ac.za<br />

Printed and bound by:<br />

ABC Press<br />

Cape Town<br />

To order, contact:<br />

<strong>PULP</strong><br />

Faculty of Law<br />

University of Pretoria<br />

South Africa<br />

0002<br />

Tel: +27 12 420 4948<br />

Fax: +27 12 362 5125<br />

pulp@up.ac.za<br />

www.pulp.up.ac.za<br />

Cover:<br />

Yolanda Booyzen, Centre for Human Rights<br />

• Main doors of the South African Constitutional Court<br />

• Raphael: ‘The School of Athens’, c.1510/11, Vatican, Apostolic Palace<br />

• Facade of the South African Constitutional Court<br />

• Cyril Ramaphosa and Roelf Meyer<br />

• Government Gazette notice<br />

ISBN: 978-0-9814124-1-2<br />

© 2008


ABBREVIATED TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

FOREWORD<br />

Chief Justice Pius Langa<br />

x<br />

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS<br />

1<br />

2<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

9<br />

10<br />

11<br />

INTRODUCTION: LAW’S AUTONOMY 1<br />

Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop<br />

THE SOUTH AFRICAN CONSTITUTION AS THE LAST 25<br />

GREAT MODERNIST PROJECT<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

REPLY 37<br />

Justice Albie Sachs<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL SUPREMACY AND APPELLATE 45<br />

JURISDICTION IN SOUTH AFRICA<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

REPLY 63<br />

Justice Kate O’Regan<br />

THE PRINCIPLE OF DEMOCRACY IN SOUTH AFRICAN 79<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL LAW<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

REPLY 97<br />

Danie Brand<br />

TRUE IN THEORY, TRUE IN PRACTICE: WHY DIRECT 113<br />

APPLICATION STILL MATTERS<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

REPLY 139<br />

Iain Currie<br />

LIMITATIONS: SHARED CONSTITUTIONAL INTER- 149<br />

PRETATION, AN APPROPRIATE NORMATIVE FRAME-<br />

WORK AND HARD CHOICES<br />

Stu Woolman & Henk Botha<br />

REPLY 187<br />

Johan van der Walt<br />

xii<br />

iii


12<br />

13<br />

14<br />

15<br />

16<br />

17<br />

18<br />

19<br />

THE WIDENING GYRE OF DIGNITY 193<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

REPLY 217<br />

Justice Laurie Ackermann<br />

TOWARDS A SUBSTANTIVE RIGHT TO EQUALITY 231<br />

Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt<br />

REPLY 255<br />

Karthy Govender<br />

THE ‘ARBITRARY DEPRIVATIONS’ VOTEX: 265<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL PROPERTY LAW AFTER FNB<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

REPLY 283<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS: REVISITING THE 303<br />

REASONABLENESS REVIEW/MINIMUM CORE DEBATE<br />

Sandra Liebenberg<br />

REPLY 331<br />

Marius Pieterse<br />

iv


FULL TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

FOREWORD<br />

Chief Justice Pius Langa<br />

x<br />

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS<br />

1<br />

2<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

INTRODUCTION: LAW’S AUTONOMY 1<br />

Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop<br />

1 Law’s autonomy<br />

2 The content of these conversations<br />

2.1 The SA Constitution as the last great modernist project<br />

2.2 Rule of law<br />

2.3 Democracy<br />

2.4 Application<br />

2.5 Limitations<br />

2.6 Equality<br />

2.7 Dignity<br />

2.8 Property<br />

2.9 Socio-economic rights<br />

3 Ideal participants in the construction of an ideal<br />

community<br />

THE SOUTH AFRICAN CONSTITUTION AS THE LAST 25<br />

GREAT MODERNIST PROJECT<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

1 On the role of the legal academy<br />

2 The ideal community of interlocutors<br />

3 The South African Constitution as the last great<br />

modernist project<br />

4 Conclusion<br />

REPLY 37<br />

A gentle provocation: A reply to Stu Woolman<br />

Justice Albie Sachs<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL SUPREMACY AND APPELLATE 45<br />

JURISDICTION IN SOUTH AFRICA<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 History<br />

3 Justification<br />

4 A single system of law<br />

5 Comparative reflections<br />

REPLY 63<br />

On the reach of the Constitution and the nature of<br />

constitutional jurisdiction: A reply to<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

Justice Kate O’Regan<br />

1 Introduction<br />

xi<br />

v


6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

9<br />

10<br />

2 A supreme, pervasive and foundational<br />

Constitution<br />

3 The unity and coherence of the legal system<br />

4 Legality<br />

5 Jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court and the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

THE PRINCIPLE OF DEMOCRACY IN SOUTH AFRICAN 79<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL LAW<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 The principle of democracy: The text<br />

3 The principle of democracy: The cases<br />

4 Conclusion<br />

REPLY 97<br />

Writing the law democratically: A reply to<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

Danie Brand<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 What Theunis does not say<br />

2.1 Democracy as an empty vessel<br />

2.2 The tension between rights and democracy<br />

3 Conclusion<br />

TRUE IN THEORY, TRUE IN PRACTICE: WHY DIRECT 113<br />

APPLICATION STILL MATTERS<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 Application doctrine under the Interim Constitution<br />

3 Application doctrine under the Final Constitution<br />

3.1 Black letter law<br />

3.2 Good faith reconstruction of Khumalo<br />

3.3 The critique of the black letter law and the good faith<br />

reconstruction<br />

4 The preferred reading<br />

5 Conclusion<br />

REPLY 139<br />

Summarising Proust: A reply to Stu Woolman<br />

Iain Currie<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 Burdens<br />

3 Drafting history<br />

4 The Woolmanian reading<br />

5 Theory v practice<br />

LIMITATIONS: SHARED CONSTITUTIONAL INTER- 149<br />

PRETATION, AN APPROPRIATE NORMATIVE FRAME-<br />

WORK AND HARD CHOICES<br />

Stu Woolman & Henk Botha<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 Delineating rights analysis and limitations analysis<br />

vi


11<br />

12<br />

13<br />

3 Balancing as a bad metaphor<br />

3.1 Definitions of balancing<br />

3.2 Critiques of balancing<br />

3.2.1 Pluralism, incommensurability and complexity<br />

3.3 Subjectivity and arbitrariness<br />

3.4 Incrementalism and conservatism<br />

3.5 Science and silence<br />

4 A (thick)er conception of limitations analysis<br />

4.1 Shared constitutional interpretation<br />

5 Norms: ‘an open and democratic society based<br />

upon human dignity, equality and freedom’<br />

5.1 Intersection, convergence, and conflict amongst<br />

constitutional values<br />

5.2 Dignity and democracy<br />

5.2.1 Primacy of dignity<br />

5.3 Democracy and openness<br />

5.3.1 Principle of democracy<br />

5.3.2 Principle of openness<br />

5.4 Judicial narratives<br />

5.4.1 Prince<br />

5.4.2 Jordan and Khosa<br />

REPLY 187<br />

Sharing interpretation: A reply to Stu Woolman &<br />

Henk Botha<br />

Johan van der Walt<br />

THE WIDENING GYRE OF DIGNITY 193<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 History<br />

3 Definitions of dignity<br />

3.1 Dignity 1: Individual as an end-in-herself<br />

3.2 Dignity 2: Equal concern and equal respect<br />

3.3 Dignity 3: Self-actualisation<br />

3.4 Dignity 4: Self-governance<br />

3.5 Dignity 5: Collective responsibility for the material<br />

conditions for agency<br />

3.6 The creation of a realm of ends<br />

4 Uses of dignity<br />

4.1 Dignity as a first order rule<br />

4.2 Dignity as a second order rule<br />

4.3 Dignity as a correlative right<br />

4.4 Dignity as a value or grundnorm<br />

5 Dignity and the politics of capability<br />

5.1 First restitution<br />

5.2 Dignity and transformation<br />

5.3 Beyond negative liberty to means and capability<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

REPLY 217<br />

The soul of dignity: A reply to Stu Woolman<br />

Justice Laurie Ackermann<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 Whence dignity?<br />

3 Dignity as ‘attribute’ in equality<br />

4 Collective dignity?<br />

5 Kelsen rather than Hart<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

vii


14<br />

15<br />

16<br />

17<br />

TOWARDS A SUBSTANTIVE RIGHT TO EQUALITY 231<br />

Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 Values and the equality right<br />

2.1 Equality as substantive equality<br />

2.2 The values underlying the equality right<br />

2.2.1 Dignity<br />

2.2.2 Equality<br />

2.2.3 Values, purposes and the parameters of the<br />

equality right<br />

3 Evaluation of unfair discrimination jurisprudence<br />

3.1 Proving discrimination in the first step of the Harksen<br />

test<br />

3.2 Grounds of discrimination<br />

3.2.1 Race<br />

3.2.2 Sexual orientation<br />

3.2.3 Sex/gender<br />

3.3 Unlisted/new grounds of discrimination<br />

3.3.1 Citizenship<br />

3.3.2 The poor<br />

3.3.3 Intersectionality<br />

3.4 The application of contextual approach<br />

4 An overview of the right and its relationship with<br />

FC section 36<br />

4.1 FC section 9(1) (rationality)<br />

4.2 FC section 9(2) (a defence to unfair discrimination)<br />

4.3 FC section 9(3) (fairness) and FC section 36<br />

4.4 Can unfairness be justified?<br />

REPLY 255<br />

A cautionary note regarding substantive equality:<br />

A reply to Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt<br />

Karthy Govender<br />

1 Caution with respect to expansive approaches<br />

to equality<br />

2 Concerns about equality<br />

2.1 Van Heerden — a flexible approach<br />

2.2 Van Heerden — a positive obligation<br />

3 FC section 9 fairness and FC section 36<br />

justification<br />

3.1 Minister of Education v Harris<br />

3.2 Volks v Robinson<br />

4 Conclusion<br />

THE ‘ARBITRARY DEPRIVATION’ VORTEX: 265<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL PROPERTY LAW AFTER FNB<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 Six points<br />

3 FNB<br />

4 The vortex<br />

REPLY 283<br />

Against regulatory taking: In defence of the<br />

two-stage inquiry: A reply to Theunis Roux<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 The FNB vortex: A cause for concern?<br />

3 Making sense of FC section 25(1)’s internal and<br />

external limitations<br />

viii


18<br />

19<br />

SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS: REVISITING THE 303<br />

REASONABLENESS REVIEW/MINIMUM CORE DEBATE<br />

Sandra Liebenberg<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 What does ‘reasonableness review’ mean in the<br />

context of socio-economic rights claims?<br />

3 An alternative model of review based on<br />

‘minimum core’ obligations<br />

4 Re-evaluating reasonableness review<br />

5 Towards substantive reasonableness<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

REPLY 331<br />

On ‘dialogue’, ‘translation’ and ‘voice’: A reply to<br />

Sandra Liebenberg<br />

Marius Pieterse<br />

1 Introduction<br />

2 Translation through dialogue: Mapping the field<br />

and the players<br />

3 Minimum core, reasonableness and translation<br />

through dialogue<br />

4 Conclusion: Towards openness, responsiveness<br />

and substantive participation<br />

ix


FOREWORD<br />

The respective enactment and coming into force of the Interim and<br />

Final Constitutions in South Africa was nothing short of a legal<br />

revolution. The new basic law mandated an entirely fresh approach to<br />

legislation, adjudication and the implementation of laws in <strong>this</strong><br />

country. Since 1994, judges, scholars, practitioners and ordinary<br />

people have started to walk <strong>this</strong> new path of constitutional<br />

democracy.<br />

The way, however, is not always certain. The provisions of our Bill<br />

of Rights are expressed in a manner that calls explicitly for judicial<br />

application of open-textured political values such as dignity, equality<br />

and freedom. They call implicitly for judicial choice from amongst a<br />

variety of possible solutions to various deep problems of governance<br />

and social interaction. It thus falls ultimately to judges to decide<br />

finally where we must place our feet as we walk our path.<br />

But that is not to say that judges should decide uninformed and<br />

unadvised. Instead they must take counsel. There is a great need for<br />

South Africans to come together and talk about these problems, to<br />

evaluate the various possible routes, and to consider which seem<br />

best. The Bill of Rights is not self-executing. Its requirements are not<br />

uncontroversial. And not all South Africans are of accord. The need to<br />

engage one another could not be more pressing: robust and respectful<br />

engagement will yield concrete and valuable suggestions to courts,<br />

government and the people on the best path forward.<br />

The essays in <strong>this</strong> book together make a valuable contribution to<br />

South Africa’s ongoing collective engagement with several deep<br />

questions of constitutional and human rights significance. Here,<br />

between two covers, we are presented with the considered views of<br />

three Constitutional Court justices and twelve leading constitutional<br />

scholars on a host of issues: the relationship between judges and<br />

scholars in our constitutional democracy; the contested meaning of<br />

the rule of law and its implications for the jurisdiction of our highest<br />

courts; the nature of democracy in South Africa; the distinction<br />

between direct and indirect application of fundamental rights; the<br />

unavoidable normative and political character of justifying limitations<br />

of fundamental rights; the call of substantive equality; the meaning<br />

and significance of human dignity as a constitutional right and value;<br />

the contours and the limits of the constitutional protection of private<br />

property; and how best to fulfil the promise of socio-economic rights.<br />

Each of these topics is treated by two commentators in dialogue<br />

form: the views of one commentator are first advanced, to which a<br />

second commentator replies. The result is a satisfying conversation<br />

that edifies the reader both in areas of well thought-out agreement<br />

and in areas of disagreement. Where the contributors converge on a<br />

particular conclusion, we are placed in a position to assess a variety<br />

of arguments supporting that outcome. We are reassured because the<br />

tendency to converge on a given solution, in favourable conditions of<br />

x


unrushed academic discourse, is a strong reason to take that solution<br />

very seriously indeed. Where contributors diverge, however, we<br />

nevertheless gain from the opportunity to assess their conflicting<br />

points of view and supporting premises and, from a newly informed<br />

and enriched perspective, to make up our own minds.<br />

This book thus contributes greatly to the vital debate in legal<br />

circles and civil society at large about a select number of core<br />

problems arising from our Constitution. It does so in a manner that<br />

demonstrates how to argue productively about basic questions of law<br />

and human rights. And it is full of constructive proposals that will light<br />

the way along South Africa’s new path. For that, the editors of and<br />

contributors to Constitutional conversations can only be commended.<br />

Pius Langa<br />

Chief Justice of South Africa<br />

Johannesburg, South Africa<br />

June 2008<br />

xi


ACKNOWLEDGMENTS<br />

The publishers and the editors would like to thank Juta Law and<br />

Academic Edge CC for permission to use material from the following<br />

chapters in Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux & Michael Bishop (eds)<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd Edition (2008):<br />

• Frank Michelman ‘The Rule of Law, Legality & the Supremacy of<br />

the Constitution’ in Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux & Michael Bishop<br />

(eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd Edition (2005)<br />

Chapter 11;<br />

• Theunis Roux ‘Democracy’ in Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux &<br />

Michael Bishop (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd<br />

Edition (2006) Chapter 10;<br />

• Stu Woolman ‘Application’ in Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux &<br />

Michael Bishop (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd<br />

Edition (2005) Chapter 31;<br />

• Stu Woolman & Henk Botha ‘Limitations’ in Stu Woolman, Theunis<br />

Roux & Michael Bishop (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa,<br />

2 nd Edition (2006) Chapter 34;<br />

• Stu Woolman ‘Dignity’ in Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux & Michael<br />

Bishop (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd Edition<br />

(2006) Chapter 36;<br />

• Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt ‘Equality’ in Stu Woolman,<br />

Theunis Roux & Michael Bishop (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa, 2 nd Edition (2007) Chapter 35;<br />

• Theunis Roux ‘Property’ in Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux & Michael<br />

Bishop (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd Edition<br />

(2004) Chapter 36;<br />

• Sandra Liebenberg ‘The Interpretation of Socio-Economic Rights’<br />

in Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux & Michael Bishop (eds)<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd Edition (2004) Chapter<br />

33.<br />

The publishers and the editors would also like to thank the Centre for<br />

Human Rights, the South African Institute for Advanced<br />

Constitutional, Public, Human Rights and International Law, Juta Law,<br />

the Constitutional Court Foundation, and Academic Edge CC for<br />

sponsoring the Constitutional Law of South Africa Public Lectures<br />

Series at the Women’s Jail on Constitution Hill and for making the<br />

conversations in <strong>this</strong> book possible.<br />

xii


DEDICATIONS<br />

‘To my grandfather, Thomas Mullins’<br />

Michael Bishop<br />

‘To my Uncle, Harry, who revealed to me the magic of books’<br />

Stu Woolman


1<br />

INTRODUCTION:<br />

LAW’S AUTONOMY<br />

Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop<br />

1 Law’s autonomy<br />

One of the wonderful things about law is its enormous variation in<br />

rhetorical forms. You can be a formalist. Well, actually, only other<br />

people can be formalists (since it has, sadly, come to be used solely<br />

as a term of derision.) But that still leaves open the possibility of<br />

being a critical legal scholar (who can drive a Rolls Royce at Harvard<br />

but still advance the needs of the proletariat), a realist (who drives<br />

fast, and yet always manages to be late for therapy), a pragmatist<br />

(who makes the best of a lousy car), an original intentist (who was<br />

born in 1994 and drives a new model BMW), a Brit crit (who drives a<br />

really lousy car and truly believes she is part of the vanguard of the<br />

proletariat), a positivist (who knows that there is a clear difference<br />

between a good car and a lousy car, but can’t remember whether her<br />

car is parked closer to the core or the penumbra), a feminist (who<br />

doesn’t think there’s anything ‘funny’ about her car), a poststructuralist<br />

(who drives two cars in binary opposition to one<br />

another), a critical race theorist (who drives a really lousy car<br />

because its ‘black’ and ‘you really wouldn’t understand’), a critical<br />

latino theorist (who waited 3 months for the factory to deliver<br />

something in beige), a natural law theorist (who believes God created<br />

his car), a minimalist (who drives a lousy car and understands that the<br />

car speaks for itself), a lit crit (who can tell a thousand illuminating<br />

stories about her car), an ubuntuist (who drives a new BMW because<br />

it ‘is because we are’), an experimentalist (who drives a lousy car but<br />

1


2 Chapter 1<br />

thinks of it as an opportunity to learn just about everything that can<br />

go wrong with an engine), a plain meaning person (who drives a box<br />

on wheels) or an ordinary meaning person (who simply drives a car).<br />

That’s just a list of jurisprudential schools. You can argue by<br />

deduction, induction, analogy, history, tradition, precedent, storytelling,<br />

politics or even logic. And if you go to the Constitutional<br />

Court, you can hire Trengove, Marcus, Moerane, Chaskalson,<br />

Unterhalter, Mtshaulana, Arendse, Gaunlett, Soni, Cockerell,<br />

Semenya, Budlender, or Kemp J Kemp to argue for you.<br />

What, if anything, does <strong>this</strong> list of lists have to do with the volume<br />

— Constitutional conversations — that sits before you? Academics, like<br />

lawyers, must be free to employ a number of different, but largely<br />

consistent, rhetorical forms in advancing their arguments. The<br />

authors of Constitutional conversations have been set free to write<br />

what they like — and to employ their preferred rhetorical forms. And<br />

that they have done. Without naming names, we can count feminists,<br />

experimentalists, ubuntuists, minimalists, critical legal scholars,<br />

natural law theorists, realists, pragmatists, ordinary meaning readers,<br />

plain meaning interpreters, and formalists amongst the contributors<br />

to <strong>this</strong> collection. That said, their interpretive freedom — for <strong>this</strong><br />

collection — is subject to a particular form of bounded rationality.<br />

One requirement, of all the authors who have written for<br />

Constitutional conversations is that they take the text of the Final<br />

Constitution, the reasoning of cases, the political institutions that<br />

govern us, the fellow academics who contribute to our greater<br />

understanding of our field, and a whole range of other quotidian<br />

academic considerations — like logic and research — quite seriously.<br />

We know that the correct reading of a founding provision may turn on<br />

the placement of a comma — and that a bad outcome may flow from<br />

an errant reading of a preposition. Our aim, as the editors and the<br />

authors of Constitutional conversations, is to produce a book that<br />

provides some insight into a select number of the problems thrown up<br />

by our basic law. We hope, collectively, to have succeeded in making<br />

greater sense of the system of constitutional law within which we<br />

operate and, should we have any talent, to have made a modest<br />

contribution towards the creation of a system of constitutional law<br />

that is both more coherent and more just. Moreover, the authors for<br />

Constitutional conversations do not merely dabble in doctrine — they<br />

create it. Some of the authors have done so from the bench — the<br />

Constitutional Court (though they operate here in an extra-curial<br />

capacity). Others operate from the relatively objective distance<br />

provided by the academy. In every contribution — save for the odd,


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 3<br />

entirely speculative colloquy 1 — the theoretical work of our authors<br />

begins with a close reading of the text and then draws down upon and<br />

engages those jurists and academics who have previously attempted<br />

to make sense of systems of law in constitutional democracies. Even<br />

when we move away from the law to less derivative disciplines, the<br />

authors of <strong>this</strong> work never for a moment deny the law its autonomy. 2<br />

For a failure to recognise law’s autonomy risks trivialising the laws<br />

that govern us and the concerns of those governed by our law. No such<br />

trivialisation is to be found in <strong>this</strong> work: All the authors are deeply<br />

committed to the project of constitutionalism in South Africa.<br />

This book benefits immensely from two sources.<br />

The first source is Stu Woolman, Theunis Roux and Michael Bishop<br />

(eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd Edition (2008)(‘CLoSA’).<br />

This four volume treatise is the leading internationally-recognised,<br />

most widely cited, scholarly commentary on the subject. One reason<br />

for its status — in the courts and the secondary literature — is that <strong>this</strong><br />

76 chapter work covers every dimension of court practice,<br />

institutional constitutional law and all of the operational provisions<br />

and the substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights. However, what<br />

really distinguishes Constitutional Law of South Africa from other<br />

commentaries, and places it on an equal footing with the finest works<br />

in other jurisdictions, is its sustained engagement with its subject<br />

matter. Many of the chapters are of monograph length and quality. 3<br />

We would be quite remiss, however, if we did not acknowledge that<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa — and the 40 authors who have co-<br />

1 See S Woolman ‘The South African Constitution as the last great modernist<br />

project’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations (2008)<br />

Chapter 2; A Sachs ‘A gentle provocation: A reply to Stu Woolman’ in S Woolman<br />

& M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations (2008) Chapter 3.<br />

2 See Woolman (n 1 above) 26-27.<br />

3 Constitutional Law of South Africa takes its readers beyond the black letter law.<br />

It offers complete reconstructions of legal doctrine, provides alternative readings<br />

of constitutional provisions, and proffers appropriate criticism of the judiciary’s<br />

decisions and the legislature’s enactments. Constitutional Law of South Africa<br />

achieves these ends through comprehensive treatment of the case law and<br />

relevant statutes; a thorough review of the secondary literature; and the ability<br />

to draw, where appropriate, on relevant foreign and international jurisprudence.<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa fills a unique space in the South African legal<br />

academy and the profession. Constitutional Law of South Africa fills a unique<br />

space in the legal academy and the profession. By being both broad and deep, it<br />

holds our basic law together. The book serves as a home for what the editors like<br />

to describe as an ‘ideal community of interlocutors’. Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa creates a space where academics, practitioners and jurists can engage one<br />

another across the entire range of extant constitutional issues. The table of<br />

contents and the contributors to Constitutional Law of South Africa can be found<br />

in the compact disk at the back of the book. We cannot thank enough those 40<br />

some odd authors for making CLoSA, the CLoSA Conference and <strong>this</strong> book<br />

possible. Their contributions can now also be found at http://www.westlaw.com.<br />

For more on Constitutional Law of South Africa, see our website, http://<br />

www.closa.co.za. For those who wish to secure the treatise itself, see Juta Law’s<br />

website at http://www.jutalaw.co.za.


4 Chapter 1<br />

authored CLoSA — has given Constitutional conversations its heft. For<br />

readers looking for a deeper treatment of the topics canvassed in<br />

Constitutional conversations, we reproduce, in a compact disk (CD)<br />

found at the back of the book, the 8 full length CLoSA chapters upon<br />

which the 8 lead essays draw.<br />

The book also succeeds because of the structure of the conference<br />

from which much of its content flows: the Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa Conference & Public Lecture Series. That three day, three<br />

night indaba was, by design, grounded in a large number of the<br />

existing chapters of Constitutional Law of South Africa, 2 nd Edition.<br />

Eight of those often monograph length treatments have been chapters<br />

reconstituted, abbreviated and often radically reconceived chapters<br />

as the lead essays in <strong>this</strong> work. (Again, the 8 original full length<br />

chapters can be found on the compact disk (CD) at the back of <strong>this</strong><br />

work.) However, neither the lead essays nor Constitutional Law of<br />

South Africa (‘CLoSA’) provide the frission that gives <strong>this</strong> new work<br />

life. That frission is created, in large part, by the conference’s<br />

respondents. For those of us who have written lead chapters, it is fair<br />

to say that our work has been enriched when we read others who offer<br />

significantly different perspectives on the same phenomena. Such<br />

perspectives have, in many instances, awakened the lead authors<br />

from their dogmatic slumber. 4<br />

Such an awakening is an unalloyed good. Constitutional lawyers in<br />

South Africa cannot for a moment sit idly back and assume that the<br />

Constitution and all our cherished political institutions provide easy<br />

answers for the depredations of apartheid or the desolations of our<br />

current political order. Whether we like the gloss a fellow academic<br />

or jurist may place on the case law or not, that academic or jurist will<br />

invariably remind us that the Final Constitution is but a way station,<br />

a stop on a never-ending journey towards a more just political order. 5<br />

2 The content of these conversations<br />

2.1 The SA Constitution as the last great modernist project<br />

The opening conversation concerns, appropriately, the role that the<br />

legal academy plays in the interpretation of the constitutional text.<br />

As <strong>this</strong> collection flows, in part, from a much larger work that<br />

purports to cover all aspects of constitutional law, it is important to<br />

know a little about the players in <strong>this</strong> initial exchange. One<br />

4 For just such a perspective, see J van der Walt Law and Sacrifice (2006) and J van<br />

der Walt ‘A Reply to Woolman and Botha on Limitations’ in S Woolman & M Bishop<br />

(eds) Constitutional conversations (2008) Chapter 11.<br />

5 Woolman (n 1 above) 32.


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 5<br />

interlocutor is an editor for <strong>this</strong> book, Stu Woolman. Woolman just<br />

happens to be the editor-in-chief and lead author of the four-volume<br />

treatise Constitutional Law of South Africa. The challenger is none<br />

other than Albie Sachs, a Justice of the Constitutional Court: a famous<br />

author and a well-known-jurist; a famous freedom fighter and one of<br />

the chief architects of our basic law. 6<br />

Woolman opens his end of the conversation by recalling a casual<br />

remark Justice Albie Sachs made — to Professor Jack Greenberg and<br />

himself — after a lecture on Grootboom at Columbia Law School in<br />

2001. 7 Justice Sachs suggested, in passing, that legal academics ‘had<br />

played an important role during the transition’. The clear implication<br />

of <strong>this</strong> bon mot was that their time has passed and that academics<br />

were no longer genuinely needed by the Court. The Court, according<br />

to Sachs, was perfectly capable of handling the cases that seized it<br />

without the assistance of academic commentary.<br />

Woolman’s first response is to explain the current role of a South<br />

African constitutional law scholar. He notes that ‘in the real world’<br />

academics must first attempt to understand any given constitutional<br />

opinion, as well as the law underlying the constitutional dispute. To<br />

the extent that the opinion is less than transparent, the academic<br />

must offer a good faith reconstruction. Where the Court’s judgment<br />

remains opaque, and perhaps wrong, it is the academic’s responsibility<br />

to criticise the Court’s judgment. And where the Court’s<br />

judgment runs entirely off the rails and misconceives the meaning of<br />

the constitutional text, the academic’s job is to offer a preferred<br />

reading. Woolman then notes that academics are not merely<br />

handmaidens to the Court. They belong to, and write for, an ‘ideal<br />

community of interlocutors’ that — through continuous dialogue —<br />

attempts to get as close as possible to ‘the truth’ about the<br />

constitutional text and the law it generates. Woolman’s ‘ideal<br />

community’ embraces judges, advocates, attorneys, fellow academics,<br />

students and other denizens of <strong>this</strong> republic. However, even<br />

as it grapples with the exigencies of the moment, the ‘ideal<br />

community’ keeps a careful eye on future generations of lawyers,<br />

jurists, academics, students and citizens.<br />

The need for such an ‘imaginary domain’ — to employ Drucilla<br />

Cornell’s felicitous phrase — and our Court’s sometimes parsimonious<br />

explication of the basic law signals the potential for something of a<br />

crisis in our constitutional jurisprudence. 8 We cannot afford a Court<br />

6 See eg A Sachs The jail diary of Albie Sachs (1966); A Sachs The soft vengeance of<br />

a freedom fighter (1990).<br />

7 Government of the Republic of South Africa & Others v Grootboom & Others 2001<br />

1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC).<br />

8<br />

D Cornell The imaginary domain: Abortion, pornography and sexual harassment<br />

(1995).


6 Chapter 1<br />

stuck in a perpetual ‘present’: a constitutional groundhogs’ day. 9<br />

There are two further obstacles to the realisation of our ‘ideal<br />

community’. 10 Firstly, the courts, particularly the Constitutional<br />

Court, do not seem to take academic commentary — the life-blood of<br />

the ideal community — particularly seriously, to the extent that they<br />

acknowledge it at all. While the Justices of our Constitutional Court<br />

are unusually, and admirably, involved in public discourse, their<br />

judgments do not reflect extended or even peripheral engagement<br />

with academia. Secondly, although significant disagreement exists<br />

within academia about the nature of the academy’s role and the<br />

nature of the Court’s role, Woolman believes that a primary<br />

responsibility of both academics and the Court is to ‘model rational<br />

political discourse’. 11 It is hard to know how the Court can discharge<br />

<strong>this</strong> responsibility if it consistently issues under-theorised judgments<br />

and fails, where possible, to engage differences of view (often<br />

expressed by members of the academy) regarding the meaning of<br />

various provisions of the basic law.<br />

Justice Sachs suggests that his aside in a collegial chat at<br />

Columbia was not meant as a rebuke, but a ‘gentle provocation’. He<br />

then recalls how, leading up to the enactment of the Interim<br />

Constitution, academics were far ahead of judges in anticipating the<br />

structure and the content of the Constitution and the changes it could<br />

be expected to bring about. Many apartheid-era judges resented the<br />

imposition of such radical change and attempted to carve out a<br />

separate space for non-constitutional common law.<br />

According to Justice Sachs, he, and many of his colleagues, found<br />

great aid in academic writings before and after the drafting of the<br />

Interim Constitution. But he then notes that after the Court produced<br />

some ground-breaking judgments that would ‘la[y] the foundations of<br />

[the] new constitutional jurisprudence’ the academic response to<br />

these judgments was ‘virtually ... zero.’ He contends that while<br />

certain issues such as direct application, equality and socio-economic<br />

rights generated intense academic debate, many other cases arrived<br />

and departed without comment.<br />

The South African legal academic community might well wish to<br />

ask <strong>this</strong> question: Is there a dearth of first-rate academic writing in<br />

South Africa? The answer might well be yes. (The reasons for that<br />

answer are rather complex and beyond the scope of <strong>this</strong><br />

introduction.) But that cannot be the whole story. There is,<br />

9 S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing Bill of Rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law<br />

Journal 762.<br />

10 On the relationship between an ideal community and an open community, see<br />

Lourens du Plessis ‘Interpretation’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of<br />

South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2008) Chapter 32.<br />

11 J Rawls Political liberalism (1993).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 7<br />

undoubtedly, enough good writing that anticipates the issues that<br />

ultimately seize the Court. Moreover, the Constitutional Court in<br />

Mhlungu avers that constitutional interpretation must takes the form<br />

of ‘a principled judicial dialogue, in the first place between members<br />

of <strong>this</strong> Court, then between our Court and other courts, the legal<br />

profession, law schools, Parliament, and, indirectly, with the public<br />

at large.’ 12 If there is enough good writing in our journals and books,<br />

and if the Court must, by its own lights, undertake a principled<br />

dialogue with academia, then it is reasonable to ask whether it is<br />

possible to engage in a meaningful and principled conversation when<br />

the Court fails to acknowledge the presence, and the contributions,<br />

of other parties to that conversation?<br />

2.2 Rule of law<br />

The ‘rule of law’ functions as a fundamental principle of any<br />

constitutional democracy. In its most basic form, it reflects, in<br />

Thomas Jefferson’s well-turned phrase, the idea that a free people<br />

‘should have a government of law, not men’. That is, all actors, the<br />

governors and the governed, are bound by the same set of rules.<br />

Legality, an earlier incarnation of the rule of law doctrine, requires<br />

that any act which does not comply with the law and the Final<br />

Constitution must be found invalid.<br />

According to Professor Michelman, these two doctrines — when<br />

married to various other constitutional injunctions — say FC section<br />

39(2)’s requirement to interpret statutes and to develop the common<br />

law in light of constitutional dictates — have the potential to turn<br />

legal disputes into constitutional matters. As a result, no case — as a<br />

matter of logic — falls beyond the jurisdiction of the Constitutional<br />

Court. Michelman’s conclusion is striking, and controversial. On an<br />

ordinary language reading of the text, the Constitutional Court is a<br />

specialist court without plenary jurisdiction. Michelman’s reading<br />

challenges <strong>this</strong> very basic assumption.<br />

Professor Michelman examines both the causes and the<br />

consequences of the Constitutional Court’s decision to fashion the<br />

rule of law doctrine and the principle of legality as constitutional<br />

doctrines rather than have them remain common-law doctrines. He<br />

demonstrates that the decisions that articulated these principles —<br />

Fedsure, Pharmaceutical Manufacturers, and their progeny — render<br />

the continued separation between the jurisdiction of the<br />

Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal largely<br />

12 S v Mhlungu 1995 3 SA 867 (CC), 1995 7 BCLR 793 (CC) para 129.


8 Chapter 1<br />

illusory. 13 The Constitutional Court can, if it wishes to do so, decide<br />

that virtually any case possesses a constitutional dimension subject to<br />

its jurisdiction. 14 In a short but fascinating section, Michelman<br />

suggests that, at least with regard to development of the common<br />

law, the division of jurisdiction between the Constitutional Court and<br />

the Supreme Court of Appeal can be reconceived as part of the debate<br />

between HLA Hart and Ronald Dworkin. If, like Hart, we believe that<br />

there are ‘open spaces’ in the law then it makes sense to leave the<br />

detail of the common law to the specialists on the Supreme Court of<br />

Appeal. On the other hand, if we follow Dworkin’s lead and believe<br />

that can be but one right answer, then the Constitutional Court ought<br />

to have the final say on all matters raising constitutional issues. In his<br />

final section, Michelman explains how the South African jurisdictional<br />

debate fits within the broader international, comparative constitutional<br />

conversations about how constitutional jurisdiction should<br />

best be divided between domestic courts. He intimates that South<br />

Africa might not be ill served by a twin-peak system in which two<br />

courts share the final say on constitutional questions.<br />

Justice Kate O’Regan responds quite forcefully to several of<br />

Professor Michelman’s conclusions. Firstly, she takes issue with<br />

Michelman’s definition of constitutional law as the law that simply<br />

structures all government action. She argues that the South African<br />

Constitution has a substantially broader and deeper influence: it<br />

merely ‘restates the legal basis for all law in a normative manner, and<br />

so has a substantive effect on ... legal reasoning and the common<br />

law.’ Secondly, Justice O’Regan rejects the notion that the Constitution<br />

could give rise to multiple parallel legal systems where<br />

constitutional law and common-law causes of action exist side-byside.<br />

She stresses that the Constitution creates a unitary legal system<br />

which encompasses common law, statutory law and customary law<br />

and ‘subjects them all to the discipline of compliance with<br />

constitutional norms and values.’ The Court’s acceptance of the<br />

proposition that <strong>this</strong> single legal system encompasses multiple forms<br />

of law does not, O’Regan J opines, commit us to legal pluralism. The<br />

Constitution remains the law from which all other law derives its<br />

13 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA & Another: In re Ex parte<br />

President of the Republic of South Africa & Others 2000 2 SA 674 (CC), 2000 3<br />

BCLR 241 (CC); Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd & Others v Greater Johannesburg<br />

Transitional Metropolitan Council & Others 1999 1 SA 374 (CC), 1998 12 BCLR<br />

1458 (CC); President of the Republic of South Africa & Another v Modderklip<br />

Boerdery (Pty) Ltd (Agri SA & Others, Amici Curiae) 2005 5 SA 3 (CC), 2005 8 BCLR<br />

786 (CC).<br />

14 See F Michelman ‘The Rule of Law, Legality and the Supremacy of the<br />

Constitution’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd<br />

Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 11 (CD track 3). But for a functionalist view of<br />

constitutional jurisdiction that does not conclude that all matters are potentially<br />

constitutional matters, see S Seedorf ‘Constitutional Jurisdiction’ in S Woolman<br />

et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2008) Chapter 4.


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 9<br />

force. Thirdly, O’Regan J contends that the principle of legality, as<br />

currently conceived, could never have operated as a common-law<br />

principle under <strong>this</strong> dispensation. It is, rather, a unique and necessary<br />

by-product of our constitutional democracy. She also demurs from<br />

Michelman’s contention that the rule of doctrine turns the<br />

Constitutional Court’s specialist jurisdiction into plenary jurisdiction.<br />

With respect to <strong>this</strong> simmering jurisdictional dispute between the<br />

Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal, Justice<br />

O’Regan declines to offer any definitive resolution. She does,<br />

however, make two important points about the nature of<br />

‘constitutional matters’: (a) the Final Constitution operates — in some<br />

form — in all the courts and tribunals of South Africa; and (b) the<br />

distinction between constitutional matters and non-constitutional<br />

matters cannot be drawn on the basis of a hard-and-fast distinction<br />

between fact and law.<br />

As many readers are aware, the difficulties in defining the Court’s<br />

jurisdiction and the sustained criticism of that division are part of<br />

what lie behind the proposed (but currently shelved) constitutional<br />

amendment that would make the Constitutional Court an apex court<br />

with plenary jurisdiction. Michelman and O’Regan’s contributions<br />

thus give rise to two questions on the future of that proposal: Has the<br />

‘textually’ limited specialist jurisdiction of the Court contributed<br />

some degree of confusion about its role in entrenching the basic law?<br />

Would the currently moribund amendment put an end to that<br />

confusion?<br />

2.3 Democracy<br />

In UDM, 15 the Constitutional Court — in a poke at the legal academy<br />

and in the service of a strategy designed to finesse its obligation to<br />

state clearly the form of democracy to which the Final Constitution<br />

commits us — noted that no academic commentary had yet provided<br />

a meaningful account of the form of democracy to which the Final<br />

Constitution commits South Africa. Into that breach, Professor<br />

Theunis Roux quite consciously stepped. 16 His monograph in<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa — and his ruminations in these<br />

pages — provide an answer to the Court’s strategic non-denial denial<br />

15 United Democratic Movement v President of the Republic of South Africa &<br />

Others (African Christian Democratic Party & Others Intervening); Institute for<br />

Democracy in South Africa & Another as Amici Curiae (No 2) 2003 1 SA 495 (CC),<br />

2002 11 BCLR 1213 (CC) para 25.<br />

16<br />

See T Roux ‘Democracy’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 10 (CD track 4).


10 Chapter 1<br />

(that the Court itself had no coherent account of the kind of<br />

democracy the South African Constitution requires.) 17<br />

Roux’s starting point is the placement of a comma in FC section<br />

1(d). This comma implies that the purpose of all democratic<br />

structures is to ‘ensure accountability, responsiveness and openness.’<br />

From <strong>this</strong> humble beginning, and after a patient and close reading of<br />

the entire text of the Final Constitution, Roux concludes that<br />

‘democracy’ cannot denote mere majority rule. The Final<br />

Constitution’s vision of democracy requires structures that enable the<br />

people to engage in representative, direct and participatory forms of<br />

democracy which ensure that government remains accountable, open<br />

and responsive. At a minimum, democracy stands for the proposition<br />

that the rights in the Bill of Rights are not in conflict with majority<br />

rule: they are, rather, in a ‘constructive tension’ with each other. But<br />

Roux’s real point here is actually somewhat stronger. Rights, on his<br />

account, are necessary conditions for meaningful representative,<br />

participatory and direct democracy.<br />

Roux acknowledges that the Court has yet to accept his two<br />

principles of democracy. In UDM, New National Party and Masondo,<br />

the Constitutional Court declined to endorse a deep, multifaceted<br />

principle of democracy and offered instead a much shallower reading<br />

of the constitutional text. 18 Roux’s response is that these cases do not<br />

preclude a deeper understanding of democracy. Roux shows how<br />

UDM, the decision that offers the most powerful case against his deep<br />

reading, can be read not as addressing the content of ‘democracy’,<br />

but rather as supporting a meta-principle that, where the Final<br />

Constitution offers no clear answer to a ‘deep’ question, courts<br />

should defer to the government in politically sensitive cases.<br />

More recent cases in the Constitutional Court, African Christian<br />

Democratic Party 19 and Matatiele I, 20 demonstrate growing support<br />

for Roux’s principle of democracy. Roux’s reading, in fact, was<br />

vindicated by the Constitutional Court in two cases that came down<br />

several months after he had articulated his position in his chapter on<br />

‘Democracy’ in Constitutional Law of South Africa. In Doctors for Life<br />

International and Matatiele II, the Court struck down legislation that<br />

had been promulgated without the kind of public participation<br />

17 See T Roux ‘Principle and Pragmatism on the South African Constitutional Court’<br />

(2009) International Journal of Constitutional Law (forthcoming).<br />

18<br />

UDM (n 15 above); Democratic Alliance & Another v Masondo NO & Another 2003<br />

2 SA 413 (CC), 2003 2 BCLR 128 (CC); New National Party of South Africa v<br />

Government of the Republic of South Africa & Others 1999 3 SA 191 (CC), 1999 5<br />

BCLR 489 (CC).<br />

19 African Christian Democratic Party v Electoral Commission & Others 2006 (3) SA<br />

305 (CC), 2006 (5) BCLR 579 (CC).<br />

20<br />

Matatiele Municipality & Others v President of the Republic of South Africa &<br />

Others 2006 5 SA 47 (CC), 2007 1 BCLR 47 (CC).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 11<br />

contemplated by our basic law. 21 In so doing, the Court’s decisions<br />

corroborate Roux’s central thesis: democracy means more, much<br />

more, than mere majority rule.<br />

By and large, Danie Brand concurs with Theunis Roux’s reading of<br />

the Constitution. The gravamen of Brand’s complaint has more to do<br />

with the style of Roux’s writing — not its elegance or its turn of<br />

phrase, which can hardly be faulted, but the manner in which Roux<br />

leaves out considerations about South African democracy that Brand<br />

believes matter. First, Brand asks why Roux does not consider the<br />

existence of a positive constitutional duty to build democratic<br />

institutions and a concomitant duty to ensure that these institutions<br />

operate in a manner that promotes representative, participatory and<br />

direct democracy. Second, Brand suggests that apart from a nod in<br />

the direction of the counter-majoritarian dilemma, Roux does not<br />

fully engage the inevitable tension between constitutional<br />

adjudication and various forms of democracy. Brand is particularly<br />

concerned with the tension between constitutional adjudication and<br />

extra-institutional, extra-formal democratic political action. He<br />

suggests, ever so delicately, that Roux does not address these two<br />

issues because Roux sees his project as a quasi-Dworkinian description<br />

of legal principle. That is, the language Roux employs ‘enjoys’ the<br />

status of an objective, empirically verifiable description of the legal<br />

text and its consequences for the case law. Brand contends <strong>this</strong><br />

unstated claim to objectivity masks the normative choice that is<br />

always present in such a description. More importantly, Brand argues,<br />

such an implicit claim actually discourages democratic engagement<br />

by denying any space for alternative readings.<br />

Brand’s last charge regarding Roux’s style is, perhaps, his most<br />

provocative claim. In short, Brand asks whether the form of our<br />

expression bears a meaningful relation to the substance of a debate.<br />

Does, Brand seems to ask, a healthy democracy require not only the<br />

lively exchange of different substantive positions, but that those<br />

positions are expressed in a particular way? A different, but related,<br />

question is whether the denotation of ‘democracy’ is always open and<br />

thus invariably contested? In sum, can we have democracy without an<br />

essentialist conception of democracy, and does the hurly-burly of<br />

21 Matatiele Municipality & Others v President of the RSA & Others (No 2) 2007 6 SA<br />

477 (CC), 2007 1 BCLR 47 (CC); Doctors for Life International v Speaker of the<br />

National Assembly & Others 2006 6 SA 416 (CC), 2006 12 BCLR 1399 (CC).


12 Chapter 1<br />

democratic politics itself invariably result in some degree of<br />

instability in our conception of democracy?<br />

2.4 Application<br />

At the CLoSA Conference and Public Lecture Series, one of the<br />

editors, Professor Stu Woolman, limited his address to a theoretical<br />

critique of the Constitutional Court’s approach to direct application<br />

and indirect application of the Bill of Rights. (The primary question<br />

raised by application, for the uninitiated, concerns the parties that<br />

are and are not burdened by the specific substantive rights found in<br />

Chapter 2 of the Final Constitution.) And that remains the central<br />

purpose of his contribution to <strong>this</strong> collection. He argues that the<br />

Constitutional Court in Khumalo v Holomisa 22 — while acknowledging<br />

and endorsing the possibility of horizontal application under the Final<br />

Constitution — wilfully misread the wording of the application<br />

provisions in FC section 8 and that its five paragraphs on the subject<br />

are patently incoherent. Woolman meticulously roots out the textual<br />

errors in the Khumalo Court’s approach. He then demonstrates that<br />

even a good faith reconstruction of Khumalo cannot stand up to even<br />

the most generous scrutiny. In place of the good faith reconstruction,<br />

Woolman proffers a preferred reading of FC section 8 and FC section<br />

39(2) that makes sense of the division between direct application and<br />

indirect application of the Bill of Rights. This preferred reading —<br />

while still imperfect — makes the best possible sense of the<br />

Constitutional Assembly’s poorly drafted sections on direct<br />

application.<br />

Professor Iain Currie first notes that he had the unenviable task —<br />

especially given the constraints of a conference paper — of responding<br />

to Woolman’s long and theoretically ambitious contribution in<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa. 23 Without immediately conceding<br />

anything regarding the merits of that contribution, Currie suggests<br />

that such ambition reflects an ‘old-fashioned’ model of academic<br />

discourse: And by ‘old-fashioned’, Currie simply means scholarship<br />

that engages carefully all of the available and relevant materials —<br />

the text, the judgments, and the work of fellow commentators. He<br />

then offers a brief historical summary of the debate over application,<br />

and notes how, under the Final Constitution, courts have been far less<br />

‘vexed’ by the relationship between direct application and indirect<br />

application than academics. Currie suggests that the reason for <strong>this</strong><br />

absence of engagement is that there is no practical difference<br />

between the two forms of application: Both approaches should<br />

22 Khumalo v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 (CC), 2002 8 BCLR 771 (CC).<br />

23<br />

See S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 31 (CD track 5).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 13<br />

produce the same results in all cases. While conceding the undeniable<br />

and persuasive theoretical power of Woolman’s account, Currie still<br />

believes he can legitimately ask whether there ‘is any reason other<br />

than the beauty and the internal coherence of our theories to bother<br />

with the distinction between direct application and indirect<br />

application?’ 24<br />

In <strong>this</strong> collection, Woolman answers Currie’s question with an<br />

emphatic ‘Yes!’ He notes how, in a string of recent judgments, the<br />

Constitutional Court has, once again, finessed the clear difference<br />

between indirect application and direct application. Woolman<br />

contends that the continuous use of indirect application empties the<br />

substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights of their content. (Quite<br />

often now, fundamental rights analysis is conducted under the vague<br />

and rather flaccid banner of FC section 39(2)’s injunction to develop<br />

or to interpret the law — statutory, common, customary — in light of<br />

the ‘spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights’.) Such a move —<br />

employing indirect application first — does not merely denude the Bill<br />

of Rights of its content. It creates an environment in which the Court<br />

sits as a court of equity and fails to provide the clear and meaningful<br />

body of precedent that must guide lower court judges crafting<br />

opinions, lawyers drafting heads of argument, government officials<br />

creating policy and citizens merely attempting to conform their<br />

behaviour to the dictates of the basic law. The Court’s casual<br />

casuistic approach does not just get application analysis back to front.<br />

It constitutes a paradigmatic violation of the rule of law.<br />

2.5 Limitations<br />

The Final Constitution, like the Canadian Charter, adopts a two-stage<br />

structure for analysis. At the first stage, a court must determine<br />

whether the exercise of a right has been impaired by law or conduct.<br />

At the second stage, the government or the party looking to uphold<br />

an impugned law — but not conduct — has an opportunity to justify<br />

that limitation if it serves ‘an open and democratic society based on<br />

human dignity, equality and freedom’. As Professors Woolman and<br />

Botha have written elsewhere:<br />

The limitation clause has a four-fold purpose. First, it functions as a<br />

reminder that the rights enshrined in the Final Constitution are not<br />

absolute. ... Secondly, the limitation clause tells us that rights may only<br />

be limited where and when the stated objective behind the restriction is<br />

designed to reinforce the values that animate <strong>this</strong> constitutional<br />

project. ... Thirdly, the test set out in the limitation clause — with a bit<br />

of judicial amplification — allows for candid consideration of those<br />

public goods or private interests that the challenged law sets in<br />

24 See I Currie & J de Waal The Bill of Rights handbook 5th Ed (2005).


14 Chapter 1<br />

opposition to the rights and freedoms enshrined in Chapter 2. Fourthly,<br />

the limitation clause could be said to represent an attempt to finesse<br />

the ‘problem’ of judicial review by establishing a test that determines<br />

the extent to which the democratically elected branches of government<br />

may craft laws that limit our constitutionally protected rights and the<br />

extent to which an unelected judiciary may override the general will by<br />

reference to the basic law. But the presence of FC s 36 serves as a<br />

reminder that the counter-majoritarian dilemma is neither a paradox<br />

nor a problem, but an ineluctable consequence of our commitment to<br />

living in a constitutional democracy. 25<br />

In addition to those thorny issues identified above, the limitations<br />

clause of the Final Constitution throws up a number of other difficult<br />

problems. How do courts divide the analysis between the two stages?<br />

What type of arguments can be used to justify limitations? What<br />

mechanisms, if any, should judges use to compare the conflicting<br />

interests that are inevitably at stake under FC section 36? Can we ever<br />

truly justify a limitation of rights — or must we simply own up to the<br />

fact that we make hard choices that grant ascendency to one<br />

preferred vision of the good over another and that such a choice<br />

invariably requires sacrifice in the deepest, and sometimes cruelest,<br />

sense of the term? These hard questions form the basis for the<br />

exchange between Woolman & Botha and Van der Walt.<br />

Woolman and Botha provide us with a fresh take on how we<br />

conceptualise the limitation of rights. The traditional metaphor used<br />

by academics and courts is that of ‘balancing’ — weighing the purpose<br />

of the right against the objective of the limitation. Woolman and<br />

Botha decry the use of ‘balancing’ on several grounds — but it offends<br />

them mostly because it is, in the words of Justice William Brennan,<br />

‘doctrinally destructive nihilism.’ 26 Limitations analysis often requires<br />

the courts to choose between incommensurable goods that, by<br />

definition, share no common metric of value. In addition, they suggest<br />

that ‘balancing’ often masks a judge’s subjective preferences (and<br />

prejudices), permits a conservative approach to constitutional<br />

analysis, and promotes a faux empirical analysis that tends to silence<br />

marginalised communities. In place of balancing, Woolman and Botha<br />

suggest a ‘thick(er)’ and more experimental conception of limitations<br />

analysis. This approach focuses on an ongoing dialogue between<br />

various courts, between the courts, the legislature and the executive,<br />

between the courts and the parties before them, and between the<br />

courts and other interested parties in the broader community,<br />

regarding the meaning of the Final Constitution. While the Court<br />

retains an important role in articulating ‘rolling’ general norms that<br />

give content to our basic law, other parties have a responsibility to<br />

25 S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of<br />

26<br />

South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 34 (CD track 6).<br />

New Jersey v TLO 469 US 325, 369 (1985).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 15<br />

‘experiment’ with different laws, policies and practices that fit within<br />

these rolling norms. Thus, courts, the other branches of government<br />

and the rest of South African society are enjoined to participate in a<br />

shared project of constitutional interpretation that reveals best<br />

practices over time. Experimental constitutionalism thus displaces<br />

the standard account of the Court as the single, final oracle of<br />

constitutional interpretation.<br />

As part of <strong>this</strong> thick(er) conception of limitations analysis,<br />

Woolman and Botha stress the need to engage with all five values in<br />

FC section 36: democracy, openness, dignity, equality and freedom.<br />

Harmonising these values is no easy task. Indeed, they invariably pull<br />

in different directions in every hard case that comes before the Court.<br />

As Woolman and Botha note:<br />

The[se] tensions ... are constitutive of the South African constitutional<br />

order. ... Any attempt to eradicate these conflicts and to deny the<br />

distinctive meaning each of these values would do real violence to the<br />

constitutional text and deny the commitment to openness and to<br />

plurality on which it is premised.<br />

Professor Johan van der Walt takes the cue for his riposte from a<br />

parenthetical in Woolman and Botha’s chapter in Constitutional Law<br />

of South Africa. Woolman and Botha write that ‘powers of judicial<br />

review are best understood, not as a part of a battle for ascendancy<br />

between courts and legislatures (though they may turn into that) ...<br />

but, rather, as shared project of constitutional interpretation.’ For<br />

Van der Walt, the real problem with respect to the call for shared<br />

interpretation, for a meaningful open-ended constitutional politics, is<br />

that it has been inappropriately constrained by these brackets. These<br />

words, he contends, should be allowed to ‘spill ... deconstructively<br />

into the rest of [the] text.’ For Van der Walt, the heart of the matter<br />

— ‘where we must dance’ — is the tension between the possible and<br />

the impossible, the immanent and the imminent, the sayable and the<br />

unsayable. It is <strong>this</strong> constant tension, and the sacrifice at the heart of<br />

<strong>this</strong> tension, notes Van der Walt, that ‘affords the notion of shared<br />

interpretation its grave significance’. On <strong>this</strong> point, Woolman, Botha<br />

and Van der Walt would, ultimately, appear to be in accord.<br />

2.6 Equality<br />

The right to equality has been one of the most widely and effectively<br />

litigated rights in the Court’s first 12 years. And understandably so. If<br />

nothing else, apartheid South Africa was defined by the racist<br />

subjugation of a majority of its citizens. One of the primary promises<br />

of the new Bill of Rights was, therefore, that all people would be<br />

treated equally before the law, that nobody would be unfairly<br />

discriminated against and that people who belonged to groups that


16 Chapter 1<br />

had previously been disadvantaged would be the beneficiaries of<br />

programs aimed at systematic and thorough historical redress.<br />

In their chapter, Professor Cathi Albertyn and Beth Goldblatt<br />

develop the rather speculative thesis that the right to equality<br />

supports a vision of substantive equality. 27 Their construction of<br />

substantive equality does not aim to provide a complete answer to the<br />

hard question — ‘equality of what?’ It reflects, however controversial,<br />

a set of intuitions about ‘a social democratic vision that entails<br />

equality of opportunities and outcomes.’<br />

After considering the basic values underlying the right to equality,<br />

Albertyn and Goldblatt conduct a brief but detailed analysis of the<br />

Constitutional Court’s jurisprudence on FC section 9(3): the right not<br />

to be subject to unfair discrimination. While generally supportive of<br />

the Court’s approach, Albertyn and Goldblatt raise a number of<br />

legitimate concerns. Firstly, the Court has, despite purporting to<br />

recognise feminist theories, failed to apply them meaningfully to<br />

cases — such as Volks 28 and Jordan 29 — that go to the heart of unfair<br />

differentiation between men and women. Secondly, the authors note<br />

how, in these (and other) cases, the Court reverts to an approach to<br />

equality analysis that fails to grasp the impact of the alleged<br />

discrimination on the complainants.<br />

Karthy Govender questions an approach to equality that focuses<br />

almost exclusively on achieving substantive equality (especially<br />

where substantive equality looks to be a stand-in for historical<br />

redress). He begins by noting that South Africa has, in fact, made<br />

relatively rapid egalitarian changes to its laws through a rather<br />

cautious and judicious use of the right to equality. Govender links his<br />

preferred approach to Justice Sach’s concern in Walker that too<br />

expansive an approach to indirect discrimination would allow ‘every<br />

tax burden, every licensing or town planning regulation’ to be<br />

challenged simply because it had disproportionate effects on<br />

different groups. 30 While Justice Sachs’ approach was not adopted in<br />

Walker, Govender argues that the Van Heerden Court achieved a<br />

similar goal through the vehicle of FC section 9(2). 31 The Court’s FC<br />

section 9(2) analysis — the historical redress provision — enables it to<br />

adopt a flexible approach that pays particular attention to the<br />

27<br />

C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Equality’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of<br />

South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2007) Chapter 35 (CD track 8).<br />

28 Volks NO v Robinson & Others 2005 5 BCLR 446 (CC).<br />

29<br />

S v Jordan & Others (Sex Workers Education and Advocacy Task Force & Others as<br />

Amici Curiae) 2002 6 SA 642 (CC), 2002 2 SACR 499 (CC), 2002 11 BCLR 1117 (CC).<br />

30 Pretoria City Council v Walker 1998 2 SA 363 (CC), 1998 2 BCLR 257 (CC).<br />

31<br />

Minister of Finance & Another v Van Heerden 2004 6 SA 121 (CC), 2004 11 BCLR<br />

125 (CC).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 17<br />

allegedly deleterious effect of the law or the conduct in question on<br />

a complainant’s dignity.<br />

Both contributions also consider the complex relationship<br />

between the FC section 9(3) inquiry into fairness and the FC section<br />

36 justification analysis. Albertyn and Goldblatt contend that while<br />

the Court has managed to draw a theoretical line between the two<br />

inquiries, that line often breaks down in cases where there is no law<br />

of general application to justify the unfair discrimination. Govender<br />

in turn argues that FC section 36 has a distinct role to play where the<br />

justification for unfair discrimination relies upon a government policy<br />

that does not address the discriminatory impact of law or policy on a<br />

particular complainant.<br />

Despite these observations, it is worth asking whether the analysis<br />

of unfair discrimination in terms of FC section 9(3) exhausts all<br />

aspects of justification that occur in terms of FC section 36 — or<br />

whether there remains a distinction with a difference. Does the<br />

phrase ‘reasonable and justifiable unfair discrimination’ — the upshot<br />

of a finding of unfair discrimination under FC section 9 and an<br />

upholding of the limitation of the equality claim under FC section 36<br />

— make any sense? Despite the repeated rhetoric of separate<br />

inquiries, a majority of the Court has yet to hold that a finding of<br />

unfair discrimination in terms of FC section 9 can be justified under<br />

FC section 36. Whatever the respective merits of their arguments,<br />

Albertyn, Goldblatt and Govender’s contributions keep <strong>this</strong><br />

conversation alive. 32<br />

2.7 Dignity<br />

Over the first 10 years of South Africa’s constitutional jurisprudence,<br />

it was fashionable to be a dignity-sceptic: dignity was said to be so<br />

‘over-used’, ‘over-cited’, ‘over-indulged’ as to mean anything and<br />

everything and therefore nothing. Neither Woolman nor Ackermann<br />

are dignity-sceptics. Quite the contrary. The question for them is not<br />

how great a role dignity should play — it already plays a pivotal role<br />

— but what the right to dignity really means and does.<br />

Woolman first traces the history of dignity’s inclusion in the<br />

Constitution — and then marks the import of South African history and<br />

a certain strand of Western philosophy for understanding what dignity<br />

means. He deduces from Kant’s various formulations of the<br />

categorical imperative, and the Constitutional Court’s jurisprudence<br />

32 For an account which questions whether the same considerations employed in a<br />

finding of unfair discrimination can then be used to justify the unfair<br />

discrimination, see S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations’ in S Woolman et al (n 25<br />

above) 34-33 and 34-40.


18 Chapter 1<br />

on dignity, five definitions of human dignity employed by the Court.<br />

These definitions range from (1) the conventional command not to<br />

treat a person simply as a means, but also as an end, to (2) the need<br />

to treat people with equal concern and respect, to (3) the recognition<br />

of others as self-governing and self-actualising beings, and finally to<br />

(4) the recognition that our own dignity is linked to the material<br />

conditions in which our fellow South Africans live. Woolman thus gives<br />

discernable, concrete content to what sceptics like to glibly dismiss<br />

as a term that means anything and everything and therefore nothing.<br />

Secondly, Woolman explains the different ways in which dignity —<br />

in all its guises — is employed in the Final Constitution. Woolman<br />

argues that dignity has four distinct roles: as a first order rule; as a<br />

second-order rule; as a correlative right; and as a grundnorm. As a<br />

first order rule litigants can rely on dignity to secure relief that would<br />

not be available under any other right. As a second order rule dignity<br />

informs — and even determines — the content of other rights — in<br />

particular the right to equality. Dignity also operates as a correlative<br />

right: the Court requires that litigants simultaneously assert all<br />

relevant rights — and dignity often features in challenges based upon<br />

privacy, freedom and security of the person, freedom of trade,<br />

occupation and profession and various socio-economic rights. Dignity<br />

as a grundnorm refers to the role dignity plays as a value that informs<br />

the interpretation of all the substantive rights found in the Bill of<br />

Rights and many of the remaining provisions of the Constitution.<br />

In his concluding section, Woolman asks how dignity can be used<br />

to promote the transformation of South African society. He suggests<br />

that dignity can be profitably linked to Amartya Sen’s theory of<br />

capabilities. 33 Such a view of dignity would require that all people are<br />

not only free from interference by the State and other private actors,<br />

but that they are provided with the material conditions that enable<br />

them ‘to pursue [their] preferred way of being in the world.’<br />

Justice Ackermann, one of the primary architects of the<br />

Constitutional Court’s dignity jurisprudence, expresses his broad<br />

agreement with Woolman’s take on dignity, particularly his reliance<br />

on Kantian principles. However, the Justice still articulates what he<br />

believes to be a number of small but significant points of<br />

disagreement.<br />

But they are not, in fact, small at all. In a path-breaking account<br />

of the relationship between dignity and the possession of a soul,<br />

Ackermann suggests that our study of dignity should not only focus on<br />

the external content of human dignity — or what Ackermann prefers<br />

33 See A Sen Development as freedom (1999).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 19<br />

to call ‘human worth’ — but on the inner content of human dignity —<br />

and our ability to come to grips with or to ‘fathom what [the]<br />

uniqueness of personhood is.’ For Ackermann, such a study must<br />

consider the teachings of the Abrahamic religions: Christianity, Islam<br />

and Judaism. While he stresses that the Final Constitution is,<br />

ultimately, a secular document, he argues persuasively that dignity<br />

cannot be properly understood without reference to its spiritual<br />

underpinnings. Nowhere else in the South African literature has <strong>this</strong><br />

claim been made — and we are fortunate to have one of the leading<br />

readers of our Constitution explain to us how the role of human worth<br />

in religious teachings enhances our secular account of <strong>this</strong> right and<br />

<strong>this</strong> value.<br />

Ackermann then expresses some concern over Woolman’s<br />

definitions of dignity. He takes issue with Woolman’s location of the<br />

demands for ‘equal concern and equal respect’ and ‘self<br />

actualisation’ within the right to dignity. He believes them to be more<br />

appropriately located in the right to equality (FC section 9) and the<br />

value of freedom (FC sections 7, 36, 39). Ackermann then contends<br />

that Woolman’s distinction between ‘first-order’ and ‘second-order’<br />

rules evince a Hartian or positivist approach to constitutional law.<br />

(Woolman has repeatedly denied the charge that a commitment to<br />

‘rules’ in law — and in particular the law which emanates from the<br />

right to dignity — necessarily commits him or anyone else to<br />

positivism.) 34 Our Constitution, Ackermann claims, ‘cries out for a<br />

Kelsenian approach’. According to him, only a Kelsenian approach to<br />

the Constitution, in general, and dignity, in particular, is consistent<br />

with the aspirational character of our basic law.<br />

2.8 Property<br />

The property clause of the Interim Constitution reflected a necessary,<br />

if tenuous, compromise between the interests of white propertyowners<br />

and the transformative goals of the ANC. The Final<br />

Constitution alters that compromise, but still recognises the need to<br />

weigh the imperatives of transformation against the ‘stability’ that<br />

flows from the protection of private interests, and thus of apartheidera<br />

economic arrangements.<br />

The property clause itself covers a broad range of issues: from<br />

compensation for the expropriation of property, to restitution and the<br />

redistribution of land. This colloquy focuses primarily on deprivation<br />

and expropriation of existing rights in land. The primary bone of<br />

34 See S Woolman ‘Dignity’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 36 (CD track 7); S Woolman ‘The Widening<br />

Gyre of Dignity’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations<br />

(2008) Chapter 12.


20 Chapter 1<br />

contention in the exchange between Professors Theunis Roux and<br />

Frank Michelman is whether the test adopted by the Constitutional<br />

Court in FNB to determine whether a person was arbitrarily deprived<br />

of property is appropriate for South Africa. 35 While both agree on the<br />

content and the effects of the test established in FNB, they disagree<br />

on its desirability.<br />

In FNB, the Court held that ‘arbitrary’ in FC section 25(1) means<br />

that the deprivation of property occurs without ‘sufficient reason’<br />

taking into account all the relevant factors including the nature of the<br />

property, the extent of the deprivation and the purpose of the<br />

deprivation. In addition, the level of scrutiny applied to a law will vary<br />

from basic rationality to strict proportionality depending on<br />

circumstances of the particular case before the court. The impact of<br />

FNB — both authors agree — is to largely reduce the six tests implicit<br />

in FC section 25 into a single inquiry. The result is, in Roux’s words, a<br />

‘reasonableness vortex’. 36 For Roux, such a vortex is dangerous<br />

because it renders it impossible to predict in advance the outcome of<br />

any application of FC section 25. As a result, government cannot know<br />

whether its plans will pass constitutional muster because the level of<br />

scrutiny that will apply will depend on the ‘facts’ of the particular<br />

case as ‘understood’ by the Court. It also means that uncompensated<br />

expropriations will be dealt with as arbitrary deprivations, instead of<br />

expropriations that simply need to be compensated. The problem<br />

with FNB is that there may be occasions when the government would<br />

simply want to compensate persons for the expropriation of property.<br />

The reasonableness vortex makes such an expropriation impossible —<br />

as a matter of doctrine — and means that South African courts will be<br />

unable to develop an equivalent of American ‘regulatory takings’<br />

doctrine that rests on a distinction between deprivation and<br />

expropriation.<br />

Michelman, on the contrary, is far more optimistic about the<br />

consequences of FNB. In a detailed analysis of FNB, Roux’s arguments<br />

and American law, Michelman demonstrates — with the experience of<br />

an American property lawyer familiar with regulatory takings doctrine<br />

— why South Africa is far better off with a general proportionality<br />

test. He contends that it was virtually inevitable that the Court would<br />

collapse expropriations and deprivations. The real ‘problem’, notes<br />

Michelman, is that the Court will treat uncompensated expropriations<br />

as arbitrary deprivations because they are uncompensated. If we are<br />

happy to accept that proposition, then it does not matter where we<br />

35<br />

36<br />

First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner, South African<br />

Revenue Service & Another; First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Minister<br />

of Finance 2002 4 SA 768 (CC), 2002 7 BCLR 702 (CC).<br />

See T Roux ‘Property’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa<br />

(2nd Edition, OS, 2004) Chapter 46 (CD track 9).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 21<br />

draw the line between deprivations and expropriations. FNB’s all-inone<br />

test then looks to be completely sensible. In any event, FC<br />

sections 25(2) and (3) will apply to instances of total acquisitive<br />

expropriation: such expropriations will remain common in South<br />

Africa for some time to come. Furthermore, Michelman believes that<br />

Roux’s worry that FNB makes it impossible to predict outcomes will<br />

diminish over time as the case law creates precedent, and thus rules,<br />

that can be applied to future matters.<br />

This exchange between Roux and Michelman has consequences<br />

that extend beyond their immediate concern with the correct<br />

interpretation of the property clause. The adoption of a<br />

‘reasonableness’ approach to rights analysis has prompted Roux and<br />

others to express concern about a mode of constitutional analysis that<br />

possesses the potential to empty many of these rights of their<br />

content.<br />

In his second demurral from Roux’s characterisation of FNB,<br />

Michelman suggests a reading that can give FC section 25(1) and FC<br />

section 36(1) distinct and meaningful roles. While arbitrariness is<br />

ordinarily viewed in terms of different points on the same axis —<br />

which makes undertaking FC section 25(1) analysis and FC section<br />

36(1) analysis duplicative — Michelman believes that the two sections<br />

can operate on different axes. He argues that while FC section 25(1)<br />

must be understood in terms of an ordinary means-ends rationality<br />

test, FC section 36(1) can deployed when a court is asked to come to<br />

grips with how various burdens are distributed. For example, in<br />

Mkontwana, the law at issue required owners to pay their tenants<br />

unpaid utility bills. 37 The law achieves the goal of ensuring that rates<br />

are paid, but may unfairly place the burden solely on landowners.<br />

According to Michelman, the law would not be arbitrary under FC<br />

section 25(1), but would be unjustifiable under FC section 36(1).<br />

2.9 Socio-economic rights<br />

Socio-economic rights, it is safe to say, have generated some of the<br />

liveliest debate amongst South African academics. The debate has,<br />

for some time, revolved around the Constitutional Court’s decision to<br />

adopt a reasonableness approach rather than a minimum-core<br />

approach. The first approach requires only that government acts<br />

reasonably in trying to fulfill gradually socio-economic rights. The<br />

minimum-core approach sets minimum standards that the State must<br />

37<br />

Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality & Another; Bissett &<br />

Others v Buffalo City Municipality & Others; Transfer Rights Action Campaign &<br />

Others v MEC, Local Government and Housing, Gauteng, & Others (KwaZulu-<br />

Natal Law Society and Msunduzi Municipality as Amici Curiae) 2005 1 SA 530 (CC),<br />

2005 2 BCLR 150 (CC).


22 Chapter 1<br />

immediately enforce. Liebenberg’s and Pieterse’s colloquy breathes<br />

new life into <strong>this</strong> debate.<br />

Professor Liebenberg contends that the major problem with a<br />

minimum core approach is that it stifles dialogue: It relies on a single<br />

top-down decision of what a socio-economic right requires. It<br />

therefore closes down further debate — in government and in civil<br />

society — about the content of the socio-economic rights found in FC<br />

sections 25, 26, 27, 28, 29 and 35. Liebenberg further argues that the<br />

alleged clarity of a minimum-core approach is illusory. It is illusory<br />

because it traps us in programs focused solely on survival — from<br />

which we may never escape — and eschews equally hard decisions<br />

about how to transform South African society in a number of equally<br />

important non-survival settings. Liebenberg thus concludes that ‘the<br />

minimum core approach is in danger of encouraging minimalism in<br />

social provisioning when the context may in fact render such<br />

minimalism unnecessary and inappropriate.’<br />

On the other hand, reasonableness review allows a contextsensitive<br />

test that is responsive to democratic dialogue. The major<br />

drawback of <strong>this</strong> approach, as Liebenberg notes, is that it collapses<br />

the traditional two-stage rights analysis and does not properly engage<br />

‘with the content, scope and underlying values of the relevant rights’.<br />

Liebenberg suggests argues that a reasonableness approach might<br />

overcome <strong>this</strong> deficiency if courts were to conduct more substantive<br />

evaluations of the content of socio-economic rights. Moreover, the<br />

reasonableness approach already possesses some of the strengths of<br />

the minimum-core argument by requiring a higher level of scrutiny<br />

where the very lives of the complainants are on the line. 38<br />

Professor Marius Pieterse’s response focuses on Liebenberg’s<br />

belief that both extant reasonableness review and minimum core<br />

doctrines stifle dialogue about the content and the contours of<br />

existing socio-economic rights doctrine and discourse. Pieterse<br />

stresses the importance of <strong>this</strong> dialogue in ‘translating’ socioeconomic<br />

rights from ‘conceptually empty, abstract principles into<br />

more concrete, claimable entitlements.’ This dialogue must occur not<br />

only between the judiciary and the other branches of government,<br />

but between other players in the ‘constitutional community’ —<br />

NGO’s, social movements, and, ultimately, the citizenry at large.<br />

Each of these players has different strengths and different roles to<br />

play. Social movements, for example, provide a voice for the people<br />

who are most in need of socio-economic rights. Academics offer<br />

38 See further S Liebenberg ‘The interpretation of socio-economic rights’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2007)<br />

Chapter 33 (CD track 10); S Liebenberg Adjudicating fundamental rights under a<br />

transformative constitution (2008).


Stu Woolman & Michael Bishop 23<br />

‘thoroughly theorised interpretations’ that can assist the state, the<br />

courts and civil society. On <strong>this</strong> fresh account, courts come to be<br />

viewed as venues for translation: forums in which various actors can<br />

debate the meaning of socio-economic rights.<br />

Within <strong>this</strong> polycentric framework, Pieterse agrees with<br />

Liebenberg that a minimum-core approach stifles participation by<br />

non-governmental players because it is a ‘once-off’, ‘top-down’<br />

imposition of a singular — hotly contested — point of view. However,<br />

Pieterse has misgivings about the ability of reasonableness review to<br />

successfully translate socio-economic rights into meaningful norms<br />

that take account of a multiplicity of different views — and which<br />

would provide information that would otherwise be unavailable to the<br />

Court in normal adversarial proceedings. Reasonableness review, as<br />

currently applied by the courts, limits dialogue to exchanges between<br />

the judiciary and the other branches of government about the virtues<br />

of existing government programs. It thereby ‘dampens’ the voices of<br />

claimants and discourages them from approaching courts for<br />

immediate relief.<br />

The reframing of the struggle between the reasonableness<br />

approach and minimum core approach in terms of dialogue and<br />

translation certainly reinvigorates an old debate. However, one might<br />

ask whether ongoing ‘dialogue’ about the meaning of socio-economic<br />

rights could become an end in itself and thereby obstruct the full<br />

realisation of FC sections 26, 27, 28 and 29.<br />

3 Ideal participants in the construction of an ideal<br />

community<br />

Where would we be without our authors? Four justices of the<br />

Constitutional Court — Chief Justice Pius Langa, Justice Kate<br />

O’Regan, Justice Albie Sachs and Justice Emeritus Laurie Ackermann<br />

— have taken the time, and made the effort — to engage the academy<br />

in a respectful conversation about the meaning of our basic law.<br />

Professor Frank Michelman, of Harvard Law School, and Professor<br />

Theunis Roux, Director of the South African Institute for Advanced<br />

Constitutional, Human Rights, Public & International Law, have<br />

contributed twice to <strong>this</strong> work: to have four contributions from two of<br />

the best constitutional law academics in their respective jurisdictions<br />

is another signal achievement of <strong>this</strong> work. But despite such apparent<br />

genuflection, there exists no hierarchy in <strong>this</strong> book. And so we are<br />

quick to note that we are equally fortunate to have first rate<br />

contributions from South Africa’s best constitutional law scholars: Iain<br />

Currie, Karthy Govender, Sandra Liebenberg, Marius Pieterse, Johan<br />

van der Walt, Cathi Albertyn, Beth Goldblatt, Henk Botha and Danie<br />

Brand.


24 Chapter 1<br />

Three institutions and three persons deserve to be singled out.<br />

Without the Centre for Human Rights, the Constitutional Law of<br />

South Africa (CLoSA) Public Lectures Series would not have taken<br />

place. It took the prescience and the sustained commitment of the<br />

Centre’s former Director, now Dean of the University of Pretoria’s<br />

Faculty of Law, Professor Christof Heyns, to make CLoSA, the<br />

conference and <strong>this</strong> work possible.<br />

Without the Pretoria University Law Press, its production<br />

manager, Lizette Besaans and its graphic designer Yolanda Booyzen,<br />

<strong>this</strong> book would never have had its spine cracked.<br />

Finally, allow us to again thank Theunis Roux and the South<br />

African Institute for Advanced Constitutional Public, Human Rights<br />

and International Law (SAIFAC). As a co-editor of CLoSA, as a cosponsor<br />

of the CLoSA conference, and as a co-author of <strong>this</strong> work,<br />

Theunis has been our tipping point. Without him, something might<br />

have happened on all three fronts — eventually. But nothing truly<br />

great would have come of any of these endeavours. Words cannot<br />

express the debt that we owe him.


2<br />

THE<br />

SOUTH AFRICAN<br />

CONSTITUTION AS THE<br />

LAST GREAT<br />

MODERNIST PROJECT<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

1 On the role of the legal academy<br />

Several years ago, at my alma mater, Columbia Law School, I had the<br />

honour of introducing Justice Albie Sachs to a packed audience eager<br />

to hear what he had to say about the Court’s then recent judgment in<br />

Grootboom. 1 After the talk, as the Justice, his host Jack Greenberg<br />

and I stood about chatting, the Justice — nodding in my direction —<br />

remarked that ‘they (legal academics) played an important role<br />

during the transition.’ 2<br />

Perhaps only another son of South Africa, Roger Federer, could<br />

have delivered a backhand so adroitly. The Justice’s intimation — and<br />

the challenging question embedded in it — was clear. While legal<br />

academics had occupied a critical position during those heady days of<br />

South Africa’s velvet revolution, now that all of the country’s political<br />

institutions — and especially the Court — were up and running, our<br />

role, as legal academics, was much harder to divine.<br />

1<br />

Grootboom & Others v Government of the Republic of South Africa & Others 2001<br />

1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC).<br />

2 It may seem a bit churlish to ask how Justice Sachs’ bon mot could function as a<br />

gentle provocation to South African academics while I was teaching at Columbia,<br />

convalescing from a long-term illness and having a quiet conversation with just<br />

Professor Jack Greenberg and Justice Sachs at Columbia Law School. See A Sachs<br />

‘A gentle provocation: A reply to Stu Woolman’ Constitutional conversations<br />

(2008) Chapter 3.<br />

25


26 Chapter 2<br />

There is, of course, more than a measure of truth to the notion<br />

that legal academics — like all academics — are handmaidens to the<br />

institutions and phenomena about which they write. But that does not<br />

make us epiphenomenal.<br />

What is our ‘phenomenological’ status, our role? What do we do<br />

exactly? Well, we fix things. Indeed, I tend to see my job as that of a<br />

mechanic — someone who pays attention to what is being written,<br />

identifies a problem and offers a solution. Perhaps, the analogy to a<br />

therapist is more apt, since what we really do is listen closely and<br />

reflect back to those who make our laws what we hear them saying:<br />

We have no power, in fact, to intervene. Only lawmakers have the<br />

ability to correct their mistakes. But even the tags of mechanic or<br />

therapist are insufficient to the task of describing the role we play:<br />

Sometimes we are architects. Courts, faced with the pressures of<br />

deciding the cases and doing justice to the persons before them, hope<br />

primarily to get ‘it’ — the judgment — right. And that is as it should<br />

be. Academics, however, do not face such constraints.<br />

In my academic guild of constitutional law-masons, we take the<br />

text of the Constitution, the reasoning of cases, the political<br />

institutions that govern us and a whole range of other quotidian<br />

academic considerations — like logic and research — quite seriously.<br />

We know that the correct reading of a founding provision may turn on<br />

the placement of a comma — and that a bad outcome may flow from<br />

an errant reading of a preposition. 3 Our aim is to produce work that<br />

makes sense of the system of constitutional law within which we<br />

operate and, should we have any talent, to make a modest<br />

contribution towards making that system both more coherent and<br />

more just. Moreover, we do not merely dabble in theory — we create<br />

it. Our work in theory offers good faith reconstructions of our courts’<br />

jurisprudence (providing doctrines where none exist), critiques of<br />

that jurisprudence (where warranted), and preferred readings of the<br />

cases and the text (if necessary).<br />

Our theoretical work begins with the close reading of texts and<br />

then draws down upon and engages those academics who have<br />

previously attempted to make sense of our system of law, systems of<br />

law in other constitutional democracies, and systems of law<br />

generally. This theoretical engagement necessarily takes us beyond<br />

3<br />

On the importance of a comma for understanding the meaning of ‘democracy’ in<br />

our Constitution, see T Roux ‘Democracy’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional<br />

Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 10, available at<br />

www.westlaw.com. For a poorly reasoned decision that founders on the shoals of<br />

an incorrect gloss on the word ‘in’, see Kaunda & Others v President of the<br />

Republic of South Africa 2005 4 SA 235 (CC), 2004 10 BCLR 1009 (CC). For a<br />

critique of <strong>this</strong> errant reading, see S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al<br />

(eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 31.


Stu Woolman 27<br />

the law — to the fields that immediately abut our own: philosophy,<br />

political science, history, literature, sociology, economics, psychology;<br />

and, sometimes, in disciplines as far a field as cognitive<br />

science, artificial intelligence and information studies. But even when<br />

we move away from the law, we never for a moment deny the law its<br />

autonomy. For even if the law can sometimes seem like the most<br />

derivative of academic disciplines, the discipline still demands that<br />

we treat its texts with respect. And such respect begins with the<br />

recognition that legal texts possess a logic and a power of their own.<br />

Indeed, a failure to recognise law’s autonomy risks trivialising the<br />

laws that govern us and the concerns of those governed by our law.<br />

Our mission then is to step back and suggest how a body of law<br />

hangs together — or if it does not cohere, then to explain why it falls<br />

apart. In both instances — the good faith reconstruction, on the one<br />

hand, or the preferred reading, on the other — we offer judges and<br />

lawyers the intellectual scaffolding upon which to build a better — a<br />

more just — legal system.<br />

These roles — of mechanic, of therapist, of architect, of mason,<br />

of critic — are those that legal academics occupy in the real world: if<br />

we do our job well. But we, as writers, also belong to an ideal<br />

community. When we write, we address ourselves to <strong>this</strong> ideal<br />

community.<br />

The notion of an ideal community throws up a number of<br />

questions. Who constitutes such a community? Who is in — and who is<br />

out? Does such a community really exist? Or, is it a fantasy? And if it<br />

is just a fantasy, and not the real thing, are there conditions peculiar<br />

to South Africa that block the formation of such an ideal community?<br />

2 The ideal community of interlocutors<br />

In our ideal community — of which you, the reader, are a part — we<br />

constitutional law academics address our Constitutional Court of 11<br />

women and men; and not just <strong>this</strong> Court, but every court; and not just<br />

the judges on the bench, but the advocates and the lawyers who<br />

appear before them; and not just these practitioners, but the future<br />

judges, legislators and lawyers who sit in our classrooms and who will<br />

someday read what we write today.<br />

Academic discourse can, of course, be quite direct. I have penned<br />

any number of pointed replies. But even when we address our fellow<br />

academics directly, we are looking over their shoulders at a<br />

community of interlocutors that has yet to take shape. We are always<br />

oriented toward a future listener, toward a community unusually<br />

expansive and porous, the kind of ‘true democracy’ of which Whitman


28 Chapter 2<br />

famously wrote: ‘I am large. I contain multitudes.’ The ‘large’,<br />

capacious book upon which <strong>this</strong> collection is based — Constitutional<br />

Law of South Africa — is one of many collective efforts to will such an<br />

ideal democratic community into being.<br />

Let me say a few more words about the community I imagine<br />

before me. Constitutional Law of South Africa — the work out of<br />

which <strong>this</strong> collection flows — is an act of collective responsibility. The<br />

book has some 57 authors who represent nine domestic law schools,<br />

six foreign law schools, five NGO’s, six law firms and legal<br />

consultancies, and half a dozen members of the bar and bench. But if<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa is an act of collective<br />

responsibility, then what, you may ask, is it an act of collective<br />

responsibility for? Our collective responsibility is to get things right.<br />

To get as close to ‘the truth’ as possible.<br />

Ours is, however, also a fractious community — and as I shall<br />

discuss in the concluding section, the invocation of ‘the truth’ elicits<br />

catcalls and wolf-whistles from some members of the academy. Even<br />

at the outset, it seems clear that my vision of an ideal community of<br />

interlocutors has its detractors — from within.<br />

In <strong>this</strong> section, I want to concentrate on what I think may be some<br />

of the barriers to the formation of an ideal community of interlocutors<br />

in South Africa. The first barrier is that of not being read, not reading,<br />

and therefore blocking the primary condition for an ideal community<br />

of interlocutors: conversation.<br />

My sense of <strong>this</strong> problem flows from two sources — the academic<br />

journals and the judgments of our courts. Our journals reflect a<br />

penchant for publishing mere restatements of the law and the all too<br />

common they-do, we-do piece of comparative jurisprudence. Even<br />

worse, from my limited vantage point, is the failure of scholars to<br />

engage with what other scholars have written — as if they were the<br />

first persons to ‘discover’ a body of law in Africa.<br />

This lack of engagement is, I am afraid, replicated on our bench.<br />

But perhaps the sources of the problem still lies not in the bench.<br />

Perhaps we, in the academy, are not producing what the courts need<br />

or want and thus not carrying our share of the conversation. Or<br />

perhaps we are not producing enough of it and the general quality is<br />

so low as to not be worth remarking upon. Needless to say, I share<br />

some of these concerns.<br />

However, I have read enough cases, and know enough about the<br />

inner workings of our highest Court, to think that the problem might<br />

lie, in part, elsewhere. My well-informed hunch is that the Court does


Stu Woolman 29<br />

not really read what we write. 4 That might explain the following<br />

scenario. The UDM Court expressly notes that no academic has<br />

answered the question: What kind of democracy does the Final<br />

Constitution demand? 5 Theunis Roux set himself the task of answering<br />

— in the most sophisticated and compelling manner possible — that<br />

very question. He succeeded. 6 And yet his efforts have gone<br />

unnoticed — or unremarked upon by the bench. Or take New Clicks. 7<br />

In all of New Clicks’ 850 page glory, the judgments, collectively, take<br />

unbelievably limited stock of academic interventions that engage the<br />

gravamen of the complaint. If there is one thing South African legal<br />

academia can boast, it is that it possesses some first rate, world class<br />

administrative law scholars: Cora Hoexter, Hugh Corder, Iain Currie,<br />

Danie Brand, Jonathan Klaaren and Jacque de Ville — amongst others.<br />

Their reward is what one might charitably describe as a footnote<br />

dump (citing all of the texts one might care to consult without remark<br />

or engagement in a single footnote). These cases are not aberrations.<br />

If one takes the Constitutional Court cases of 2007 as an example,<br />

then one confronts a paucity of references to works that I know to be<br />

germane to the issues raised in these matters. 8<br />

Another — alternative or supplementary — explanation is that<br />

many Justices do not think that members of the academy ought to be<br />

criticising the bench. That deeply embedded sense of hierarchy is an<br />

4<br />

Justice Sachs claims, without merit, that nothing was written about the First<br />

Certification Judgment. However, each year, I use Matthew Chaskalson and<br />

Dennis Davis’ trenchant analysis of the decision in order to teach my students<br />

about the inextricable link between law and politics. See M Chaskalson & D Davis<br />

‘Constitutionalism, the Rule of Law and the First Certification Judgment’ (1997)<br />

13 South African Journal on Human Rights 430. While the First Certification<br />

Judgment Court strives mightily to maintain the artificial distinction between law<br />

and politics, Chaskalson & Davis demonstrate how a very specific view of<br />

constitutional politics drives the refusal to certify the text.<br />

5 United Democratic Movement v President of the Republic of South Africa &<br />

Others (African Christian Democratic Party & Others Intervening; Institute for<br />

Democracy in South Africa & Another as Amici Curiae) (No 2) 2003 1 SA 495 (CC),<br />

2002 11 BCLR 1179 (CC).<br />

6 T Roux ‘Democracy’ in Woolman et al (n 3 above) Chapter 10.<br />

7<br />

Minister of Health & Another v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd & Others 2006 2<br />

SA 311 (CC), 2006 1 BCLR 1 (CC).<br />

8 Of the 23 number of judgment handed down from January 2007 through October<br />

2007: seven judgments cite no academic literature at all; three judgments cite<br />

one academic piece; of the remaining 13 judgments, the results are variable. The<br />

Constitutional Court hits a highwater mark in Sidumo of 19 citations. Sidumo &<br />

Another v Rustenburg Platinum Mines Ltd & Others 2008 2 BCLR 158 (CC).<br />

Sidumo, however, had four discrete opinions (and the majority of citations, as<br />

usual, came in the dissenting judgments). The remaining 12 judgments contained<br />

a total of 84 academic citations. As Ronald Reagan noted ‘Facts are stupid<br />

things’, and a mere summing up of totals does not tell us much about the<br />

literature cited. Three characteristics jump out at <strong>this</strong> reader: (1) high numbers<br />

of academic citations appear only in multiple opinion judgments; (2) many of the<br />

authorities cited are foreign academic authorities; (3) the number of citations to<br />

actual constitutional texts (articles or books) — as opposed to texts (articles or<br />

books) that deal with some specialised branch of the law such as contracts,<br />

delict, court practice or labour law — is extremely small.


30 Chapter 2<br />

anachronism — an English inheritance that we would do well to<br />

abandon. No one likes to be criticised. But silence hardly promotes<br />

the robust, vibrant and reasoned discourse that the Court ought to be<br />

modelling — especially in a country with a very short history of truly<br />

open, no-holds-barred debate, one-party rule, a relatively weak<br />

media and a thin civil society.<br />

And yet, despite <strong>this</strong> silence, or rather the lack of written<br />

engagement, the Justices of our Constitutional Court are anything but<br />

aloof. The Justices regularly attend conferences that raise knotty<br />

questions of doctrine, present papers about both pressing<br />

constitutional issues and more general theoretical concerns and<br />

appear at book launches of works critical of their endeavours. It is<br />

hard to imagine a group of Justices more engaged personally and<br />

professionally with the academic community, and the broader South<br />

African society of which it is a critical part. Having recognised its<br />

primary role as that of deepening constitutional democracy and<br />

entrenching the rule of law, the Court has, thankfully, not been afraid<br />

to roll up its sleeves and get its hands dirty. This very work contains<br />

the responses of four Constitutional Court judges engaging the<br />

concerns of colleagues in the ivory tower. And, I think, they engage<br />

us because their concerns are our concerns.<br />

How does one reconcile these two different modes of<br />

engagement? Perhaps the Constitutional Court, like so many other<br />

courts of its kind, is more concerned with the legitimation of its own<br />

authority — through its judgments — than sparring with academics<br />

who take a different line on the matter at hand (and who, by taking<br />

a different line, necessarily call the Court’s authority into question.)<br />

And perhaps it is enough that our Justices participate in talks, book<br />

launches and conferences — here and abroad — in a manner that<br />

clearly suggests that ‘justice’ is not delivered by immortals from on<br />

high, but by men and women just like you and I. 9<br />

9<br />

I must admit, however, that I am not entirely convinced by <strong>this</strong> line of argument.<br />

That the problem may be one of authority often happens as judgments circulate<br />

chambers. The academic arguments that buttress the Court’s opinion or the<br />

opinion of a particular justice are circulated in memoranda that develop over<br />

time into the final judgment. By the time the Court and its members have staked<br />

out their various positions and arrived at their various conclusions, the<br />

sophisticated engagement with academic interventions is no longer necessary.<br />

And that engagement often winds up on the cutting room floor. Again, <strong>this</strong><br />

eventuality is, perhaps, not surprising. Academic pieces are written within a vast,<br />

open space. Legal judgments must, to some degree, close down that space to<br />

arrive at a conclusion that ‘coheres’ with its other statements of law and does not<br />

speculate open how all reasonably similar or related disputes might operate. John<br />

Rawls could call his magnum opus A theory of justice (1973). The Court must<br />

deliver the only recognised just and legitimate outcome. That, however, is no<br />

excuse for a failure to recognise the sources from which the Court draws its<br />

conclusions, and for the failure to mark off the space for arguments that support<br />

its conclusions from those that do not.


Stu Woolman 31<br />

3 The South African constitution as the last great<br />

modernist project<br />

Talk of ‘truth’ with a capital T is rather unfashionable in some<br />

quarters these days. Fortunately, such a philosophical fashion has not<br />

yet taken root here: South Africa remains, to my mind, the last great<br />

modernist project. Our Final Constitution is certainly written as if it<br />

is such. It commits us to great ideals and the material transformation<br />

of the lives of those who cannot yet enter the public square without<br />

still experiencing shame. There is simply too much truth yet to be<br />

told. Part of our collective responsibility — for those of us who write<br />

for <strong>this</strong> collection, for Constitutional Law of South Africa and for<br />

other scholarly outlets — is to put our basic law on as solid a footing<br />

as possible, so that other members of the legal fraternity may do what<br />

they need to do to realise the great ends of <strong>this</strong> modernist project.<br />

How should academics do <strong>this</strong>? We must do exactly what I suggest<br />

that the Constitutional Court must do: Model rational political<br />

discourse. The law does not simply secure its authority by arriving at<br />

the right answers. It secures its authority by getting there the right<br />

way. If those who make the law refuse to say what they mean — or<br />

mean what they say — then it falls to the rest of us to try to offer a<br />

good faith reconstruction of their meaning. And when that good faith<br />

reconstruction fails to cohere with the basic dictates of logic, reason<br />

or justice, then it falls to us to say so.<br />

This collection of colloquies — and the book upon which those<br />

colloquies are based, Constitutional Law of South Africa — offers a<br />

fine example of what I mean when I talk about modelling rational<br />

discourse. Frank Michelman has written the definitive restatement<br />

and critique of our Rule of Law doctrine. 10 He has done what no court<br />

of 11 women and men — who must often compromise on their<br />

conclusions — could do. He has put the Court’s jurisprudence on a<br />

more solid footing — and we are all the better for it. Justice O’Regan,<br />

both as an architect of that jurisprudence and a former member of<br />

the academy, honours us by responding to Professor Michelman’s good<br />

faith reconstruction and, in so doing, gets us all a little closer to the<br />

truth. Indeed, the same can be said about <strong>this</strong> collection’s exchanges<br />

on democracy, application, limitation, dignity, equality and socioeconomic<br />

rights.<br />

There are those who question whether we can make such claims<br />

regarding truth or justice. They claim — not without reason — that law<br />

as it is currently practised — by lawyers and legal academics such as<br />

10<br />

F Michelman ‘The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the constitution’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (n 3 above) Chapter 11.


32 Chapter 2<br />

myself — fails to take crisis as its departure point, and thus fails to<br />

take the needs and the concerns of those it serves seriously. 11 They<br />

argue that the law is willing to sacrifice those persons most in need of<br />

its protection and then allege, with some merit, that the law does so<br />

in the name, but not necessarily the service, of a just and fair social<br />

order. These charges are serious indeed. Professor Johan van der Walt<br />

has recently devoted an entire book to elucidating these theses. 12<br />

And when he writes that law constitutes ‘the sacrificial selfdestruction<br />

of hospitality, the self-destruction that takes place with<br />

every attempt to give effect to hospitality,’ it is hard not to concede<br />

that even when we take the moral salience of every action — be it<br />

public or private — into account, that all law and all human action<br />

involves some form of sacrifice. In Van der Walt’s words:<br />

[T]he horizontalising demand for justification will require agents of<br />

disempowerment to provide concrete information as to why the<br />

particular form of disempowerment cannot or could not be avoided. This<br />

information will not, of course, level the playing field, or it will only<br />

level it on a symbolic level. However, the consistent demand for<br />

information that justifies the curtailment of fundamental rights will<br />

serve consistently to destabilise the position of anyone implicated in<br />

such curtailments. Constant exposure to public scrutiny will leave their<br />

positions less entrenched then they would have been were they able to<br />

rely on privileges and immunities. 13<br />

Those of us who work in the guild of constitutional law-masons —<br />

whether academics, jurists, practitioners and students — cannot for a<br />

moment sit idly back and assume that the Constitution and all our<br />

lovely political institutions provide an answer for the depredations of<br />

apartheid or the desolations of our current political order. Van der<br />

Walt is correct in noting that the Constitution is but a way station, a<br />

stop on a never-ending journey towards a more just political order.<br />

The virtue of such work as his is to wipe any smugness off the face of<br />

those of us who work within <strong>this</strong> constitutional order and think that<br />

such work is enough to set things right in a country where some 50 per<br />

cent of us — at one time or another — experience hunger and<br />

homelessness. Every act in every day South African life, Van der Walt<br />

reminds us, possesses an unavoidable moral salience. Or rather, we<br />

avoid that moral salience — and the sacrifices those acts entail — at<br />

the peril of our ‘souls’.<br />

11 See T Madlingozi ‘Legal academics and progressive politics in South Africa: Moving<br />

beyond the Ivory Tower’ (2006) 2 <strong>PULP</strong> Fictions: A Space for Dialogue 5. But see A<br />

Kok ‘A Reply to Tshepo Madlingozi’ (2006) 2 <strong>PULP</strong> Fictions: A Space for Dialogue<br />

25.<br />

12<br />

See J van der Walt Law and sacrifice (2006).<br />

13 n 10 above, 73.


Stu Woolman 33<br />

Van der Walt’s observations are not new. After the Holocaust,<br />

Stalin’s purges and the dropping of atomic bombs on Hiroshima and<br />

Nagasaki, and after the victory of Allied forces and the creation of the<br />

various international institutions founded at Bretton Woods, members<br />

of the Frankfurt School articulated a trenchant critique of modernity<br />

that remains difficult to admit in full, but equally impossible to reject<br />

out of hand: That liberation and domination in the modern democratic<br />

constitutional state are flip-sides of the same coin. That is, the<br />

liberation from one form of political economy, that of monarchy and<br />

mercantilism, invites new forms of domination that flow from<br />

another, that of the bureaucratic, democratic capitalist state. Adorno<br />

puts <strong>this</strong> basic thesis as follows:<br />

The dual nature of progress, which always developed the potential of<br />

freedom simultaneously with the reality of oppression, gave rise to a<br />

situation in which peoples were more and more inducted into the control<br />

of nature and social organisation, but grew at the same time, owing to<br />

the compulsion which culture placed upon them, incapable of<br />

understanding in what way culture went beyond such integration. ...<br />

They make common cause with the world against themselves, and the<br />

most alienated condition of all, the omnipresence of commodities, their<br />

own conversion into appendages of machinery, is for them a mirage of<br />

closeness. ... The concept of dynamism ... is raised to an absolute,<br />

whereas it ought, as an anthropological reflex of the laws of production,<br />

to be itself critically confronted, in an emancipated society, with need.<br />

The conception of unfettered activity, of uninterrupted procreation, of<br />

chubby insatiability, of freedom of frantic bustle, feeds on the bourgeois<br />

concept of nature that has always served solely to proclaim social<br />

violence as unchangeable. ... It was in <strong>this</strong>, and not in their alleged<br />

levelling down, that the positive blue-prints of socialism ... were rooted<br />

in barbarism. It is not man’s lapse into luxurious indolence that is to be<br />

feared, but the savage spread of the social under the mask of universal<br />

nature, the collective as a blind fury of activity. The naïve supposition of<br />

an unambiguous development towards increased production is itself of a<br />

piece of that bourgeois outlook which permits development in only one<br />

direction because, integrated into a totality, dominated by quantification,<br />

it is hostile to qualitative difference. If we imagine emancipated<br />

society as emancipation from precisely such totality, then vanishing lines<br />

come into view that have little in common with increased production<br />

and its human reflections. 14<br />

14<br />

T Adorno Minima moralia: Reflections from damaged life trans EFN Jephcott<br />

(1951) 146–156. Horkheimer describes the French Revolution as a ‘condensed<br />

version of later history’ and in words even more prescient for the common era<br />

writes:<br />

More and more, economic questions are becoming technical ones. The<br />

privileged position of administrative officers and technical and planning<br />

engineers will lose its rational basis in the future; naked power is<br />

becoming its only justification. The awareness that the rationality of<br />

domination is already in decline when the authoritarian state takes over<br />

society is the real basis for its identity with terrorism.


34 Chapter 2<br />

I do not think it surprising then that those persons who helped to<br />

bring about the end of apartheid — almost half a century after the<br />

world had declared itself rid of Nazi Germany — would imbue their<br />

founding document with a bit of grim realism about the emancipatory<br />

powers of the post-apartheid state. We find in FC section 12 a<br />

preoccupation with the worst forms of abuse that the state — and<br />

modern society — can visit upon the individual. FC section 12 reminds<br />

us that the post-apartheid state retains the power to put people in<br />

prison without reason and without end, and that ours remains a<br />

society in which bodies are raped, tortured and otherwise exploited.<br />

Take FC section 12(1)(b) — the right not to be detained without trial.<br />

All of the original interpreters of our basic law understood that FC<br />

section 12(1)(b) was designed to remind us of apartheid’s many<br />

depredations. As Ackermann J writes in De Lange:<br />

When viewed against its historical background, the first and most<br />

egregious form of deprivation of physical liberty which springs to mind<br />

when considering the construction of the expression ‘detained without<br />

trial’ in s 12(1)(b) is the notorious administrative detention without trial<br />

for purposes of political control. This took place during the previous<br />

constitutional dispensation under various statutory provisions which<br />

were effectively insulated against meaningful judicial control. Effective<br />

judicial control was excluded prior to the commencement of the detention<br />

and throughout its duration. During such detention, and facilitated<br />

by <strong>this</strong> exclusion of judicial control, the grossest violations of the life<br />

and the bodily, mental and spiritual integrity of detainees occurred. This<br />

manifestation of detention without trial was a virtual negation of the<br />

rule of law and had serious negative consequences for the credibility and<br />

status of the judiciary in <strong>this</strong> country. 15<br />

14<br />

15<br />

15<br />

M Horkheimer ‘The authoritarian state’ in A Arato & E Gebhardt (eds) The<br />

essential Frankfurt School reader (1982) 95 105. Perhaps no better explanation<br />

exists for the current existential and political crisis in the West and in the Middle<br />

East. More However, and more, as pessimistic economic as questions both Adorno are becoming and Horkheimer technical are ones. about Thethe<br />

human privileged condition, position they of were administrative by no means officers fatalists. and technical Both imagined and planning that neo-<br />

Marxist engineers dialectic will — as lose opposed its rational to liberal basis enlightenment in the future; conceptions naked power of development<br />

becoming and progress its only — might justification. strengthen The ‘freedom’ awareness and that bring the about rationality the end of of<br />

is<br />

exploitation. domination See is T already Adorno & in M decline Horkheimer when Dialectic the authoritarian of enlightenment state takes (1972). over<br />

De Lange society v Smuts is the NO real & basis Others for 1998 its identity 3 SA 785 with (CC), terrorism. 1998 7 BCLR 779 (CC) para 26.<br />

Sachs J sounds similar concerns when he writes that in terms of the<br />

M Horkheimer ‘The authoritarian state’ in A Arato & E Gebhardt (eds) The<br />

essential Interim Frankfurt Constitution School ... reader the words (1982) ‘detention 95 105. without Perhaps trial’ no better stood explanation<br />

alone as<br />

exists an for express the current bar to existential physical restraint and political by the crisis State in the and West accordingly and the had Middle to<br />

East. function However, as the as pessimistic sole textual as basis both for Adorno analysing and the Horkheimer constitutionality are about of allthe<br />

human forms condition, of coercive they State were power by no involving means fatalists. physical restraint. Both imagined Now it that is just neo-<br />

Marxist one dialectic item in an — as extensive opposed and to nuanced liberal enlightenment catalogue, and conceptions therefore needs of development<br />

be and given progress a specific — might significance strengthen which ‘freedom’ both justifies and bring its place about in the the end list of<br />

to<br />

exploitation. and separates See T Adorno it from & M the Horkheimer other items. Dialectic It accordingly of enlightenment reclaims (1972). its<br />

commonly accepted identity in South Africa as relating to a specific and<br />

De Lange unmistakable v Smuts NO prohibition & Others of 1998 the 3 special SA 785 and (CC), intense 1998 form 7 BCLR of 779 deprivation (CC) para of26.<br />

Sachs liberty J sounds that similar scarred concerns our recent when history. he writes that in terms of the<br />

n 10 above, Interim para Constitution 173. ... the words ‘detention without trial’ stood alone as


Stu Woolman 35<br />

Many, but by no means all, of our Constitutional Court justices<br />

understand that various commonplace acts of barbarism under<br />

apartheid will find renewed expression in our post-apartheid state,<br />

and that genuine emancipation requires constant vigilance against<br />

new forms of domination. I would suggest that a majority of the De<br />

Lange Court recognised that permitting presiding officers (who were<br />

neither magistrates nor judges) to imprison, indefinitely and<br />

repeatedly, recalcitrant witnesses in insolvency proceedings was of a<br />

piece with the apartheid practice of detention without trial, and that<br />

<strong>this</strong> identification of a ‘new’ form of exploitation underwrites the<br />

Court’s finding that <strong>this</strong> particular statutory grant of power to punish<br />

is unconstitutional.<br />

Ackermann J’s words may seem rather tepid compared to<br />

Adorno’s largely nihilistic critique of modernity. And that is not just<br />

because judges are not philosophers. The Frankfurt School’s post-<br />

Marxist dismissal of the Enlightenment’s commitment to truth is not,<br />

as I noted at the outset of <strong>this</strong> section, a philosophical fashion that<br />

has taken root here. South Africa remains the last great modernist<br />

project. FC section 12 will not, therefore, be read as a double-edged<br />

sword by our courts. It will be read instead as a reminder that<br />

exploitation remains a dominant, if not ineradicable feature of our<br />

landscape, and that it falls to our politicians, judges, lawyers and<br />

various organs of civil society to ensure that the great emancipatory<br />

ends of our modernist project are not undermined by new forms of<br />

exploitation. Academics — whether modernist or post-modernist in<br />

inclination — have an important role to play in <strong>this</strong> great<br />

emancipatory project: speaking truth to power, even when that<br />

power is exercised by the virtuous women and men who sit on our<br />

highest Court.<br />

4 Conclusion<br />

Have we academics, as I write here seven years after the Grootboom<br />

lecture, answered Justice Sach’s crisply struck backhand? In my mind,<br />

I see us, collectively stretched, answering with a forehand volley to a<br />

momentarily empty space. I see the Justice giving chase.


3 Reply<br />

A gentle provocation: A reply to Stu Woolman<br />

Justice Albie Sachs<br />

Actually, Stu Woolman, it wasn’t a deft backhander. Even when I still<br />

had my right arm and could play a reasonable game of ping-pong, my<br />

backhand was only average. No, it was more of a carefully calculated<br />

drop-shot; what I recall saying to you was meant as a gentle<br />

provocation.<br />

I felt that in the run-up to the creation of our constitutional<br />

democracy, academics had been far ahead of judges in preparing for<br />

the conceptual transformations that lay ahead. There was a heady<br />

and inspiring surge of legal energy in academe. Top minds were<br />

actively and directly engaged in the constitution-making process. Law<br />

faculties put on workshops and educational programmes to get the<br />

profession and the country ready for immense jurisprudential change.<br />

Etienne Mureinik recorded his marvellous turn of phrase about the<br />

Constitution being a bridge from a culture of authority to a culture of<br />

justification. I still recall how Canadian law professor David Beatty<br />

put the concept of proportionality right there on the map, telling us<br />

in effect: It’s proportionality, stupid. And simultaneously Thandabantu<br />

Nhlapho was preparing us for the era when customary African<br />

law would both gain greater legitimacy and yet achieve far more<br />

forward thrust.<br />

The judges, on the other hand, seemed to be to be frozen in<br />

positivistic time. Some were downright sullen. A fine incumbent of<br />

the newly-renamed Supreme Court of Appeal, whom I remembered<br />

37


38 Chapter 3<br />

fondly as an enlightened colleague at the Cape Town Bar, clearly<br />

believed until his retirement that, freed of apartheid deformation,<br />

the common law did everything that the Constitution purported to do,<br />

only in a more measured and legally appropriate way. And what a<br />

furore arose when the UCT Law Faculty invited Cape judges (as nonpaying<br />

participants!) to join members of the legal profession at a<br />

workshop on the new Constitution. What could academics teach the<br />

judiciary, when, after all, judges declared the law, while academics<br />

only analysed what the judges said? A small minority, headed by<br />

Judge-President Gerald Friedman wanted to go, and the compromise<br />

was that they could attend, but only on condition they didn’t ask<br />

questions or take part in discussion. My informant told me that the<br />

first hand that went up at the workshop was that of Gerald Friedman!<br />

When I had been in practice at the Cape Bar thirty years earlier,<br />

it had been axiomatic that dead authors could be quoted, but live<br />

ones only if they had been ‘elevated to the Bench’. The most we could<br />

do with South African writers was to quote from authoritative<br />

textbooks; indeed we never went to court without Gardiner and<br />

Landsdown on Criminal Law, and Herbstein and Van Winsen on Civil<br />

Procedure. Yet the understanding was that these treatises did no<br />

more than systematise what the cases had decided. There was no<br />

question of the authors engaging with the decisions and offering their<br />

own opinions. And if we even thought of reading journal articles, we<br />

never imagined citing them in argument. Heaven forbid. Why, then,<br />

was the dominant legal tradition in South Africa so rigidly hierarchical<br />

in respect of the relation between judges and academics?<br />

When working on my PhD at Sussex University I came across some<br />

clues. I discovered writings by Max Weber on why Roman Law was not<br />

received in England as it was in the rest of Europe. I later summarised<br />

what he had said as follows:<br />

[O]ne is forced to ask why a certain intellectual style developed amongst<br />

lawyers in England, as opposed, say, to those in continental Europe. Max<br />

Weber has suggested that the answer lies in the success of the English<br />

legal profession in keeping legal education under its control and out of<br />

the hands of the Universities. Rather than regarding native genius as an<br />

explanation of the character of legal reasoning, he sees the legal<br />

profession as the creator of the concept of native genius, which it used<br />

as a weapon in defence of its group interest. Thus it was in the interests<br />

of the legal profession to assert the superiority of their indigenous<br />

practical wisdom over the imported speculations of the University<br />

professors, and <strong>this</strong> led to a continuing emphasis on the virtues of the<br />

English case-law.<br />

I added that the profession had been so successful in <strong>this</strong> respect that<br />

not only did it continue to control the qualifications for legal practice,


Reply - Justice Albie Sachs 39<br />

but had even succeeded in getting the Universities, which they<br />

treated as subalterns, to extol its timeless virtues.<br />

Then much later when I myself had been ‘elevated’ from being<br />

professor to the Bench, I came across an address in which US Supreme<br />

Court Justice William Brennan provided further illumination.<br />

Criticising what he saw as the deadening role of the desiccated,<br />

precedent-based legal text-book, he explained, in an address entitled<br />

Reason, passion and ‘The progress of the law’, that the judicial<br />

branch in his country had been born not on the lofty peaks of pure<br />

reason, but in the trenches of partisan politics. 1 In response, two<br />

important checks on judicial discretion had been institutionalised —<br />

the recording of precedent, and the requirement of a public and<br />

reasoned explanation of the judicial result. The outcome was an<br />

endless string of cites of precedent that began to dominate judicial<br />

opinions.<br />

The effect of <strong>this</strong> practice was to distance the judge from the<br />

outcome of the case: It appeared that precedent alone determined<br />

each outcome. Brennan observed that the rise of the legal treatise,<br />

with its strangely disembodied character, intensified <strong>this</strong> distancing<br />

process:<br />

The goal of the treatise — to classify reported cases into objective and<br />

determinative categories of legal principle — appealed to the positivist<br />

minds of the late-nineteenth century. As one historian had put it:<br />

The legal treatise was regarded by its admirers as above all<br />

demonstrating the ‘scientific’ nature of the law. Through classification<br />

of subjects, it sought to show that law proceeds not from will but from<br />

reason. Through its ‘black letter’ presentation of supposed ‘general<br />

principles’ of law it sought to suppress all controversy over policy while<br />

promoting the comforting ideal of a logical, symmetrical and, most<br />

importantly, inexorable system of law.<br />

Conspicuously absent from the treatises was any narrative voice. The<br />

earliest treatises contain no commentary whatsoever, and even in later<br />

editions authors eschewed personal commentary on the cases and<br />

principles. The absence of commentary was consistent with, and no<br />

doubt helped to reinforce, the nineteenth-century conception of law as<br />

something that judges discovered but did not help define. 2<br />

Brennan added that we could now begin to understand why <strong>this</strong><br />

conception of judge-as-oracle arose, and why the legal community<br />

clung so tenaciously to it.<br />

1<br />

(1988) 10 Cardozo Law Review 3.<br />

2 As above.


40 Chapter 3<br />

This brings me to my next question: working with a pristine<br />

Constitution that represented a total rupture with the past, and with<br />

no local precedent to guide us, what materials could we as judges use<br />

to orient our decisions? If I look at my early judgments I can see that<br />

what I was seeking was not authoritative pronouncement. It was<br />

philosophy, a phrase, a persuasive argument. It was rationale. It was<br />

a formulation that added structure and texture to what Brennan<br />

refers to as ‘passion’, that is ‘the range of emotional and intuitive<br />

responses to a given set of facts or arguments, responses which often<br />

speed into our consciousness far ahead of the lumbering syllogisms of<br />

reason.’ Sometimes I wanted to store up ideas in the larder of whoknows-when-it-might-be-useful.<br />

But usually the spur to ‘scorn<br />

delights and spend laborious days’ came from the imperious need to<br />

find a persuasive answer to a case at hand. And frequently the words<br />

that said it best — and made me feel a little less intellectually lonely<br />

— were to be found in the imperious constitutional narrative of Tribe<br />

or the quieter recommendations of Hogg, or in the brilliant<br />

observations of Jackson or the poignant cadences of Brennan,<br />

Marshall and Blackmun in dissent.<br />

What we required at that stage was prescience rather than<br />

precedent. As judges it was our duty to raise our heads above the<br />

parapet of legal history. Academics had alerted us earlier to<br />

Canadian, German and Indian jurisprudence. What shots would they<br />

fire at our own jurisprudence? I could not wait. And it was my<br />

disappointment in <strong>this</strong> respect that led me to throw down a polite<br />

gauntlet to Stu Woolman.<br />

Granted, I might have suffered a little bit of pique from what<br />

Freud once referred to as the narcissism of small differences. Yet I am<br />

convinced that something more substantial was involved. My<br />

colleagues and I had laboured mightily to lay some foundations of a<br />

new constitutional jurisprudence. Laurie Ackermann was my neighbour<br />

in Chambers and his research and writing were prodigious. He<br />

scoured judicial reasoning throughout the world to find how courts in<br />

other open and democratic societies were dealing with the issues<br />

before us. Arthur Chaskalson, whose Chambers were nearby, would<br />

meet almost every evening with Laurie and the two would stand for<br />

an hour or more talking earnestly in the passage. Arthur’s judgments<br />

were wide-ranging and magisterial. Ismail Mahomed also did intense<br />

international research, managing to transmute the ideas he alighted<br />

upon into incandescent and unmistakably South African idiom. In a<br />

deeply thoughtful judgement on corporal punishment for juveniles,<br />

Pius Langa extracted telling observations from leading judicial minds<br />

in many jurisdictions.<br />

In the absence of South African precedent, then, our external<br />

points of reference were comparative constitutional jurisprudence.


Reply - Justice Albie Sachs 41<br />

We produced what I thought then, and still believe today, to be a<br />

number of judgments of profound legal significance. And after each<br />

one, academic reaction was virtually ... zero.<br />

Makwanyane, 3 the capital punishment case, the first we heard,<br />

was extensively analysed all over the world, except in one country,<br />

South Africa. I recall only one local law-journal article, by a good legal<br />

scholar, that barely engaged with the deep jurisprudential and moral<br />

issues debated in eleven separate judgments, and came to the banal<br />

conclusion that the decision merely reflected the socio-political<br />

outlooks of the judges. From a purely technical point of view,<br />

Mhlungu 4 was probably the most important case of that whole period.<br />

The Court divided sharply between those who supported a literalist<br />

approach to constitutional interpretation, and those who aligned<br />

themselves with a purposive one. Surely, I thought, there would be a<br />

deluge of academic articles in support of the purposive approach. Yet<br />

the only commentary I came across was a beautifully wrought piece<br />

supporting the literalist approach, followed by a highly amusing but<br />

totally obscure post-modern reply. So much for my hope expressed in<br />

Mhlungu, of ‘principled judicial dialogue, in the first place between<br />

members of <strong>this</strong> Court, then between our Court and other courts, the<br />

legal profession, law schools, Parliament, and, indirectly, with the<br />

public at large’! 5<br />

Then there was a truly landmark case of immense significance: In<br />

Executive Council of the Western Cape 6 we struck down two<br />

eminently progressive Presidential Proclamations on the basis that<br />

Parliament could not entrust its lawmaking authority to the President.<br />

I have spoken about <strong>this</strong> case in many parts of the world, putting it on<br />

a par with the election of 27 April 1994 as a moment when, because<br />

of the way in which Nelson Mandela emphasised his fidelity to the<br />

Constitution as interpreted by <strong>this</strong> Court, constitutional democracy<br />

became deeply rooted in our country. I recall reading a note on the<br />

case some time afterwards, but nowhere did I come across any<br />

attempt to assess its grand reach. I could go on. The First<br />

Certification Judgment 7 was nothing less than a judicial encyclopaedia<br />

of contemporary constitutionalism: It passed virtually<br />

unnoticed by academia. The dis-juncture was so strong it was as if it<br />

was now academia’s moment to be frozen in time.<br />

3<br />

S v Makwanyane & Another 1995 3 SA 391 (CC), 1995 6 BCLR 665 (CC).<br />

4 S v Mhlungu 1995 3 SA 867 (CC), 1995 7 BCLR 793 (CC).<br />

5 n 4 above, para 129.<br />

6<br />

Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislation & Others v President of the<br />

RSA & Others 1995 4 SA 877 (CC), 1995 10 BCLR 1289 (CC).<br />

7 Ex Parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly In Re: Certification of the<br />

Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 4 SA 744 (CC), 1996 10<br />

BCLR 1253 (CC).


42 Chapter 3<br />

The one spark of academic excitement was over the question of<br />

vertical versus horizontal application of the Constitution. It was an<br />

issue of some interest to me, because I think I was the one who put it<br />

on the South African agenda when I returned from exile in 1990. Yet<br />

from a practical point of view it had been rendered largely moot by<br />

the constitutional requirements that all statutes had to be<br />

interpreted, and the common law developed, in keeping with the<br />

spirit of the Constitution, and the express authorisation of legislation<br />

to deal with the effects of past discrimination. Yet here academics<br />

went to town, picking up on what was a real and live debate between<br />

conservative and progressive commentators positions in the USA, but<br />

of little relevance in South Africa. 8<br />

It was only in the Sodomy case 9 that serious academic questioning<br />

took place on the way the courts were dealing with a central<br />

constitutional theme, namely, equality. I disagreed with the<br />

challenge made by Dennis Davis, and said so in my judgment, but<br />

strongly welcomed the dialogue. At last academia seemed to be<br />

recovering its nerve. The Grootboom case, 10 to which Stu Woolman<br />

refers, triggered a further revival of academic contestational bravura.<br />

Once again, while disagreeing with much of the critique levelled at<br />

our thinking on the applicability of the minimum core approach, I<br />

have strongly appreciated the value of the debate.<br />

For a decade now there has been real and fruitful engagement. In<br />

one important matter academic scholarship undoubtedly proved to be<br />

fundamental. In FNB, 11 Andre van der Walt’s creative articulation of<br />

the new constitutional vision of property law in the context of our<br />

history of dispossession, became central to the Court’s jurisprudence<br />

on property rights. Other areas where academic writing has been<br />

especially influential include the rights of the child, remedies for<br />

spousal abuse, homelessness, customary law as living law and a new<br />

approach to administrative law (if Cora Hoexter received a royalty<br />

every time she was cited, she could take early retirement!). And there<br />

are many, many more areas directly enriched by serious and<br />

persuasive scholarship. Indeed, my law clerks groan at the amount of<br />

academic literature they are expected to read and later to cite.<br />

And it should also be remembered that many ideas in scholarly<br />

books and articles are picked up through submissions by counsel in<br />

8<br />

See S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 31.<br />

9 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality & Another v Minister of Justice &<br />

Others 1999 1 SA 6 (CC), 1998 1 BCLR 1517 (CC).<br />

10 Grootboom & Others v Government of the Republic of South Africa & Others 2001<br />

1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC).<br />

11<br />

First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner for the South African<br />

Revenue Services & Another 2002 4 SA 768 (CC), 2002 7 BCLR 702 (CC).


Reply - Justice Albie Sachs 43<br />

argument. We do not always cite the legal scholarship that influences<br />

us — there is a degree of intellectual seepage and osmosis that doesn’t<br />

always respect copyright — but academic contributions often<br />

irreversibly enter our brains and affect our legal imaginations in<br />

subtle and lasting ways, especially when presented by articulate and<br />

‘passionate’ counsel for amici.<br />

In my view, if the debates involving judges and scholars that led<br />

to <strong>this</strong> book are anything to go by, dialogue between the judiciary and<br />

the academic world is likely to become increasingly fruitful in the<br />

years to come. US Supreme Court Justice Robert Jackson, whom I love<br />

to quote, sardonically remarked that the ‘Court does not have the last<br />

word because it is infallible. It is infallible because it has the last<br />

word.’ We judges have to acknowledge, however, that the last word<br />

on the infallibility of the judges themselves will lie with the academic<br />

critics.<br />

O dialogo continua! Long may the dialogue continue!


4<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL<br />

SUPREMACY AND<br />

APPELLATE JURISDICTION<br />

IN SOUTH AFRICA<br />

Frank I Michelman<br />

1 Introduction<br />

At the core of Chapter 11 of Constitutional Law of South Africa, on<br />

‘The rule of law, legality, and the supremacy of the Constitution’, 1<br />

lies an outlander’s account (mine) of a process of incorporation, into<br />

post-transition South African constitutional law, of what historically<br />

had been known as a common-law doctrine of legality. I have cast the<br />

tale largely, but not wholly, as one of a technical doctrinal<br />

development, and of course it is one that has arisen out of a wholly<br />

South African set of local historical and institutional circumstances. I<br />

expect there is no other country in the world where the relevant legal<br />

texts, history, and institutional setting could throw up a similar<br />

cluster of interpretive issues and related stakes, more or less<br />

consequential as you may consider the stakes to be.<br />

It would be fair to ask what interest <strong>this</strong> technical — and locallooking<br />

— material might hold for me or any scholar outside South<br />

Africa. Later on I shall offer a response to that question, coming from<br />

the standpoint of a participant in worldwide academic study of<br />

comparative constitutionalism, and hinging on the fact (as it appears<br />

to me) that the process of migrating the legality doctrine from<br />

1 F Michelman ‘Rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the constitution’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005)<br />

Chapter 11, available at www.westlaw.com.<br />

45


46 Chapter 4<br />

common-law to constitutional status in South Africa coincided with a<br />

moment of epiphany within the Constitutional Court — of the crystallisation<br />

there of a conviction that no part of South African law can<br />

be allowed to remain outside the Constitution’s tent or beyond the<br />

Constitution’s gaze. But I must begin by sketching out the main<br />

business of the Chapter as I wrote it. 2<br />

2 History<br />

We start with a few points of history that have a bearing on my<br />

Chapter. First, by the time of the early 1990s, it was settled that<br />

South Africa would have a new political constitution — a new, and<br />

newly democratic, set of arrangements for the basic institutions of<br />

government and of law in <strong>this</strong> country; and, further, that as a part of<br />

the new constitutional order there would be a justiciable Bill of<br />

Rights. All of those points — a transformed constitutional order,<br />

democracy, a justiciable Bill of Rights — were on the side of the<br />

future.<br />

And what, then, of the past? For, second, there was also an<br />

expectation of — there was careful provision for — substantial continuity<br />

both in bodies of law and in judicial institutions and personnel.<br />

For <strong>this</strong> expectation and provision, there were compelling pragmatic<br />

reasons so obvious that I won’t go into them here. Enough for now to<br />

say that the country, by design and not by accident, found itself on<br />

the near side of the formal transition from the old order to the new<br />

with a major part of its everyday, working legal system in<br />

uninterrupted operation.<br />

Putting the first two points together, we arrive at the third:<br />

Express provision was made for submitting the inherited law to critical<br />

inspection under the new Constitution and Bill of Rights, and for<br />

modulation of the former as required to conform it to the principles<br />

and values of the latter. And then fourth: Chief and final<br />

responsibility for such inspection was to be lodged in a newly created<br />

judicial tribunal, the Constitutional Court, whose members would be<br />

selected with a view to the work of constitutional scrutiny, both of<br />

the law inherited and of the law to come.<br />

But furthermore, fifth — and <strong>this</strong> was a choice not so seemingly<br />

obvious and inevitable — it became settled as well that the new court<br />

would not have a plenary, last-resort jurisdiction but rather would be<br />

2 Readers are referred to the book chapter for more extended discussion of claims<br />

summarily put forth in what follows, and also for citations to sections of<br />

Constitutions and paragraphs of opinions with which I have not cluttered <strong>this</strong><br />

conversation-piece.


Frank I Michelman 47<br />

confined to ‘constitutional matters’, leaving final judicial authority in<br />

non-constitutional cases where it had previously resided, with the<br />

Appellate Division of the Supreme Court (later to become the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal). No one reading the pertinent sections of<br />

the Interim Constitution (and later the Final Constitution) could doubt<br />

<strong>this</strong> was a deliberate choice, one for which those who made it<br />

presumably had reasons, and one which they expected could and<br />

would be followed in ways having visible and mandatory effects on the<br />

conduct of judicial business in South Africa.<br />

3 Justification<br />

What reasons? Some undoubtedly were thoroughly technical and nonideological,<br />

having to do with considerations of an apt and efficient<br />

division of labour between tribunals perceived as having somewhat<br />

differing destinies and trajectories of specialisation and expertise.<br />

But possibly that was not all there was to it. This next observation has<br />

to be speculation on my part, and it touches on what may be a<br />

contentious point, but perhaps a part of the thinking behind the<br />

Interim Constitution’s strict division of appellate authority between<br />

the new Constitutional Court and the old Appellate Division was to<br />

ensure a space for the continued (or revitalised) evolution of a<br />

positively valued, largely common-law inspired South African legal<br />

heritage, perceived at its best and not at its worst. There is matter in<br />

the Constitutional Court’s very first opinion, in Zuma, that points<br />

clearly in that direction, 3 and so — as we shall see — do certain<br />

subsequent stances of the Court. So the suggestion is, for better or for<br />

worse, that the new Constitution’s bifurcation of appellate<br />

jurisdiction may be understood as meant, in part, to preserve an<br />

institutional sphere in which an extant, salvageable, South African<br />

legal tradition could work its way back on track, in partnership with<br />

the new Constitution — sharing the load, so to speak, not only of<br />

developing but of recovering a redemptive jurisprudence for South<br />

Africa.<br />

Whether or not in part for that reason, the Interim Constitution<br />

did plainly divide final appellate authority between the Constitutional<br />

Court and the Appellate Division. It did so along the line of<br />

3 S v Zuma 1995 2 SA 642 (CC), 1995 4 BCLR 401 (CC) (In Zuma’s Case, the<br />

Constitutional Court rejected the idea that ‘all the principles of law which have<br />

hitherto governed our courts are to be ignored.’ ‘Those principles,’ the Court<br />

affirmed, ‘obviously contain much of lasting value.’ Specifically, the common<br />

law’s traditional principles concerning onus placement in criminal trials —<br />

principles that have ‘existed in <strong>this</strong> country for over 150 years’ — ‘are<br />

fundamental to our concepts of justice and forensic fairness;’ so much so that the<br />

Constitution’s fair-trial guarantee should be construed in a manner continuous<br />

with those principles and reflective of them, and so a statute from 1977 that<br />

deviated from those principles must, accordingly, be nullified.)


48 Chapter 4<br />

‘constitutional matters’, and indeed it did so quite emphatically. Not<br />

only did it confine the Constitutional Court to constitutional matters<br />

(and some accessories that I shall soon mention), it very neatly fenced<br />

the Appellate Division out of the constitutional arena by providing<br />

that the latter’s jurisdiction would not overlap with that of the<br />

Constitutional Court. Plainly, then, the drafters — who could not have<br />

meant to leave the Appellate Division with a docket forever empty —<br />

must have been supposing that ‘constitutional matters’ does not<br />

cover all matters. As we shall see, the events recounted in my book<br />

chapter could have led to the result of leaving no cases for the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal to adjudicate, had the Final Constitution not<br />

let down the barrier against entry by the latter court onto<br />

constitutional terrain, subject to review by the Constitutional Court<br />

where constitutional matters are concerned. The Final Constitution<br />

does at the same time expressly continue to treat the Supreme Court<br />

of Appeal as final in non-constitutional matters, thus carrying forward<br />

the plain implication that not all matters are constitutional, making<br />

the Constitutional Court’s jurisdiction less than plenary. Or that, at<br />

any rate, is the official story, on what I take to be the most<br />

straightforward reading of the constitutional texts.<br />

Whether actual practice could ever possibly have matched that<br />

story proves, however, to be a great deal less clear in hindsight. When<br />

you consider the scope and the breadth of the norms of the<br />

Constitution and Bill of Rights — extending to the achievement of<br />

equality, the protection of human dignity and of the freedom and<br />

security of the person, guaranteed rights of access to court, to<br />

administrative justice, to subsistence, water, health care services,<br />

housing, and social security; when you consider the constitutional<br />

mandate to construe statutes with a view to promoting the spirit,<br />

purport and objects of the Bill of Rights; when you consider the<br />

mandate to develop the common law in a manner that will promote<br />

the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights; when you add the<br />

Constitutional Court’s declared (inevitable) authority to decide<br />

questions ancillary to the decision of constitutional matters and<br />

furthermore to decide with finality whether an appeal involves a<br />

constitutional or ancillary matter; when you consider all of that, you<br />

have to doubt whether there is any case in the slightest degree likely<br />

to be brought before the Constitutional Court, that the Court, if so<br />

minded, cannot credibly find to fall within its jurisdiction. I think, as<br />

I say <strong>this</strong>, of Judge Carole Lewis’s remarks in her recent Oliver<br />

Schreiner Lecture, to the effect that the distinction between<br />

constitutional and other issues, ‘in the context of a body of law that<br />

must necessarily be constitutionally coherent, ... is, and always was,


Frank I Michelman 49<br />

an illusion.’ 4 And yet the Constitutional Court, taking seriously that<br />

the Constitution plainly purports to make its jurisdiction less than<br />

plenary, tried to give effect to that intention. The Court, from time<br />

to time, refused to involve itself further in a case, giving as its reason<br />

a discovery that the case raised no matter of constitutional import.<br />

Two prominent examples are Boesak 5 and Metcash Trading. 6 In both<br />

those decisions, the leading idea is that the constitutional order does<br />

not tremble every time some court in the legal system commits an<br />

error in applying the law to the facts, or perhaps even in construing<br />

the law. No system is or could be proof against garden-variety judicial<br />

mistakes, and correction of such mistakes does not, in itself (when no<br />

other constitutional commitment is at stake), come within the domain<br />

of a court confined to constitutional matters.<br />

But now suppose a day arrives when the Constitutional Court<br />

construes the Constitution to contain (to all intents and purposes) a<br />

clause — virtually a part of the Bill of Rights — reading ‘everyone has<br />

the right to legality.’ Of course such a day did come, in<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers. 7 And what, then, can be left of the<br />

idea that the Constitutional Court’s jurisdiction is less than plenary,<br />

so that some cases fall beyond its power to decide? What conceivable<br />

application for Constitutional Court review does not contain a claim<br />

that some state official — assuming we include judges among state<br />

officials — has acted contrary to law or without legal authorisation?<br />

And where now is the gap between the Constitutional Court’s<br />

authority in constitutional matters and a totally plenary jurisdiction?<br />

My Chapter argues that a gap may still remain. The argument is,<br />

however, a delicate one at best, and the gap it leaves will rarely if<br />

ever be one that the Constitutional Court will be compelled to<br />

recognise as covering the case before it, should it see fit to adjudicate<br />

the case.<br />

A question thus comes naturally to mind about what<br />

considerations might have prompted the Constitutional Court to<br />

enunciate a doctrine — the existence of which amounts to a<br />

subjective constitutional right to legality — that seems to run so hard<br />

against the Constitution’s evident design to make the Constitutional<br />

Court’s judicial competence less than plenary. Direct and explicit<br />

textual compulsion cannot have been one of them, or so my Chapter<br />

contends. The inclusion in Final Constitution section 1(c) of the ‘the<br />

4<br />

See C Lewis ‘Reaching the pinnacle: Principles, policies and people for a single<br />

apex court in South Africa’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 509<br />

512.<br />

5<br />

S v Boesak 2001 1 SA 912 (CC), 2001 1 BCLR 36 (CC).<br />

6 Van der Walt v Metcash Trading Ltd 2002 4 SA 317 (CC), 2002 5 BCLR 454 (CC).<br />

7 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa & Another: In re Ex<br />

Parte President of the Republic of South Africa & Others 2000 2 SA 674 (CC), 2000<br />

3 BCLR 241 (CC).


50 Chapter 4<br />

rule of law’ as one of the Republic’s founding values does not by itself<br />

seem to give rise to any subjective right or judicially enforceable<br />

norm — and indeed it cannot be read to do so in the light of the<br />

Constitutional Court’s later decision in NICRO. 8 What is more, the<br />

constitutionalisation of the legality doctrine occurred initially in<br />

Fedsure, 9 on the watch of the Interim Constitution, an instrument<br />

containing no express textual reference whatever to legality or the<br />

rule of law.<br />

By the Constitutional Court’s own account in Fedsure (never<br />

revised, so far as I am aware), a textual basis for the constitutionalised<br />

right to legality is not to be sought in any clause of the Bill<br />

of Rights. The legality right is rather an implication from the whole<br />

constitutional scheme, or one might say an implication from the<br />

scheme’s most profound and obvious commitment, that to<br />

constitutionalism itself. The principle of legality had been a main<br />

fixture in pre-transition South African public law, and surely it must<br />

continue now to be one. It would have been incongruous, to say the<br />

least, to conclude otherwise.<br />

Whether legality would continue to be a judicially enforceable<br />

norm in South African law was a no-brainer. That, however, was not<br />

exactly the question decided by the Constitutional Court in Fedsure<br />

and Pharmaceutical Manufacturers. Rather, as my Chapter explains,<br />

the issue precisely in contention in those cases was which tribunal, as<br />

between the Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal,<br />

would have the last word in cases of disputable application of the<br />

principle of legality. The Constitutional Court would have it — or so it<br />

evidently has seemed to the jurists engaged in debating and resolving<br />

the question — if and only if the legality doctrine has been completely<br />

sucked up by the Constitution, retaining no separate life as a doctrine<br />

of the common law drawing breath (so to speak) outside the tent of<br />

the Constitution.<br />

Such plainly was the view of Supreme Court of Appeal set forth in<br />

Container Logistics, 10 and in Pharmaceutical Manufacturers the<br />

Constitutional Court responded in kind. It did so, moreover, in<br />

sweeping terms that go well beyond any tussle over which tribunal<br />

would exercise final control over applications of the legality doctrine,<br />

in particular. The Constitutional Court declared, in effect, that no law<br />

in South Africa draws breath outside the tent of the Constitution:<br />

8 Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention (NICRO) &<br />

Others 2005 3 SA 280 (CC), 2004 5 BCLR 445 (CC).<br />

9<br />

Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd & Others v Greater Johannesburg Transitional<br />

Metropolitan Council & Others 1999 1 SA 374 (CC), 1998 12 BCLR 1458 (CC).<br />

10 Commissioner of Customs and Excise v Container Logistics (Pty) Ltd;<br />

Commissioner of Customs and Excise v Rennies Group t/a Renfreight 1999 3 SA<br />

771 (SCA), 1999 8 BCLR 833 (SCA).


Frank I Michelman 51<br />

‘There is only one system of law,’ the Court declared. ‘It is shaped by<br />

the Constitution which is the supreme law, and all law, including the<br />

common law, derives its force from the Constitution and is subject to<br />

constitutional control.’ 11 Thus, where the Final Constitution seems to<br />

say quite plainly that there are two piles of cases — one falling under<br />

the final authority of the Constitutional Court, the other under that<br />

of the Supreme Court of Appeal — the Constitutional Court appears,<br />

in Pharmaceutical Manufacturers, to have announced that all legal<br />

matters in South Africa are potentially constitutional matters, which<br />

whenever identified as such would apparently fall within that Court’s<br />

purview.<br />

I have devoted a portion of my book chapter to advancing what I<br />

take to be the reasons and considerations underlying that stance on<br />

the part of the Constitutional Court, or maybe one had better say the<br />

underlying necessity of it. Very briefly, my Chapter envisions the<br />

Court noticing two important points about judicial applications of the<br />

principle of legality to actions of government (and the same points<br />

would hold regarding applications of sundry clauses in the Bill of<br />

Rights). The first is that such applications — or in other words,<br />

questions of whether legality has been breached — can often be<br />

questions over which competent lawyers will disagree in all good<br />

faith. The second is that sometimes a contestable application might<br />

have the effect of blocking or undoing actions by the government in<br />

settings strongly infused with what we may call concerns and<br />

sensibilities of transformation. (I mentioned Kyalami Ridge 12 and Bel<br />

Porto 13 as examples of situations in which both features appear.) In<br />

light of those two considerations, my Chapter suggests, the<br />

Constitutional Court did well to conclude that its clearly assigned,<br />

special role and responsibility in the transformative constitutional<br />

order requires it to insist that judicial applications of the principle of<br />

legality must finally be reviewable by it, hence must be classified as,<br />

without exception, constitutional matters.<br />

Quite arguably, as my Chapter has it, the practical consequence<br />

of <strong>this</strong> classification of legality as always and ineluctably a<br />

constitutional claim is to turn the Constitutional Court into a court of<br />

plenary jurisdiction in all but name — if it were not that already —<br />

apparently in the teeth of FC sections 167 and 168. If so, my Chapter<br />

suggests, then that is a consequence that must be borne if the<br />

Constitutional Court is to act in a way that carries out the special trust<br />

that the Constitution and the country have reposed in it. Such, my<br />

11<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 7 above) para 44.<br />

12 Minister of Public Works & Others v Kyalami Ridge Environmental Association &<br />

Others (Mukhwevho Intervening) 2001 3 SA 1151 (CC), 2001 7 BCLR 652 (CC).<br />

13<br />

Bel Porto School Governing Body & Others v Premier, Western Cape, & Another<br />

2002 3 SA 265 (CC), 2002 9 BCLR 891 (CC).


52 Chapter 4<br />

Chapter surmises, has been the Court’s judgment, or its instinct, in<br />

deciding as it did in Fedsure and Pharmaceutical Manufacturers — a<br />

judgment and an instinct which I must say strike me as defensible at<br />

the very least.<br />

In saying so, I hope I shall not be understood as suggesting, either<br />

as my own belief or that of the Court, that a firm commitment to the<br />

rule of law must or may ever take second place to the teleology of<br />

social transformation in South Africa. That, most decidedly and<br />

emphatically, is not my view, and I see no sign of its being the Court’s<br />

view. My view on <strong>this</strong> comes at the place in my Chapter where I<br />

ponder the meaning of the linkage, in FC section 1(c), of two founding<br />

values, one named ‘supremacy of the Constitution’ and the other<br />

named ‘the rule of law’. What that linkage signifies, my Chapter<br />

proposes, after some discussion, is <strong>this</strong>:<br />

In the Constitution’s sight, legal-systemic unity — every site of law<br />

pulling in the same direction — is a relative or contingent value, not an<br />

absolute one. What that value is contingent on is the direction of the<br />

pull. It is when the sites pull together toward the vindication of human<br />

dignity, human rights, non-racialism, non-sexism, and the rest that the<br />

unity of the country’s law in their service figures as a true value.<br />

Accordingly, the Constitution means by ‘the rule of law’ ... not just the<br />

rule of rules but the rule of justice, as the Constitution envisions justice.<br />

‘Supremacy of the Constitution and the rule of law’ signifies the unity of<br />

the legal system in the service of transformation by, under, and<br />

according to law. 14<br />

4 A single system of law<br />

Now comes a more venturesome part of these remarks, pushing<br />

beyond anything you can find written in my book chapter. I want to<br />

raise a question about the precise sense in which we should<br />

understand the Constitutional Court to be insisting, in Pharmaceutical<br />

Manufacturers, on a comprehension of South Africa’s legal order as<br />

being a single system of law under the Constitution’s control.<br />

To get my question rolling, consider a portion of the<br />

Constitutional Court’s opinion in another case of resounding import in<br />

South Africa’s constitutional jurisprudence and constitutional culture,<br />

that of Carmichele. ‘The proper development of the common law<br />

under section 39(2),’ wrote the Court, ‘requires close and sensitive<br />

interaction between, on the one hand, the High Courts and the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal which have particular expertise and<br />

experience in <strong>this</strong> area of the law and, on the other hand, <strong>this</strong><br />

14 Michelman (n 1 above).


Frank I Michelman 53<br />

Court.’ 15 (Note the use of the phrase ‘<strong>this</strong> area’ of the law.) ‘Not<br />

only’, the Court continued, ‘must the common law be developed in a<br />

way which meets the section 39(2) objectives, but it must be done in<br />

a way most appropriate for the development of the common law<br />

within its own paradigm.’ 16 (Note the use of the words ‘own paradigm.’)<br />

The term ‘common law’, it seems, denotes an ‘area’ within<br />

the law that works according to a distinct ‘paradigm’.<br />

In many or most cases, the Court thought, the spirit, purport, and<br />

objects of the Bill of Rights might be aptly served by any of several,<br />

notionally different ways to develop the common-law under section<br />

39(2) of the Constitution. ... Not all would necessarily be equally<br />

beneficial for the common law. ... Our common law of delict spans many<br />

centuries and the debate regarding delictual liability, its elements and<br />

their relationship to one another, remains lively. Without the benefit of a<br />

fully considered judgment from either the SCA or the High Court as to<br />

whether, from the perspective of the common law, one solution would<br />

be better than any other, <strong>this</strong> Court is at a ‘grave disadvantage’. 17<br />

The picture conveyed by those remarks is <strong>this</strong>: It will happen<br />

sometimes that the common law is found to require some adjustment<br />

to bring it into the constitutionally required state of harmony with the<br />

spirit, purport, and objects of the Bill of Rights. But common law<br />

doctrines tend to be composed of multiple moving parts, and a<br />

knowledgeable lawyer often will be able to perceive the possibility of<br />

several different doctrinal entry points for making adjustments to the<br />

common law, any one of which might satisfy the Constitution.<br />

Take for example the common law of defamation, as it stood just<br />

prior to the decision of the Supreme Court of Appeal in Bogoshi. 18 It<br />

seems some adjustment was required to bring that law into kilter with<br />

the constitutional commitment to freedom of expression (but without<br />

throwing it out of whack with the commitment to human dignity).<br />

Adjustment might conceivably have taken the form of shifting the<br />

onus on truth or falsity from the defendant to the plaintiff. But as we<br />

learned from Bogoshi and Khumalo, 19 it might also have taken — it did<br />

take — the quite different form of a new defense, for media<br />

defendants, of reasonable <strong>publication</strong> in the public interest. (I pass by<br />

the interesting point, not a crucial one for <strong>this</strong> discussion, that the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal made no suggestion in Bogoshi that it was<br />

engaged there in an application of constitutional law, or that its<br />

15 Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security (Centre for Applied Legal Studies<br />

Intervening) 2001 4 SA 938 (CC), 2001 10 BCLR 998 (CC) para 55.<br />

16 As above.<br />

17 n 15 above, para 56.<br />

18<br />

National Media Ltd & Others v Bogoshi 1998 4 SA 1196 (SCA), 1999 1 BCLR 1 (SCA).<br />

19 Khumalo & Others v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 (CC), 2002 8 BCLR 771 (CC).


54 Chapter 4<br />

detection of a need to revamp the common law of defamation was<br />

impelled by anything other than the long entrenched, deep-lying<br />

principles of the common law itself.)<br />

The Constitutional Court’s view, as expressed in Carmichele and<br />

as confirmed by that Court’s actions in quite a number of other cases,<br />

is that the choice among such possibilities — where any of several<br />

would satisfy the Constitution’s requirements, so the unity (in that<br />

sense) of the entire law of South Africa is not at stake — ought to be<br />

shaped by considerations having to do with preserving, insofar as<br />

possible, the internal integrity (or might one say the unity?) of the<br />

common law viewed as an identifiable, bounded component of South<br />

African law. That would be a main reason why deciding among such<br />

constitutionally acceptable choices is normally and properly business<br />

in which the Supreme Court of Appeal, not the Constitutional Court,<br />

should take the lead. In these cases, the Constitution, as some might<br />

say, runs out before all the available legal-doctrinal options are<br />

resolved. And that would seem to be a main reason why judges whose<br />

decisional writ cannot outrun the Constitution consider themselves<br />

well advised to leave the labouring oar in such cases to others to<br />

whom the Constitution has ostensibly assigned a broader<br />

jurisdictional competence.<br />

It is interesting to ponder how <strong>this</strong> picture might look to partisans<br />

in the well-known debate between HLA Hart and Ronald Dworkin.<br />

Jurisprudes will recall Hart’s view that the normative fabric of the law<br />

inevitably leaves open spaces, wherein judges necessarily exercise a<br />

discretionary choice as if they were legislators, choosing as they<br />

suppose legislators would or ought to do. And then they also will recall<br />

Dworkin’s counter-insistence that for any case at law brought before<br />

a judge of the law, there can be only a single legally correct answer,<br />

and the judge’s job in every case is to find that answer out as best she<br />

can.<br />

In relation to that debate, the Constitutional Court’s view as<br />

expounded in Carmichele might be described as a straddle. From the<br />

standpoint of the Constitution, there are indeed those bounded<br />

spaces of discretion envisioned by Hart. They are the spaces where<br />

the Constitution runs out before the case is fully solved, in which<br />

some further exercise of judgment (‘discretion’) necessarily is<br />

required to reach a doctrinally complete solution to the case. But<br />

from the standpoint of the common law, choosing within the bounds<br />

imposed by the Constitution, there is no such open space; rather,<br />

there is a unique right answer — that which will best comport with the<br />

general fabric of common-law doctrine and principle while<br />

comporting also with the Constitution’s demands — the ascertainment<br />

of which is properly the business of judges steeped in the knowledge


Frank I Michelman 55<br />

and the wisdom of the common law, who will determine it according<br />

to the paradigm of the common law.<br />

Let us now assume a strong Dworkinian stance and press the<br />

question of whether or how <strong>this</strong> straddle position can be fit together<br />

with the signature utterance of the Constitutional Court’s opinion in<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers — that ‘there is only one system of<br />

law’, that being a system ‘shaped by the Constitution’ and ‘under<br />

constitutional control’. If that be so — if there is only one system of<br />

law here, reflecting one ‘objective normative value system’ 20 (to<br />

quote again from Carmichele) — then Dworkinians seem bound to say<br />

that in no case can that objective order of values, which the<br />

Constitution represents and for which it speaks, leave an open space<br />

where judges retain freedom to choose among alternative possible<br />

settings of the multiple moving parts of common-law doctrine, on<br />

‘common-law’ grounds that are not themselves, in principle, already<br />

determined by that systemically unifying order of values. Rather, it<br />

seems Dworkinians must say it is always to be the task of whatever<br />

court may be seized of the case — and most unavoidably the task of<br />

whatever court has final appellate authority over it — to decide which<br />

unique answer is the right answer from the standpoint of the one<br />

system of law over which the Constitution presides. It thus may seem<br />

that if the Constitutional Court has got it right in Pharmaceutical<br />

Manufacturers, its stance in Carmichele has conceded significantly to<br />

Hart, against Dworkin.<br />

Viewing matters thus, Dworkinians might be tempted to regard as<br />

a flight from responsibility the Constitutional Court’s declared<br />

practice of qualified deferral, in some cases, to the expert commonlaw<br />

judgment or wisdom of the Supreme Court of Appeal. The<br />

responsibility, they would mean, of a court of last resort in a unified<br />

legal system to decide, in each case coming before it, what the law<br />

requires — meaning the law entire, the ‘one system of law’, of which<br />

the Constitutional Court speaks in Pharmaceutical Manufacturers,<br />

inspired by the one objective normative order of values of which it<br />

speaks in Carmichele. An objective normative value system is not,<br />

after all, a Swiss cheese. Something going under that name ought, in<br />

a Dworkinian view, to contain a uniquely right answer to every<br />

question of law affecting every topic to which law can extend. Take,<br />

for example, the topic of ministerial responsibility for delictual<br />

misconduct by police officers. In Phoebus Apollo, 21 the Constitutional<br />

Court found that topic, as it came before the Court in that case, to<br />

implicate no matter of constitutional concern. Dworkinians might<br />

lodge objection against such a finding. They might accordingly say<br />

20 Carmichele (n 15 above) para 54.<br />

21<br />

Phoebus Apollo Aviation Bpk v Minister of Safety and Security 2003 2 SA 34 (CC),<br />

2003 1 BCLR 14 (CC).


56 Chapter 4<br />

that an amendment to the Constitution removing the nominal<br />

confinement of the Constitutional Court to constitutional matters<br />

would be beneficial, because it would deny to that Court any<br />

semblance of a refuge from the full responsibility flowing to it, as<br />

court of last resort presiding over the entirety of South Africa’s one,<br />

single legal order shaped and controlled by the Constitution. That<br />

would be, I think, in the spirit of Judge Lewis’s Schreiner Lecture. The<br />

current jurisdictional dispensation, she says, ‘threatens to impede<br />

the coherent development of the law.’ 22 The coherent development<br />

of what? Not of ‘common’ law, or ‘constitutional’ law, but, simply, of<br />

‘the law’.<br />

But must we really carry the argument so far? Perhaps not. I can<br />

think of no reason, Dworkinian or other, why the Constitutional Court<br />

may not sometimes find that one or another appeal from a commonlaw<br />

decision of a High Court or the Supreme Court of Appeal presents<br />

no question of sufficient constitutional concern to invoke its<br />

jurisdiction, in the sense that the Constitutional Court cannot just<br />

now see how the deciding court’s setting of the applicable commonlaw<br />

doctrine could be thought to run afoul of the spirit, purport, and<br />

objects of the Bill of Rights. Dismissing such a case on jurisdictional<br />

grounds does not commit the Court to the view that the doctrinal<br />

topic at hand (say, ministerial responsibility for police-officer delicts)<br />

lies beyond constitutional purview in the event that some future<br />

rendition or application of the doctrine should be perceived to raise<br />

constitutional hackles. Thus the jurisdictional dismissal in Phoebus<br />

Apollo did not preclude the Constitutional Court from looking again at<br />

the common-law doctrine of respondeat superior, in the light of the<br />

different circumstances presented by the later case of K. 23<br />

Such an account jibes well, I suggest, with the Court’s<br />

recognition, in Carmichele and elsewhere, of compelling practical<br />

reasons to divide appellate working responsibility between itself and<br />

the Supreme Court of Appeal — combined with its insistence on<br />

repeated occasions, of which Pharmaceutical Manufacturers is the<br />

most dramatic, on there being reasons just as good for reserving to<br />

itself the authority to decide which of the two tribunals has the<br />

labouring oar or the final say in any given case. Which of the two has<br />

the labouring oar or the final say in any given case must depend on<br />

whether one or another common-law resolution propounded by the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal does or does not remain within the bounds<br />

of the province where reliance on that court’s special focus and<br />

experience rings true, and that means within the province composed<br />

of the set of possible common-law and statutory solutions that match<br />

22<br />

Lewis (n 4 above) 513.<br />

23 K v Minister of Safety and Security 2005 6 SA 419 (CC), 2005 9 BCLR 835 (CC).


Frank I Michelman 57<br />

up appropriately with the spirit, purport, and objects of the<br />

Constitution so far as anyone now is able to see. Of course there can<br />

be not the slightest doubt that final authority for setting those bounds<br />

must remain with the Constitutional Court. That surely is the<br />

ineluctable, irreducible meaning of the supremacy of the<br />

Constitution.<br />

5 Comparative reflections<br />

I conclude with some reflections from the angle of comparative<br />

constitutional design studies. On the map of that academic field as it<br />

currently stands, one fixture is the question — as it sometimes is<br />

framed — of a ‘centralised’ versus ‘decentralised’ form of judicial<br />

organisation for constitutional adjudication. Under that heading, two<br />

questions that are best held distinct sometimes become confused.<br />

One is whether appellate authority to pronounce on points of<br />

constitutional law shall be reserved to a single tribunal. 24 Another is<br />

whether whatever tribunal has authority to pronounce with finality on<br />

constitutional matters shall be confined to such matters, as opposed<br />

to acting as court of last resort on all justiciable matters. South<br />

Africa’s choices to date have been first ‘yes’ but more recently ‘no’<br />

on the first question, and (ostensibly and continuously) ‘yes’ on the<br />

second.<br />

The South African events recounted above shed light on these<br />

questions. One clear lesson is the potential awkwardness (to put it<br />

mildly) of combining a ‘yes’ answer to the first question with a ‘yes’<br />

answer to the second. We see from these events how it may not be<br />

possible (a) to restrict appellate competence on constitutional questions<br />

to a single court without, in effect, (b) making that same court<br />

the country’s sole court of last resort (although not necessarily its sole<br />

appellate court) on all points of law that may arise in the country’s<br />

legal system, whether out of statutes, executive and administrative<br />

orders and regulations, common law, customary law, or whatever.<br />

Whether (a) will be possible without (b) depends, as the South African<br />

events show clearly, on how extensive and inclusive is to be the field<br />

of potential application of constitutional norms. We see that<br />

restriction of constitutional-matter competence to a single appellate<br />

tribunal will be tantamount in practice to making that tribunal<br />

24<br />

Note the focus on appellate jurisdiction. Discussions usually recognise that at<br />

least one court of first instance (and probably more than one in a country with a<br />

regionalised system of first-instance courts) must be granted such authority, along<br />

with at least one appellate court — the reason being that some questions of<br />

constitutional import (the voluntariness of a criminal accused’s alleged<br />

confession, for example) cannot conveniently be decided from scratch at the<br />

appellate level, although of course trial-level determinations of them may be<br />

(and typically are) subject to some degree of appellate scrutiny.


58 Chapter 4<br />

supreme and final over all justiciable matters, unless you are willing<br />

to amputate whole large limbs of law (I mean like private law, or<br />

family law, or commercial law) from the body of law always<br />

potentially subject to scrutiny in light of the norms of the<br />

Constitution.<br />

This amputatory way, I may note, has in fact been the American<br />

way — a branch of what we call the ‘state action’ doctrine — of<br />

preserving a last-resort domain for the supreme courts of the states<br />

that is proof against United States Supreme Court review. 25 But of<br />

course that method — of cordoning off (say) private law from federal<br />

constitutional inspection, as the American ‘state action’ rule is meant<br />

in part to do — may seem too high a price to pay for whatever benefits<br />

(say, of focus, expertise, or administrative efficiency) one might<br />

perceive in preserving multiple courts of last resort, each presiding<br />

over some different branch of the country’s law. If you are resolved<br />

to refuse absolute insulation of any part or particle of the law from<br />

constitutional inspection, as has world-famously been true in South<br />

Africa (your horizontality jurisprudence being continuing front-page<br />

news in comparative constitutionalism circles), then to make your<br />

constitutional court the sole appellate tribunal for matters<br />

implicating the constitution would be, in effect, to make it the sole<br />

appellate tribunal, period, and hence the sole tribunal of last resort<br />

for all points of law arising in cases that enter the judicial system. Or<br />

so the events recounted above suggest to me — and so, evidently, did<br />

the drafters of the Final Constitution wisely conclude.<br />

These events show that the question of restricting to<br />

constitutional matters the tribunal that pronounces with finality on<br />

such matters cannot usefully be addressed without simultaneously<br />

facing the question of what fraction of all legal matters the category<br />

of constitutional matters takes in — which really amounts to the<br />

question of what sorts of norms you wish your constitution to contain.<br />

At one extreme, call it the narrow one, the choice might be to restrict<br />

constitutional-legal norms to those setting the formal rules and<br />

protocols for electing the government and the legislature, for the<br />

enactment of statutes, and the like, and leave everything else to the<br />

free and unrestricted choice of Parliament. Limitation of a court’s<br />

jurisdiction to constitutional matters would then really mean<br />

something. At the other extreme, call it the sweeping one, the choice<br />

might be to write into the Constitution broadly couched substantive<br />

25 A signature decision is Flagg Bros. Inc. v Brooks 436 US 149 (1978)(holding, in<br />

effect, that ordinary private and commercial law are not products of ‘state<br />

action’ coming within the (allegedly strictly vertical) purview of the US<br />

Constitution’s guarantees respecting individual rights, and calling ‘intolerable’<br />

the thought that every case coming to court in the US is potentially a<br />

constitutional case reviewable by the Supreme Court).


Frank I Michelman 59<br />

protections for dignity, freedom, equality, property, privacy,<br />

expression, and for the right to be treated with legality, then make<br />

some or all of those protections unambiguously applicable to all the<br />

conduct and transactions that occur in civil society, ‘private’ as well<br />

as ‘state’, ‘horizontal’ as well as ‘vertical’. And then the nominal<br />

limitation of the court to constitutional matters will not prevent the<br />

constitutional court from seizing control of any matter that it believes<br />

requires its attention.<br />

Let us now return to that other dimension I mentioned of the<br />

‘centralised’/‘decentralised’ review discussion, the question of<br />

reserving to a single appellate tribunal the authority to pronounce at<br />

all on questions of constitutional law, whether or not with finality.<br />

Again, the South African case suggests strongly that the question<br />

cannot be decided intelligently without facing at the same time the<br />

question of how sweeping or how narrow a body of norms are to be<br />

encompassed within the country’s constitutional law. If the choice<br />

approaches South Africa’s in the direction of sweepingness, then<br />

confinement of appellate authority over constitutional matters to a<br />

single tribunal will mean in effect, restriction to one of the number of<br />

appellate tribunals for the entire legal system of the country — a<br />

choice that for many countries will be out of the question. No doubt<br />

most countries will be happy to restrict to one the number of last<br />

resort tribunals for constitutional matters — indeed that comes<br />

naturally to most of us as the option most strongly preferred (else how<br />

will we resolve conflicts and disagreements of legal interpretation<br />

that are bound to arise among multiple courts sitting on the same<br />

level?) — but that is not the same question as the one of restricting to<br />

one the number of competent appellate tribunals for constitutional<br />

matters, which is what the South Africans at first tried to do but later<br />

found impracticable as recounted above. South African constitutional<br />

designers seem now to have settled comfortably on restricting to one<br />

the number of last-resort appellate tribunals for constitutional<br />

matters, but not the number of appellate tribunals having<br />

competence in that field.<br />

The South African experience may further suggest to some<br />

adventurous minds what I am sure would be for most of us a jarring<br />

and unexpected possibility. I have in mind the possibility of<br />

deliberately designing a judicial system so that no single tribunal<br />

figures as the sole available court of last resort for questions of<br />

constitutional law, as those may arise in sundry cases entering the<br />

judicial system at sundry points of entry. Something closely<br />

resembling such a multiple-peaks arrangement was, after all, the<br />

proposal of the Supreme Court of Appeal deciding Container Logistics,


60 Chapter 4<br />

at least for cases engaging the norm of legality. 26 No doubt we all<br />

would say that for any given case there must be a single court of last<br />

resort. That is true by definition (what would it mean to say that there<br />

is more than one court of last resort for any given case?) — and a good<br />

thing, too, in the sight of all who share the commonsense view that<br />

every episode of litigation had best come to an end sometime. Saying<br />

so does not, however, answer the question, prompted by the South<br />

African story, of whether or why, one and the same court must serve<br />

as court of last resort in every single case that turns on a point of<br />

constitutional law. Why not share out the work? Why not have two or<br />

more tribunals (or sets of tribunals) authorised and available to act as<br />

court of last resort in constitutional cases? There would be some<br />

serious detriments in such an arrangement, to be sure, but might<br />

there also be some benefits?<br />

In South Africa, as things stand, the more-than-one tribunals of<br />

last resort in constitutional matters would be the Constitutional Court<br />

and the Supreme Court of Appeal. (The required tweak is simple: Just<br />

revoke the former court’s power of review of decisions of the latter<br />

in constitutional matters.) In the US, the multiple tribunals of last<br />

resort in matters of US constitutional law would presumably be the<br />

federal Supreme Court on the one hand and the set composed of the<br />

highest courts of the states on the other hand. As it happens, that’s<br />

not the way it works in the US. Americans have avoided that result by<br />

our choice to provide for US Supreme Court review of state supreme<br />

court decisions on points of federal constitutional law. But was that a<br />

necessary choice, an inevitable choice? Judge Learned Hand found it<br />

so in his famous Holmes Lectures, 27 and still I must say it appears just<br />

a shade less inevitable to me now than it once did — largely as a result<br />

of my study of South African case law. (That is not to say I would<br />

recommend any change in our practice to Americans just now.)<br />

A multiple-peaks possibility for South Africa was more-or-less<br />

placed on the table by the Supreme Court of Appeal deciding<br />

Container Logistics. It was rejected by the Constitutional Court in<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers, it would seem definitively (the only<br />

question now under live debate being official expansion to plenary of<br />

the last-resort jurisdiction possessed solely by the Constitutional<br />

Court). As matters now stand, the Constitutional Court is vested with<br />

power to review any and every decision on a point of South African<br />

law rendered by any other court in the system, the only pre-<br />

26 ‘Closely resembling’, I say, but not quite the same thing. The proposition of the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal was that it might invalidate one or another government<br />

action on the ground of deviation from a common-law norm of legality which is<br />

not at the same time a norm of constitutional law and so (<strong>this</strong> was the clearly<br />

intended implication) does not give rise to a constitutional matter reviewable by<br />

the Constitutional Court.<br />

27 L Hand The Bill of rights: The Oliver Wendell Holmes lectures (1958).


Frank I Michelman 61<br />

conditions being that (a) the Court’s attention is actively invited by<br />

someone with standing to invite it (a rather loose but not negligible<br />

condition under your Constitution’s generous provisions on standing),<br />

and (b) (in many but not all cases) the Court sees fit to undertake<br />

review. Such a resolution, I have maintained, has surely been correct<br />

in South African circumstances. A question that remains is whether<br />

the same is necessarily so for every other country. The disadvantages<br />

of a multiple-peaked arrangement are clear and well-understood.<br />

Study of the South African case law may prompt one to think more<br />

seriously than most of us have done hitherto about what its possible<br />

advantages might be, in a country at a different stage in its<br />

constitutional-legal history.


5 Reply<br />

On the reach of the Constitution and the<br />

nature of constitutional jurisdiction:<br />

A reply to Frank Michelman 1<br />

Justice Kate O’Regan<br />

1 Introduction<br />

Thank you for the invitation to participate in <strong>this</strong> discussion. I would<br />

like to preface my remarks by complimenting the editors and authors<br />

on the <strong>publication</strong> of the second edition of Constitutional Law of<br />

South Africa. As somebody engaged daily with research on constitutional<br />

law in South Africa, I can say that <strong>this</strong> text is always useful<br />

and so I am delighted that a new edition has been published. I am sure<br />

it will enrich the quality of research and debate on constitutional law.<br />

I would particularly like to record my gratitude to the authors and<br />

editors, as I know a text of <strong>this</strong> sort is very labour intensive; and that<br />

extraordinarily long hours are worked for little material reward. I am<br />

sure I speak on behalf of many of us here in offering our appreciation<br />

of those efforts.<br />

1 This response was offered in response to Professor Michelman’s original Chapter<br />

in CLoSA. See F Michelman ‘The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the<br />

Constitution’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd<br />

Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 11, available at www.westlaw.com. This text is based<br />

on a transcript of the remarks I made on the first evening of Constitutional Law<br />

of South Africa Public Lecture Series (March 2006). I have merely edited and<br />

clarified those remarks. I have chosen <strong>this</strong> course, partly due to time constraints,<br />

and partly in a choice to record the remarks I actually made. That means, of<br />

course, that I have not supplemented that transcript to include comments on<br />

Professor Michelman’s revised speech published in <strong>this</strong> volume.<br />

63


64 Chapter 5<br />

Thank you too for the opportunity to respond to Professor<br />

Michelman, a constitutional lawyer whom I much admire. I thoroughly<br />

enjoyed reading Chapter 11 of Constitutional Law of South Africa,<br />

‘The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the Constitution’.<br />

There can be no doubt that discussions of the sort facilitated by<br />

<strong>this</strong> conference are of great value in contributing to our<br />

understanding of constitutional democracy. Nevertheless, I must also<br />

say, at the outset, that I found preparation for our discussion difficult<br />

for two inter-related reasons. First, as a sitting judge, there are<br />

important concerns of confidentiality and appropriate judicial<br />

reticence which limit the scope of my comments. It is my view that,<br />

as a matter of jurisprudential philosophy, every effort should be made<br />

in a judgment to articulate the premises and assumptions on which it<br />

is founded. At times, the result of <strong>this</strong> philosophy may have been, and<br />

may still be, to expand the boundaries of the doctrine of judicial<br />

notice beyond the terrain in which it has ordinarily been applied to<br />

enable the description of social, economic and political context in<br />

judicial decision making.<br />

Such a philosophy, while accepting that it has epistemological<br />

limits and recognising that there is always a potential for judicial selfdelusion,<br />

is, in my view, the proper approach to judicial reasoning in<br />

a constitutional democracy that asserts as founding values openness,<br />

responsiveness and accountability. 2 In responding to the text of the<br />

chapter written by Professor Michelman, I rely largely on the<br />

reasoning to be found in the judgments of the Constitutional Court.<br />

The second difficulty lies in the fact that Professor Michelman’s<br />

chapter runs to some 60 pages. I did not have the text of what he was<br />

going to say <strong>this</strong> evening, which differs somewhat from the chapter<br />

and understandably expands on some of its reasoning. So I thought it<br />

might be easiest if I started by identifying the arguments to which I<br />

was responding. Having heard him speak <strong>this</strong> evening, it is clear that<br />

my remarks are directed at aspects of the chapter which he has not<br />

repeated in full. In addition, he has raised some other arguments<br />

tonight which I will not have time to address. In the circumstances, it<br />

will be particularly helpful for me to start by explaining to what I am<br />

responding. I also accept that I may have misunderstood his reasoning<br />

in the chapter, and to the extent I have, I apologise in advance.<br />

The propositions to which I would like to respond are twofold. The<br />

first is that the development of the doctrine of legality by the<br />

Constitutional Court was not based on any constitutional text or<br />

principle; 3 and that the effect of the doctrine of legality is to render<br />

2<br />

See FC sec 1.<br />

3 See Michelman (n 1 above) 11-3.


Reply - Justice Kate O’Regan 65<br />

the jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court plenary and<br />

simultaneously to diminish the final appellate jurisdiction of the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal. 4<br />

The second proposition is that the effect of the Constitution is<br />

threefold: to render the norms of the Constitution supreme over other<br />

legal norms; to render them (the constitutional norms) ‘pervasive’, in<br />

the language that Professor Michelman uses in the chapter, which<br />

means that they influence the development of all other legal norms;<br />

and to render them the legal basis for all other norms. 5<br />

In formulating a response to these two propositions, it seems to<br />

me that there are four issues that I wish to address. First, I want to<br />

start by considering the scope or ambit of our Constitution. Secondly,<br />

I want to look at the issue of the unity and the coherence of our legal<br />

system. Thirdly, I shall talk a little bit about the doctrine of legality.<br />

And finally I shall talk briefly about the jurisdiction of the Supreme<br />

Court of Appeal and the Constitutional Court.<br />

2 A supreme, pervasive and foundational Constitution<br />

Professor Michelman commences his CLoSA chapter by stating that<br />

‘constitutional law [is] the law that structures and arranges political<br />

and legal institutions, their workings, and their interactions.’ 6 Now<br />

<strong>this</strong> definition of constitutional law is a perfectly competent<br />

definition of the constitutional law in many legal systems. Moreover,<br />

it describes, at least in part, what our Constitution does. Our<br />

Constitution does structure the arrangements of government. Indeed<br />

the definition is probably an entirely adequate definition of the<br />

apartheid constitution. But it is not an adequate definition to capture<br />

the full scope of constitutional law in the new South African legal<br />

order. It is important to start by recognising the full ambit of<br />

constitutional law in South Africa.<br />

Sections 167 and 168 of the Constitution which established the<br />

jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court, on the one hand, and the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal, on the other, are a primary focus of the<br />

chapter. Professor Michelman reasons, in effect, that because it is<br />

clear that the drafters intended the Supreme Court of Appeal to have<br />

final jurisdiction in matters that are not constitutional, understanding<br />

the Constitution to have a broad ambit cannot be correct. 7 This is a<br />

matter to which I shall briefly return later.<br />

4 n 1 above, 11-11 – 11-12.<br />

5 n 1 above, 11-37.<br />

6<br />

n 1 above, 11-1.<br />

7 n 1 above, 11-4 – 11-12.


66 Chapter 5<br />

It seems to me that the proper starting point is the relationship of<br />

the Constitution to the legal system generally. That relationship<br />

needs to be understood in the light of the text and the context of our<br />

Constitution.<br />

In approaching <strong>this</strong> question, our Constitution needs to be<br />

understood in its historical context. Our Constitution is emphatically<br />

a constitution that compels social transformation. This is plain from<br />

both its text, in particular, the preamble, 8 and from its context. This<br />

commitment has been recognised by the Constitutional Court and<br />

other courts on many occasions.<br />

Secondly, I would assert that in approaching and understanding<br />

the scope of the Constitution, the Constitution must be understood as<br />

establishing a coherent system of both government and law in South<br />

Africa. In <strong>this</strong> regard I am persuaded by the writing of Professor<br />

Charles Black, 9 an American professor of constitutional law, who<br />

recognised that constitutions, by their very nature, establish systems<br />

of government that need to be interpreted coherently in the light of<br />

the overall structure established. Text is important, but<br />

understanding the framework and structure of the overall scheme is<br />

as important.<br />

A third proposition of great relevance in the light of the second<br />

is, as Professor Michelman has mentioned, that the provisions of our<br />

Constitution are among the most comprehensive to be found<br />

anywhere. We often talk about the comprehensiveness of the Bill of<br />

Rights — which refers to the fact that our Bill of Rights contains rights<br />

not to be found in other constitutions, such as administrative law, 10<br />

8 The Preamble provides in relevant part:<br />

We therefore, through our freely elected representatives, adopt <strong>this</strong><br />

Constitution as the supreme law of the Republic so as to — Heal the<br />

divisions of the past and establish a society based on democratic values,<br />

social justice and fundamental human rights; Lay the foundations for a<br />

democratic and open society in which government is based on the will of<br />

the people and every citizen is equally protected by law; Improve the<br />

quality of life of all citizens and free the potential of each person; and<br />

Build a united and democratic South Africa able to take its rightful place<br />

as a sovereign state in the family of nations.<br />

9 C Black Structure and relationship in constitutional law (1969).<br />

10 Sec 33 of the Constitution provides:<br />

(1) Everyone has the right to administrative action that is lawful,<br />

reasonable and procedurally fair.<br />

(2) Everyone whose rights have been adversely affected by<br />

administrative action has the right to be given written reasons.<br />

(3) National legislation must be enacted to give effect to these rights,<br />

and must:<br />

(a) provide for the review of administrative action by a court or,<br />

where appropriate, an independent and impartial tribunal;<br />

(b) impose a duty on the state to give effect to the rights in<br />

subsections (1) and (2); and<br />

(c) promote an efficient administration.


Reply - Justice Kate O’Regan 67<br />

labour law, 11 environmental law 12 and social and economic rights. 13<br />

The sheer range of rights is therefore comprehensive, but the scope<br />

of the Bill of Rights is even more comprehensive because, as section<br />

8 makes plain, many of the rights in the Bill of Rights will bind private<br />

11 Sec 23 of the Constitution provides:<br />

(1) Everyone has the right to fair labour practices.<br />

(2) Every worker has the right:<br />

(a) to form and join a trade union;<br />

(b) to participate in the activities and programmes of a trade union;<br />

and<br />

(c) to strike.<br />

(3) Every employer has the right:<br />

(a) to form and join an employers’ organisation; and<br />

(b) to participate in the activities and programmes of an employers’<br />

organisation.<br />

(4) Every trade union and every employers’ organisation has the right:<br />

(a) to determine its own administration, programmes and activities;<br />

(b) to organise; and<br />

(c) to form and join a federation.<br />

(5) Every trade union, employers’ organisation and employer has the<br />

right to engage in collective bargaining. National legislation may be<br />

11 enacted to regulate collective bargaining. To the extent that the<br />

FC sec<br />

legislation<br />

23 provides:<br />

may limit a right in <strong>this</strong> Chapter, the limitation must comply<br />

(1) with Everyone section 36(1). has the right to fair labour practices.<br />

(2) (6) Every National worker legislation has the right: may recognise union security arrangements<br />

contained (a) to form in collective and join agreements. a trade union; To the extent that the legislation may<br />

limit (b) a right to participate in <strong>this</strong> Chapter in the the activities limitation and must programmes comply with of a section trade union; 36(1).<br />

12 Sec 24 provides: and<br />

Everyone (c) to has strike. the right:<br />

(3) Every (a) to employer an environment has the right: that is not harmful to their health or wellbeing;<br />

form and<br />

join an employers’ organisation; and<br />

(b) to participate have the environment in the activities protected, and programmes for the benefit of an of present employers’ and<br />

(a) to<br />

organisation.<br />

future generations, through reasonable legislative and other<br />

(4) Every measures trade union that: and every employers’ organisation has the right:<br />

(a) to (i) determine prevent pollution its own administration, and ecological programmes degradation; and activities;<br />

(b) to (ii) organise; promote and conservation; and<br />

(c) to (iii) form secure and join ecologically a federation. sustainable development and use of<br />

(5) Every trade natural union, resources employers’ while organisation promoting justifiable and employer economic has the and<br />

right to engage social in development.<br />

collective bargaining. National legislation may be<br />

13 See, enacted for example, to regulate secs 26 and collective 27. Sec 26 bargaining. provides: To the extent that the<br />

legislation (1) Everyone may has limit the a right right to in have <strong>this</strong> access Chapter, to adequate the limitation housing. must comply<br />

with (2) The section state 36(1). must take reasonable legislative and other measures, within<br />

(6) its available National resources, legislation to may achieve recognise the progressive union security realisation arrangements<br />

of <strong>this</strong> right.<br />

contained (3) No one in may collective be evicted agreements. from To their the home, extent or that have the their legislation home<br />

may demolished, limit a right without in <strong>this</strong> an Chapter order of the court limitation made must after comply considering with section all the<br />

36(1).<br />

12 relevant circumstances. No legislation may permit arbitrary evictions.<br />

Sec 27 Sec provides: 27 provides:<br />

13 (1) Everyone has the right to have access to:<br />

(a) health care services, including reproductive health care;<br />

(b) sufficient food and water; and<br />

(c) social security, including, including, if they if are they unable are to unable support to themselves support<br />

themselves and their dependents, and their dependents, appropriate appropriate social assistance. social assistance.<br />

(2) The state must take reasonable legislative and other measures, within<br />

its available resources, to achieve the progressive realisation of each of<br />

these rights.<br />

(3) No one may be refused emergency medical treatment.


68 Chapter 5<br />

individuals and corporations, as well as the state. 14 The Constitution<br />

also requires courts, when developing the common law or interpreting<br />

statutes, to promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of<br />

Rights. 15 In considering the range of the Constitution, it is also<br />

important to note its remedial provisions. They are unusual. A court<br />

that finds law or conduct to be inconsistent with the Constitution<br />

must declare it to be invalid 16 though courts are given powers to issue<br />

further ‘just and equitable’ orders to mediate the effect of a<br />

declaration of invalidity. Finally, it should be noted that the<br />

Constitutional Court has the inherent jurisdiction to develop the<br />

common law, along with the Supreme Court of Appeal and the High<br />

Courts. 17<br />

A further crucial textual pointer lies in the transitional provisions<br />

of both the Interim Constitution and the 1996 Constitution. Both<br />

Constitutions confirmed that old laws continued in force only to the<br />

extent that they were not inconsistent with the new Constitution. 18<br />

Thus, the transitional provisions ensured the continued validity of<br />

14 Sec 8(2) of the Constitution provides: ‘A provision of the Bill of Rights binds a<br />

natural or a juristic person if, and to the extent that, it is applicable, taking into<br />

account the nature of the right and the nature of any duty imposed by the right.’<br />

15 Sec 39(2) provides: ‘When interpreting any legislation, and when developing the<br />

common law or customary law, every court, tribunal or forum must promote the<br />

spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights.’<br />

16 Sec 172(1) provides:<br />

(1) When deciding a constitutional matter within its power, a court:<br />

(a) must declare that any law or conduct that is inconsistent with the<br />

Constitution is invalid to the extent of its inconsistency; and<br />

(b) may make any order that is just and equitable, including:<br />

(i) an order limiting the retrospective effect of the declaration<br />

(ii)<br />

of invalidity; and<br />

an order suspending the declaration of invalidity for any<br />

period and on any conditions, to allow the competent<br />

authority to correct the defect.<br />

17 Sec 173 provides: ‘The Constitutional Court, Supreme Court of Appeal and High<br />

Courts have the inherent power to protect and regulate their own process, and to<br />

develop the common law, taking into account the interests of justice.’<br />

18 Item 2 of schedule 6 of the 1996 Constitution provides:<br />

(1) All law that was in force when the new Constitution took effect,<br />

continues in force, subject to:<br />

(a) any amendment or repeal; and<br />

(b) consistency with the new Constitution.<br />

(2) Old order legislation that continues in force in terms of subitem (1):<br />

(a) does not have a wider application, territorially or otherwise, than<br />

it had before the previous Constitution took effect unless<br />

subsequently amended to have a wider application; and<br />

(b) continues to be administered by the authorities that administered<br />

it when the new Constitution took effect, subject to the new<br />

Constitution.<br />

Sec 229 of the Interim Constitution (Constitution of the Republic of South Africa<br />

Act 200 of 1993) provided:<br />

Subject to <strong>this</strong> Constitution, all laws which immediately before the<br />

commencement of <strong>this</strong> Constitution were in force in any area which forms<br />

part of the national territory, shall continue in force in such area, subject<br />

to any repeal or amendment of such laws by a competent authority.


Reply - Justice Kate O’Regan 69<br />

law, but on condition only that the old laws were not inconsistent with<br />

the new text. It is not surprising that the continuance of old laws was<br />

rendered conditional in <strong>this</strong> way. Under the old apartheid order,<br />

legislation was made by an undemocratic parliament and both the<br />

substance and the legitimacy of the legislation it enacted was<br />

therefore questionable. The new Constitution provides a basis for<br />

legal continuity by asserting that as long as old law is consistent with<br />

the new Constitution it will continue as law. The legal basis for the<br />

continued validity of the old law is therefore the imprimatur<br />

bestowed by the Constitution itself.<br />

Finally, and perhaps most importantly, in looking at <strong>this</strong> overall<br />

scope of our Constitution, the Constitution starts with a section which<br />

establishes the founding values of our state. 19 These values include<br />

the values of human dignity, the achievement of equality, the<br />

advancement of human rights and freedoms, non-racialism and nonsexism,<br />

the supremacy of the Constitution and the rule of law. In so<br />

doing, our Constitution makes clear that it is introducing a normative<br />

value system upon which our society must be ordered. The scope of<br />

such a constitution goes far beyond the minimalism of the definition<br />

of constitutional law mentioned by Professor Michelman at the start<br />

of his chapter. Not only does the Constitution structure the<br />

relationships of government but it requires a fundamental law reform<br />

project in terms of which all existing laws’ validity must be<br />

determined through the prism of the new Constitution. This is not a<br />

trifling constitution fiddling with the edges of a legal system. It<br />

restates the legal basis for all law in a normative manner and so has<br />

a substantive effect on the legal system including legal reasoning and<br />

the common law. It is indeed a supreme, pervasive and foundational<br />

Constitution.<br />

The radical character of the Constitution is unsurprising in a<br />

country undergoing a political revolution through the means of<br />

constitutional change in order to overcome both an evil and an unjust<br />

past and the consequences of that past. To say those consequences<br />

require urgent redress may seem obvious — but our Constitution<br />

expressly commits us to such an urgent response. Thus, the<br />

Constitution did more than establish a democracy and create a bill of<br />

19<br />

Sec 1 of the 1996 Constitution provides:<br />

The Republic of South Africa is one, sovereign, democratic state founded<br />

on the following values:<br />

(a) Human dignity, the achievement of equality and the advancement<br />

of human rights and freedoms.<br />

(b) Non-racialism and non-sexism.<br />

(c) Supremacy of the constitution and the rule of law.<br />

(d) Universal adult suffrage, a national common voters roll, regular<br />

elections and a multi-party system of democratic government, to<br />

ensure accountability, responsiveness and openness.


70 Chapter 5<br />

rights. It made clear that the continuity of our legal system was<br />

maintained on condition only that it would be consistent with our new<br />

constitutional norms.<br />

In my view the new Constitution’s legal reform goes beyond the<br />

content of law to require a change in the techniques of jurisprudence.<br />

I have not been able to consider sufficiently the remarks about legal<br />

reasoning Professor Michelman has made towards the end of his<br />

presentation, but I think they are not inconsistent with the<br />

proposition that legal reasoning under our new constitutional order<br />

needs to be different from how it was. Legal reasoning must embrace<br />

the normative values of the Constitution. However, I do not want to<br />

suggest that all legal reasoning must be primary order reasoning at<br />

high levels of abstraction. The implications of the Constitution for<br />

legal reasoning do not mean that we ditch secondary-level rules —<br />

rules of the common law, for example — in favour of primary-level<br />

reasoning alone. The main effect of the Constitution is to require<br />

courts to fill normative concepts in our legal system with the values<br />

of the Constitution, not with the open-textured concepts of the past,<br />

such as ‘the legal convictions of the community’. 20 A more nuanced<br />

understanding of the Constitution’s implications for legal reasoning is,<br />

unfortunately, beyond the brief time allocated to me <strong>this</strong> evening.<br />

Our Constitution thus does far more than provide the structures of<br />

government, (which it also does). It heralds a fundamental change in<br />

the basis of the legal system. It states explicitly the norms which<br />

underlie our constitutional order and binds the judiciary (and other<br />

arms of government) to give effect to these norms.<br />

Perhaps where I disagree with Professor Michelman is that the text<br />

of our Constitution is reasonably capable of a minimalist understanding.<br />

I do accept that there are times that legal principles are<br />

capable of producing different legal answers, all of which may be<br />

reasonable. I do not believe that a minimalist understanding of our<br />

20<br />

See Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security & Another (Centre for Applied<br />

Legal Studies Intervening) 2001 4 SA 938 (CC), 2001 10 BCLR 995 (CC) para 56<br />

where it is stated that:<br />

Before the advent of the Interim Constitution, the refashioning of the<br />

common law in <strong>this</strong> area entailed ‘policy decisions and value judgments’<br />

which had to ‘reflect the wishes, often unspoken, and the perceptions,<br />

often but dimly discerned, of the people’. A balance had to be struck<br />

between the interests of the parties and the conflicting interests of the<br />

community according to what ‘the (c)ourt conceives to be society's<br />

notions of what justice demands’. Under s 39(2) of the Constitution<br />

concepts such as ‘policy decisions and value judgments’ reflecting ‘the<br />

wishes ... and the perceptions ... of the people’ and 'society's notions of<br />

what justice demands’ might well have to be replaced, or supplemented<br />

and enriched by the appropriate norms of the objective value system<br />

embodied in the Constitution. (footnotes omitted).


Reply - Justice Kate O’Regan 71<br />

Constitution would have been a reasonable one in the light of both its<br />

text and context as I hope I have described to you <strong>this</strong> evening.<br />

3 The unity and the coherence of the legal system<br />

The second issue that I want to address is the unity of our legal<br />

system. The question that arises is whether the Constitution envisages<br />

a united and coherent system of law governed by one set of principles<br />

and values, or a bifurcated system or indeed possibly, as Professor<br />

Michelman suggests, three or four or even five different legal systems<br />

governed by different principles and values which would result in the<br />

Constitution leaving unaffected areas of the common law and<br />

customary law. Professor Michelman suggests that the Constitution<br />

could have been interpreted to permit a pluralist legal system based<br />

on different rules and legal values: For example, a constitutional<br />

doctrine of legality could have run concurrently with a common law<br />

doctrine of legality, which might have been different in content, and<br />

would have been adjudicated not by the Constitutional Court but by<br />

the Supreme Court of Appeal. He suggests that such an approach<br />

might have given a greater area of final jurisdiction to the Supreme<br />

Court of Appeal, even if the cost might have been to introduce some<br />

level of incoherence or inconsistency into the overall legal system.<br />

One of the early questions the Constitutional Court had to<br />

consider was what the relationship would be between common-law<br />

remedies in areas of the law covered by the Bill of Rights, and direct<br />

constitutional remedies. There was no doubt that the Constitution<br />

required infringements of the Constitution to be remedied. 21 The<br />

question was whether the Constitution, properly interpreted,<br />

permitted a claim under common law, for example in the area of<br />

administrative law, as well as a simultaneous constitutional claim<br />

directly under the provisions of section 24 of the interim Constitution<br />

which entrenched the right to administrative justice. The question<br />

has also arisen in the area of personal damages for alleged assaults by<br />

the police. 22 Bear in mind that if that were to be so, it might have<br />

been quite possible to have a successful claim under say, the<br />

Constitution, but not under the common law, or vice versa. The two<br />

systems could have co-existed side by side, perhaps based on entirely<br />

different rules.<br />

21 Sec 38 of the Constitution provides in part: ‘Anyone listed in <strong>this</strong> section. Has the<br />

right to approach a competent court, alleging that a right in the Bill of Rights has<br />

been infringed or threatened, and the court may grant appropriate relief,<br />

including a declaration of rights.’<br />

22 See Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 3 786 (CC), 1997 7 BCLR 851 (CC)<br />

where the question was whether a plaintiff could sue for constitutional damages<br />

in addition to delictual damages.


72 Chapter 5<br />

Were the Constitution to have been so interpreted, assuming for<br />

a moment it was capable of such an interpretation, the scope for<br />

duplication of claims in our legal system would have been extensive,<br />

particularly as the 1996 Constitution makes clear that many of the<br />

rights in the Bill of Rights bind private individuals as well as the state.<br />

Two causes of action could have arisen, for example, where a person<br />

complained of an infringement of dignity, or personal liberty, or<br />

security of the person. The first would have been under the actio legis<br />

aquiliae or actio injuriarum, (depending on the nature of the claim)<br />

and the other a constitutional remedy. Duplication could have arisen<br />

in labour law, administrative law, environmental law, the right to<br />

freedom and security of the person and even criminal procedure.<br />

Again, with the distinction between the jurisdiction of the<br />

Constitutional Court, on the one hand, and the Supreme Court of<br />

Appeal, on the other, these claims could have been resolved in<br />

different courts, with potentially very different outcomes and scant<br />

jurisprudential cross-pollination.<br />

The question whether the Constitution always gives rise to a freestanding<br />

cause of action, even where an appropriate common law or<br />

statutory remedy already exists, has been answered in the negative<br />

by the Constitutional Court. Textual support for <strong>this</strong> conclusion is to<br />

be found in section 39(2): 23 Section 39(2) requires the common law<br />

and statutes to be developed and interpreted in a manner that is<br />

consistent with the spirit, purport and object of the Bill of Rights.<br />

Section 173 24 makes it clear that the Constitutional Court has the<br />

inherent jurisdiction to develop the common law. The question has<br />

perhaps been most thoroughly considered in the area of<br />

administrative law in the cases analysed by Professor Michelman.<br />

Fedsure, 25 and perhaps more emphatically, Pharmaceutical<br />

Manufacturers, 26 made clear that the Interim Constitution and now<br />

the 1996 Constitution do not contemplate a dualist system of<br />

administrative law with a duplication of remedies, but rather that<br />

existing common-law remedies should give effect to the<br />

constitutional right to administrative justice and be developed and<br />

interpreted in the light of that right.<br />

One of the most important reasons for <strong>this</strong> conclusion was the<br />

dubious legal and constitutional basis for administrative law prior to<br />

1994. The questions ‘why do the courts have the power to review<br />

administrative decisions?’ and ‘what is the ambit of that power?’ were<br />

23 See n 15 above.<br />

24 See n 17 above.<br />

25<br />

Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd & Others v Greater Johannesburg Transitional<br />

Metropolitan Council & Others 1999 1 SA 374 (CC), 1998 12 BCLR 1458 (CC).<br />

26 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA & Another: In re Ex Parte<br />

President of the Republic of South Africa & Others 2000 2 SA 674 (CC), 2000 3<br />

BCLR 241 (CC).


Reply - Justice Kate O’Regan 73<br />

troubling questions for public lawyers in South Africa as they have<br />

been troubling administrative lawyers in the United Kingdom and<br />

other Commonwealth countries. 27 As the Constitutional Court said in<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers:<br />

The control of public power by the courts through judicial reviews is and<br />

has always been a constitutional matter. Prior to the adoption of the<br />

interim Constitution <strong>this</strong> control was exercised by the courts through the<br />

application of common-law constitutional principles. Since the adoption<br />

of the interim Constitution such control has been regulated by the<br />

Constitution which contains express provisions dealing with these<br />

matters. 28<br />

The precise constitutional basis for the common law principles of<br />

judicial review during the apartheid years was generally undertheorised<br />

and the absence of clear principles often had a harmful<br />

effect on the development of administrative law and its system and<br />

method. In South Africa, of course, the undemocratic and racist<br />

character of the South African parliament further rendered the<br />

understanding of judicial review complex and contested.<br />

But the constitutional revolution changed all <strong>this</strong>. The text of the<br />

1996 Constitution made explicit as founding values the rule of law and<br />

the supremacy of the Constitution; and the Bill of Rights established<br />

a right to administrative justice. The courts’ role in protecting the<br />

right to administrative justice now springs directly from the<br />

Constitution and not from some implied and inarticulate<br />

understanding of the former constitutional dispensation.<br />

The judgment in Fose makes plain that common law remedies will<br />

often be adequate and appropriate relief for infringement of<br />

constitutional rights 29 and that there are powerful reasons for not<br />

excluding them in favour of creating new forms of constitutional<br />

remedies. The result is that the Constitution does not foster a divided<br />

legal system split between the common law and the Constitution;<br />

between old methods of legal reasoning and a new constitutional,<br />

normative system of reasoning; and between a venerable court with<br />

nearly a century of history behind it and a Johnny-come-lately with<br />

27 See TRS Allan ‘The constitutional foundations of judicial review: Conceptual<br />

conundrum or interpretative inquiry?’ (2002) 61(1) Cambridge Law Journal 87;<br />

TRS Allan ‘Doctrine and theory in administrative law: An elusive quest for the<br />

limits of jurisdiction’ (2003) Public Law 429; NW Barber ‘The academic<br />

mythologians’ (2001) 21 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 369; P Craig & N<br />

Bamforth ‘Constitutional analysis, constitutional principle and judicial review’<br />

(2001) Public Law 763; P Craig ‘Constitutional foundations, the rule of law and<br />

supremacy’ (2003) Public Law 92; C Forsyth ‘Of fig leaves and fairytales: The<br />

ultra vires doctrine, the sovereignty of parliament and judicial review’ in C<br />

Forsyth (ed) Judicial review and the Constitution (2000).<br />

28<br />

n 26 above, para 33.<br />

29 n 22 above, paras 98-99.


74 Chapter 5<br />

only a decade of decision-making under its belt. No, the Constitution<br />

envisages a unified legal system within an overall objective,<br />

normative framework provided by the explicit text of our<br />

Constitution. That legal system encompasses statute law, common<br />

law and customary law and subjects them all to the discipline of<br />

compliance with constitutional norms and values. All courts are<br />

enjoined to work within <strong>this</strong> unified system on the foundation of the<br />

constitutional text.<br />

This means, simply, that each area of the law requires careful<br />

consideration to determine whether it complies with the<br />

constitutional framework or not. No area of the law is exempt from<br />

reconsideration but many will require little, if any re-cultivation.<br />

Some areas of law have already seen significant development both by<br />

the Supreme Court of Appeal and the Constitutional Court and also<br />

usefully by the legislature, sometimes under express constitutional<br />

direction: I think for example of legislation regulating access to<br />

freedom of information, the promotion of equality, and the<br />

promotion of administrative justice, to name a few areas.<br />

I would now like to respond very briefly to what Professor<br />

Michelman said at the end of his remarks about legal pluralism. It is<br />

clear, as the Constitutional Court enunciated in Carmichele, 30 that<br />

the law might quite constitutionally regulate an issue in several<br />

different ways. And which way is selected may be left either to the<br />

legislature or to other courts to determine. This possibility, however,<br />

does not mean that there is more than one legal system. There is still<br />

one legal system whose precise content is not entirely or perhaps even<br />

substantially determined by the Constitution. But it is not correct to<br />

say that because you may have different ways of regulating a matter<br />

constitutionally, you no longer have one legal system. Similarly, I am<br />

anxious about describing the possibility of different but<br />

constitutionally competent ways of regulation as ‘legal pluralism’. It<br />

is clear from the text of our Constitution that we do have a legally<br />

pluralist society. 31 The area of family law is the classic example<br />

where we have different communities, different cultures and<br />

different systems of family law. What is clear from the Constitution<br />

is that all those systems of family law may exist as long as they are<br />

30 Carmichele (n 20 above).<br />

31<br />

See, for examples, secs 211 and 212 which provide for customary law and<br />

traditional leadership.


Reply - Justice Kate O’Regan 75<br />

consistent with the Constitution. 32 Within the constitutional<br />

framework, the rules of family law may be developed by the courts or<br />

the legislature. The recognition of pluralism, within an overall<br />

normative constitutional framework, seems to me to be one of the<br />

strengths of our constitutional structure.<br />

4 Legality<br />

I turn now to the doctrine of legality. I am not going to repeat what<br />

Fedsure was about in any great detail. The case was pleaded as an<br />

administrative law ultra vires case, and concerned the passing of<br />

rates by-laws by a municipality. The Constitutional Court said:<br />

The constitutional status of a local government is thus materially<br />

different to what it was when Parliament was supreme, when not only<br />

the powers but the very existence of local government depended<br />

entirely upon superior legislatures. The institution of elected local<br />

government could then have been terminated at any time and its<br />

functions entrusted to administrators appointed by the central or<br />

provincial governments. That is no longer the position. Local<br />

governments have a place in our constitutional order, have to be<br />

established by the competent authority, and are entitled to certain<br />

powers, including the power to make by-laws and impose rates. 33<br />

The question that then arose was whether a local government which<br />

acted outside its empowering legislation was acting lawfully or not,<br />

and whether that was a constitutional question. The Court held<br />

unanimously that it was.<br />

I can think of no more fundamental doctrine in a constitutional<br />

democracy than the notion that all arms of government, particularly<br />

the executive, must act within the terms of their legal authority.<br />

Time does not permit the citation of a range of august authorities to<br />

support <strong>this</strong> statement. One may look at the German constitutional<br />

principle of the rechtstaat, the French principle of état de droit; or<br />

Jefferson’s assertion that the United States of America should have a<br />

government of law, not men: all assert the principle that in a<br />

constitutional democracy, the executive and legislative arms of<br />

government have no power other than that conferred upon them by<br />

32 Sec 15(2) provides:<br />

Religious observances may be conducted at state or state-aided<br />

institutions, provided that:<br />

(a) those observances follow rules made by the appropriate public<br />

authorities;<br />

(b) they are conducted on an equitable basis; and<br />

(c) attendance at them is free and voluntary.<br />

33 Fedsure (n 25 above) para 38.


76 Chapter 5<br />

law or the constitution. The principle flows from the fundamental<br />

purpose and principles of the Constitution itself.<br />

To suggest that the authority for the doctrine of legality arises in<br />

South Africa from the common law and not from the Constitution<br />

seems to me to misunderstand the purpose and ambit of the<br />

Constitution. This seems to be all the more plain given the troubled<br />

normative status of the common-law remedies in our previous<br />

constitutional dispensation to which I have already referred. The<br />

fundamental constitutional character of the doctrine of legality<br />

becomes apparent when one considers whether it would be<br />

constitutionally legitimate for parliament to enact law that would<br />

suggest that local government could act beyond its powers with<br />

impunity. Could parliament enact a statute which states — simply and<br />

without any meaningful guidance — that a municipality can act<br />

beyond the scope of Municipal Structures Act 34 without anybody<br />

raising a constitutional eyebrow? I think not. And I think that is<br />

because we have a deep-seated principle of legality in constitutional<br />

democracy that requires lawful, rational conduct of the executive and<br />

legislative arms of government.<br />

The last thing I want to say about the doctrine of legality is to<br />

respond to the proposition that the doctrine of legality renders the<br />

jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court plenary. 35 This proposition<br />

appears to be based on an assertion that where a court reaches a<br />

decision on the law or facts which an appellate court may consider to<br />

be wrong, it acts inconsistently with the principle of legality. The<br />

consequence would be that the Constitutional Court would be able to<br />

interfere with that judgment no matter what its subject matter and<br />

regardless of the fact that the Constitutional Court only has<br />

jurisdiction over constitutional matters.<br />

In my view <strong>this</strong> reasoning is not founded on any existing<br />

constitutional jurisprudence other than a statement in<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers which was dealing with executive<br />

power at the margins of legislative power: That statement is to the<br />

effect that all public power should be exercised lawfully. 36 At least<br />

two other judgments of the Constitutional Court would suggest that<br />

the line of reasoning is flawed. In both Boesak 37 and Metcash, 38 the<br />

Court held that there are decisions of lower courts which, even if<br />

wrong on the facts, do not give rise to constitutional matters unless<br />

some separate constitutional issue arises.<br />

34 Act 117 of 1998.<br />

35<br />

See Michelman (n 1 above) 11-11.<br />

36 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers (n 26 above) para 79.<br />

37 S v Boesak 2001 1 SA 912 (CC), 2001 1 BCLR 36 (CC), 2001 1 SACR 1 (CC).<br />

38<br />

Van der Walt v Metcash Trading Limited 2002 4 SA 317 (CC), 2002 5 BCLR 454<br />

(CC).


Reply - Justice Kate O’Regan 77<br />

5 Jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court and the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal<br />

The final issue I would like to deal with is the relative jurisdiction of<br />

the Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal. Time does<br />

not permit me to spend a lot of time on <strong>this</strong> matter and indeed some<br />

of my remarks have already adverted to <strong>this</strong> question. What I would<br />

like to emphasise, is that the Constitutional Court has always<br />

acknowledged the crucial role the Supreme Court of Appeal in<br />

developing the common law in the light of the spirit, purport and<br />

objects of the Bill of Rights. 39 This acknowledgment is based on a<br />

recognition of the particular expertise of the Supreme Court of<br />

Appeal. The Court has also emphasised the need for the Constitution<br />

to live in all courts in South Africa. This assertion is based on the fact<br />

that if the Constitution were to live only in the judgments of the<br />

Constitutional Court it would have little life in our legal system at all.<br />

The Constitutional Court is a specialist court, it sits en banc with 11<br />

judges and its ability to hear cases is limited. Contrast its limited<br />

ability to hear cases with the thousands and thousands of cases heard<br />

by courts throughout our country in any year. The principle of<br />

recognising the importance of the Constitution living in other courts<br />

throughout our legal system is to make sure that the rights and<br />

provisions of the Constitution live in our law in a real way.<br />

The final issue in relation to the jurisdiction of the two courts is<br />

the troubled question ‘what constitutes a constitutional matter’?<br />

Difficulty arises in answering it because of the broad scope of our<br />

Constitution (to which I have referred); and the fact that there are<br />

not other legal systems to look to for guidance. I want to deal,<br />

particularly, however, with the argument which has often been put in<br />

both academic debate and in legal argument to the Court, which can<br />

perhaps most simply be described as the fact-law dichotomy. On <strong>this</strong><br />

argument, an issue of law may be a constitutional matter (or an issue<br />

connected with a constitutional matter), but an issue of fact may<br />

never be. The Constitutional Court has rejected <strong>this</strong> dichotomy as the<br />

basis for determining the scope of its jurisdiction. 40 Too many cases<br />

turn on the application of open-textured laws to facts in ways which<br />

render a distinction between fact and law uncertain and indeterminate<br />

and thus mean that the distinction does not provide a<br />

principled and systematic basis for the determination of the Court’s<br />

jurisdiction. Where an individual’s rights have been infringed because<br />

39<br />

40<br />

See, for example, Amod v Multilateral Motor Vehicle Accidents Fund 1998 4 SA<br />

753 (CC), 1998 10 BCLR 1207 (CC), Carmichele (n 20 above); and Fedsure (n 25<br />

above).<br />

Boesak (n 37 above) para 15; Rail Commuters Action Group & Others v Transnet<br />

t/a Metrorail & Others 2005 2 SA 395 (CC), 2005 4 BCLR 301 (CC) paras 51-53.


78 Chapter 5<br />

a legal norm has been applied to a set of facts in a manner oblivious<br />

or careless of constitutional rights, a constitutional issue is raised.<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

In conclusion, the last ten years have seen a flowering of<br />

constitutional jurisprudence in which the common law has been<br />

developed to protect the rights entrenched in the Final Constitution.<br />

Much of <strong>this</strong> development, particularly in the last five years, has<br />

taken place in judgments of the Supreme Court of Appeal, and the<br />

High Courts. In my opinion, one of the great strengths of our<br />

Constitution lies in the fact that it requires every court to honour and<br />

protect the rights of the Constitution. In so doing, it ensures that the<br />

Constitution lives in all courts, and not only in the Constitutional<br />

Court.<br />

May I once again thank the organisers of the CLoSA Conference<br />

and Public Lecture Series for <strong>this</strong> opportunity to respond to an<br />

important chapter in the new edition of Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa; and I would like to again thank Professor Michelman for his<br />

interesting and erudite analysis of the principle of legality in South<br />

Africa that has given rise to <strong>this</strong> exchange of views.


6<br />

THE PRINCIPLE OF<br />

DEMOCRACY IN<br />

SOUTH AFRICAN<br />

*<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL LAW*<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

1 Introduction<br />

Given the interpretive function assigned to it by the Constitutional<br />

Court in NICRO, 1 the logical place to start in trying to articulate the<br />

principle of democracy in South African constitutional law is the<br />

provision on founding values. FC section 1 reads:<br />

The Republic of South Africa is one, sovereign democratic state founded<br />

on the following values: ... (d) Universal adult suffrage, a national<br />

common voters roll, regular elections and a multi-party system of<br />

democratic government, to ensure accountability, responsiveness and<br />

openness.<br />

On its face, the principle of democracy that <strong>this</strong> provision supports is<br />

one that attributes to the institutions of representative government a<br />

particular purpose, namely, ‘to ensure accountability, responsiveness<br />

and openness’. For <strong>this</strong> reading, though not for the argument of <strong>this</strong><br />

* This chapter is an extract from T Roux ‘Democracy’ in S Woolman et al (eds<br />

Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 10, available<br />

at www.westlaw.com.<br />

1 Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Reintegration<br />

of Offenders (NICRO) & Others 2005 3 SA 280 (CC), 2004 5 BCLR 445<br />

(CC) para 21.<br />

79


80 Chapter 6<br />

essay as a whole, the placement of the comma after ‘government’ in<br />

FC section 1(d) is crucial. Without the comma, the words ‘to ensure<br />

accountability, responsiveness and openness’ would have qualified<br />

the phrase ‘multi-party system of government’ alone, and FC section<br />

1(d) would for the most part have consisted of a list of institutions the<br />

purpose of which was left unstated. But <strong>this</strong> is not the provision that<br />

the Constitutional Assembly adopted. Nor is it a provision that would<br />

have made very much sense. Listing a range of institutions without<br />

any apparent purpose, except in the case of the last one, would have<br />

been an odd way for the Constitutional Assembly to have gone about<br />

articulating a founding value. Values, after all, provide standards<br />

against which conduct may be measured, whereas institutions are<br />

only valuable to the extent that they serve a valued purpose. The<br />

grammatically correct reading is therefore also the reading that<br />

makes best sense of the purposes underlying FC section 1(d). What the<br />

placement of the comma after ‘government’ does is to make it clear<br />

that the Final Constitution’s commitment to the institutions of<br />

representative government is not a commitment to the value of these<br />

institutions in and of themselves, but a commitment to a particular<br />

kind of relationship between government and the governed, one in<br />

which the people’s representatives are controlled by and responsible<br />

to the people, and in which the reasons behind the exercise of<br />

governmental power are publicly explained.<br />

Put in <strong>this</strong> way, it is immediately apparent that FC section 1(d)’s<br />

conception of democracy, and the deep principle of democracy it<br />

supports, would be incompatible with a model of democracy in which<br />

political parties vied for the people’s votes, only to ignore the people<br />

once elected. In adopting FC section 1(d), the Constitutional Assembly<br />

also conclusively rejected the somewhat sceptical view in certain<br />

contributions to democratic theory about the quality of democracy in<br />

a representative system. On the contrary, there is something of JS<br />

Mill’s optimism about FC section 1(d) in the way it confidently draws<br />

a causal link between the adoption of the institutions of<br />

representative government and the consequences it assumes will<br />

surely follow. To judge by FC section 1(d) alone, the principle of<br />

democracy in South African constitutional law is something like <strong>this</strong>:<br />

Government in South Africa must be so arranged that the people,<br />

through the medium of political parties and regular elections, in which<br />

all adult citizens are allowed to participate, exert sufficient control over<br />

their elected representatives to ensure that: (a) representatives are<br />

held to account for their actions; (b) government responds to the needs<br />

of the people; and (c) the reasons for all collective decisions are publicly<br />

explained.<br />

Unfortunately, not all the cases read FC section 1(d) in <strong>this</strong> way. And<br />

there’s the rub, for the principle of democracy must endeavour to


Theunis Roux 81<br />

reconcile the best interpretation of the constitutional text with the<br />

way the courts have in fact interpreted those same provisions. The<br />

major stumbling block in the way of the interpretation of FC section<br />

1(d) just offered is the decision of the unanimous Constitutional Court<br />

in UDM. 2 In that case, the Court was asked to place a value-laden<br />

construction on the commitment to multi-party democracy in FC<br />

section 1(d) that would have prevented Parliament from changing the<br />

then applicable electoral system so as to allow for floor-crossing. The<br />

possible reasons behind the Court’s refusal to give such a value-laden<br />

reading are discussed in the chapter from which <strong>this</strong> essay is drawn. 3<br />

They are relevant here only to the extent that it is necessary to<br />

discern whether the Court in UDM, in declining to interpret FC section<br />

1(d) in the value-laden way it was asked to do, at the same time<br />

attributed to FC section 1(d) a different set of values that have<br />

changed the way in which the principle of democracy in South African<br />

constitutional law must be stated. Here, at least, advocates of the<br />

value-laden reading may be thankful for a bit of luck, for the Court in<br />

UDM did not base its refusal to apply that reading on the primacy of a<br />

countervailing set of values located in FC section 1(d), but on a<br />

countervailing principle, extrinsic to FC section 1(d), namely, the<br />

principle that, where the Final Constitution does not clearly prescribe<br />

a particular model, the judiciary should defer to the legislature in<br />

politically sensitive cases concerning the design of the electoral<br />

system. Since that countervailing principle is not a principle located<br />

in FC section 1(d) itself, it is not part of the normative universe that<br />

needs to be taken into account when stating the principle of<br />

democracy derivable from FC section 1(d). Rather, the principle that<br />

the court should defer to the legislature in such cases is a selfstanding<br />

principle, one that was accorded greater weight on the facts<br />

of the UDM case, but one that will not be relevant to all cases in which<br />

the principle of democracy is implicated.<br />

The principle of democracy derived from the plain meaning of FC<br />

section 1(d) accordingly survives UDM. Will it also remain unchanged<br />

as the best interpretation of the legal materials when called upon to<br />

explain the other provisions in the Final Constitution on democracy<br />

and the cases decided under them? This is a complicated question and<br />

it will be easier to answer it in two stages. First, it will be necessary<br />

to consider whether the reading of FC section 1(d) offered at the<br />

beginning of <strong>this</strong> essay fits with the other express references to<br />

democracy in the Final Constitution and the rights in the Bill of Rights<br />

2 United Democratic Movement & Others v President of the Republic of South<br />

Africa & Others (African Christian Democratic Party & Others Intervening;<br />

Institute for Democracy in South Africa & Another as Amici Curiae) (No 2) 2003 1<br />

SA 495 (CC), 2002 11 BCLR 1179 (CC).<br />

3<br />

See T Roux ‘Democracy’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) § 10.3(b).


82 Chapter 6<br />

that are integral to democracy. Once <strong>this</strong> task is complete, it will be<br />

possible to decide whether the case law necessitates an amendment<br />

to the principle of democracy discernible in the constitutional text.<br />

2 The principle of democracy: The text<br />

The principle of democracy derived from FC section 1(d) is supported<br />

by the preamble. The first part of the preamble characterises<br />

democracy not as a value-neutral set of procedures for achieving<br />

other valued ends, but as a value system in itself. This is in keeping<br />

with FC section 1(d)’s commitment to the institutions of representative<br />

government as a means to ensure a particular kind of<br />

relationship between government and the governed. The second part<br />

of the preamble also affirms the core idea that democracy is a system<br />

of government ‘based on the will of the people’ and in which ‘every<br />

citizen is equally protected by law’. The principle of political equality<br />

to which <strong>this</strong> part of the preamble refers is reflected in FC section<br />

1(d)’s commitment to universal adult suffrage on a national common<br />

voters’ roll. The two statements of that principle are not incompatible<br />

with each other, and together can be incorporated into the<br />

democratic principle’s understanding of political equality as a<br />

necessary condition for the sort of relationship between government<br />

and the governed that it seeks to establish. Finally, the preamble’s<br />

concern with the connection between the consolidation of democracy<br />

in South Africa and South Africa’s relationship to other sovereign<br />

states is not part of the democratic principle itself, but rather a<br />

statement about the consequences that are expected to follow from<br />

the observance of that principle. It is therefore not necessary to try<br />

to incorporate the third part of the preamble into our understanding<br />

of the principle of democracy in South African constitutional law.<br />

The main feature of the reading of the relationship between rights<br />

and democracy in the chapter on which <strong>this</strong> essay is based was that<br />

these two concepts should not be seen to be in conflict with each<br />

other, but rather as being in a kind of constructive tension, the<br />

resolution of which should take place on a case-by-case basis in<br />

accordance with the democratic values of ‘human dignity, equality<br />

and freedom’. 4 These values are repeated in FC sections 7(1), 36(1)<br />

and 39(1). They also appear in a slightly extended form in FC section<br />

1(a). The repetition of the same set of values in these provisions is<br />

deliberate, the intention being to make it clear that the rights in the<br />

Bill of Rights do not detract from democracy, but are rather<br />

constitutive of it. This Dworkinian approach to the relationship<br />

between rights and democracy is plainly incompatible with any<br />

4 See Roux (n 3 above) § 10.3(c).


Theunis Roux 83<br />

attempt to equate the principle of democracy in South African<br />

constitutional law with the majority-rule principle. 5 This is just not<br />

what the Final Constitution says, anywhere. Even if there were<br />

isolated references to democracy in the Final Constitution that could<br />

be read in <strong>this</strong> way, 6 the overwhelming weight of the express and<br />

implied references to democracy in the Constitution comes down in<br />

favour of the opposite view. The principle of democracy in South<br />

African constitutional law is not that collective decisions shall be<br />

taken by majority vote, but something more nuanced than <strong>this</strong>,<br />

including at the very least the notion that the people’s will may be<br />

trumped by individual rights where <strong>this</strong> serves the democratic values<br />

of ‘human dignity, equality and freedom’.<br />

All the rights in the Bill of Rights contribute in one way or another<br />

to <strong>this</strong> more nuanced principle. In most cases, the contribution is<br />

indirect. In some cases, however, the contribution is explicit. Thus,<br />

when FC section 16(1) provides that ‘[e]veryone has the right to<br />

freedom of expression’, or when FC section 19(3)(a) provides that<br />

‘[e]very adult citizen has the right to vote’, the clear intention is to<br />

secure these rights against majority override, not for anti-democratic<br />

reasons, but so as to safeguard the conditions necessary for<br />

democracy. To be sure, these rights may be limited by law of general<br />

application, adopted by majority vote. But such limitation, according<br />

to FC section 36(1), will be in keeping with the principle of democracy<br />

only if the law in question itself serves the democratic values of<br />

‘human dignity, equality and freedom’.<br />

At <strong>this</strong> point the Final Constitution needs to be read very<br />

carefully. 7 FC sections 7(1), 36(1) and 39(1) consistently tell us that<br />

the democratic values that the rights in the Bill of Rights are intended<br />

5 Note that the argument is not that the majority-rule principle is not a principle of<br />

South African constitutional law. Rather, the argument is that the principle of<br />

democracy cannot be equated with the majority-rule principle.<br />

6 Such as the reference to democracy in FC sec 160(8)(b), which several courts,<br />

including the Constitutional Court, have read as referring to majority rule.<br />

75<br />

It Note might that be the useful argument at <strong>this</strong> not point that also the to majority-rule contrast the principle reading is of not the a principle of of<br />

democracy South African offered constitutional here with law. the one Rather, proposed the argument in I Currie is & that J de the Waal principle The Bill of<br />

Rights democracy handbook cannot 5 be ed equated (2005) 13-18. with the Currie majority-rule and De Waal principle. begin their treatment of<br />

6 ‘democracy Such as the and reference accountability’ to democracy by asserting FC sec that, 160(8)(b), in addition which to the several rule courts, of law,<br />

‘the including Constitution the Constitutional also requires Court, the have government read as referring to respect to majority the principle rule. of<br />

7 democracy’ serious. In (13). arguing The that principle there in are general, in fact they two remark, self-standing means principles, that ‘government one of<br />

can democracy only be and legitimate one of in accountability, so far as it rests they on divest the consent the principle of the of governed’ democracy (13). of<br />

They its true then content, list all the and provisions set up the in which possibility direct of reference a conflict is made between to democracy, these two<br />

and principles quote in FC which sec 1(d) a more in full shallow (14). One principle can quibble of democracy that, apart may win from out. FC sec If FC 1(d), sec<br />

most 1(d) is of taken the provisions to be the they closest cite thing are not to a references statement to of ‘the the principle principle of of democracy’<br />

but in the to Final the word Constitution, ‘democracy’, then but it is <strong>this</strong> clear is that not that the principle important. of Currie democracy and De connotes Waal’s<br />

reference a unified conception to FC sec of 1(d) democracy as central and to accountability the principle in of which democracy the institutions is certainly of<br />

correct. representative They then government on to are make not two divorced mistakes, from however the purpose — first, for in which asserting they that are<br />

there established. ‘no definition To extract of the democracy principle of in accountability the Constitution from nor FC an sec exhaustive 1(d) in <strong>this</strong> list way of<br />

the deprives requirements the institutions that the of principle representative imposes’, government and, secondly, of their in distinguishing<br />

instrumental<br />

from purpose, the and principle the principle of democracy, of democracy whose of its existence deeper meaning. they affirm, a separate,


84 Chapter 6<br />

to serve are ‘human dignity, equality and freedom’. On the other<br />

hand FC section 1(d) provides that the institutions of representative<br />

government are intended to ensure ‘accountability, responsiveness<br />

and openness’. 8 Is there a contradiction here? No, because FC section<br />

1(d) is only one of four values on which the democratic South African<br />

state is founded, the others being ‘[h]uman dignity, the achievement<br />

of equality and the advancement of human rights and freedoms’ (FC<br />

section 1(a)), ‘[n]on-racialism and non-sexism’ (FC section 1(b)) and<br />

‘[s]upremacy of the constitution and the rule of law’ (FC section 1(c)).<br />

It follows that FC section 1(d) does not purport to be an exhaustive<br />

list of the values that the commitment to democracy in South Africa<br />

is intended to serve. Rather, it is a more limited list of the values that<br />

the institutions of representative government are thought to be<br />

capable of ensuring. The remaining values in FC section 1 can and<br />

must be integrated into our understanding of the principle of<br />

democracy in South African constitutional law. This can be done by<br />

rephrasing the principle of democracy derived from FC section 1(d) in<br />

the form of two linked propositions — the proposition already given<br />

about the way in which government ought to be arranged, and then a<br />

complementary proposition:<br />

The rights necessary to maintain such a form of government must be<br />

enshrined in a supreme-law Bill of Rights, enforced by an independent<br />

judiciary, whose task it shall be to ensure that, whenever the will of the<br />

majority, expressed in the form of a law of general application, runs<br />

counter to a right in the Bill of Rights, the resolution of that tension<br />

promotes the values of human dignity, equality and freedom.<br />

connected but normatively distinct ‘principle of accountability’ (17). The first<br />

statement is mistaken because it is not in the nature of a legal principle<br />

exhaustively to list all the requirements it imposes. Rather, as noted above, the<br />

principle of democracy is a function of the constitutional text, the cases decided<br />

to date and the cases yet to be decided. The list of requirements imposed by such<br />

a principle is in theory infinite. Currie and De Waal’s second mistake is more<br />

serious. In arguing that there are in fact two self-standing principles, one of<br />

democracy and one of accountability, they divest the principle of democracy of its<br />

true content, and set up the possibility of a conflict between these two principles<br />

in which a more shallow principle of democracy may win out. If FC sec 1(d) is<br />

taken to be the closest thing to a statement of the principle of democracy in the<br />

Final Constitution, then it is clear that the principle of democracy connotes a<br />

unified conception of democracy and accountability in which the institutions of<br />

representative government are not divorced from the purpose for which they are<br />

established. To extract the principle of accountability from FC sec 1(d) in <strong>this</strong> way<br />

deprives the institutions of representative government of their instrumental<br />

purpose, and the principle of democracy of its deeper meaning.<br />

8<br />

It is also possible to argue that ‘accountability, responsiveness and openness’ are<br />

really goals (as in, desirable end-states) not values, and in <strong>this</strong> way to resolve the<br />

apparent contradiction between FC FC sec sec 1(d) 1(d) and and FC FC secs secs 7(1), 7(1), 36(1) 36(1) and and 39(1). 39(1). See<br />

Dworkin’s See Dworkin’s distinction distinction between between goals goals and and values values in in R R Dworkin Taking rights<br />

seriously (1977) 22. However, we are expressly told in the beginning of FC sec 1<br />

that the items to to follow are are founding values not not goals. goals. In In any any case, case, it is it possible is possible to<br />

reconcile to reconcile these in another provisions way, in as another rest way, of as <strong>this</strong> the section rest of makes <strong>this</strong> section clear. makes clear.


Theunis Roux 85<br />

The next part of the Final Constitution that needs to be taken into<br />

account are the provisions setting out the powers and functions of the<br />

various legislative bodies. These provisions may be divided into three<br />

basic types: provisions requiring legislative bodies to take account of<br />

representative and participatory democracy in the way they design<br />

their rules and orders; provisions requiring legislative bodies to allow<br />

minority party participation in their proceedings; and provisions<br />

requiring legislative bodies to facilitate public access to and<br />

involvement in their proceedings. All these provisions qualify the<br />

majority-rule principle underlying the provisions on national,<br />

provincial and local government legislative authority as a whole: that<br />

is, the principle that whichever party wins the most votes in an<br />

election is entitled to form the government. The qualification that<br />

the three sets of provisions place on the majority-rule principle is that<br />

the commitment to multi-party democracy in FC section 1(d) is not<br />

one that may be fulfilled at election-time alone, but one that must be<br />

carried through to the day-to-day operation of the various<br />

legislatures, such that the views of citizens who voted for minority<br />

parties are fairly reflected in any discussions that take place. In<br />

addition, the third type of provision requires that the legislatures<br />

should allow citizens on occasion to bypass their elected representatives<br />

in order to participate directly in the proceedings of the<br />

legislature. This qualification may be expressed by restating the first<br />

element of the democratic principle in the following way:<br />

Government in South Africa must be so arranged that the people,<br />

through the medium of political parties and regular elections, in which<br />

all adult citizens are entitled to participate, exert sufficient control over<br />

their elected representatives to ensure that (a) representatives are held<br />

to account for their actions, (b) government listens and responds to the<br />

needs of the people, in appropriate cases directly, [and] (c) collective<br />

decisions are taken by majority vote after due consideration of the views<br />

of minority parties, and (d) the reasons for all collective decisions are<br />

publicly explained. (Words added are underlined; words deleted appear<br />

in square brackets.)<br />

Is it also necessary to amend the statement of the democratic<br />

principle in light of other rights integral to democracy, such as the<br />

right to freedom of expression, political rights and socio-economic<br />

rights? To a large extent, these rights have already been taken into<br />

account in the statement of the second element of the democratic<br />

principle. At the risk of privileging certain rights over others and<br />

making the statement of the second element long and unwieldy, one<br />

might amend it thus:<br />

The rights necessary to maintain such a form of government, including<br />

the right to freedom of expression, the right to form political parties,<br />

the right to vote, and the right to the minimum standard of welfare<br />

necessary to participate in the democratic process, must be enshrined in


86 Chapter 6<br />

a supreme-law Bill of Rights, enforced by an independent judiciary,<br />

whose task it shall be to ensure that, whenever the will of the majority,<br />

expressed in the form of a law of general application, runs counter to a<br />

right in the Bill of Rights, the resolution of that tension promotes the<br />

values of human dignity, equality and freedom.<br />

This way of stating the second element of the principle, though<br />

accurate, is somewhat inelegant. On balance, therefore, it is<br />

probably better to leave the second element as it stood after<br />

consideration of FC sections 7(1), 36(1) and 39(1). This means that the<br />

principle of democracy derivable from the constitutional text, before<br />

consideration of the case law, is something like <strong>this</strong>:<br />

(1) Government in South Africa must be so arranged that the people,<br />

through the medium of political parties and regular elections, in which<br />

all adult citizens are entitled to participate, exert sufficient control over<br />

their elected representatives to ensure that: (a) representatives are<br />

held to account for their actions, (b) government listens and responds to<br />

the needs of the people, in appropriate cases directly, (c) collective<br />

decisions are taken by majority vote after due consideration of the views<br />

of minority parties, and (d) the reasons for all collective decisions are<br />

publicly explained. (2) The rights necessary to maintain such a form of<br />

government must be enshrined in a supreme-law Bill of Rights, enforced<br />

by an independent judiciary, whose task it shall be to ensure that,<br />

whenever the will of the majority, expressed in the form of a law of<br />

general application, runs counter to a right in the Bill of Rights, the<br />

resolution of that tension promotes the values of human dignity, equality<br />

and freedom.<br />

3 The principle of democracy: The cases<br />

The introduction to <strong>this</strong> essay considered the extent to which the<br />

Constitutional Court’s decision in UDM may be said to have altered the<br />

principle of democracy supported by FC section 1(d). For the same<br />

reason that UDM cannot be said to have altered that principle, it<br />

cannot be said to have altered the more extended principle<br />

discernible in the constitutional text as a whole. By declining to<br />

engage with the substantive values underpinning multi-party<br />

democracy, UDM does not stand for a countervailing interpretation of<br />

the democratic principle, but for an independent principle of judicial<br />

deference in politically sensitive cases, such as those involving the<br />

design of the electoral system. Whatever one thinks of the<br />

correctness of UDM, therefore, it cannot be said to alter the principle<br />

of democracy. Rather, UDM stands for the meta-principle that where<br />

the principle of democracy and the principle of judicial deference in<br />

politically sensitive cases conflict, the latter principle must prevail.<br />

As it so happens, that part of UDM strikes one as intuitively wrong, but<br />

it is not necessary to make a case for that intuition here. It is<br />

sufficient to conclude that the statement of the principle of


Theunis Roux 87<br />

democracy discernible in the constitutional text need not be altered<br />

in order to accommodate UDM.<br />

UDM was, of course, not the first case to rely on the principle of<br />

judicial deference in a politically sensitive case concerning the design<br />

of the electoral system. In New National Party v Government of the<br />

Republic of South Africa (‘NNP’), Yacoob J held, in a decision from<br />

which only O’Regan J dissented, that the standard of review in<br />

challenges to electoral statutes based on the right to vote was bare<br />

rationality. 9 In her powerful dissent, O’Regan J stressed the centrality<br />

of the right to vote in the consolidation of South African democracy,<br />

remarking that: ‘The right to vote is foundational to a democratic<br />

system. Without it, there can be no democracy at all.’ 10 In according<br />

special importance to the right to vote in <strong>this</strong> way O’Regan J aligned<br />

herself with the consensus view in democratic theory that, if any right<br />

needs to be safeguarded against majority override, it is the right to<br />

vote. For <strong>this</strong> reason, O’Regan J’s judgment also supports the second<br />

element of the principle of democracy adumbrated above. It is<br />

integral to the Final Constitution’s conception of democracy that<br />

rights be capable of trumping the will of the majority where such a<br />

result better serves ‘the democratic values of human dignity, equality<br />

and freedom’. By excluding the right to vote from the operation of<br />

<strong>this</strong> principle, and by subjecting the state’s regulation of it to a<br />

standard of bare rationality, NNP is clearly wrong.<br />

Although the decisions in August 11 and NICRO, 12 by vindicating<br />

prisoners’ right to vote in the face of executive neglect and legislative<br />

override, they do so without calling into question the standard of<br />

review laid down in that case. 13 August and NICRO, counterbalance<br />

the decision in NNP somewhat, therefore, despite endorsing the<br />

centrality of the right to vote in South African democracy, neither<br />

support nor detract from the principle of democracy discernible in the<br />

constitutional text. At best, they are agnostic on the question<br />

whether that principle can be enforced in cases where the state does<br />

not act irrationally. 14<br />

9<br />

1999 3 SA 191 (CC), 1999 5 BCLR 489 (CC) paras 19-24.<br />

10 n 9 above, para 122.<br />

11 August v Electoral Commission 1999 3 SA 1 (CC), 1999 4 BCLR 363 (CC).<br />

12<br />

NICRO (n 1 above).<br />

13 August (n 11 above) was decided twelve days before NNP (n 9 above) and NICRO<br />

(n 1 above) some five years later.<br />

14<br />

It should not be necessary to add that South African constitutional law does not<br />

need a deep principle of democracy to guard against irrational state action. The<br />

principle of the rule of law, including the doctrine of legality, would do <strong>this</strong> job<br />

just as well. See F Michelman ‘The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the<br />

Constitution’ in Woolman et al (n 3 above) Chapter 11.


88 Chapter 6<br />

Another case in which the principle of democracy appears at first<br />

blush to have given way to the principle of judicial deference in<br />

politically sensitive cases is Democratic Alliance v ANC & Others. 15 In<br />

that case, the Cape High Court was asked to decide whether FC<br />

section 160(8) meant that the party-political composition of a<br />

municipal council’s committees, including the executive committee,<br />

had to be proportional to the parties’ support in the council. The High<br />

Court decided that it did not, holding that FC section 160(8) primarily<br />

conferred on minority parties a right to participate in the proceedings<br />

of a municipal council and its committees, and that the composition<br />

of the committees need not exactly reflect the composition of the<br />

municipal council itself. This decision appears to have been strongly<br />

influenced by the decision in UDM, which had been handed down<br />

shortly before, and indeed gave rise to the dispute in Democratic<br />

Alliance. As in UDM, the High Court in Democratic Alliance held that,<br />

due to the political sensitivity of the case, a high degree of judicial<br />

deference was in order. 16 To <strong>this</strong> extent, the decision in Democratic<br />

Alliance may be insulated from the principle of democracy on the<br />

same basis as UDM. However, before <strong>this</strong> stage of the decision had<br />

been reached, the Court in Democratic Alliance made a finding that<br />

is potentially more damaging to the deep principle of democracy. I am<br />

referring here to the Court’s unquestioning acceptance of a<br />

concession by counsel that, read on its own, the requirement imposed<br />

by FC section 160(8)(b) would be satisfied by a first-past-the-post<br />

system in which all the members of a municipal council’s executive<br />

and other committees came from the majority party. FC section<br />

160(8)(b), it will be recalled, provides that the manner in which<br />

members of a municipal council are entitled to participate in the<br />

proceedings of the municipal council and its committees must be<br />

‘consistent with democracy’. The construction placed by the High<br />

Court in Democratic Alliance on <strong>this</strong> provision evinces a very shallow<br />

conception of democracy indeed. Read on its own, the High Court<br />

held, the requirement that municipal councillors’ participatory rights<br />

be consistent with democracy imposes an imprecise standard that<br />

would be satisfied by any number of arrangements, including a<br />

winner-takes-all system. The principle of democracy in FC section<br />

160(8)(b), the High Court thereby implied, though not equivalent to<br />

the principle of majority rule, is insufficiently determinate as to be<br />

clearly incompatible with it. 17<br />

15 2003 1 BCLR 25 (C).<br />

16 15 n 2003 15 above, 1 BCLR 41B-F. 25 (C).<br />

17 16 See n 15 also above, MEC 41B-F. for Development Planning and Local Government in the Provincial<br />

17 Government municipal council of Gauteng be approved v Democratic by a Party majority 1998 of 4 SA members, 1157 (CC), whereas 1998 7 the BCLR LGTA 855<br />

(CC). provided This for case approval concerned by a two-thirds challenge to majority, sec 16(5) with of the a Local deadlock-breaking<br />

Government<br />

Transition mechanism Act allowing 209 of the 1993 MEC (LGTA) to approve in terms the of budget. FC sec One 160(3)(b) of the read questions with FC raised sec<br />

160(2)(b). in <strong>this</strong> case The was constitutional whether the provisions LGTA framework require offended that the budget a range of of a principles, municipal<br />

council including be the approved principle by of a democratic majority of government. members, whereas The Court the LGTA held that, provided even for if<br />

approval there was by such two-thirds a principle, majority, ‘a deadlock-breaking with a deadlock-breaking mechanism mechanism to avoid impasse allowing [in<br />

the approving MEC to a municipal approve the budget] budget. would One not of be the in breach questions of [it]’ raised (para in <strong>this</strong> 56). case was


Theunis Roux 89<br />

Here, then, we have a statement of the principle of democracy<br />

that appears to be diametrically opposed to the one contained in the<br />

constitutional text. What are we to make of it? The first thing to say<br />

is that the High Court, in accepting the concession offered by the<br />

applicant’s counsel in relation to FC section 160(8)(b), made a<br />

mistake. What the applicant’s counsel and the Court seem to have<br />

missed is that the requirement of democracy in FC section 160(8)(b)<br />

applies both to municipal councillors’ entitlement to participate in<br />

the proceedings of committees of the municipal council and to their<br />

entitlement to participate in the proceedings of the municipal council<br />

itself. FC section 160(8)(b) cannot therefore establish as weak a<br />

standard as the High Court says it does. A first-past-the-post system<br />

in which the majority party participated in the proceedings of the<br />

municipal council to the exclusion of minority parties would plainly be<br />

unconstitutional. In fact, a careful reading of FC section 160(8)(b)<br />

reveals that it has nothing at all to do with party-political<br />

participation in the municipal council or its committees. That issue is<br />

dealt with in FC section 160(8)(a), which provides that the manner in<br />

which municipal councillors are entitled to participate in the<br />

proceedings of the council and its committees must allow ‘parties and<br />

interests reflected within the Council to be fairly represented’. As the<br />

High Court in Democratic Alliance itself decides, <strong>this</strong> is the provision<br />

that is directly relevant to disputes about the extent of party-political<br />

participation in the proceedings of the municipal council and its<br />

committees. FC section 160(8)(b) has to do with something else,<br />

namely the manner of members’ participation in such proceedings,<br />

which must be ‘consistent with democracy’. To discern what <strong>this</strong><br />

requirement means would have required the High Court to undertake<br />

a detailed analysis of <strong>this</strong> phrase. Given counsel’s concession in<br />

relation to FC section 160(8)(b), it is easy to understand why the High<br />

Court did not do so: the task of deciding what the phrase ‘consistent<br />

with democracy’ means is nothing short of the task undertaken in <strong>this</strong><br />

essay. Offered a convenient way out, the High Court took it, and we<br />

are accordingly left no wiser about what the principle of democracy<br />

really means. By the same token, however, Democratic Alliance v ANC<br />

cannot be read as detracting from the principle of democracy<br />

discernible in the constitutional text as a whole. Since it makes no<br />

attempt to interpret the text beyond FC section 160(8), it cannot be<br />

taken as a serious attempt to articulate that principle, and its holding<br />

in <strong>this</strong> respect may therefore be disregarded.<br />

whether the LGTA framework offended a range of principles, including the<br />

principle of democratic government. The Court held that, even if there was such a<br />

principle, ‘a deadlock-breaking mechanism to avoid impasse [in approving a<br />

municipal budget] would not be in breach of [it]’ (para 56).


90 Chapter 6<br />

The Constitutional Court’s interpretation of FC section 160(8) is<br />

contained in Democratic Alliance & Another v Masondo NO &<br />

Another. 18 Two of the three opinions in <strong>this</strong> case, Sachs J’s concurring<br />

and O’Regan J’s dissenting opinion, come quite close to the reading<br />

of the constitutional text offered here. These opinions will be<br />

discussed in a moment. First, however, it is necessary to ask whether<br />

the majority opinion in Masondo detracts from the principle of<br />

democracy discernible in the constitutional text. As was the case with<br />

UDM and Democratic Alliance v ANC, the answer must be ‘no’. This<br />

time, fortunately, the reason for <strong>this</strong> conclusion is quite simple. The<br />

difference between the three opinions handed down in Masondo had<br />

to do with the question whether the principle of democracy was<br />

implicated in that case at all, rather than with differing views about<br />

the content of the principle. Had the majority been asked whether<br />

they agreed with Sachs and O’Regan JJ’s vision for South African<br />

democracy they would probably have said, ‘Yes, of course.’ But that<br />

was not the point of their disagreement. The point of their<br />

disagreement was whether mayoral committees in an executive<br />

mayoral system are best understood as executive bodies or as bodies<br />

in which the functions of the legislature and the executive are<br />

combined. The majority took the former approach, and in effect held<br />

that the principle of democracy in FC section 160(8) did not apply to<br />

the case. 19 Sachs and O’Regan JJ, on the other hand, held that<br />

mayoral committees were mixed executive-legislative bodies<br />

because, in the nature of things, much of the deliberation over<br />

collective decisions in an executive mayoral system will occur in the<br />

mayoral committee. Both Sachs and O’Regan JJ therefore felt that<br />

the principle of democracy was indeed implicated, the difference<br />

between their two opinions being attributable to O’Regan J’s view<br />

that the absence of minority-party participation in the mayoral<br />

committee per se contradicted the ‘fair representation’ part of that<br />

principle, and Sachs J’s view that it all depended on the way that the<br />

system was implemented.<br />

It is impossible to summarise Sachs J’s remarks in Masondo on the<br />

principle of democracy in South African constitutional law without<br />

depriving them of their special flavour:<br />

The requirement of fair representation [in FC section 160(8)(a)]<br />

emphasises that the Constitution does not envisage a mathematical form<br />

of democracy, where the winner takes all until the next vote-counting<br />

exercise occurs. Rather, it contemplates a pluralistic democracy where<br />

continuous respect is given to the rights of all to be heard and have their<br />

18 2003 2 SA 413 (CC), 2003 2 BCLR 128 (CC).<br />

19 n 18 above, para 22 (holding that the governing principle was the need for<br />

effective and efficient service delivery, which is the more appropriate principle<br />

when it comes to the assessment of the conduct of the executive).


Theunis Roux 91<br />

views considered. The dialogic nature of deliberative democracy has its<br />

roots both in international democratic practice and indigenous African<br />

tradition. It was through dialogue and sensible accommodation on an<br />

inclusive and principled basis that the Constitution itself emerged. It<br />

would accordingly be perverse to construe its terms in a way that belied<br />

or minimised the importance of the very inclusive process that led to its<br />

adoption, and sustains its legitimacy.<br />

The open and deliberative nature of the process goes further than<br />

providing a dignified and meaningful role for all participants. It is<br />

calculated to produce better outcomes through subjecting laws and<br />

governmental action to the test of critical debate, rather than basing<br />

them on unilateral decision-making. It should be underlined that the<br />

responsibility for serious and meaningful deliberation and decisionmaking<br />

rests not only on the majority, but on minority groups as well. In<br />

the end, the endeavours of both majority and minority parties should be<br />

directed not towards exercising (or blocking the exercise) of power for<br />

its own sake, but at achieving a just society where, in the words of the<br />

Preamble, ‘South Africa belongs to all who live in it ...’. At the same<br />

time, the Constitution does not envisage endless debate with a view to<br />

satisfying the needs and interests of all. Majority rule, within the<br />

framework of fundamental rights, presupposes that after proper<br />

deliberative procedures have been followed, decisions are taken and<br />

become binding. Accordingly, an appropriate balance has to be<br />

established between deliberation and decision.<br />

These two paragraphs, though somewhat eclectic in their blending of<br />

different democratic theories, powerfully articulate many of the<br />

elements of the principle of democracy discernible in the constitutional<br />

text. The key aspects of the principle in Sachs J’s formulation<br />

are: (a) the rejection of the winner-takes-all conception of<br />

democracy, except in so far as majority rule remains the basic way of<br />

taking decisions once the values of participation and deliberation<br />

have been adequately served; and (b) the notion that democracy is<br />

not an event that takes place only at election time, but rather a<br />

‘continuous’ process in which every reasonable attempt is made to<br />

accommodate, or at least listen to, divergent views. If there is one<br />

theoretical influence in the mix that dominates the rest, it is the<br />

theory of deliberative democracy, and in particular Habermas’s<br />

notion that communicative power is the only legitimate form of power<br />

in the modern nation-state. 20 The principle of majority rule, in Sachs<br />

J’s formulation, is legitimate only to the extent that it is subordinated<br />

to a deeper principle of democracy that stresses the value of<br />

participation and of deliberation before decisions are taken.<br />

20 Cf Sachs J’s later remark in Matatiele Municipality & Others v President of the<br />

Republic of South Africa & Others 2006 5 SA 47 (CC), 2006 5 BCLR 622 (CC) para<br />

110: ‘In our constitutional order, the legitimacy of laws made by Parliament<br />

comes not from awe, but from openness’.


92 Chapter 6<br />

O’Regan J’s statement of the principle contained in FC section<br />

160(8)(a) is very similar, but does contain one difference that may be<br />

crucial for the way the principle of democracy is conceived in other<br />

cases. Although Sachs J, like the Cape High Court in Democratic<br />

Alliance v ANC, interprets the phrase ‘consistent with democracy’ in<br />

FC section 160(8)(b) as meaning consistent with the principle of<br />

majority rule, 21 it is clear from the remarks just quoted that he thinks<br />

the Final Constitution’s overarching vision for South African<br />

democracy is much more nuanced than <strong>this</strong>, and that the operation of<br />

the majority-rule principle, not just in FC section 160(8), but<br />

generally, is constrained by the need to engage in meaningful<br />

deliberation beforehand. For Sachs J, therefore, the principle of<br />

democracy in South African constitutional law is a deep one, roughly<br />

corresponding to the statement of that principle set out above.<br />

O’Regan J, on the other hand, says in so many words that the principle<br />

of democracy, at least in FC section 160(8)(b), is coterminous with the<br />

principle of majority rule:<br />

[FC] section 160(8)(b) is clear that the principle of fair representation is<br />

always subject to democracy and the will of the majority. The principle<br />

established by section 160(8) is a principle which requires inclusive<br />

deliberation prior to decision-making to enrich the quality of our<br />

democracy. It does not subvert the principle of democracy itself.’ 22<br />

It is clear from <strong>this</strong> passage that, when O’Regan J uses the phrase,<br />

‘the principle of democracy’, she means the principle of majority<br />

rule. Her reading of FC section 160(8), in other words, is that it<br />

contains two principles — a principle of fair representation and a<br />

principle of democracy — and that these two principles may be<br />

reconciled with each other by reading the former to apply to the<br />

manner in which minority parties should be allowed to participate in<br />

the proceedings of a municipal council and its committees, and the<br />

latter to the way in which decisions are taken. This reading of FC<br />

section 160(8) is questionable. Textually, there is nothing in FC<br />

section 160(8)(b) that says that <strong>this</strong> provision applies to decisionmaking,<br />

and certainly not to the exclusion of other issues. The<br />

operation of the majority-rule principle with regard to decisionmaking<br />

in a municipal council is set out in FC section 160(3). It<br />

provides that certain decisions of a municipal council must be taken<br />

‘with a supporting vote of a majority of its members’ and others ‘by<br />

a majority of the votes cast’. Given <strong>this</strong> comprehensive regulation of<br />

the issue, it is unclear why FC section 160(8)(b) should be read as<br />

restating the majority-rule principle in relation to participation in the<br />

21<br />

Masondo (n 18 above) para 38.<br />

22 Masondo (n 18 above) para 78 (my emphasis).


Theunis Roux 93<br />

proceedings of the municipal council and its committees. 23 The most<br />

obvious construction to be placed on FC section 160(8)(b), when read<br />

with the comprehensive regulation of decision-making in FC section<br />

160(3), is that it applies to the manner of participation in a municipal<br />

council and its committees, and not to the way decisions are taken.<br />

What FC section 160(8)(b) says is that, in addition to being fairly<br />

represented, minority parties are entitled to participate in the<br />

meetings of a municipal council and its committees in a manner<br />

‘consistent with democracy’. The principle of democracy to which FC<br />

section 160(8)(b) here refers must mean, not the majority-rule<br />

principle, which is stated in FC section 160(3), but the deeper<br />

principle of democracy discernible in the constitutional text as a<br />

whole.<br />

It would thus seem that O’Regan J’s equation of the FC section<br />

160(8)(b) requirement with the principle of majority-rule in decisionmaking<br />

is open to question. Nevertheless, that is conclusively what<br />

she says, and we are therefore left with a dissenting opinion that fails<br />

to attribute to the principle of democracy the full meaning argued for<br />

in <strong>this</strong> essay. Even Sachs J’s concurring opinion, though it appears to<br />

support that reading of the principle more fully, might in the end be<br />

said to depend on the textual peg of the phrase ‘fair representation’.<br />

Without that phrase, it is not self-evident that either O’Regan J or<br />

Sachs J would have read FC section 160(8) in the manner that they<br />

did. Masondo therefore leaves us with less than fulsome support for<br />

the reading of the principle of democracy outlined above.<br />

Two more recent decisions, however, come much closer to that<br />

reading, and moreover were delivered by a near unanimous Court. In<br />

African Christian Democratic Party, the first occasion on which<br />

O’Regan J has written for the majority in a case concerning political<br />

rights, the Court held that provisions in electoral statutes should be<br />

interpreted in favour of ‘enfranchisement rather than disenfranchisement<br />

and participation rather than exclusion’. 24 This holding<br />

was expressly tied to FC section 1(d), which is quoted in full in the<br />

preceding paragraphs, along with Sachs J’s commentary on FC section<br />

1(d) in August. 25 O’Regan J’s judgment was concurred in by all the<br />

members of the Court with the exception of Skweyiya J. Here, then,<br />

we have conclusive support for the deep principle of democracy<br />

23 It is possible that the intention of FC sec 160(8)(b) was to extend the majorityrule<br />

principle in FC sec 160(3) to proceedings of the committees of a municipal<br />

council. However, as noted earlier, <strong>this</strong> reading is strained since FC sec 160(8)<br />

expressly applies both to proceedings of the committees of a municipal council<br />

and to proceedings of the municipal council itself, that is, the council in plenary<br />

session.<br />

24 African Christian Democratic Party v Electoral Commission & Others 2006 3 SA<br />

305 (CC), 2006 5 BCLR 579 (CC) para 23.<br />

25<br />

August (n 11 above) para 17, quoted in African Christian Democratic Party (n 24<br />

above) para 22.


94 Chapter 6<br />

operating as a guide to the interpretation of statutes affecting<br />

political rights. 26<br />

In a decision handed down three days later, Matatiele Municipality<br />

& Others v President of the Republic of South African &<br />

Others, 27 we find even more conclusive evidence that a majority of<br />

the Constitutional Court may yet endorse the deep principle of<br />

democracy. In <strong>this</strong> case, an amendment to the Final Constitution<br />

altering a provincial boundary was challenged under FC section<br />

155(3)(b) for unconstitutionally limiting the authority of the Municipal<br />

Demarcation Board. Although the Court ultimately decided against<br />

the applicants on <strong>this</strong> point, it affirmed the importance of the<br />

Demarcation Board ‘to our constitutional democracy’ and the role of<br />

FC section 153(3)(b) read with FC section 1(d) in guarding against<br />

political manipulation of the demarcation process. This dictum,<br />

though not crucial to the outcome of the case and therefore not part<br />

of the ratio, suggests a slightly less deferential approach to the<br />

legislative regulation of the voting system than was evident in UDM.<br />

Of course, the political stakes were not as high in Matatiele, and<br />

therefore it is easy to downplay the importance of <strong>this</strong> dictum.<br />

Nevertheless, it does suggest that the meta-principle in UDM — that<br />

the principle of democracy must give way to the principle of<br />

deference to legislative determinations of the content of the<br />

electoral system — is not sacrosanct.<br />

A second aspect of Matatiele provides even greater support for<br />

the principle of democracy evident in the constitutional text as a<br />

whole. Faced with a concession by applicants’ counsel that the<br />

procedures for the amendment of the Final Constitution had been<br />

duly followed, a majority of the Court refused to accept it. There was<br />

enough on the papers, the Court held, to suggest that the people of<br />

Matatiele had not been properly consulted about the decision to<br />

transfer the area in which they lived to a different province. 28<br />

Although a court should as a rule be cautious about deciding issues<br />

that were not raised by the parties in their pleadings, <strong>this</strong> rule had to<br />

‘yield to the interests of justice’. 29 FC section 118(1)(a) was open to<br />

the interpretation that the people directly affected by a decision to<br />

alter a provincial boundary should be consulted by the provincial<br />

legislature concerned, either through public hearings or by giving<br />

them an opportunity to make written submissions. These issues, the<br />

26 African Christian Democratic Party does not, however, overturn the standard of<br />

review applied in New National Party (n 9 above) since FC sec 19 was used in<br />

African Christian Democratic Party as a basis for an enfranchisement-friendly<br />

reading of the statute in question, rather than a direct challenge to it.<br />

27 Matatiele (n 20 above).<br />

28<br />

Matatiele (n 20 above) para 69.<br />

29 Matatiele (n 20 above) para 66.


Theunis Roux 95<br />

Court held, ‘lie at the very heartland of our participatory<br />

democracy’. 30<br />

The order in Ngcobo J’s majority judgment in Matatiele was<br />

supported by all but two of the judges. Three other judges supported<br />

the order but not all of the reasoning in the majority judgment. The<br />

joint dissenting judgment of Skweyiya and Yacoob JJ takes issue, not<br />

with the Court’s remarks on the possible interpretation of FC section<br />

118(1)(a), but with the majority’s decision to refer the case to further<br />

hearing. It therefore leaves the majority’s provisional reading of <strong>this</strong><br />

provision untouched. Sachs J, in concurring in both the order and the<br />

reasoning in the majority judgment, restates his conception of<br />

democracy in Masondo in even more explicitly Habermasian terms,<br />

holding that ‘the legitimacy of laws made by Parliament comes not<br />

from awe, but from openness’. 31 For Sachs J, at least, the principle<br />

of democracy derived from FC section 1(d) is a deep one that is<br />

capable of invalidating virtually any law or conduct, provided that<br />

there is a textual peg on which to hang it. O’Regan J, in supporting<br />

the majority’s order but not all of its reasoning, is a little more<br />

cautious. For her, the central question in the case was whether the<br />

people of Matatiele had a legitimate grievance and, if so, the<br />

consequences for government’s relationship with that community if<br />

that grievance were left unaddressed. In her words: ‘Were we to<br />

leave undetermined the legal issues raised by Ngcobo J ... it would<br />

create uncertainty and doubt which might continue to be a source of<br />

disquiet and anger for decades to come’. 32 The fact that the case<br />

involved a constitutional amendment, in other words, only<br />

heightened the need to ensure that government was responsive to the<br />

concerns of the Matatiele community. In <strong>this</strong> indirect way, O’Regan<br />

J’s judgment, too, though it does not mention it expressly, provides<br />

support for the deep principle of democracy.<br />

4 Conclusion<br />

What then, in conclusion, are we to make of the principle of<br />

democracy at <strong>this</strong> stage of our jurisprudence? The constitutional text<br />

clearly supports a deep reading of that principle that conforms to<br />

accounts of democracy in political theory which insist that, for<br />

democracy to be meaningful, government must facilitate real public<br />

participation in decision-making and genuine deliberation. That <strong>this</strong><br />

is indeed the principle of democracy in South African law has not yet<br />

been confirmed by a majority of the Constitutional Court. Of the<br />

current judges, Sachs J has come closest to endorsing <strong>this</strong> reading,<br />

30 Matatiele (n 20 above) para 72.<br />

31<br />

Matatiele (n 20 above) para 110.<br />

32 Matatiele (n 20 above) para 90.


96 Chapter 6<br />

and O’Regan J certainly appears very sympathetic to it. The other<br />

judges, however, have remained largely agnostic, with two<br />

exceptions: the decisions in NNP and UDM. UDM is all the more<br />

important given that it was joined by Sachs and O’Regan JJ. UDM<br />

therefore remains the greatest obstacle in the way of the recognition<br />

of the deep principle of democracy in South African constitutional<br />

law. Yet it is possible to distinguish UDM on the basis that, rather than<br />

standing for a different principle of democracy, <strong>this</strong> decision stands<br />

for a meta-principle, namely, that the deep principle of democracy<br />

must yield to a principle of judicial deference in politically sensitive<br />

cases, such as those involving legislative determinations of the<br />

electoral system. To the extent that <strong>this</strong> meta-principle still stands in<br />

the way of the deep principle of democracy, there are indications in<br />

African Christian Democratic Party and Matatiele that the metaprinciple<br />

is weakening, and that we will shortly have a decision in<br />

which the majority of the Court endorses the deep principle in a case<br />

in which it really matters. 33<br />

33 Since the writing of <strong>this</strong> essay, the Constitutional Court has delivered judgment in<br />

two cases dealing with Parliament’s constitutional duty to facilitate public<br />

involvement in its processes. Both decisions provide powerful support for the<br />

deep principle of democracy argued for here. See Doctors for Life International v<br />

Speaker of the National Assembly & Others 2006 6 SA 416 (CC), 2006 12 BCLR<br />

1399 (CC) and Matatiele Municipality & Others v President of South Africa &<br />

Others 2007 6 SA 477 (CC), 2007 1 BCLR 47 (CC). More recently, the Court has<br />

recognised the limits of the right to public participation. See Merafong Demarcation<br />

Forum & Others v President of the RSA & Others [2008] ZACC 10.


7 Reply<br />

Writing the law democratically:<br />

A reply to Theunis Roux<br />

Danie Brand*<br />

1 Introduction<br />

As always, responding to Theunis Roux here is a genuine pleasure.<br />

Theunis’ account of the principle of democracy in South African<br />

constitutional law is as comprehensive, rigorous and detailed as<br />

anything he has written. His analysis of the constitutional text clearly<br />

supports the thick conception of democracy that he proposes as<br />

opposed to a thinner, procedural model. 1 His description of<br />

democracy-related cases obviously demonstrates the growing support<br />

for his concept of democracy that he claims. 2 And his reading of UDM 3<br />

and other cases not conforming to his thick conception of democracy<br />

as showing that the Constitutional Court has not rejected the thick<br />

conception, but has decided these cases on the basis of a ‘metaprinciple’<br />

of judicial deference in politically sensitive matters again<br />

seems right on the button — indeed it is a further illuminating<br />

* My thanks to Theunis Roux and Stu Woolman for asking me to do <strong>this</strong> response, to<br />

Stu and Michael Bishop for their patience and to Karin van Marle for her<br />

comments.<br />

1 T Roux ‘The principle of democracy in South African constitutional law’ in S<br />

Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations (2008) 79-96.<br />

2<br />

Roux (n 1 above).<br />

3 United Democratic Movement & Others v President of the Republic of South<br />

Africa & Others (African Christian Democratic Party & Others Intervening;<br />

Institute for Democracy in South Africa & Another as Amici Curiae) (No 2) 2003 1<br />

SA 495 (CC), 2002 11 BCLR 1179 (CC).<br />

97


98 Chapter 7<br />

example of the kind of realist/institutional analysis of the case law<br />

that I have come to appreciate in Theunis’ work. 4<br />

But responding to Theunis has also been difficult: his chapter<br />

presents such a gleaming facade that I struggled to find a meaningful<br />

critical foothold. So I decided to respond by writing about two things<br />

that he does not say about democracy and South African<br />

constitutional law and a third that his not saying them suggests. First,<br />

I touch on what I see as a curiously limited conception of the scope<br />

and the nature of democracy-related constitutional duty that<br />

emerges from the case law Theunis analyses. Second, I write about<br />

the tension between democracy and the work of courts enforcing a<br />

justiciable constitution that haunts any positively stated<br />

constitutional principle of democracy. Third, I end by asking why<br />

Theunis did not write about these two issues and what the fact that<br />

he didn’t says about the democratic credentials of his chapter.<br />

2 What Theunis does not say<br />

2.1 Democracy as an empty vessel<br />

Theunis’ focus in his analysis of the case law is on the background<br />

conception of democracy that emerges from that case law and the<br />

question of whether that conception accords with the ‘thick’ principle<br />

of democracy he claims the Final Constitution envisages. When I read<br />

the same cases Theunis did I am struck by an obviously related, but<br />

different issue — the conception of constitutional duty that emerges<br />

from the cases.<br />

This conception, although it lurks in the background of NICRO, 5 DA<br />

v ANC, 6 Masondo, 7 and ACDP, 8 is stated most explicitly in NNP 9 and<br />

UDM. Quite apart from the thin rationality standard of review that he<br />

fashions in NNP (which Theunis bluntly and correctly describes as<br />

‘clearly wrong’), 10 Yacoob J in that case articulates a two-fold duty<br />

imposed on the state by the right to vote. First, he holds that the right<br />

4<br />

For another such example, see T Roux ‘Legitimating transformation: Political<br />

resource allocation in the South African Constitutional Court’ (2003) 10<br />

Democratisation 92.<br />

5<br />

Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention and the Reintegration<br />

of Offenders (NICRO) & Others 2005 3 SA 280 (CC), 2004 5 BCLR 445<br />

(CC).<br />

6<br />

Democratic Alliance v ANC & Others 2003 1 BCLR 25 (C).<br />

7 Democratic Alliance & Another v Masondo & Another 2003 2 SA 413 (CC), 2003 2<br />

BCLR 128 (CC).<br />

8<br />

African Christian Democratic Party v The Electoral Commission & Others 2006 3<br />

SA 305 (CC), 2006 5 BCLR 579 (CC).<br />

9 New National Party v Government of the Republic of South Africa 1999 (3) SA 191<br />

(CC) 1999 (5) BCLR 489 (CC).<br />

10 Roux (n 1 above) 87.


Reply - Danie Brand 99<br />

requires the State indeed to present regular elections. 11 Second, he<br />

holds that these elections must be arranged such that they are free<br />

and fair and that any arrangement with <strong>this</strong> purpose that prevents<br />

otherwise eligible voters from registering to vote and from voting will<br />

be upheld as long as ‘people who would otherwise be eligible to vote<br />

are [despite the arrangement at issue] able to do so if they want to<br />

vote and if they take reasonable steps in pursuit of the right to<br />

vote’. 12 For Yacoob J then, the state, to give effect to a right central<br />

to the constitutional principle of democracy, can be asked to do no<br />

more than present regular elections, and to arrange those elections<br />

to be free and fair in such a way that it is possible for otherwise<br />

eligible people to vote.<br />

In UDM, the issue was whether representative institutions were<br />

arranged in a manner that meets that element of the constitutional<br />

standard of democracy that requires the existence of a multi-party<br />

democracy. The Court’s definition of multi-party democracy — a<br />

system ‘that contemplates a political order in which it is permissible<br />

for different political groups to organise, promote their views through<br />

public debate and participate in free and fair elections’ 13 — and its<br />

finding that the floor-crossing legislation passes constitutional muster<br />

because, although it probably frustrates the will of the electorate, it<br />

doesn’t actively ‘undermine multi-party democracy’ 14 seem informed<br />

by the same understanding of the nature of the state’s democracyrelated<br />

duties as Yacoob J’s judgment in NNP. Again the idea seems<br />

to be that the state has done enough if it (a) ensures that the required<br />

institutions of democracy exist and (b) ensures that they are arranged<br />

in such a way that it is only possible for democracy to operate within<br />

them. 15<br />

In sum, the NNP/UDM Court’s understanding of what the state<br />

must do to give effect to the Final Constitution’s conception of<br />

democracy requires only that the State build the institutions of<br />

democracy (elections; representative institutions; processes of direct<br />

consultation etc) and then to sit back and wait for democracy to<br />

arrive.<br />

The problem with such an articulation is two-fold. First, it reflects<br />

an entirely institutional understanding of democracy that equates<br />

11 NNP (n 9 above) para 12–17.<br />

12<br />

NNP (n 9 above) para 21.<br />

13 UDM (n 3 above) para 26 (my emphasis).<br />

14 T Roux ‘Democracy’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa<br />

(2nd Edition, OS, 2006) 10-27.<br />

15 The duty as described in UDM is lighter than in NNP — it is acceptable for the<br />

Court that representative institutions are operated such that they render<br />

permissible the free political activity that is required by multi-party democracy.<br />

UDM (n 3 above) para 26.


100 Chapter 7<br />

democracy with the institutions of government intended to give<br />

effect to it. Such an institutional understanding is flawed. 16 A<br />

collection of democratic institutions is not democracy itself — it is<br />

simply a structure inside which democracy might take place.<br />

Democracy itself is a value-system, as Theunis points out, 17 a<br />

discursive practice, 18 a way of doing and being, a mode of political<br />

action, a culture. Certainly the Constitutional Court is correct in<br />

assuming that the Final Constitution requires in the first place that<br />

certain democratic institutions be created and maintained. But that<br />

is only part of the picture. Such a democratic system without a<br />

democratic culture and practice amongst those that partake in it is an<br />

empty shell. A statement of the democracy-related constitutional<br />

duties of the State that requires only that a series of democratic<br />

institutions be created, without also engaging the problem of creating<br />

and fostering the democratic culture with which to give those<br />

institutions life, is incomplete.<br />

The second problem with the Constitutional Court’s conception of<br />

the State’s democracy-related constitutional duties is that it is a<br />

decidedly negative description, at odds with the decidedly<br />

affirmative nature of our Constitution. The point no longer needs to<br />

be made that our Constitution is an affirmative document, requiring<br />

not only that the vision of society that it proclaims be respected, but<br />

also ‘protect[ed], promot[ed] and fulfil[led]’. 19 This is true, I would<br />

say, also of the constitutional principle of democracy. In the Preamble<br />

we read that a ‘society’ based on democratic values must be<br />

‘established’ and a democratic South Africa be ‘built’. In FC section<br />

1(d) the elements of democracy must be ‘ensured’. In FC section 7(2),<br />

we read that the right to vote and other democracy-related rights<br />

must be protected, promoted and fulfilled. We cannot, therefore,<br />

accept as sufficient the Court’s assertion that an election arranged in<br />

such a manner that it is possible for those who want to vote and who<br />

take reasonable steps to vote passes constitutional muster; 20 or that<br />

an arrangement of the institutions of representative democracy that<br />

‘frustrates the will of the electorate’ can be left to stand because it<br />

allows multi-party democracy. 21<br />

The duty the Final Constitution imposes on the State is much more<br />

onerous than <strong>this</strong>. It must make it probable rather than possible that<br />

people will vote in elections; indeed it must encourage them to do so.<br />

16<br />

Roux (n 1 above). See also Roux (n 14 above) 10-23.<br />

17 Roux (n 14 above) 10-23.<br />

18 N Fraser ‘Talking about needs: Interpretive contests as political conflicts in<br />

welfare-state societies’ (1989) 99 Ethics 291 297.<br />

19 FC sec 7(2). See K Klare ‘Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism’<br />

(1998) 14 South African Journal on Human Rights 146 154.<br />

20<br />

NNP (n 9 above) para 21.<br />

21 UDM (n 3 above) para 26.


Reply - Danie Brand 101<br />

It must not only ‘lay the foundations for a democratic ... society’ 22 by<br />

creating the different institutions necessary for that purpose, but<br />

must also build, foster and encourage the culture of democracy — and<br />

by culture I mean the discursive practice and political organisation<br />

required for democracy to operate inside and outside of those vessels.<br />

Now, Theunis explicitly disavows a purely institutional understanding<br />

of democracy in his chapter in Constitutional conversations<br />

and in CLoSA. 23 If asked, I am also sure that he would not disagree<br />

that the Final Constitution’s affirmative nature applies to the<br />

constitutional principle of democracy. Finally, although not explicit<br />

about it, Theunis’ articulation of the constitutional principle of<br />

democracy in its use of active and substantive terms leaves room for<br />

a non-institutional, affirmative reading of the constitutional duties<br />

arising from it. Nevertheless, in his analysis of the cases, Theunis does<br />

not engage the question of the nature and scope of democracyrelated<br />

constitutional duty and the Constitutional Court’s limited<br />

understanding thereof. Why he doesn’t do so I can only guess. He<br />

might respond that he was asked to write only one chapter and not a<br />

whole book on the Constitution and democracy! But I do think that it<br />

is, perhaps, an important opportunity missed.<br />

The absence of recognition of the Final Constitution’s affirmative<br />

nature that we see in the democracy cases that Theunis analyses is<br />

but one example of the Constitutional Court’s failure, outside of its<br />

jurisprudence on socio-economic rights, to come to grips with <strong>this</strong><br />

question — to develop, that is, a cogent theory of positive<br />

constitutional duty that applies, as it should, across the board to all<br />

constitutional rights, standards, principles and values. In <strong>this</strong> light,<br />

the added critical engagement with the cases that an affirmative,<br />

non-institutional gloss to Theunis’ principle of democracy would have<br />

necessitated would have been most welcome. South African legal<br />

academics in general have, along with the Court, so far failed<br />

adequately to engage <strong>this</strong> issue. 24<br />

2.2 The tension between rights and democracy<br />

The second thing Theunis does not say about democracy in our<br />

constitutional law has to do with the inevitable tension that exists<br />

between democracy on the one hand and the work of courts enforcing<br />

a constitution on the other that haunts any constitutional standard of<br />

democracy.<br />

22<br />

Preamble to the Final Constitution.<br />

23 Roux (n 1 above) and Roux (n 14 above).<br />

24 For one relatively recent exception, see DM Davis ‘Adjudicating the socioeconomic<br />

rights in the South African constitution: Towards “deference lite”’<br />

(2006) 22 South African Journal on Human Rights 301.


102 Chapter 7<br />

Of course, throughout his chapter Theunis refers to <strong>this</strong> tension.<br />

He discusses the tension as it manifests itself in that old bugbear of<br />

constitutional theorists, the counter-majoritarian dilemma — the<br />

dilemma that democratically unaccountable courts through the<br />

exercise of their power to review conduct of the representative<br />

branches of government get to trump formal expressions of the<br />

collective will. Although Theunis develops a nuanced response to <strong>this</strong><br />

aspect of the dilemma 25 he goes no further than that — and therein<br />

lies the gap.<br />

The counter-majoritarian dilemma, as we all well know, is but one<br />

example of the tension between rights and democracy. It is an<br />

institutional rendition of it that focuses on the tension between rights<br />

and democracy only as it is mediated through the democratic<br />

institutions of government. An exclusive focus on the countermajoritarian<br />

dilemma leaves out of account the tension between<br />

rights and the work of courts in enforcing them on the one hand, and<br />

the non-institutional aspects of democracy — the political practice or<br />

culture of democracy that operates inside and outside of the formal<br />

institutions of democracy — on the other.<br />

The different examples of the tension described in <strong>this</strong> noninstitutional<br />

manner are well known. Critics have for example pointed<br />

out that the work of courts applying a constitution can exercise a<br />

stifling effect on democratic political action by destroying the various<br />

forms of social organisation upon which such action depends. 26 Courts<br />

enforcing constitutional rights can also, so it has been argued, work<br />

to erode democracy by promoting ‘a false expectation in<br />

disadvantaged individuals and groups that the pursuit of legal rights<br />

through the courts can effect lasting social change’ whereas ‘rights ...<br />

operate instead to ... channel potentially radical demands for change<br />

into legal claims which, by definition, will not be disruptive of the<br />

social and economic status quo.’ 27 Constitutional law as enforced<br />

through courts can finally discourage democratic political action<br />

simply by bracketing previously contested social questions as<br />

25 Roux (n 1 above) 81-84.<br />

26<br />

See J Habermas ‘Law as medium and law as institution’ in G Teubner (ed)<br />

Dilemmas of law in the welfare state (1986) 204 211. See also JWG van der Walt<br />

The twilight of legal subjectivity: Towards a deconstructive republican theory of<br />

law (1995) unpublished LLD dissertation, Rand Afrikaans University 324. For a<br />

recent exploration of the different facets of <strong>this</strong> problem in a South African<br />

context, see L Williams ‘Issues and challenges in addressing poverty and legal<br />

rights: A comparative United States/South African analysis’ (2005) 21 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 436.<br />

27 M Jackman ‘Constitutional rhetoric and social justice: Reflections on the<br />

justiciability debate’ in J Bakan & D Schneiderman (eds) Social justice and the<br />

constitution: Perspectives on a social union for Canada (1992) 17 22. For<br />

discussions of <strong>this</strong> problem in the South African literature, see S Wilson ‘Taming<br />

the constitution: Rights and reform in the South African education system’ (2004)<br />

20 South African Journal on Human Rights 418 423-424.


Reply - Danie Brand 103<br />

somehow not subject to further political contestation — either<br />

because of the finality with which courts usually present their<br />

decisions, 28 or because of the presentation by courts of their<br />

engagement with contested social issues as value-neutral, conducted<br />

on the basis of an objective set of materials, 29 or because courts in<br />

their judgments use language and rhetorical strategies to describe<br />

social issues as incapable of political engagement (as, for example,<br />

too technically complex for political engagement, or of private rather<br />

than public concern, or simply as insoluble, so that political<br />

engagement with it becomes futile). 30<br />

The gap that Theunis’ failure to engage <strong>this</strong> non-institutional<br />

aspect of the tension between rights and democracy leaves in his<br />

account of the principle of democracy in South African constitutional<br />

law is illustrated in his CLoSA chapter’s discussion of the relationship<br />

between democracy and socio-economic rights. First, as he recounts,<br />

these rights are said to be supportive — indeed, constitutive — of<br />

democracy in that access to the basic resources that they guarantee<br />

enables impoverished people to participate as fully-fledged members<br />

of society in the democratic process. 31 Second, he relates how these<br />

rights in their justiciable form have been said to raise the countermajoritarian<br />

dilemma in particularly acute form and so to stand in<br />

particularly acute tension with democracy. 32<br />

Both these aspects of the relationship between socio-economic<br />

rights and democracy have indeed been the focus of sustained<br />

scholarly and judicial engagement in South Africa and elsewhere. But<br />

there is a third aspect to the relationship between socio-economic<br />

28 See eg H Botha ‘Freedom and constraint in constitutional adjudication’ (2004) 20<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 249.<br />

29 See eg UDM (n 3 above) para 11: ‘This case is not about the merits or demerits of<br />

the disputed legislation. That is a political question and of no concern to <strong>this</strong><br />

Court. What has to be decided is not whether the disputed provisions are<br />

appropriate or inappropriate, but whether they are constitutional or<br />

unconstitutional.’ For a discussion of <strong>this</strong> problem, see Botha (n 28 above) 249-<br />

250 and K Van Marle ‘Revisiting the politics of post-apartheid constitutional<br />

interpretation’ (2003) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 549 552-553.<br />

30 See Fraser (n 18 above); T Ross ‘The rhetoric of poverty: Their immorality, our<br />

helplessness’ (1991) 79 Georgetown Law Journal 1499 1499-1500; LA Williams<br />

‘Welfare and legal entitlements: The social roots of poverty’ in D Kairys (ed) The<br />

politics of law. A progressive critique 3 ed (1998) 569 569. For my own<br />

engagement with <strong>this</strong> issue see D Brand ‘The “politics of need interpretation” and<br />

the adjudication of socio-economic rights claims in South Africa’ in AJ van der<br />

Walt (ed) Theories of social and economic justice (2005) 17.<br />

31<br />

Roux (n 14 above) 10-57 — 10-62.<br />

32 As above.


104 Chapter 7<br />

rights and democracy that Theunis does not mention. Recently Edgar<br />

Pieterse and Mirjam van Donk wrote: 33<br />

The realisation of socio-economic rights is an inherently political<br />

process, which needs to involve rights holders (directly, or through<br />

associations and organisations representing their interests) in determining<br />

the desired outcomes, objectives, strategies and acceptable<br />

trade-offs so that they are enabled to take control of their own<br />

destinies. This inevitably implies a political process of negotiation,<br />

disagreement, conflict, occasionally consensus, and, at a minimum,<br />

forms of mutual accommodation.<br />

It would seem, on their view, that not only is the realisation of socioeconomic<br />

rights a prerequisite for democracy, as Theunis contends.<br />

Democracy is for them also a prerequisite for the realisation of socioeconomic<br />

rights. Sustainable eradication of poverty and deprivation<br />

depends crucially on the extent to which impoverished people have<br />

the capacity and are allowed the space to participate ‘in determining<br />

the desired outcomes, objectives, strategies and acceptable tradeoffs’<br />

involved in shaping their fate and to partake of the ‘political<br />

process of negotiation, disagreement, conflict, occasionally consensus,<br />

and, at a minimum, forms of mutual accommodation’ which<br />

that entails.<br />

Certainly, courts — were they to make themselves accessible to<br />

impoverished people and shape their doctrine and forms of reasoning<br />

and processes to fit the resources that impoverished people appearing<br />

before them can command — can and do act as spaces in or channels<br />

through which the impoverished can engage in the kind of political<br />

action I refer to here and work in other ways to support the political<br />

struggle against poverty. 34 I do not wish to discount that. But often,<br />

in the very act of protecting or advancing the interests of the<br />

impoverished, courts enforcing socio-economic rights work to erode<br />

the capacity for such political action. This can happen in any of the<br />

ways I mention above, but for the moment I will focus on one such<br />

way.<br />

Thomas Ross, writing about US welfare rights jurisprudence, has<br />

pointed out how US courts in their judgments often use and so confirm<br />

certain rhetorical strategies that are used by participants in the<br />

political discourse around poverty and need to depoliticise that<br />

debate and render democratic political contestation around it<br />

impossible. So, for example, he shows how courts have in their<br />

judgments confirmed descriptions of the impoverished as somehow<br />

themselves responsible for their plight; or descriptions of problems of<br />

33 E Pieterse & M van Donk ‘The politics of socio-economic rights in South Africa. Ten<br />

34<br />

years after apartheid’ (2004) 5:5 Economic and Social Rights Review 12 13.<br />

Roux (n 14 above) 10-61.


Reply - Danie Brand 105<br />

poverty as attributable to natural causes outside the control of the<br />

state or society. 35 What these rhetorical tropes have in common for<br />

Ross is that they are used to mask complicity and justify inaction in<br />

the face of poverty. For example: political actors attribute<br />

deprivation to the personality traits of impoverished people so that<br />

the complicity of the legal and political system in creating poverty can<br />

be obscured. Challenges to the status quo can thereby be avoided and<br />

the positions of the relatively affluent can likewise be justified. So it<br />

becomes the fault of impoverished people themselves that they are<br />

poor and they, and no one else, are the ones who can do something<br />

about it. 36<br />

Courts use these rhetorical strategies for the same purposes. They<br />

are invoked most often in the course of assertions of the so-called<br />

‘judicial can’t’ 37 — when courts seek to justify their decision not to<br />

decide a particular matter or issue. An unfortunate by-product of<br />

their invocation, both in the political discourse and by courts, is that<br />

their use de-politicises: The effect of personalising the causes of<br />

poverty or attributing them to other causes outside the control of<br />

society is also to place them outside the realm of political<br />

contestation. Political engagement with them becomes futile. 38<br />

Our Constitutional Court’s engagement with socio-economic<br />

rights has shown invocation by the Court of such depoliticising<br />

rhetorical tropes. The ‘judicial can’t’ most often invoked by the Court<br />

in socio-economic rights cases has been the bogeyman of separation<br />

of powers. 39 A central theme of the Court’s socio-economic rights<br />

jurisprudence has been its efforts to develop a suitable theory of<br />

deference so as to avoid intruding unduly into the spheres of power of<br />

the legislature and the executive (and the state administration). The<br />

Court has, in <strong>this</strong> respect, struggled with basic questions such as<br />

which kinds of issues it is competent to engage with at all, what its<br />

standard of scrutiny should be where it does engage with the issues,<br />

and what the scope of its power is to provide relief.<br />

What is interesting is the basis upon which the Court has sought to<br />

justify the choices it has made in <strong>this</strong> regard. It has relied in the first<br />

place on ‘institutional capacity’ arguments — its perceived lack of the<br />

requisite technical expertise and institutional capacity properly to<br />

engage with the issues. The Court has utilised these institutional<br />

capacity arguments to justify its choice not to decide a particular<br />

35<br />

Ross (n 30 above) 1502 - 1509.<br />

36 Ross (n 30 above) 1510.<br />

37 R Cover Justice accused: Anti-slavery and the judiciary process (1975) 119-120.<br />

38<br />

See in <strong>this</strong> respect, in general, Fraser (n 18 above).<br />

39 Roux (n 14 above) 10-58.


106 Chapter 7<br />

question raised in the course of socio-economic rights litigation; 40 to<br />

reject the ‘minimum core content’ approach to deciding claims for<br />

access to basic resources; 41 and to justify its adoption of what it has<br />

called a ‘restrained role’ in reviewing state conduct in light of socioeconomic<br />

rights (as embodied in its reasonableness review<br />

approach.) 42<br />

The Court, when it employs <strong>this</strong> rhetoric, enters into an obviously<br />

depoliticising discourse and so erodes capacity for democratic<br />

political action. It describes the relevant issues as ‘technical<br />

problems for managers and planners ... in contradistinction to<br />

political matters.’ 43 However, it cannot be denied that the Court is,<br />

quite often, as institutionally constrained as it claims to be and that<br />

depoliticisation on that basis alone is to some extent inevitable.<br />

What does make the Court’s use of <strong>this</strong> depoliticising trope<br />

problematic is not so much the fact that it defers, but that to which<br />

it defers. In justifying the self-limitation of its powers of review and<br />

remedy the Court has also relied on another set of arguments:<br />

‘constitutional comity’ arguments. When it declines to decide a<br />

particular issue, or apply a stringent standard of scrutiny, or impose<br />

an intrusive order, it defers not only to the complexity of the issues<br />

at hand. It also, more importantly, defers to the other branches of<br />

government on the understanding that they are, in the context of<br />

institutional spheres of power, the appropriate fora to decide them. 44<br />

Certainly, at the heart of the Court’s concern with constitutional<br />

comity in its engagement with socio-economic rights is a concern for<br />

democracy. The Court defers to the other branches in order to<br />

demonstrate respect for the democratic will of which they are the<br />

repositories. 45 But the conception of democracy that underlies <strong>this</strong><br />

concern is, again, a peculiarly limited one: it is the kind of<br />

‘institutional’ understanding of democracy that I referred to above.<br />

Democracy is equated with, and reduced, to the institutions intended<br />

to give effect to it and occurs only within those institutions. This<br />

understanding stands in contrast to an understanding of democracy as<br />

a certain mode of political action or a culture that takes place not<br />

only in the democratic institutions of the official governmental<br />

40<br />

See eg Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 5 SA 721 (CC), 2002<br />

41<br />

10 BCLR 1033 (CC) para 128.<br />

Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 1 SA 46 (CC), 2000<br />

42<br />

11 BCLR 1169 (CC) para 33; TAC (n 40 above) para 37.<br />

TAC (n 40 above) para 38. See also the Court’s justification for the lenient<br />

standard of scrutiny adopted in Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-<br />

Natal 1998 1 SA 765 (CC), 1997 12 BCLR 1696 (CC) para 29.<br />

43 Fraser (n 18 above) 299.<br />

44 See eg Soobramoney (n 42 above) para 29; Grootboom (n 41 above) para 41; and<br />

45<br />

TAC (n 40 above) paras 96-114 & 129-133.<br />

Roux (n 14 above) 10-58.


Reply - Danie Brand 107<br />

system, but also outside of it, in a range of different ‘discursive<br />

arenas’ and ‘publics’. 46<br />

In <strong>this</strong> light it becomes clear that the rhetorical strategies that<br />

the Court employs to justify its choices with respect to self-limitation<br />

of its powers operate to depoliticise issues of poverty, need and social<br />

provisioning of the State in two respects. First, and most obviously,<br />

the Court’s rhetoric depoliticises in that it describes the issues in<br />

question as technical rather than political in nature. As pointed out<br />

above, <strong>this</strong> move can, to some extent, be viewed as inevitable.<br />

However, second, the Court’s rhetoric depoliticises in that it<br />

relegates the discourse about these issues, even in their technical<br />

sense, wholly to the formally constituted political branches of<br />

government ‘whose responsibility [and right] it is to deal with such<br />

matters’. 47 The message to impoverished people is therefore not only<br />

that the issues that they deal with are difficult ones in a technical<br />

sense, requiring of them sustained, informed engagement 48 which<br />

they, like the Court, might not have the capacity for. It is also that<br />

the issues are, as with the Court, simply not their business. The<br />

Court’s rhetoric casts them not as active participants in the process<br />

of interpretation of their needs, engaged in political action as<br />

Pieterse and Van Donk would want them to be, but as the passive<br />

recipients of services. 49 In <strong>this</strong> way their capacity for democratic<br />

political action is undermined — principally, I would say because the<br />

Court’s rhetoric determines the way in which the state will in future<br />

interact with them.<br />

Now Theunis, if asked why he did not engage <strong>this</strong> broader<br />

description of the tension between rights and democracy might<br />

certainly again answer that he was writing only one chapter and not<br />

a whole book. But, as with the first problem I raised in section 2<br />

above, I believe that his failure to do so constitutes another important<br />

opportunity missed. Various commentators have not only identified in<br />

the Court’s jurisprudence these forms of the tension, but have also<br />

suggested ways in which the court, by adapting its forms of reasoning,<br />

ways of working and its doctrine, could better manage these aspects<br />

of the tension than it does: Karl Klare, for example, has advocated<br />

judicial candour about the presence of personal choice in judicial<br />

interpretation to render judges more accountable for the decisions<br />

they make; 50 Henk Botha has pointed to the fashioning and use of<br />

flexible standards rather than bright line rules as a way of avoiding<br />

46<br />

Fraser (n 18 above) 297.<br />

47 Soobramoney (n 42 above) para 29.<br />

48 Wilson (n 27 above) 447.<br />

49<br />

Habermas (n 26 above) 210; see also Fraser (n 18 above) 307.<br />

50 Klare (n 19 above) 164.


108 Chapter 7<br />

the depoliticising finality of judicial decisions. 51 I have myself<br />

identified in the Court’s socio-economic rights jurisprudence ways in<br />

which the Court, for example by rewarding in its judgments political<br />

engagement and punishing undemocratic conduct, can foster the<br />

democratic capacity of the impoverished and so counteract the<br />

depoliticising tendencies in its work. 52<br />

Against <strong>this</strong> background the Constitutional Court’s fixation with<br />

one aspect of the tension between rights and democracy that I briefly<br />

outlined above in the context of its socio-economic rights<br />

jurisprudence does not only erode democracy because it works to<br />

depoliticise the issues the Court engages with as described. It erodes<br />

democracy also because it means that the Court, despite an extensive<br />

and nuanced body of literature alerting them to the problem, 53 takes<br />

virtually no account of the variety of other ways in which their work<br />

potentially stands in tension to democracy and as a result also takes<br />

no account of the myriad ways in which they can alleviate the<br />

problem. Had Theunis engaged them on <strong>this</strong> point in his chapter, they<br />

would have been challenged anew to address it in some way.<br />

3 Conclusion<br />

It remains for me to ask one more question — well, perhaps two, the<br />

answer to the first implying the second. Why is it that Theunis fails to<br />

engage in his chapter the two issues I outline above? In the two<br />

preceding sections I already suggested an answer to <strong>this</strong> question —<br />

Theunis might say simply that he was not writing a book but only one<br />

chapter of a book. But, given the thoroughness and the academic<br />

rigour that I know Theunis for, I don’t think such academic lassitude<br />

is the explanation. What Theunis would probably say — if I could be so<br />

bold as to suggest what his answer would be — is that it was simply<br />

not his brief or his purpose to address these two questions; that his<br />

brief and his purpose in his CLoSA chapter and consequently in <strong>this</strong><br />

briefer essay was, against the background of a survey of political<br />

science literature and on the basis of a close reading of the<br />

constitutional text and the case law, to describe — and only to<br />

describe — the principle of democracy in South African constitutional<br />

law. If that were indeed Theunis’ answer, it would raise for me the<br />

second and my final question — is such a project viable, and more<br />

importantly, is it desirable?<br />

Why do I ask <strong>this</strong>? Three things strike me about the nature of<br />

Theunis’ chapter here and about the corresponding section in his<br />

51 Botha (n 28 above).<br />

52<br />

Brand (n 30 above) 33-36.<br />

53 See eg Klare (n 19 above); Botha (n 28 above).


Reply - Danie Brand 109<br />

CLoSA chapter. 54 The first has to do with his basic approach. Theunis<br />

does not set out to write about democracy and constitutional law —<br />

had he done so, he would have had to write about democracy as<br />

something certainly inside of, but also outside of, apart from the Final<br />

Constitution and the law, and he would have had to address more<br />

thoroughly the non-institutional aspects of the relationship between<br />

democracy and the law. Theunis writes about ‘[t]he principle of<br />

democracy in South African constitutional law’ (my emphasis). As<br />

Theunis explains in a footnote in the section in his CLoSA chapter that<br />

corresponds to his chapter here, his approach in <strong>this</strong> respect is a<br />

Dworkinian one 55 — he writes about democracy as a ‘legal standard’,<br />

intrinsic to the law and therefore capable of determination from a<br />

close reading of the legal material alone. 56 Elsewhere, he makes <strong>this</strong><br />

explicit, writing that ‘the principle of democracy is a function of the<br />

constitutional text, the cases decided to date and the cases yet to be<br />

decided.’ 57<br />

The second is the virtual absence of engagement with anything<br />

other than the constitutional text and the case law in Theunis’<br />

chapter here and in the section corresponding to it in his CLoSA<br />

chapter. Apart from a few references for obvious reasons to his own<br />

chapter in CLoSA, Theunis engages in his chapter here only once with<br />

one South African work that deals with democracy in constitutional<br />

law: Iain Currie and Johan de Waal’s The bill of rights handbook. 58<br />

Apart from that there are only two further references to scholarly<br />

work of any kind. 59 For the rest his references are solely to the<br />

54 Theunis’ chapter here is drawn almost wholesale, with some cosmetic changes,<br />

from § 10.5 in his CLoSA chapter on democracy. See Roux (n 14 above) 10-62 – 10-<br />

77.<br />

55 In saying <strong>this</strong> I do not mean that Theunis is in general Dworkinian in approach —<br />

judging from the other work of Theunis’ that I have had the privilege of reading I<br />

would describe him as a realist positivist, or a realist/pragmatist positivist in his<br />

own mould, precisely because of his usual practice of combining close analysis of<br />

the legal material with analysis of the institutional political context within which<br />

the law operates. Nevertheless, in <strong>this</strong> chapter he uses the term ‘principle’ in its<br />

Dworkinian sense.<br />

56<br />

Roux (n 14 above) 10-62, n 2.<br />

57 Roux (n 1 above) n 7.<br />

58 I Currie & J de Waal The bill of rights handbook 5 ed (2005). See Roux (n 1 above)<br />

n 7.<br />

59 One reference to Ronald Dworkin’s Taking rights seriously (1977) (Roux (n 1<br />

above) n 8) and one to Frank Michelman’s chapter on the rule of law in CLoSA - F<br />

Michelman ‘The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the Constitution’ in<br />

Woolman et al (n 14 above) Chapter 11 (Roux (n 1 above) n 14).


110 Chapter 7<br />

constitutional text and the case law. 60<br />

The third has to do with the absence of Theunis from his chapter.<br />

Reading Theunis’ chapter here reminds me of one of the most<br />

arresting moments of academic discussion I have witnessed. A few<br />

years ago I visited a colleague who was on a fellowship in London and<br />

attended with her a short conference at Birkbeck College, University<br />

of London at which the political philosopher Slavoj Žižek spoke. On<br />

the same panel as Žižek a young Italian scholar, whose name I have<br />

unfortunately forgotten, gave a wonderfully detailed and structured<br />

exposition of aspects of the work of Jacques Lacan. He had 21 points,<br />

if I remember correctly and started simply by saying ‘One ...’<br />

followed by an exposition of the first point, ‘Two ...’ and so on, until<br />

he concluded with ‘Twenty-one’ — a pure and perfect description.<br />

When he finished, Žižek turned his quite penetrating eyes on him and<br />

said: ‘Very good, very good. But where are you?’.<br />

Having read Theunis’ chapter I also want to ask him ‘But where<br />

are you?’. Throughout his chapter Theunis is very careful only to<br />

describe — he assiduously avoids expressing any opinion about the<br />

virtues or otherwise of the principle of constitutional law that he<br />

extracts from the constitutional text and from the various cases. In<br />

two instances Theunis does suggest possible criticism of the case law<br />

— with respect to the judgments in NNP and in UDM. 61 However, in<br />

only one of these instances is the criticism positively asserted — in the<br />

other instance Theunis merely hints at the possible criticism and then<br />

says that he will, if at all, engage with it in another forum. 62 If<br />

anything, these hints strengthen Theunis’ assertion of an objective<br />

empirical description — the suggestion seems to be that he can and<br />

will enter into critique on a normative basis in other fora, but <strong>this</strong><br />

forum is reserved for pure description only.<br />

Taken together, these three features of Theunis’ chapter leave his<br />

project here open to a quite specific reading — that it is a project of<br />

pure, neutral description of a legal standard, conducted on the basis<br />

of an empirically determinable and self-evident set of legal materials,<br />

the constitutional text and the cases. Now, any project of description<br />

60 I should be clear here about what I mean — I do not claim that Theunis as a<br />

general rule fails to engage scholarly work relevant to the topics he addresses in<br />

his writing, or even that he fails to engage scholarly work on democracy in his<br />

democracy chapter in CLoSA. In that chapter Theunis engages in an admirably<br />

exhaustive overview of political philosophy literature about democracy (albeit<br />

one with a particular philosophical slant, excluding various critical engagements<br />

with democracy). I do claim that where he turns to a description of the law he<br />

leaves out of account literature outside the constitutional text — that is as true of<br />

the section in his CLoSA chapter devoted to a description of the principle of<br />

democracy in South African constitutional law as it is of his chapter here.<br />

61<br />

See Roux (1 above) 84-85.<br />

62 As above.


Reply - Danie Brand 111<br />

of the legal standard of democracy in South African law is of course<br />

extremely valuable. As Stu Woolman tells us in his first chapter to <strong>this</strong><br />

volume, 63 the Constitutional Court has already once, in UDM, been<br />

allowed to escape having to give substantive content to the<br />

Constitution’s idea of democracy, because, on its version, no<br />

academic had as yet done the ‘grunt work’ 64 of providing a systematic<br />

description of that conception. 65 With Theunis having done the ‘grunt<br />

work’ now, it will not be able to use the same excuse again. But<br />

‘simple’ description — especially if it pretends at or unwittingly<br />

creates the impression of a neutral finding of the law — also has its<br />

limits and poses its own problems.<br />

We have it from Karl Klare that neutral and empirical description<br />

or interpretation of the law is impossible, and that attempts at such<br />

a project are fraught. Drawing on two decades of critical scholarship,<br />

Klare illustrated to South African scholars and lawyers already in 1996<br />

that any claim to the neutral, ‘pure’ description of law is, in the first<br />

place, false. Legal material is never self-evident, so that<br />

interpretation/description for him always involves choice — even if<br />

only choice as to what constitutes the relevant legal material, or what<br />

constitutes the field of enquiry — and that choice is always informed<br />

also by extra-legal materials and considerations. 66 Secondly, and<br />

more important here, Klare also illustrated the dangers of the<br />

pretence of objective, ‘purely legal’ interpretation or description of<br />

law: Such pretence masks and so insulates from interrogation the<br />

choice that is always there in interpretation. In <strong>this</strong> way democratic<br />

engagement with the interpretation or description of the law that<br />

arises is discouraged. 67 To be true, Klare’s warning was directed in<br />

particular at judges, certainly in part because of the peculiar<br />

rhetorical power that their pronouncements and their processes of<br />

reasoning hold. We know that our work as academics is taken nowhere<br />

near as seriously and that we certainly do not, as judges do, ‘model<br />

intellectual and institutional practices appropriate to a culture of<br />

[democracy]’ to any audience but ourselves. 68 Nevertheless, in a book<br />

entitled Constitutional conversations and with respect to a chapter in<br />

it on democracy, can I be forgiven for asking: If indeed Theunis aims<br />

at providing a ‘pure’ description of the principle of democracy in<br />

South African constitutional law in his chapter here, how democratic<br />

is his writing in <strong>this</strong> respect?<br />

63<br />

S Woolman ‘The South African constitution as the last great modernist project’ in<br />

64<br />

S Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations (2008) 25.<br />

To use the phrase Stu Woolman often employs when describing in part the task he<br />

sets authors in CLoSA.<br />

65 UDM (n 3 above) para 25.<br />

66 Klare (n 19 above) 162-163.<br />

67<br />

Klare (n 19 above) 164.<br />

68 Klare (n 19 above) 147.


8<br />

TRUE<br />

IN THEORY, TRUE<br />

IN PRACTICE: WHY<br />

DIRECT APPLICATION<br />

STILL MATTERS<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

No man has the right to pretend that he is practically expert in a science<br />

and yet show contempt for theory without revealing that he is an<br />

ignoramus in his field. Apparently such a man believes that he can get<br />

further than he can by using theory, by groping about in experience on<br />

experiments without developing certain principles which constitute<br />

what I call theory and without having thought out an integrated<br />

approach to his work which, when it is developed according to method,<br />

is called a system.<br />

...<br />

Nowhere do people engage in practical pursuits speak with more<br />

pretentiousness derogatively of theory and neglecting all pure rational<br />

principles, than on the question of what is required for a good<br />

constitution. This is because a legal constitution that has existed for a<br />

long time accustoms people to live by its rule by and by and makes them<br />

inclined to evaluate their happiness as well as their rights in light of the<br />

conditions under which everything has been quietly going forward. Men<br />

fail to do the opposite; namely, to evaluate the existing constitution<br />

according to [standards] provided by reason in regard to happiness and<br />

right. As a result, men prefer <strong>this</strong> passive state to the dangerous task of<br />

seeking a better one. 1<br />

1 I Kant ‘Concerning the common saying: This may be true in theory, but does not<br />

apply in practice’ in I Kant Basic writings of Immanuel Kant trans CJ Freidrich<br />

(1793) 8:276 and 8:305-306.<br />

113


114 Chapter 8<br />

Application<br />

8(1) The Bill of Rights applies to all law, and binds the legislature, the<br />

executive, the judiciary and all organs of state.<br />

(2) A provision of the Bill of Rights binds a natural or a juristic person if,<br />

and to the extent that, it is applicable, taking into account the nature of<br />

the right and the nature of any duty imposed by the right.<br />

(3) When applying a provision of the Bill of Rights to a natural or juristic<br />

person in terms of subsection (2), a court (a) in order to give effect to a<br />

right in the Bill, must apply, or if necessary develop, the common law to<br />

the extent that legislation does not give effect to that right; and (b) may<br />

develop rules of the common law to limit the right, provided that the<br />

limitation is in accordance with section 36(1).<br />

(4) A juristic person is entitled to the rights in the Bill of Rights to the<br />

extent required by the nature of the rights and the nature of that<br />

juristic person.<br />

1 Introduction<br />

When jurists, lawyers and academics say they wish to talk about the<br />

application of the Bill of Rights under the Final Constitution, by and<br />

large, they have a single vexed question in mind: Upon whom do the<br />

burdens of the Bill of Rights fall? That is, they want to know (or they<br />

want to tell us), as a general matter, which kinds of persons or parties<br />

may have the substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights enforced<br />

against them, what kinds of laws attract meaningful scrutiny and what<br />

conditions or circumstances must obtain for a substantive provision to<br />

be said to apply to a given dispute.<br />

My answer to <strong>this</strong> vexed and complicated question takes the<br />

following form. I rehearse briefly the terms and the outcome of the<br />

application debate under the Interim Constitution. I do so because<br />

past is, quite obviously, prologue: The drafters of the Final<br />

Constitution spoke directly to concerns about the text of the Interim<br />

Constitution; the Constitutional Court accepted the invitation of the<br />

drafters of the Final Constitution to revisit — and to recast — the<br />

application doctrine developed under the Interim Constitution. In<br />

addition to an abbreviated analysis of the Court’s application doctrine<br />

under the Interim Constitution, <strong>this</strong> chapter contains an assessment<br />

of the general jurisprudential concerns that framed the initial debate<br />

and that recur, albeit in transmogrified form, under the Final<br />

Constitution.


Stu Woolman 115<br />

My subsequent approach to application under the Final<br />

Constitution warrants a few prefatory remarks. The treatment of<br />

‘burdens’ begins with the Constitutional Court’s articulation of the<br />

black letter law on application in Khumalo v Holomisa. 2 As we shall<br />

see, the Khumalo Court does not explain in any detail what the<br />

various parts of FC section 8 mean or how they are designed to work.<br />

This lack of transparency requires me to offer a good faith<br />

reconstruction of the application doctrine articulated by the Khumalo<br />

Court. This good faith reconstruction cannot be the last word on the<br />

application doctrine under the Final Constitution. Although the good<br />

faith reconstruction fleshes out the Khumalo Court’s conclusions in a<br />

manner that coheres with the judgment’s various textual and<br />

jurisprudential premises, even a reconstructed Khumalo is<br />

unsatisfactory and, ultimately, unredeemable.<br />

This chapter engages the good faith reconstruction in a number of<br />

different ways. It sets out six primary doctrinal objections to the<br />

Khumalo Court’s statement of the law. These six objections are<br />

grounded, to varying degrees, in conflicting statements by the<br />

Constitutional Court — as well as courts of more general jurisdiction<br />

— about what each of the subsections in FC section 8 and FC section<br />

39 should be understood to mean. This chapter offers a very brief<br />

account of a second body of black letter law: namely, what the courts<br />

have said the discrete subsections — FC sections 8(1), 8(2), 8(3) and<br />

39(2) — denote. (For lawyers, jurists and academics who wish to know<br />

in detail what the all of our courts have said about FC sections 8(1),<br />

8(2), 8(3) and 39(2), the Constitutional Law of South Africa chapter<br />

on ‘Application’ upon which I draw here offers a fairly exhaustive<br />

account.) 3 This black letter law governs subjects as diverse as the<br />

meaning of the term ‘all law’, the binding of the judiciary, the<br />

legislature, the executive and organs of state, how the common law<br />

is to be developed and transformed, the creation of new remedies<br />

under the Bill of Rights, as well as such doctrines as reading down,<br />

shared constitutional interpretation, stare decisis and objective<br />

normative value systems.<br />

In an ideal world, the general framework articulated in Khumalo<br />

would be internally (logically) consistent and would be externally<br />

consistent with (map directly on to) the courts’ express understanding<br />

of what the specific sections in FC section 8 and FC section 39 signify<br />

and the manifold doctrines they generate. In other words, Khumalo<br />

would provide the edifice, and other cases that had a bearing on our<br />

understanding of application would slot neatly into its structure. As<br />

we shall see, the dissonance created by the disjunction between the<br />

2 Khumalo v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 (CC), 2002 8 BCLR 771 (CC).<br />

3<br />

S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 31, available at www.westlaw.com.


116 Chapter 8<br />

black letter law on the general framework for application analysis and<br />

the black letter law on the meaning of its various textual components<br />

constitutes one of the primary grounds for rejecting the Court’s<br />

current application doctrine. In its stead, I offer a preferred reading<br />

that meets all of the doctrinal objections to Khumalo and,<br />

concomitantly, gives each of the constituent parts of the text, and the<br />

related doctrines they generate, a reading that fits the general<br />

framework for application. 4<br />

2 Application doctrine under the Interim Constitution<br />

The Constitutional Court answered the question of burdens under the<br />

Interim Constitution in Du Plessis & Others v De Klerk & Another. 5 The<br />

facts. The thumbnail sketch of Du Plessis that follows merely<br />

adumbrates the choices that the Constitutional Court had before it<br />

under the Interim Constitution and some of the arguments that the<br />

Constitutional Court once again engaged, at least tacitly, in Khumalo<br />

under the Final Constitution.<br />

According to the prevailing pre-Du Plessis discourse, the<br />

Constitutional Court had two options. It could take a vertical<br />

approach. On such a reading of the text, the Bill of Right’s substantive<br />

provisions engaged directly only legal relationships between the state<br />

and the individual. It could take a horizontal approach. On such a<br />

reading, all legal relationships between the state and the individual<br />

and all legal relationships between private persons would have been<br />

4 For those readers who wish to immerse themselves in some of the finer points of<br />

application doctrine, a detailed appendix in S Woolman ‘Application’ (n 3 above)<br />

at 31-132 — 31-168, takes stock of the most important interventions made by<br />

other commentators on <strong>this</strong> subject. These academic contributions ought not to<br />

be considered mere arcana. At their best, these arguments develop, in full,<br />

theories of application merely hinted at in judicial opinions and about which the<br />

text is, inevitably, mute. As to other points of entry into <strong>this</strong> debate, the full<br />

chapter offers the only available comprehensive account of the subject in the<br />

South African literature.<br />

5 1996 3 SA 850 (CC), 1996 5 BCLR 658 (CC). In 1993 the Pretoria News published a<br />

series of articles dealing with the supply of arms by South Africa to UNITA in<br />

Angola. The articles suggested that private air operators and airstrip owners —<br />

the plaintiffs — were aiding the Department of Foreign Affairs in fuelling the<br />

Angolan war. The plaintiffs instituted a defamation action in May 1993. The<br />

defendants filed pleas denying that the articles suggested wrongful conduct by<br />

the plaintiffs or defamed the plaintiffs. The defendants argued, in the<br />

alternative, that even if the articles were defamatory, they were published in the<br />

public interest. In October 1994 — after the Interim Constitution came into effect<br />

— the defendants asked to amend their plea in order to claim that the right of<br />

freedom of expression, IC sec 15, afforded them a new defence. The<br />

Constitutional Court held that the substantive provisions of Bill of Rights of the<br />

Interim Constitution were not, in general, capable of application to any legal<br />

relationship other than that between legislative or executive organs of state at all<br />

levels of government and natural or juristic persons. In particular, IC sec 15,<br />

freedom of expression, was not capable of application to any legal relationship<br />

other than that between persons and legislative or executive organs of the state<br />

at all levels of government and natural or juristic persons.


Stu Woolman 117<br />

subject to direct review for conformity with the specific substantive<br />

rights set out in IC Chapter 3. Despite <strong>this</strong> basic difference in<br />

orientation, every jurist, practitioner or academic interpreting the<br />

Interim Constitution was committed to the following three<br />

propositions. Statutes, when relied upon by the state, were subject<br />

to constitutional review. Statutes, when relied upon by a private<br />

party in a private dispute, were subject to constitutional review. The<br />

common law, when relied upon by the state, was subject to<br />

constitutional review. Moreover, almost every jurist, practitioner and<br />

academic agreed that the heart of the application debate was<br />

whether the common law, when relied upon by a private party in a<br />

private dispute, was subject to constitutional review.<br />

On <strong>this</strong> heart of the matter, the majority of the Constitutional<br />

Court in Du Plessis v De Klerk came firmly down on the side of<br />

verticality. The Du Plessis Court held that the substantive provisions<br />

of the Bill of Rights of the Interim Constitution applied only to law<br />

emanating from the legislature or the executive and to the conduct of<br />

these two branches of government. Driven by a ‘traditional’ view of<br />

what constitutions do, and bewitched by a text that ostensibly did not<br />

apply to all law or bind the judiciary, the Du Plessis Court endorsed a<br />

doctrine whose most notable feature was its insulation of commonlaw<br />

disputes between private parties from direct application of the<br />

specific substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights.<br />

The extended version of <strong>this</strong> chapter offers several demurrals to<br />

the Du Plessis doctrine. As three dissenting justices in Du Plessis<br />

noted, the text did not settle the debate. But it did lead the Du Plessis<br />

Court to the jurisprudentially untenable conclusion that while rules of<br />

common law that govern disputes between private parties are not<br />

subject to direct application of the specific substantive provisions of<br />

the Bill of Rights, (because constitutions traditionally do not apply to<br />

relations between private parties), rules in statutes or regulations<br />

that govern disputes between private parties are subject to direct<br />

application of the specific substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights.<br />

So the ‘fact’ that a legal dispute is between private parties would<br />

appear to be a necessary but not a sufficient condition for the Du<br />

Plessis Court’s conclusion.<br />

Indeed, it is hard to know whether it should be called a ‘condition’<br />

at all. I call the very logic of the Du Plessis Court into question<br />

because whether the law governing a dispute between private parties<br />

was subject to direct application under the Interim Constitution was<br />

entirely and fortuitously contingent upon the form the law took.<br />

Embedded in the Du Plessis Court’s differential treatment of these<br />

two bodies of law is the premise that the common law — unlike<br />

legislation — protects a private ordering of social life that is neutral<br />

between the interests of various social actors. That premise is false.


118 Chapter 8<br />

Moreover, abstention from constitutional review of common-law rules<br />

functions as a defence of deeply entrenched and radically<br />

inegalitarian distributions of wealth and power by immunising from<br />

review those rules of property, contract and delict that sustain those<br />

inegalitarian distributions. The differential treatment of the two<br />

bodies of law also rests on a traditional distinction between the public<br />

realm and the private realm. At a minimum, <strong>this</strong> distinction fails to<br />

recognise the extent to which the state structures all legal<br />

relationships. With the ineluctable erosion of the public-private<br />

divide, one of the last justifications for treating common law and<br />

legislation differently disintegrates as well. What we are left with is<br />

a doctrine that traditionally produces an incoherent body of decisions<br />

and that cannot explain why courts, perfectly capable of vindicating<br />

autonomy interests when asked to review statutory provisions<br />

governing private relationships for consistency with the Bill of Rights,<br />

prefer not to subject common-law rules governing private<br />

relationships to the same form of scrutiny. 6<br />

3 Application doctrine under the Final Constitution<br />

3.1 Black Letter Law<br />

Du Plessis effectively foreclosed debate on the direct application of<br />

the substantive provisions of the Interim Constitution’s Bill of Rights<br />

to rules of common law governing private disputes. The drafters of<br />

the Final Constitution, however, reconsidered the Interim<br />

Constitution’s provisional position on application. Unlike the Interim<br />

Constitution, the Final Constitution’s Bill of Rights points unequivocally<br />

toward a much broader conception of direct application: FC<br />

6 I have employed the terms verticality and horizontality above and shall continue<br />

to do so in <strong>this</strong> chapter where necessary. However, it seems fairly clear that these<br />

two terms have outlived their usefulness and that the current debate over<br />

application warrants a change in nomenclature. The post-Khumalo black letter<br />

law on application and the preferred reading of those same application provisions<br />

eschew any mention of verticality or horizontality. The debate over application of<br />

the Bill of Rights is now best characterised solely in terms of direct application<br />

and indirect application. Direct challenges describe instances in which the<br />

prescriptive content of at least one specific substantive provision of the Bill of<br />

Rights applies to the law or to the conduct at issue. Indirect challenges describe<br />

instances in which the prescriptive content of no specific provision of the Bill of<br />

Rights applies to the law or to conduct at issue. Indirect challenges rely, in terms<br />

of FC sec 39(2), upon the spirit, purport and objects of the entire Bill to interpret<br />

or to develop the law in order to settle the dispute before the court. (That is not<br />

to say that a specific right might not be relevant — say as value, but not as a rule<br />

— to an indirect challenge. I only claim that there must be a distinction with a<br />

difference between the direct application of a right and the relevance of a right<br />

to a more amorphous assessment of whether a rule of law remains in step with<br />

the general spirit of our constitutional order. See Minister of Home Affairs v<br />

National Institute for Crime Prevention 2005 3 SA 280 (CC), 2004 5 BCLR 445 (CC)<br />

(On the difference between how constitutional norms operate as values and how<br />

they operate as rules.))


Stu Woolman 119<br />

section 8(1) states that the Bill applies to ‘all law’ and binds ‘the<br />

judiciary’; FC section 8(2) states that the provisions of the Bill will<br />

bind private persons.<br />

In Khumalo, the Constitutional Court accepted the Final<br />

Constitution’s invitation to broaden its conception of the law and the<br />

relationships to which the substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights<br />

apply directly. The signal difference between Du Plessis and Khumalo<br />

is that the Khumalo Court reads FC section 8(2) to mean that some of<br />

the specific provisions of the Bill of Rights will apply directly to some<br />

disputes between private parties some of the time.<br />

The black letter law on application in terms of Khumalo takes the<br />

following form.<br />

FC section 8(1) stands for the following two propositions:<br />

• All law governing disputes between the state and natural persons or<br />

juristic persons is subject to the direct application of the Bill of<br />

Rights.<br />

• All state conduct that gives rise to disputes between the state and<br />

natural persons or juristic persons is likewise subject to the direct<br />

application of the Bill of Rights.<br />

FC section 8(2) stands for the following proposition:<br />

Disputes between natural persons and/or juristic persons may be subject<br />

to the direct application of the Bill of Rights, if the specific right<br />

asserted is deemed to apply.<br />

FC section 8(3) stands for the following proposition:<br />

Where direct application of the right asserted occurs in terms of FC<br />

section 8(2), and the court further finds a non-justifiable abridgment of<br />

that right, then the court must develop the law in a manner that gives<br />

adequate effect to the right infringed. 7<br />

3.2 Good faith reconstruction of Khumalo<br />

For reasons the opinion does not adequately explain, the Khumalo<br />

Court chose to ignore two of FC section 8(1)’s injunctions: that the Bill<br />

7<br />

FC sec 39(2), although not engaged expressly in Khumalo, stands, under a<br />

secondary body of black letter law, for the following propositions: (1) Where an<br />

asserted right is, under FC sec 8(2), deemed not to apply directly to a dispute<br />

between private parties, the court may still develop the common law or interpret<br />

the apposite provision of legislation in light of the more general objects of the Bill<br />

of Rights. (2) Even where a right is asserted directly, the court may still speak as<br />

if a finding of inconsistency or invalidity requires that a new rule of common law<br />

be developed in terms of FC sec 39(2).


120 Chapter 8<br />

of Rights applies to ‘all law’ and that the Bill of Rights binds ‘the<br />

judiciary’. One might have thought that such an explanation was<br />

warranted, given that it was precisely the absence of these phrases —<br />

‘all law’ and ‘binds the judiciary’ — in a comparable section of the<br />

Interim Constitution that led the Du Plessis Court to reach the<br />

conclusion that the Interim Constitution’s Bill of Rights did not apply<br />

directly to disputes between private parties governed by the common<br />

law. The Khumalo Court claims instead that had it given FC section<br />

8(1) a gloss that ensured that the substantive provisions of the Bill of<br />

Rights applied to all law-governed disputes between private parties —<br />

regardless of the provenance of the law — it would have rendered FC<br />

section 8(3) meaningless. That particular assertion is unfounded — or<br />

at the very least radically under-theorised.<br />

While it is quite easy to poke holes in the gossamer thin fabric of<br />

Khumalo, such victories, pyrrhic as they are, do not advance<br />

understanding; thus the need for a good faith reconstruction of<br />

Khumalo. This good faith reconstruction fleshes out the Khumalo<br />

Court’s conclusions in a manner that simultaneously coheres with its<br />

jurisprudential commitments, avoids surplusage in so far as the<br />

Court’s pre-commitments permit, and satisfies basic considerations of<br />

textual plausibility and naturalness. The good faith reconstruction<br />

begins with a perfectly understandable and workable distinction<br />

between a constitutional norm’s range of application and that same<br />

norm’s prescriptive content. The ‘range of application’ speaks to FC<br />

section 8(1)’s commitment to ensuring that each and every genus of<br />

law is at least formally subject to the substantive provisions of the Bill<br />

of Rights. The ‘prescriptive content’ speaks both to FC section 8(2)’s<br />

invitation to apply the substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights to<br />

disputes between private parties and to the interpretative exercise<br />

required to determine whether a given substantive provision of the<br />

Bill is meant to engage the kind of dispute before the court. However,<br />

even <strong>this</strong> effort to put Khumalo on the most solid footing possible<br />

comes up short in six significant ways.<br />

3.3 The critique of the black letter law & the good faith<br />

reconstruction<br />

The Khumalo Court quite consciously crosses over the public-private<br />

divide. The text of the Final Constitution left it little choice. But<br />

Khumalo’s one step forward is followed by two steps back. Whereas<br />

all disputes between the state and an individual are subject to the<br />

direct application of the Bill of Rights under the Final Constitution,<br />

Khumalo tells us that only some disputes between private parties will<br />

be subject to some of the provisions of the Bill of Rights. This revised<br />

public-private distinction in application jurisprudence creates the<br />

following anomaly.


Stu Woolman 121<br />

In Du Plessis, the traditional view of constitutional review was<br />

used to suppress direct application of the Bill of Rights with respect<br />

to disputes between private parties governed by the common law. In<br />

Khumalo, the new view of constitutional review is used to defer — and<br />

potentially suppress — direct application of the Bill of Rights with<br />

respect to all disputes between private parties. Here’s the rub. Direct<br />

application is deferred — and by that I simply mean turned into a<br />

question of interpretation — with respect to all disputes between<br />

private parties. It matters not whether the law governing disputes<br />

between private parties is grounded in statute, subordinate<br />

legislation, regulation, common law or customary law. Put slightly<br />

differently, whereas the Interim Constitution’s Bill of Rights was<br />

understood to apply directly, and unequivocally, to legislation that<br />

governed private disputes, the Final Constitution’s Bill of Rights does<br />

not. Less law is subject to the direct unqualified application of the Bill<br />

of Rights under the Khumalo Court’s reading of the Final Constitution<br />

than it was under the Du Plessis Court’s reading of the Interim<br />

Constitution.<br />

Doctrinal tension generates a second objection. The<br />

Constitutional Court has constructed a powerful set of doctrines in<br />

which (1) every exercise of state power is subject to constitutional<br />

review and (2) every law is subject to the objective theory of<br />

unconstitutionality. Much is rightly made of the Constitutional Court’s<br />

bold assertion in Fedsure, Pharmaceutical Manufacturers and their<br />

progeny that all law derives its force from the basic law — the Final<br />

Constitution — and that all law, and all conduct sourced in the law,<br />

must, as a logical matter, be consistent with the basic law. 8 Despite<br />

the first requirement — and despite the fact that FC section 8(1)<br />

applies to all law and binds the legislature, the executive and the<br />

judiciary — primary legislation or subordinate legislation that governs<br />

a dispute between private persons will not necessarily be subject to<br />

the direct application of the Bill of Rights. Those same provisions in<br />

legislation or subordinate legislation would, however, automatically<br />

be subject to the direct application of the provisions of Bill of Rights<br />

if they were invoked by an individual in a dispute with the State.<br />

The absurdity of <strong>this</strong> distinction is brought into even sharper relief<br />

by the Court’s own doctrine of objective unconstitutionality. (The<br />

relative desuetude of <strong>this</strong> doctrine is offset by the fact that it has, as<br />

8 Fedsure Life Assurance Ltd & Others v Greater Johannesburg Transitional<br />

Metropolitan Council & Others 1999 1 SA 374 (CC), 1998 12 BCLR 1458 (CC);<br />

Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA: In Re Ex Parte President of The<br />

Republic of South Africa 2000 2 SA 674 (CC), 2000 (3) BCLR 241 (CC).


122 Chapter 8<br />

yet, not been repudiated by the Constitutional Court.) 9 In its most<br />

general form, the doctrine holds that the validity or the invalidity of<br />

any given law is in no way contingent upon the parties before the<br />

Court in a particular matter. If a provision of legislation would be<br />

deemed to be unconstitutional when invoked by an individual in a<br />

dispute between the State and an individual, then it must likewise be<br />

unconstitutional when invoked by an individual in a dispute between<br />

that individual and another individual. (Or to make the reach of the<br />

doctrine even clearer: a challenge to a provision of legislation will be<br />

deemed to be unconstitutional if it is found to violate a specific<br />

substantive constitutional right — even if the plaintiff herself will not<br />

benefit from the finding and even if the factual predicate that<br />

grounds the court’s finding of unconstitutionality is different from the<br />

factual predicate upon which the plaintiff is grounded.) However, the<br />

Court’s differentiation between FC section 8(1) disputes that are<br />

invariably subject to the direct application of the Bill of Rights and FC<br />

section 8(2) disputes that are not invariably subject to the direct<br />

application of the Bill of Rights is logically incompatible with the<br />

doctrine of objective unconstitutionality. The Khumalo application<br />

doctrine relies upon the ability to distinguish constitutional cases —<br />

and thus the constitutionality of laws — upon the basis of the parties<br />

before the court. The doctrine of objective unconstitutionality denies<br />

the ability to distinguish constitutional cases — and thus the<br />

constitutionality of laws — upon the basis of the parties before the<br />

court. This contradiction is a direct consequence of the Khumalo<br />

Court’s refusal to give the term ‘all law’ in FC section 8(1) its most<br />

obvious construction and the Court’s preference for making FC<br />

section 8(2) the engine that drives the analysis of all disputes between<br />

private parties. Not even the good faith reconstruction of Khumalo<br />

can meet <strong>this</strong> second objection.<br />

The third objection flows from the Khumalo Court’s refusal to say<br />

anything about FC section 8(1)’s binding of the judiciary. Perhaps the<br />

most damning consequence of <strong>this</strong> structured silence is that it offends<br />

a canon of constitutional interpretation relied upon by Justice<br />

O’Regan in Khumalo itself: ‘We cannot adopt an interpretation which<br />

would render a provision of the Constitution to be without any<br />

apparent purpose.’ 10 Not only does Justice O’Regan refuse to give the<br />

provision ‘any apparent purpose’, we cannot, even on the good faith<br />

reconstruction, give it any apparent purpose. The good faith<br />

reconstruction gains its traction through a distinction between a<br />

9 See Ingledew v Financial Services Board: In re Financial Services Board v Van der<br />

Merwe & Another 2003 4 SA 584 (CC), 2003 8 BCLR 825 (CC) at para 20 (‘This<br />

court has adopted the doctrine of objective constitutional invalidity.’) See also De<br />

Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions, Witwatersrand Local Division 2004 1 SA<br />

406 (CC), 2003 12 BCLR 1333 (CC) (confirms continued validity of doctrine).<br />

10 Khumalo (n 2 above) para 32.


Stu Woolman 123<br />

constitutional norm’s range of application and that same norm’s<br />

prescriptive content. That creates the interpretational space to argue<br />

that while FC section 8(1) speaks to each specific constitutional<br />

norm’s range of application — and does not distinguish one genus of<br />

law from another — FC section 8(2) speaks to the prescriptive content<br />

of each specific constitutional norm and directs us to consider<br />

whether that prescriptive content ought to be understood to govern<br />

the private conduct of the private parties that constitutes the<br />

gravamen of the complaint. This good faith reconstruction does no<br />

work with respect to the phrase ‘binds the judiciary’ because the<br />

distinction between ‘range’ and ‘prescriptive content’ engages the<br />

relationship between constitutional norms and ordinary law. It does<br />

not speak to the provenance of a given law. The reason it cannot be<br />

recast in a manner that speaks to the differing concerns of FC section<br />

8(1) and FC section 8(2) is that FC section 8(2) does not concern itself<br />

with our different lawmaking institutions — legislative, executive or<br />

judicial. What is left? A weak reading in which the judiciary is bound<br />

— not in terms of the ‘law’ it makes — but purely in terms of its<br />

‘conduct’ (or ‘non-law-making conduct’). It seems to me to defy both<br />

logic and common sense to argue that when FC section 8(1) binds the<br />

legislature and the judiciary, it means to bind the actions of<br />

legislators or judges solely in their personal capacity. When we bind<br />

the legislature, we must bind both the law it makes and the non-lawmaking<br />

actions it takes. The text offers no reason to treat the<br />

judiciary any differently. We certainly want state actors — legislators<br />

and judges alike — to care about the manner in which they comport<br />

themselves. But we care primarily about the laws that they make that<br />

govern our society as whole. But that is not what Khumalo says, nor<br />

can it be reconstructed in such a manner as to say so.<br />

The fourth objection to Khumalo’s construction of FC section 8<br />

turns on the style of the argument. In short, before Justice O’Regan<br />

decides whether to engage the applicant’s exception to the action in<br />

defamation in terms of freedom of expression, she has already<br />

concluded: (a) that the law of defamation is in pretty good shape<br />

post-Bogoshi; 11 (b) that freedom of expression is important but not<br />

central to an open and democratic society; and (c) that dignity —<br />

especially as viewed through the lens of reputation — is of paramount<br />

concern. Only after having reached these conclusions does Justice<br />

O’Regan decide that <strong>this</strong> matter warrants direct application of<br />

freedom of expression to the common law of defamation in a dispute<br />

between private parties.<br />

Based upon the Court’s own jurisprudence and our good faith<br />

reconstruction of Khumalo, a court should first decide whether the<br />

11 National Media Ltd v Bogoshi 1998 4 SA 1196 (SCA), 1999 1 BCLR 1 (SCA).


124 Chapter 8<br />

specific substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights apply to the dispute<br />

before the court. If, as in Khumalo, the court determines that<br />

freedom of expression applies directly, then the generally accepted<br />

approach to rights analysis has us begin with a determination of the<br />

scope of freedom of expression and follows with an assessment of<br />

whether the law of defamation constitutes a prima facie infringement<br />

of that right. In Khumalo, it would most certainly have been found to<br />

be such. The second question is whether the law of defamation — as<br />

currently constructed — is a justifiable limitation of the right to<br />

freedom of expression. Instead, the judgment looks, in manner of<br />

delivery, much like the kind of judgment in which, under FC section<br />

39(2), the common law is developed via indirect application of the Bill<br />

of Rights. The style of the judgment suggests that the Khumalo Court<br />

considers it relatively unimportant to engage <strong>this</strong> dispute as if, in<br />

fact, direct application takes place. Or more accurately, by packaging<br />

Khumalo as if it were simply a common law judgment, the Khumalo<br />

Court intimates that the difference between direct application and<br />

indirect application of the Bill of Rights is minimal, if not nonexistent.<br />

I might be inclined to accept <strong>this</strong> elision of the analytical<br />

processes required by FC section 8 and FC section 39(2) were it not<br />

for the fact that the Supreme Court of Appeal and the Constitutional<br />

Court have handed down judgments regarding constitutional<br />

jurisdiction, stare decisis and indirect application under FC section<br />

39(2) that manifest a clear desire not to disturb settled bodies of<br />

common law precedent and that cannot help but immunise a<br />

substantial body of apartheid-era decisions from reconsideration by<br />

lower courts. 12 This claim requires some amplification.<br />

Leaving aside the problem of surplusage raised by our courts’<br />

occasional interchangeable use of FC section 8 and FC section 39(2),<br />

the Supreme Court of Appeal in Afrox, extending the reasoning of the<br />

Constitutional Court in Walters, has held that at least one critical<br />

difference exists between direct application under FC section 8 and<br />

12 The cosmology of common law jurisdictions is such that some lawyers express<br />

discomfort with the notion that a common law rule found inconsistent with the<br />

Final Constitution could occasion a finding of invalidity. But that locution is, in<br />

fact, endorsed by the Constitutional Court. See National Coalition for Gay and<br />

Lesbian Equality & Another v Minister of Justice & Others 1999 1 SA 6 (CC), 1998<br />

12 BCLR 1517 (CC), 1998 2 SACR 556 (CC) para 73 (Court declares ‘common-law<br />

offence of sodomy ... inconsistent with the 1996 Constitution and invalid.’) See<br />

also Shabalala v Attorney General, Transvaal 1996 1 SA 725 (CC), 1995 12 BCLR<br />

1593 (CC), 1995 2 SACR 761 (CC); S v Thebus 2003 (6) SA 505 (CC), 2003 10 BCLR<br />

1100 (CC), 2003 2 SACR 319 (CC) (Court notes that a finding of inconsistency with<br />

respect to common law may occasion an order that goes beyond invalidity to<br />

develop a new rule of law.)


Stu Woolman 125<br />

indirect application under FC section 39(2). 13 A High Court may revisit<br />

pre-constitutional Appellate Division precedent only where a party<br />

has a colourable claim grounded in the direct application of a<br />

substantive provision of the Bill of Rights. High Courts may not alter<br />

existing common law precedent (whether pre-constitutional or postconstitutional)<br />

through indirect application of FC section 39(2). (The<br />

rest of our appellate courts’ novel doctrine of constitutional stare<br />

decisis further constrains the High Courts’ constitutional jurisdiction.)<br />

What happens when our appellate courts’ marry <strong>this</strong> restrictive<br />

doctrine of stare decisis to an incrementalist gloss on indirect<br />

application in terms of FC section 39(2)? It spawns an application<br />

doctrine that effectively disables the High Court from undertaking<br />

meaningful constitutional review of existing common law precedent<br />

(as well as all other constructions of law) and thereby protects<br />

‘traditional’ conceptions of law and existing legal hierarchies. This<br />

observation about the manner in which our existing array of<br />

application, stare decisis and constitutional jurisdiction doctrines<br />

conspire to blunt the transformative potential of the basic law is one<br />

of the strongest rejoinders to those jurists and commentators who<br />

have suggested that whether one relies upon FC section 8 (1), or FC<br />

section 8(2) or FC section 39(2), the song remains the same: How<br />

should the law governing a dispute be developed, re-formulated or reinterpreted?<br />

A series of related objections flows from a conflation of the<br />

purpose and mechanism of direct application and the purpose and<br />

mechanism of indirect application. (These errors appear in both the<br />

case law and the academic commentary.) This conflation takes<br />

several forms. First, there is no meaningful difference between direct<br />

application of the Bill of Rights to the common law under FC section<br />

8 and indirect application of the Bill of Rights under FC section 39(2).<br />

Second, those who believe a meaningful difference exists between<br />

analysis under FC section 8 and FC section 39(2) rely on a clear<br />

cleavage between rules and values. Third, since no clear cleavage<br />

exists between the rule-governed analysis and the value-governed<br />

analysis under the Final Constitution, then any distinction between<br />

the two sections, grounded in the belief that they require different<br />

kinds of analysis, collapses.<br />

With respect to the first claim — that no meaningful difference<br />

exists between direct application of the Bill of Rights under FC section<br />

8 and indirect application under FC section 39 — one might expect an<br />

13<br />

Afrox Healthcare Bpk v Strydom 2002 6 SA 21 (SCA); Ex parte Minister of Safety<br />

and Security & Others: In re S v Walters & Another 2002 4 SA 613 (CC), 2002 7<br />

BCLR 663 (CC), 2002 (2) SACR 105 (CC). See also S Woolman & D Brand ‘Is there a<br />

constitution in <strong>this</strong> courtroom?: Constitutional jurisdiction after Afrox and<br />

Walters’ (2003) 18 South African Public Law 38.


126 Chapter 8<br />

explanation as to why FC section 8 is entitled ‘Application’ and FC<br />

section 39 is entitled ‘Interpretation’. The refusal to take the text<br />

seriously and to claim that no meaningful distinction exists between<br />

FC section 8 and FC section 39(2) flies directly in the face of Justice<br />

O’Regan’s injunction — in Khumalo v Holomisa — that we should not<br />

attribute meaning to one section of the Final Constitution that<br />

renders another section, quite literally, senseless. 14 If FC section 8(2)<br />

and FC section 39(2) both mean the same thing, then one of those<br />

sections is entirely superfluous. In Khumalo, Justice O’Regan quite<br />

rightly held that the attribution of distinct purposes to the two<br />

sections is an absolutely essential exercise. Under FC section 8, the<br />

specific substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights apply to each and<br />

every kind of law, and each and every form of conduct (whether<br />

public or private, where appropriate). FC section 8 does not mean<br />

that the prescriptive content of the substantive provisions in the Bill<br />

of Rights cover each and every legal dispute. Put another way, while<br />

the specific provisions in the Bill of Rights cover a large domain of law<br />

and conduct activity, they do not engage all law and conduct. The<br />

independent purpose of FC section 39(2) is to engage law and conduct<br />

that are not engaged by any of the specific provisions set out in<br />

Chapter 2.<br />

A counterfactual makes <strong>this</strong> last distinction clear. Assume that FC<br />

section 39(2) and FC section 8 do require the same mode of analysis.<br />

Assume, as Chris Roederer 15 and the Masiya, Barkhuizen and NM<br />

Courts 16 would have us do, that <strong>this</strong> mode of analysis is purely a<br />

14 Khumalo (n 2 above) para 32 (‘We cannot adopt an interpretation which would<br />

render a provision of the Constitution without any apparent purpose.’)<br />

15 C Roederer ‘Post-matrix legal reasoning: Horizontality and the role of values in<br />

South African law’ (2003) 18 South African Journal on Human Rights 57.<br />

16 Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions & Others 2007 5 SA 30 (CC), 2007 8 BCLR<br />

(CC). The facts and the outcome of Masiya are clear enough. Mr Masiya had been<br />

convicted in a regional magistrate’s court of the anal rape of a nine-year-old girl.<br />

However, as the law stood prior to conviction, the anal rape satisfied only the<br />

desiderata for a conviction of indecent assault. The magistrate developed the<br />

common-law definition of rape to include non-consensual penetration of the penis<br />

into the vagina or anus of a person and made the common-law definition of rape<br />

gender-neutral. On appeal, the High Court both agreed with the magistrate’s<br />

reasons for developing the definition and confirmed Masiya’s conviction on the<br />

charge of rape. The Constitutional Court was asked to confirm the High Court’s<br />

judgments — and, in particular, its development of the common-law definition of<br />

rape and the attendant alterations of the Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977 and<br />

the Criminal Law Amendment Act 105 of 1997. Nkabinde J, writing for the<br />

majority, held that the current definition of rape remained consistent with the<br />

Bill of Rights. (That is, the common law had ‘correctly’ characterised coerced<br />

anal penetration as mere indecent assault.) However, the Masiya court then found<br />

14 that Khumalo the pre-Masiya (n 2 above) definition para 32 (‘We still fell cannot short adopt of the an spirit, interpretation purport and which objects would of<br />

the render Bill a of provision Rights. The of the majority Constitution held that without the definition any apparent of rape purpose.’) must be extended<br />

15 to C Roederer include non-consensual ‘Post-matrix legal anal reasoning: penetration Horizontality of the anus and of the females. Role of The Values same in<br />

majority South African refused Law’ to (2003) extend 18 SAJHR the definition 57. of rape to non-consensual anal


Stu Woolman 127<br />

value-driven exercise. Why even have a Bill of Rights? Why not just<br />

have a short list of a general goods that embraces all of the values<br />

made manifest in the substantive provisions in Chapter 2? The<br />

correct reply is that the drafters intended for there to be two<br />

different processes. The first process — direct application — takes<br />

the rights and freedoms — and the general rules derived from them —<br />

as our departure point for determining whether law or conduct is<br />

invalid. The second process — indirect application — allows for a<br />

mode of analysis that neither specifies whether a particular right<br />

demands vindication nor permits a finding of invalidity. Instead, as<br />

Carmichele and Thebus tell us, the courts operate under a general<br />

injunction to bring all law into line with the ‘spirit, purport and<br />

objects’ of the Bill of Rights and the ‘objective, normative value<br />

system’ made manifest in the text of the Final Constitution as a<br />

whole. 17<br />

penetration of the anus of females. The same majority refused to extend the<br />

definition of rape to non-consensual anal penetration of males on the grounds<br />

that the court’s remedial powers were limited to the parties before the court and<br />

the facts of the instant matter. On <strong>this</strong> point, Langa CJ, joined by Sachs J,<br />

dissented. Both justices contended that the definition of rape should embrace<br />

non-consensual anal penetration of men. The Chief Justice reasoned that once<br />

the court accepted that rape was predominantly about the impairment of dignity,<br />

it made no sense for the law to distinguish between men and women. As a matter<br />

of logic and experience, the Chief Justice draws the unassailable conclusion that<br />

when it comes to anal rape it makes no sense to distinguish between men and<br />

women: it is an unconstitutional affront to the dignity of both. As a matter of<br />

institutional comity, the Chief Justice is correct in noting that the recognition of<br />

anal rape of men as rape does not require any legislative intervention. Coerced<br />

anal intercourse is anal rape: whether the victim happens to possess a penis or a<br />

vagina. In these circumstances, the Chief Justice recognises that it is ludicrous to<br />

suggest, as the majority does, that the court should not make new constitutional<br />

16<br />

common penetration law of ‘on the the anus basis of of females. what the The facts same might majority be’. Masiya refused (n to 14 extend above) the at<br />

para definition 29. Men, of rape absent to non-consensual vaginas, are raped anal penetration all the time. of The males common on the law, grounds the<br />

province that the court’s of the courts, remedial is more powers than were adequate limited to the task parties of righting/rewriting before the court and the<br />

law the as facts it stands. of the For instant further matter. analysis On of <strong>this</strong> Masiya point, — and Langa two CJ, other joined recent by judgments Sachs J,<br />

that dissented. bear out Both the justices thesis contended that a failure that the to definition undertake of direct rape should application embrace has<br />

genuinely non-consensual deleterious anal penetration consequences of men. — Barkhuizen The Chief v Napier Justice 2007 reasoned 5 SA that 323 (CC), once<br />

2007 the court (7) BCLR accepted 691 (CC); that NM rape v was Smith predominantly 2007 (5) SA 250 about (CC), the 2007 impairment (7) BCLR of 751 dignity, (CC)<br />

— it made see S Woolman no sense for ‘The the amazing, law to distinguish vanishing Bill between of Rights’ men (2007) and women. 124 South As a African matter<br />

Law of logic Journal and experience, 762. the Chief Justice draws the unassailable conclusion that<br />

17 Carmichele when it comes v Minister to anal of rape Safety it makes and Security no sense 2001 to distinguish 4 SA 938 (CC), between 2001 men 10 BCLR and<br />

995 women: (CC) it para is an 54. unconstitutional See also Thebus affront (n 12 above). to the dignity If FC sec of both. 39(2) objectives As a matter map of<br />

directly institutional to comity, <strong>this</strong> ‘normative the Chief Justice value system’, is correct then in noting the Constitutional that the recognition Court may of<br />

assert anal rape constitutional of men as jurisdiction rape does not through require FC any sec 39(2) legislative whenever intervention. it believes Coerced that a<br />

rule anal of intercourse common law is anal (or rape: conduct whether in light the of victim such rules) happens or the to possess interpretation a penis or of a<br />

statute vagina. In (or these conduct circumstances, in light of the a Chief given Justice set of recognises statutory that provisions) it ludicrous does not to<br />

conform suggest, with as the its majority understanding does, that of our the basic court constitutional should not make norms. new The constitutional<br />

Court relies<br />

upon common <strong>this</strong> law characterisation ‘on the basis of FC what sec the 39(2) facts in Carmichele might be’. Masiya in order (n to 14 compel above) the at<br />

High para Court 29. Men, and absent the Supreme vaginas, Court are raped of Appeal all the to develop time. The the common law, law the of<br />

delict. province Thus, of the despite courts, the is Thebus more than Court’s adequate admission to the that task FC of sec righting/rewriting<br />

39(2) ‘does not<br />

specify the law what as it triggers stands. For the further need to analysis develop of Masiya the common – and two law other or in recent which<br />

circumstances judgments that the bear development out the thesis of the that common a failure law is to justified’, do direct the application failure of any has<br />

court deleterious to adhere consequences to the FC sec — Barkhuizen 39(2) obligation v Napier to develop 2007 5 the SA 323 common (CC), law 2007 or (7) to<br />

interpret BCLR 691 a (CC); statute NM in v Smith light of 2007 the (5) demands SA 250 of (CC), the 2007 Final (7) Constitution’s BCLR 751 (CC). ‘objective For a<br />

normative similar analysis value S system’ Woolman risks ‘The reversal amazing, by vanishing our highest Bill constitutional of Rights’ (2007) tribunal. 124<br />

Thebus South African (n 12 above) Law Journal para 762. 27. This sword of Damocles is particularly dangerous


128 Chapter 8<br />

Both Professor Roederer and the Masiya, Barkhuizen and NM<br />

Courts further presuppose that those who believe a meaningful<br />

difference exists between analysis under FC section 8 and FC section<br />

39 rely incorrectly on a cleavage between rules and values. They<br />

claim, expressly and implicitly, that since FC section 39 requires that<br />

we analyse specific substantive rights, rules of common law or<br />

provisions of statutes in light of the same five core values — openness,<br />

democracy, human dignity, equality, freedom — or the same general<br />

‘spirit, purport and objects’, then we must necessarily be engaged in<br />

the same kind of ‘global’ assessment of rights, rules and statutory<br />

provisions whether we undertake direct application or indirect<br />

application. This is false. First, when we ask whether a statutory<br />

provision or a rule of common law – say the definition of rape or<br />

indecent assault — violates the right to dignity or the right to equality,<br />

we do not engage in some global assessment of competing Bill of<br />

Rights considerations. We know that FC section 9 — the right to<br />

equality — requires us to ask very specific kinds of questions about<br />

‘differentiation’, ‘discrimination’, ‘unfairness’, ‘systemic disadvan-<br />

17 because the Court cannot ‘specify ... the circumstances’ under which the sword<br />

may drop: its authority is unconstrained by determinate standards. This then is<br />

the linguistic trick that causes the specific substantive provisions of the Bill of<br />

Rights — FC sec 9 through FC sec 35 — to disappear, and then to reappear in the<br />

rather amorphous form of ‘an objective normative value system’. This rhetorical<br />

flourish of a phrase plays an equally important role in instances of FC sec 39(2) —<br />

informed ‘statutory interpretation’. See Rail Commuters Action Group & Others v<br />

Transnet Ltd t/a Metrorail & Others. 2005 2 SA 359 (CC), 2005 4 BCLR 301 (CC). In<br />

Rail Commuter Action Group v Transnet Ltd T/A Metrorail 2003 (5) SA 518 (C)<br />

573, 2003 3 BCLR 288 (C), the High Court, per Davis J and Van Heerden J,<br />

entertained a direct challenge to secs 15(1) and 23(1) of the South African<br />

Transport Services Act 9 of 1989 in terms of FC sec 11 and FC sec 12(1)(c). They<br />

held that these substantive provisions of the Final Constitution imposed a legal<br />

duty on Transnet to ensure that all railway commuters — regardless of race or<br />

class — enjoyed a certain level of physical safety. In Transnet Ltd T/A Metrorail v<br />

Rail Commuters Action Group 2003 6 SA 349 (SCA), 2003 12 BCLR 1363 (SCA), the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal differed with the Cape High Court over the content of<br />

the civic morality enshrined in the Final Constitution. The Supreme Court of<br />

Appeal rejected the proposition that our constitutionally-mandated morality<br />

demanded that a legal duty of care be imposed on Transnet in order to remedy<br />

the endemic violence visited upon commuters from historically disadvantaged<br />

communities. The Constitutional Court then reversed the Supreme Court of<br />

Appeal. However, the Constitutional Court chose not to follow the High Court’s<br />

route and view the constitutional infirmity as a direct infringement of<br />

fundamental rights. Instead, the Constitutional Court construed the enabling<br />

legislation in terms of FC sec 39(2) and found that it imposed prospectively, a<br />

duty of care on Metrorail. Three decisions – three different modes of analysis. The<br />

problem with the Constitutional Court’s Rail Commuter Action Group judgment is<br />

that by employing FC sec 39(2), it once again obviates the need to give<br />

meaningful content to the substantive provisions — FC secs10, 11 and 12 — upon<br />

which it expressly relies. The same sort of vanishing act occurs in Laugh It Off<br />

Promotions CC v SAB International (Finance) BV t/a Sabmark International &<br />

Another 2006 1 SA 144 (CC), 2005 8 BCLR 743 (CC). The Laugh It Off Court’s<br />

preference for FC sec 39(2) — informed statutory interpretation over direct<br />

constitutional interpretation in terms of FC sec 16 raises the question of how the<br />

Court can meaningfully assert constitutional jurisdiction — in order to overturn<br />

the Supreme Court of Appeal’s judgment — while employing a form of<br />

adjudication that largely eschews actual fundamental rights analysis.


Stu Woolman 129<br />

tage’ and ‘the impairment of dignity’. We know that FC section 10<br />

demands that we ask whether a given rule of law treats individuals as<br />

mere means, whether it recognises that individuals are always endsin-themselves,<br />

or whether it allows for inhumane punishment or<br />

treatment. Second, it could hardly be the case that when we interpret<br />

‘the right to access to housing’ in light of those five core values, we<br />

end up with the same content as when we interpret ‘the right to<br />

access to court’ in light of those five core values. However general<br />

their wording might be, these specific substantive rights generate<br />

rules with real purchase. And they appear in distinct provisions in the<br />

Bill of Rights because they seek to achieve manifestly different ends.<br />

Does the putative collapse of the rule/value distinction better<br />

justify the result in Masiya or the arguments offered by Professor<br />

Roederer? Well, once we make <strong>this</strong> move, there is only one question<br />

we could ask when faced with any allegation of a rights violation:<br />

‘Stepping back from it all, is the law or conduct under review the kind<br />

of law or conduct that the entire scheme of the Bill of Rights is meant<br />

to achieve?’ Such a broad inquiry inevitably makes questions about<br />

the distinct kinds of application required by FC sections 8 and 39<br />

superfluous. But <strong>this</strong> interpretative strategy floats so free of the text<br />

that it makes any analysis of the specific rights in FC sections 9<br />

through 35 superfluous. That would seem to violate with a vengeance<br />

the non-redundancy or non-surplusage requirement articulated by<br />

Justice O’Regan in Khumalo.<br />

In considering the dangers of the Court’s collapse of the rule/<br />

value distinction in Masiya, Barkhuizen, NM and other case, it may be<br />

worth reflecting upon the Constitutional Court’s own distinction<br />

between rules and values and the different uses to which the Final<br />

Constitution puts them. In Minister of Home Affairs v National<br />

Institute for Crime Prevention and the Reintegration of Crime<br />

Offenders & Others, Chaskalson CJ writes:<br />

The values enunciated in section 1 of the Constitution are of<br />

fundamental importance. They inform and give substance to all the<br />

provisions of the Constitution. They do not, however, give rise to<br />

discrete and enforceable rights in themselves. This is clear not only from<br />

the language of section 1 itself, but also from the way the Constitution is<br />

structured and in particular the provisions of Chapter 2 which contains<br />

the Bill of Rights. 18<br />

Values are one thing, the NICRO Court holds, rules another. While it<br />

is certainly true that the fundamental values articulated in the Final<br />

Constitution will shape the rules expressed therein, and that the rules<br />

will have a reciprocal effect with respect to our understanding of<br />

18 2005 3 SA 280 (CC), 2004 5 BCLR 445 (CC) para 21.


130 Chapter 8<br />

those fundamental values, there remains a distinction with a<br />

difference. Rights give rise to rules and enforceable claims. Values do<br />

not. The Masiya, Barkhuizen and NM Courts and Professor Roederer<br />

ignore <strong>this</strong> distinction at our peril.<br />

The sixth objection expands upon an issue raised above: Unless<br />

the two processes of application — direct and indirect — are identical,<br />

then the various sections of the Bill of Rights that deal with<br />

application (or interpretation) must contemplate at least two distinct<br />

modes of analysis and must employ language that reflects such a<br />

distinction. Here then is my contention. As a matter of logic, one must<br />

know when direct application is or is not required in order to know<br />

when indirect application is or is not required. Direct application<br />

means that the prescriptive content of the substantive rights found in<br />

FC sections 9 through 35 engages the law or conduct at issue. Where<br />

the prescriptive content of the substantive rights found in FC sections<br />

9 through 35 does not engage the law or the conduct at issue, then FC<br />

section 39(2) tells us that the more general spirit, purport and objects<br />

of the chapter may inform our efforts to bring all law into line with<br />

the Final Constitution. If we reverse the spin, and we first use FC<br />

section 39(2) to bring the law into line with the general spirit, purport<br />

and objects of the Bill of Rights, there is simply nothing left to be<br />

done in terms of the direct application of the specific substantive<br />

provisions of the Bill of Rights. The reason is obvious. If the general<br />

spirit, purport and objects of Chapter 2 — which embraces (at a<br />

minimum) the entire value domain reflected by the specific<br />

substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights — does not require a change<br />

in the law (or a change in conduct brought about by a change in the<br />

law), then no narrower set of purposes reflected in a single<br />

substantive provision of the Bill of Rights could be expected to do so.<br />

Contrary to Professor Currie’s take on application, indirect<br />

application was not meant to ‘avoid’ actual constitutional analysis in<br />

terms of the specific substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights. 19<br />

Indeed FC section 39(2) enables a court to go beyond the limited<br />

substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights. FC section 39(2) promises<br />

an expansive understanding of judicial review under the Bill of Rights,<br />

not a cramped understanding. However, before one can engage in<br />

indirect application and the development of new rules of law in terms<br />

of FC section 39(2), one must first delineate the ambits of the specific<br />

constitutional provisions relied upon in the applicant’s challenge to<br />

existing law. Only when one has determined those ambits, and found<br />

19<br />

I Currie & J de Waal The Bill of Rights handbook 5 ed (2005). There is, in the<br />

academic literature an ongoing confusion between ‘reading down’ (which still<br />

requires Bill of Rights interpretation in terms of a specific provision) and indirect<br />

application which requires no such engagement with a specific substantive<br />

provision.


Stu Woolman 131<br />

that they do not speak to the issues raised by an ordinary rule of law,<br />

can one turn to the more open-ended invitation of FC section 39(2).<br />

Analysis of the specific provisions of the Bill of Rights — and the<br />

consistency of law or conduct with those provisions — must be<br />

logically prior to the analysis of the common law or the interpretation<br />

of statutes in terms of the general spirit, purpose and objects of the<br />

Bill of Rights. When FC section 39(2) — indirect application — is given<br />

priority over FC section 8 — it does too much work and turns all of FC<br />

section 8 — the entire section on Application — into surplusage. Again<br />

FC section 39(2), on such a reading, does exactly what Justice<br />

O’Regan, in Khumalo, says we must not do: it makes FC section 8(1),<br />

FC section 8(2) and FC section 8(3) entirely redundant. 20<br />

4 The preferred reading<br />

There is a better way. My preferred reading satisfies the demands of<br />

naturalness, textual plausibility, coherence, surplusage and ideology,<br />

and, just as importantly, meets the objections lodged against both<br />

Khumalo and the good faith reconstruction of Khumalo. That<br />

preferred reading takes the following form.<br />

FC section 8(1) covers ‘all law’ — regardless of provenance, form,<br />

and or the parties before the court. FC section 8(1) also covers all<br />

state conduct — by all branches of government and all organs of the<br />

state — whether that conduct takes the form of law or reflects some<br />

other manifestation or exercise of state power. In sum, FC section<br />

8(1) should be understood to stand for the following proposition:<br />

All rules of law and every exercise of state power are subject to the<br />

direct application of the Bill of Rights.<br />

FC section 8(2) covers dispute-generating conduct between private<br />

actors not ‘adequately’ governed by an express rule of law. There are<br />

two basic ways to read ‘not governed adequately by an express rule<br />

of law.’ First, it could contemplate the possibility of a dispute over an<br />

aspect of social life that is not currently governed by any rule of law<br />

at all. Such instances are rare. Indeed there is good reason to believe<br />

that such instances do not exist at all. The second and better reading<br />

views non-rule governed conduct in a much narrower sense. In many<br />

instances a body of extant rules — or even background norms — may<br />

be said to govern a particular set of private relationships. FC section<br />

8(2) calls our attention to the fact that these rules of law may not give<br />

adequate effect to the specific substantive provisions of the Bill of<br />

Rights and may require the courts to develop a new rule of law that<br />

does give adequate effect to a particular provision in the Bill of Rights<br />

20 Khumalo (n 2 above) para 32.


132 Chapter 8<br />

in so far as a dispute between private persons requires it to do so. In<br />

sum, FC section 8(2) should be understood to stand for the following<br />

proposition:<br />

While, on the Hohfeldian view, a body of extant legal rules — or<br />

background norms — will always govern a social relationship, those same<br />

rules will not always give adequate effect to a provision in the Bill of<br />

Rights. FC section 8(2) calls attention to the potential gap between<br />

extant rules of law and the prescriptive content of the Bill of Rights,<br />

and, where necessary, requires the courts to bridge that gap by bringing<br />

the law into line with the demands of particular constitutional norms.<br />

If we decide that the right invoked engages the conduct in question<br />

and that the right has been unjustifiably infringed, then we move on<br />

to FC section 8(3). FC sections 8(3)(a) and (b) enjoin the court to<br />

develop new rules of law and remedies designed to give effect to the<br />

right infringed. Thus, where FC section 8(2) acknowledges gaps in<br />

existing legal doctrine, FC section 8(3) aims to fill those gaps. In sum,<br />

FC section 8(3) should be understood to stand for the following<br />

proposition:<br />

If the court finds that the right relied upon warrants direct application<br />

to the conduct that has given rise to the dispute, and further finds a<br />

non-justifiable abridgment of the right, then the mechanisms in FC<br />

sections 8(3)(a) and (b) must be used to develop the law in a manner<br />

that gives adequate effect to the right infringed.<br />

It may be, however, that the prescriptive content of the substantive<br />

provisions of the Bill of Rights does not engage the rule of law or<br />

conduct at issue. Two things can happen. A court can decide that the<br />

Bill of Rights has nothing at all to say about the dispute in question. A<br />

court can decide that although no specific provision of the Bill of<br />

Rights is offended by the law or the conduct in question, the Bill of<br />

Rights warrants the development of the law in a manner that coheres<br />

with its general spirit, purport and objects. In sum, FC section 39(2)<br />

should be understood to stand for the following proposition:<br />

Where no specific right can be relied upon by a party challenging a given<br />

rule of law or the extant construction of a rule of law, the courts are<br />

obliged to interpret legislation or to develop the law in light of the<br />

general objects of the Bill of Rights.<br />

The preferred reading, unlike the good faith reconstruction of<br />

Khumalo, is untroubled by fortuitous differences between forms of<br />

law. It does not suppress or defer application of the Bill of Rights to<br />

disputes between private persons governed by either legislation or<br />

common law. The preferred reading, unlike the good faith<br />

reconstruction of Khumalo, generates no tension between the legality<br />

principle and the doctrine of objective unconstitutionality. It<br />

recognises all forms of law as exercises in state power and makes each


Stu Woolman 133<br />

and every exercise of state power subject to constitutional review. It<br />

does not rest on a distinction between the parties before the court<br />

and thus does not offend the doctrine of objective unconstitutionality.<br />

The preferred reading, unlike the good faith reconstruction<br />

of Khumalo, does not offend the surplusage canon of<br />

constitutional interpretation. It alone gives the phrase ‘binds the<br />

judiciary’ meaningful content by recognising that the phrase engages<br />

all emanations of law from the courts. The preferred reading, unlike<br />

the good faith reconstruction of Khumalo, is not plagued by a host of<br />

conflicting doctrinal commitments that blunt the transformative<br />

potential of the Bill of Rights. Proper apportionment of analytical<br />

responsibilities between FC section 8(1), FC section 8(2), FC section<br />

8(3) and FC section 39(2) finesses the many difficulties created by a<br />

hide-bound doctrine of stare decisis that permits little, if any,<br />

development of the common law in light of FC section 39(2). 21<br />

5 Conclusion<br />

Defenders of the Court’s approach to application suggest — in<br />

straightforward realist fashion — that the mechanism for the<br />

21<br />

A caveat and a codicil are in order. The caveat is that there is no unassailable<br />

answer to the question of burdens raised by FC sec 8. Shoddy drafting left us with<br />

a text — FC sec 8 — that generates multiple possible readings and that resists a<br />

simple mechanical explanation because its component parts are difficult to<br />

reconcile. That does not mean that no grounds exist for preferring one reading<br />

over another. Indeed, the appropriate response to that standard academic trope<br />

— ‘so what’ — is to construct an analytical framework for direct application under<br />

FC sec 8 that coheres with the manifold doctrinal demands of indirect<br />

application, stare decisis, the rule of law, constitutional jurisdiction, objective<br />

unconstitutionality, textual plausibility and naturalness. This chapter constitutes<br />

one such answer. The codicil reflects the recognition that questions of application<br />

in terms of FC sec 8 are, at bottom, questions of interpretation. This proposition<br />

has two dimensions: one logical, one historical. As a logical matter, we could<br />

function perfectly well without a provision on application. Whether the<br />

provenance of the law at issue or nature of the parties before the court have<br />

some bearing on the disposition of a matter could well be accommodated as part<br />

of the interpretation of a right. The presence of FC sec 8 reflects the judgment of<br />

the drafters that our Final Constitution must speak to the application of the Bill<br />

to the exercise of both public and private power, and that constitutional texts<br />

have always done so (even where those texts have operated to protect existing<br />

hierarchies of private power.) Because the drafters of the Final Constitution set<br />

their face against the traditional immunisation of certain kinds of private dispute<br />

from constitutional review, all legal disputes are now notionally subject to the<br />

strictures of the Bill of Rights. As a result, the line drawing exercise that<br />

animated the debate around the Interim Constitution’s application provisions<br />

ought to have proved of diminished import by now. That the application debate<br />

has not withered away cannot be explained by the logic of the text alone. The<br />

text points towards such a withering away. The continued debate over application<br />

reflects the extent to which the meaning of our basic law is determined by extant<br />

historical conditions: The echo of the Interim Constitution, the limited<br />

jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court versus the plenary jurisdiction of the<br />

Supreme Court of Appeal and, perhaps most importantly, the felt need to chart a<br />

careful course between the Scylla of transformation and the Charybdis of<br />

tradition.


134 Chapter 8<br />

application of the Bill of Rights — direct application or indirect<br />

application — matters little in terms of either the outcomes we get or<br />

the depth and coherence of the decisions that justify those outcomes.<br />

Professor Frank Michelman and Professor Iain Currie claim — not<br />

without merit — that a muscular approach to FC section 39(2) could<br />

deliver exactly the same reasoning and exactly the same outcomes as<br />

direct application of the substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights.<br />

Of course, their optimism assumes that the courts employ a<br />

muscular approach to FC section 39(2) analysis. However, in three<br />

recent decisions — Barkhuizen, 22 Masiya, 23 and NM 24 — the Court<br />

reaches troubling conclusions through murky, if not tendentious, lines<br />

of reasoning. All three decisions abjure the direct application of the<br />

substantive provisions of Bill of Rights and rely instead on the openended<br />

provisions of FC section 39(2).<br />

The result, as I have argued elsewhere, is that a penchant for<br />

outcome-based decision-making, and a concomitant lack of analytical<br />

rigour, has finally caught up with the Constitutional Court. 25 Of<br />

particular import in these three cases is the Court’s persistent refusal<br />

to engage in the direct application of the Bill of Rights. Rather flaccid<br />

analysis in terms of three vaguely defined values — dignity, equality<br />

and freedom — almost invariably substitutes for more rigorous<br />

interrogation of constitutional challenges in terms of the specific<br />

substantive rights found in Chapter 2. If the drafters of the<br />

Constitution had intended such a substitution, then the structure and<br />

the language of the Bill of Rights would reflect that intention. It<br />

doesn’t. Moreover, <strong>this</strong> strategy — of speaking in values — has freed<br />

the Court almost entirely from the text; the strategy thereby grants<br />

the Court the license to decide each case as it pleases, virtually<br />

unmoored from its own precedent. That, again, cannot be what the<br />

drafters of the Constitution intended.<br />

Another consequence of <strong>this</strong> strategy is that the Court has<br />

unwittingly undermined the Bill of Rights. By continually relying on FC<br />

section 39(2) to decide challenges both to rules of common law and<br />

to provisions of statutes, the Court obviates the need to give the<br />

specific substantive rights in Chapter 2 the content necessary to<br />

determine the actual validity of the rule being challenged in the<br />

instant matter and of similar rules challenged in subsequent matters.<br />

This strategy also enables the Court to skirt the nuanced process of<br />

22 Barkhuizen v Napier 2007 5 SA 323 (CC), 2007 7 BCLR 691 (CC).<br />

23 n 16 above.<br />

24<br />

NM v Smith & Others 2007 5 SA 250 (CC), 2007 7 BCLR 751.<br />

25 S Woolman ‘The amazing, vanishing Bill of Rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law<br />

Journal 762. For a dissenting view, see F Michelman ‘On the uses of interpretive<br />

charity: Some notes from abroad on application, avoidance, equality and<br />

objective unconstitutionality’ (2008) Constitutional Court Review 1.


Stu Woolman 135<br />

justification that FC section 36 or some other express limitations<br />

clause in a specific substantive right might require. The persistent<br />

refusal to give rights identifiable content — by avoiding direct<br />

application — results in a Bill of Rights increasingly denuded of<br />

meaning.<br />

The over-reliance on FC section 39(2) also has the unintended<br />

consequence of undermining the rule of law. The two-step interpretative<br />

process engineered by the drafters of the Bill of Rights ought<br />

to produce black letter constitutional law. Clear delineation of the<br />

ambit of a right articulates one type of rule; similarly crisp limitations<br />

analysis articulates another type of rule. The articulation of such<br />

express black letter rules of law enables the citizenry and the<br />

government to conform their behaviour to our Constitution. In a<br />

domain for which rules are even more germane, the judicial system,<br />

rules of black letter constitutional law ensure that lower courts and<br />

lawyers can identify the law and thereby settle, litigate and<br />

adjudicate, with some confidence, fundamental rights cases. The use<br />

of FC section 39(2) may be a handy way to secure agreement amongst<br />

11 judges regarding the appropriate outcome of a case at the same<br />

time as they finesse (or suppress) the logic behind the outcome.<br />

However, <strong>this</strong> strategy — while useful in cobbling together majorities<br />

on the Constitutional Court — often leaves readers of a judgment at<br />

an absolute loss as to how the Bill of Rights might operate in some<br />

future matter. An approach to constitutional adjudication that makes<br />

it difficult for lower court judges, lawyers, government officials and<br />

citizens to discern, with some degree of certainty, how the basic law<br />

is going to be applied, and to know, with some degree of certainty,<br />

that the basic law is going to be applied equally, constitutes a<br />

paradigmatic violation of the rule of law. 26<br />

26<br />

Judge Dennis Davis has laid <strong>this</strong> very same complaint: the absence of rule-based<br />

content in the Constitutional Court’s Bill of Rights jurisprudence makes it difficult<br />

for High Courts to discharge effectively their function. See D Davis ‘Democracy,<br />

dignity and deliberation’ Conference on dignity and the jurisprudence of Laurie<br />

Ackermann (27 July 2007, University of Cape Town). Moreover, there are signs<br />

that the Court itself — or members of the Court — are aware of the dangers that<br />

attach to <strong>this</strong> failure. In an interview on SA-FM, Justice O’Regan noted that the<br />

Constitutional Court could, in its first decade of existence, have provided a<br />

stronger, theoretically more secure foundation for its Bill of Rights jurisprudence<br />

— a choice that would have put the current Court’s jurisprudence on more solid<br />

footing. Interview with Justice O’Regan on SA-FM (27 July 2007).


136 Chapter 8<br />

We have gone beyond the point where we could explain<br />

(descriptively) the Court’s jurisprudence in terms of (the often<br />

misunderstood notion of) ‘incompletely theorised agreements’. 27<br />

27<br />

C Sunstein One case at a time (1996). The incompletely theorised agreements<br />

that are the mainstay of judicial minimalism are explained by Sunstein as follows:<br />

A minimalist court settles the case before it, but leaves many things<br />

undecided. It is alert to the existence of reasonable agreement in a<br />

heterogenous society. It knows that there is much that it does not know;<br />

it is intensely aware of its own limitations. It seeks to decide cases on<br />

narrow grounds. ... Alert to the problem of unanticipated consequences,<br />

it sees itself as part of a system of democratic deliberation; it attempts to<br />

promote the democratic ideals of participation, deliberation and<br />

responsiveness. It allows for continued space for democratic reflection<br />

from Congress and the states. It wants to accommodate new judgments<br />

about facts and values.<br />

As above, ix – x. However, Sunstein’s minimalism only secures traction because it<br />

is parasitic upon a deep, and widely shared, set of constitutional doctrines (and<br />

tacit) assumptions amongst judges, lawyers and citizens. Sunstein recognises the<br />

necessity of a solid core:<br />

Anyone who seeks to leave things undecided is likely to accept a wide shared, set<br />

of constitutional doctrines (and tacit) assumptions amongst judges, lawyers and<br />

citizens. Sunstein recognises the necessity of a solid core:<br />

Anyone who seeks to leave things undecided is likely to accept a wide<br />

range of things, and these constitute a ‘core’ of agreement about<br />

constitutional essentials. In American constitutional law at the turn of the<br />

century, a distinctive set of substantive ideals now form that core.<br />

As above, x. See also C Sunstein ‘Leaving things undecided’ (1996) 110 Harvard<br />

Law Review 4; C Sunstein ‘Incompletely theorised agreements in constitutional<br />

law’ John M Olin Law & Economics Working Paper No 322 (2007), available at<br />

27 www.law.uchicago.edu/laweconwkngPprs_301-350/322.pdf<br />

C Sunstein One case at a time (1996). The incompletely theorised<br />

(accessed<br />

agreements<br />

14 July<br />

2008).<br />

that are<br />

More<br />

the<br />

recently,<br />

mainstay<br />

Sunstein<br />

of judicial<br />

has<br />

minimalism<br />

turned his<br />

are<br />

attention<br />

explained<br />

to social<br />

by Sunstein<br />

phenomena<br />

as follows:<br />

that<br />

produce more accurate assessments and better solutions to problems on<br />

substantially A minimalist larger court scales settles than courts the case of law. before See C it, Sunstein but leaves Infotopia: many How things many<br />

minds undecided. produce knowledge It is alert (2006). to the Markets, existence though of reasonable often imperfect, agreement rely in upon a<br />

limited heterogenous ‘shared’ information society. It knows (sometimes that there no is more much than that price) it does and not know; generate<br />

optimal, it is or intensely at least aware substantially of its own more limitations. efficient, It and seeks thicker to decide outcomes. cases on Some<br />

open-source narrow grounds. software, . . like . Alert Linux, to the produces problem incredibly of unanticipated rich results consequences, without any<br />

central it sees planning. itself as The part web of itself a system — the of environment democratic deliberation; for Linux — it produces attempts both<br />

optimal to promote and suboptimal the democratic outcomes, depending ideals of participation, how information deliberation is solicited and and<br />

how responsiveness. further cooperative It allows endeavors for continued are organised. space Thinness for democratic is, therefore, reflection not a<br />

virtue from in itself Congress (even and for the Sunstein). states. It wants It may to be accommodate a virtue within new judgments systems with<br />

information about facts deficits and values. or significant distortions in the manner in which decisionmakers<br />

As above<br />

use<br />

ix –<br />

the<br />

x. However,<br />

information<br />

Sunstein’s<br />

they possess.<br />

minimalism<br />

A growing<br />

only secures<br />

contingent<br />

traction<br />

of constitutional<br />

because it is<br />

law<br />

parasitic<br />

scholars<br />

upon<br />

have<br />

a deep,<br />

recognised<br />

and widely<br />

that problems<br />

shared,<br />

of<br />

set<br />

information<br />

of constitutional<br />

deficit,<br />

doctrines<br />

lack of crosscultural<br />

(and<br />

tacit) assumptions<br />

understanding<br />

amongst<br />

and limited<br />

judges,<br />

institutional<br />

lawyers and<br />

competence<br />

citizens. Sunstein<br />

can be<br />

recognises<br />

‘solved’ by<br />

the<br />

a<br />

subtle<br />

necessity<br />

recasting<br />

of solid<br />

of<br />

core:<br />

existing constitutional doctrines and judicial remedies that<br />

extract better information and thereby achieve more mindful results. See eg M<br />

Dorf Anyone & C Sabel who seeks ‘A constitution to leave things of democratic undecided is experimentalism’ likely to accept (1998) a wide 98<br />

Columbia range Law of things, Review and 267; these M Dorf constitute & B a Friedman ‘core’ of ‘Shared agreement constitutional about<br />

interpretation’ constitutional (2000) essentials. Supreme In American Court constitutional Review 61; law C Sabel at the turn & W of the Simon<br />

‘Destabilisation century, a distinctive rights: How set public of substantive law litigation ideals succeeds’ now form that (2004) core. 117 Harvard<br />

Law<br />

As above<br />

Review<br />

x.<br />

1015.<br />

See also<br />

For<br />

C<br />

the<br />

Sunstein<br />

application<br />

‘Leaving<br />

of experimental<br />

things undecided’<br />

constitutionalism<br />

(1996) 110<br />

to<br />

Harvard<br />

South<br />

African<br />

Law Review<br />

jurisprudence,<br />

4; C Sunstein<br />

see<br />

‘Incompletely<br />

Woolman (n<br />

theorised<br />

3 above);<br />

agreements<br />

S Woolman<br />

in constitutional<br />

& H Botha<br />

‘Limitations’<br />

law’ John M<br />

in<br />

Olin<br />

Woolman<br />

Law &<br />

et<br />

Economics<br />

al (eds) Constitutional<br />

Working Paper<br />

Law<br />

No<br />

of<br />

322<br />

South<br />

(January<br />

Africa<br />

2007),<br />

(n 3<br />

above)<br />

available<br />

Chapter<br />

at http://www.law.uchicago.edu/lawecon.<br />

34; S Woolman The selfless Constitution:<br />

More recently,<br />

Experimentation<br />

Sunstein has<br />

&<br />

flourishing<br />

turned his attention<br />

as the foundations<br />

to social phenomena<br />

of South Africa’s<br />

that produce<br />

basic law<br />

more<br />

(forthcoming<br />

accurate<br />

2008).


Stu Woolman 137<br />

Incompletely theorised agreements presuppose that current<br />

information deficits and normative differences about both the just<br />

and the good will at least be partially ameliorated as time and<br />

experience throw up new opportunities to expand our understanding<br />

of how given rights ought to function in given environments. 28 The<br />

28<br />

28<br />

Professor Currie is, thus far, the only South African constitutional law scholar to<br />

have articulated a full-blown theory of judicial review, and it tracks, at a very<br />

high degree of abstraction, Sunstein’s views on incompletely theorised<br />

agreements and judicial minimalism. See I Currie ‘Judicious avoidance’ (1999) 15<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 138. Two problems with Professor Currie’s<br />

account warrant mention here. Professor Currie may have been correct, as a<br />

descriptive matter, to ascribe (some notion of) judicial minimalism to the<br />

Constitutional Court in its first few years of existence. The shallowness of the<br />

Chaskalson Court’s judgments and the unanimity the Chaskalson Court imposed on<br />

its potentially fractious bench are noteworthy features of its first four years.<br />

However, Professor Currie has, over time, elevated an accurate description of a<br />

small cohort of cases to a highly questionable normative account. His more recent<br />

work shows no signs of backing away. See Currie & de Waal (n 17 above). Currie’s<br />

difficulty is that South Africa, circa 1995 to 1999, possessed no core of fully or<br />

reasonably theorised agreements about constitutional norms that would allow for<br />

meaningful incompletely theorised agreements. As of 2007, the Constitutional<br />

Court continues to offer incompletely theorised judgments in the (general)<br />

absence of theorised cores. Minimalism of the kind espoused by Professor Currie<br />

only works against a background of shared understandings. It is the absence of<br />

shared understandings — on the Court and in the society at large — that make it<br />

impossible to accept judicial minimalism as either an accurate description of or a<br />

desirable prescription for our Bill of Rights’ jurisprudence. (In liberal societies,<br />

<strong>this</strong> distinction between the shared assumptions necessary for society to work<br />

(and to work fairly) and more general assumptions about the correct way to live<br />

tracks the standard philosophical distinction between the right (justice) and the<br />

good (morality). A liberal democratic society requires a significant amount of<br />

shared assumptions about the right in order to operate: It consciously leaves upon<br />

space for disagreement about comprehensive visions of the good.) See J Rawls<br />

Political liberalism (1993). These comments about the dangers of an unreflective<br />

understanding of judicial minimalism are not the abstract musings of an armchair<br />

sociologist. At least one sitting Justice on the Constitutional Court has stated — in<br />

a public forum — that ‘judicial minimalism’ was and remains attractive for<br />

members of the Constitutional Court exactly because it does not require the<br />

eleven justices to possess a core of shared understandings. A Sachs ‘Democracy,<br />

Dignity and Deliberation’ Conference on Dignity and the Jurisprudence of Laurie<br />

Ackermann (27 July 2007, University of Cape Town).<br />

Robert Post and Reva Siegal have just recently offered a far more nuanced set of<br />

objections to Cass Sunstein’s minimalist project. See R Post & R Reva Siegal ‘Roe<br />

rage: Democratic constitutionalism and backlash’ (2007) 42 Harvard Civil Rights-<br />

Civil Liberties Law Review. 373, 377, 391-406 (footnotes omitted). In response to<br />

Sunstein’s minimalism — which assiduously eschews judicial pronouncements on<br />

contentious value choices — Post and Siegal advance a theory of constitutional<br />

interpretation they call ‘democratic constitutionalism’. ‘Democratic constitutionalism’,<br />

they argue, ’suggests that some degree of conflict may be an<br />

inevitable consequence of vindicating constitutional rights, whether rights are<br />

secured by legislation or by adjudication. ... Democratic constitutionalism<br />

suggests ... that controversy provoked by judicial decision-making might even<br />

have positive benefits for the American constitutional order. Citizens who oppose<br />

court decisions are politically active. They enact their commitment to the<br />

importance of constitutional meaning. They seek to persuade other Americans to<br />

embrace their constitutional understandings. These forms of engagement lead<br />

citizens to identify with the Constitution and with one another. Popular debate<br />

about the Constitution infuses the memories and principles of our constitutional<br />

tradition with meanings that command popular allegiance and that would never


138 Chapter 8<br />

Court’s ongoing failure to develop coherent doctrines in many areas<br />

of fundamental rights jurisprudence does not only undermine the Bill<br />

of Rights and the rule of law. It places the Court’s very authority at<br />

risk. 29<br />

Professor Currie’s reply concedes that, theoretically, the Court’s<br />

application jurisprudence is incoherent. The three aforementioned<br />

cases, and the Court’s general over-reliance on FC section 39(2), give<br />

credence to the claim that the Court’s ongoing failure to apply<br />

directly the Bill of Rights is having an untoward effect on the<br />

jurisprudence that our highest Court generates. So what is true in<br />

theory would appear to be true in practice. 30<br />

develop if a normatively estranged citizenry were passively to submit to judicial<br />

judgments.’<br />

29<br />

See T Roux ‘Principle and pragmatism on the Constitutional Court of South Africa<br />

2009 — International Journal of Constitutional Law — (forthcoming). Professor<br />

Roux explains the thinness of the Court’s jurisprudence primarily in terms of the<br />

need to secure institutional legitimacy. That institutional legitimacy was deemed<br />

necessary not just so the Court could survive, but so that it could survive in order<br />

to pursue such intrinsic goods as the entrenchment of the rule of law and the Bill<br />

of Rights.<br />

30 In his very generous reply, Professor Currie claims that <strong>this</strong> issue of ‘burdens’ is no<br />

longer vexed. He may be correct — to the extent the Court no longer cares.<br />

However, my article — ‘The amazing vanishing Bill of Rights’ (n 25 above) — has<br />

elicited two very lengthy responses from Frank Michelman and Andre van der Walt<br />

on the subject. See F Michelman ‘On the uses of interpretive Charity’ (2008)<br />

Constitutional Court Review (forthcoming) and A van der Walt ‘Normative<br />

anarchy and pluralism’ (2008) Constitutional Court Review (forthcoming).


9 Reply<br />

Summarising Proust: A reply to Stu Woolman<br />

Iain Currie<br />

1 Introduction<br />

I feel a little like I’m about to take part in the All-England Summarise<br />

Proust competition. Fans of Monty Python’s Flying Circus will<br />

remember that contestants had to give a fifteen-second summary of<br />

Proust's À La Recherch e du Temps Perdu, once in a swimsuit and once<br />

in evening dress. No one could do it of course, 1 and they had to give<br />

the first prize to the girl with the biggest ... but I’m digressing. Proust<br />

comes to mind because the immediately striking thing about Stu<br />

Woolman’s monumental ‘Application’ in Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa is its striking monumentality, which easily defeats any attempt<br />

at summary. Stu begins his Chapter with <strong>this</strong> warning: ‘There is more,<br />

much more, to “application” than the text [of section 8] might<br />

suggest’. 2 This turns out to be putting things a little mildly. You get<br />

the feeling that it was only the anguished cavilling of the Juta<br />

accountants that contained Stu’s inexhaustible will to expatiate and<br />

that finally brought the Chapter in at only its current thousand or so<br />

pages.<br />

1 Mr Rutherford from Leicester’s attempt: ‘Er, well, Swann, Swann, there's <strong>this</strong><br />

house, there’s <strong>this</strong> house, and er, it’s in the morning, it’s in the morning — no, it’s<br />

the evening, in the evening and er, there's a garden and er, <strong>this</strong> bloke comes in —<br />

bloke comes in — what’s his name — what's his name, er just said it — big bloke —<br />

Swann, Swann ...’.<br />

2<br />

S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2005) Chapter 31, available at www.westlaw.com.<br />

139


140 Chapter 9<br />

But it is precisely <strong>this</strong> unruly expatiation, breaking out all over the<br />

place, that makes the chapter such a pleasure to read. It is a pleasure<br />

of a particularly academic kind, and I mean to use that word with as<br />

positive a charge as possible. The chapter is rich, dense, theoretically<br />

ambitious, comprehensive in its scope and surely exhaustive in its<br />

engagement with the literature. (I say ‘surely’ because I can’t help<br />

thinking there might just be something in the older issues of the<br />

Zeitschrift für Auspuffskonstruktion that has been overlooked.<br />

Something to check up on for the third edition perhaps.) It even has<br />

an Appendix. Yes, an Appendix for those greedy constitutional-law<br />

wonks whose appetite for the South African application literature has<br />

not been utterly satiated by the main text. There must surely be one<br />

or two of them, and it is good to know that they have been catered<br />

for. Everyone who has ever written anything on the issue is thoroughly<br />

read, engaged with and has their innumerable errors patiently and<br />

unflinchingly exposed and corrected. No resort to lazy footnotes (‘But<br />

see contra ...’), <strong>this</strong> is scholarly engagement of an old-fashioned kind<br />

that respects the views of those it contests (not least by taking the<br />

time to read them) and that is little practiced these days. This sort of<br />

capacious scholarship sits a little uneasily in a book at least notionally<br />

aimed at the practitioner’s market. But if you saw the author sitting<br />

so uneasily at a party you would think him to be the most interesting<br />

person in the room. You might also, it has to be said, place yourself<br />

behind the fishtank to avoid that slightly manic eye and the five-hour<br />

argument that would surely ensue from meeting it.<br />

2 Burdens<br />

When we discussed what to talk about at <strong>this</strong> event Stu and I agreed<br />

that we would focus on just one aspect of the chapter — burdens.<br />

Burdens is of course the application issue. ‘When jurists, lawyers and<br />

academics say they wish to talk about the application of the Bill of<br />

Rights under the Final Constitution’, Stu contends, ‘by and large, they<br />

have a single vexed question in mind: Upon whom do the burdens of<br />

the Bill of Rights fall?’ 3 He is right that burdens (‘duties’, or, more<br />

precisely still, the burdening of private actors with duties to respect<br />

rights) is the issue over which most ink has been spilled and,<br />

continuing the practice, over which <strong>this</strong> chapter spills most of its ink.<br />

But is that adjective quite correct — is it really a ‘vexed’ question? —<br />

and is he right that ‘jurists’ (meaning, I think, judges) and ‘lawyers’<br />

are quite as vexed about it as academics have been?<br />

The fact is that the case law on application (in the ‘burdens’<br />

sense) under the Final Constitution really does not make much of a<br />

3<br />

S Woolman ‘True in theory, true in practice: Why direct application still matters’<br />

in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations (2008) 112.


Reply - Iain Currie 141<br />

fuss about it. In Khumalo the Constitutional Court disposed of section<br />

8 in five Delphic paragraphs 4 that fall apart if you try to read them too<br />

closely (‘gossamer thin fabric’ is Stu’s nice description of those<br />

paragraphs). 5 Nevertheless, it is hard to read Khumalo as saying<br />

anything other than that section 8(2) direct application is the correct<br />

mode of application in most horizontal disputes. However in Thebus<br />

the Court, without reference to Khumalo and without reference to<br />

any of the academic literature on the issue, said nothing about the<br />

difficult relationship between section 8 and section 39, but hinted in<br />

yet another couple of puzzling paragraphs that section 39 (indirect<br />

application) was the default mode for considering challenges to the<br />

common law. 6 K v Minister of Safety and Security seems to say much<br />

the same thing, but also gives a more active role to the previously<br />

neglected section 8(1). 7 Read these three decisions (and Carmichele) 8<br />

and you have pretty much exhausted the Constitutional Court’s<br />

output on the horizontality issue. 9<br />

None of it reads like the work of a court that finds the issue<br />

particularly vexing (contrast it, for example, with the evident<br />

vexation brought on by the issue of the application of PAJA in the<br />

New-Clicks decision). 10 All of <strong>this</strong> output is, Stu’s apt description<br />

again, ‘under-theorised’ (in places, it is not theorised at all). 11 Nor<br />

will you find a great deal more in the output of the High Courts or the<br />

SCA. Is <strong>this</strong> because application (at least the vexed issue of the form<br />

of application applicable in horizontal cases) is an academic issue of<br />

little concern to actual legal practice?<br />

3 Drafting history<br />

What is the burdens issue? A brief drafting history of the application<br />

provisions of the Final Constitution is necessary to answer <strong>this</strong><br />

question. In Du Plessis v De Klerk 12 the Constitutional Court held that<br />

4 Khumalo & Others v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 (CC), 2002 8 BCLR 771 (CC) paras 29-<br />

33.<br />

5 Woolman (n 3 above) 118.<br />

6 S v Thebus & Another 2003 6 SA 505 (CC), 2003 10 BCLR 1100 (CC) paras 24-32.<br />

7<br />

K v Minister of Safety and Security 2005 6 SA 419 (CC), 2005 9 BCLR 835 (CC)<br />

paras 13-19.<br />

8 Carmichele v Minister of Safety & Security 2001 4 SA 938 (CC), 2001 10 BCLR 995<br />

(CC).<br />

9 Subsequent to delivering <strong>this</strong> paper, the Court handed down Barkhuizen v Napier<br />

2007 5 SA 323 (CC), 2007 7 BCLR 691 (CC). Barkhuizen addressed horizontal<br />

application of the Bill of Rights to contracts.<br />

10 Minister of Health & Another NO v New Clicks South Africa (Pty) Ltd & Others<br />

(Treatment Action Campaign & Another as Amici Curiae) 2006 2 SA 311 (CC), 2006<br />

1 BCLR 1 (CC).<br />

11 Contrast the Final Constitution case law — Khumalo in particular — with the level<br />

of close textual attention and theoretical and comparative reflection in Du Plessis<br />

v De Klerk 1996 3 SA 850 (CC), 1996 5 BCLR 658 (CC).<br />

12 n 11 above.


142 Chapter 9<br />

the interim Bill of Rights did not have direct application in so-called<br />

‘horizontal’ disputes; that is to disputes between private litigants<br />

governed by the common law. This was principally because of the<br />

absence of the word ‘judiciary’ in IC section 7: ‘[The Bill of Rights]<br />

shall bind all legislative and executive organs of state at all levels of<br />

government’. The omission meant that the Bill of Rights placed duties<br />

to uphold constitutional rights only on the legislative and executive<br />

organs of state. Individuals were not directly bound by the Bill of<br />

Rights. The interim Bill of Rights did however have indirect<br />

application. Even if individuals were not directly bound by the Bill of<br />

Rights, the courts had to interpret legislation and to develop the<br />

common law so that the ordinary law recognised and protected the<br />

rights in the Bill of Rights. Note that <strong>this</strong> approach requires a strong<br />

distinction to be maintained between two forms of application of the<br />

Bill of Rights: direct and indirect.<br />

With the Du Plessis decision in mind, and concerned that confining<br />

the Bill of Rights to direct vertical application would result in the<br />

toleration of private violations of rights, the Constitutional Assembly<br />

created a different application and jurisdictional scheme in the Final<br />

Constitution with the intention of providing for direct horizontal<br />

application. The textual changes were:<br />

(a) the addition of the words ‘judiciary’ and ‘all law’ in section 8(1),<br />

missing from the corresponding application provision of the Interim<br />

Constitution;<br />

(b) the direct imposition of duties to uphold rights on individuals in<br />

section 8(2) ‘to the extent that [the right] is applicable, taking into<br />

account the nature of the right and the nature of any duty imposed by<br />

the right’;<br />

(c) while envisaging direct horizontal application in ‘applicable’ cases,<br />

the 1996 Bill of Rights also required the courts to apply the Bill of Rights<br />

indirectly, in similar terms to section 35(3) of the Interim Constitution.<br />

FC section 39(2) states: ‘When interpreting any legislation, and when<br />

developing the common law or customary law, every court, tribunal or<br />

forum must promote the spirit, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights’.<br />

There is no doubt that these changes were intended to introduce<br />

direct horizontal application. However, they also created a number of<br />

interpretative puzzles that make up what we are calling the ‘burdens<br />

issue’: (a) what is the impact of including the judiciary in section 8(1),<br />

the direct application provision of the Final Constitution? (b) what on<br />

earth does section 8(2) mean and how does it interact with section<br />

8(1)? (c) when, in horizontal cases, will it be appropriate to use<br />

section 39(2) (ie indirect rather than direct application)?<br />

The judiciary dealt with these puzzles using an ancient judicial<br />

strategem: It ignored them. The presence of the indirect application<br />

provisions of section 35(3) of the Interim Constitution (and now in


Reply - Iain Currie 143<br />

section 39(2) of the Final Constitution), Kentridge AJ prophetically<br />

stated in Du Plessis, ‘makes much of the vertical/horizontal debate<br />

irrelevant’. 13 Since Du Plessis, under both the Interim and Final<br />

Constitutions, the courts have routinely approached the issue of the<br />

effect of the Bill of Rights on the common law indirectly. The<br />

invitation of section 8(2) — to apply rights directly in horizontal<br />

situations — was snubbed. Khumalo seemed, in its fuzzy way, to signal<br />

a change — giving direct horizontality something of the role that the<br />

drafters of the Final Constitution had envisaged for it. But since then<br />

(Thebus, 14 K 15 and most of the output of the High Courts 16 and the<br />

SCA) 17 , Khumalo has been quietly forgotten and horizontal<br />

application has returned to its well-worn, indirect groove.<br />

4 The Woolmanian Reading<br />

But the reassuring comforts of old, bad habits are not available to the<br />

theorist. Theory demands a solution to the interpretative puzzles<br />

above, moreover it must be a solution that coheres with all other<br />

aspects of constitutional doctrine: ‘the manifold doctrinal demands of<br />

indirect application, stare decisis, the rule of law, constitutional<br />

jurisdiction, objective unconstitutionality, textual plausibility and<br />

naturalness’. 18 Here then is my long deferred summary of the<br />

Woolmanian ‘preferred reading’ of the Final provisions (distinguished<br />

from the ‘black-letter law’ laid down in Khumalo’s enigmatic five<br />

paragraphs):<br />

13 Du Plessis (n 11 above) para 60.<br />

14 n 6 above.<br />

15<br />

n 7 above.<br />

16 See, eg, Seema v Lid van die Uitvoerende Raad vir Gesondheid, Gauteng 2002 1<br />

SA 771 (T); Geldenhuys v Minister of Safety and Security 2002 4 SA 719 (C).<br />

17<br />

See, eg, Minister of Safety and Security & Another v Hamilton 2004 2 SA 416<br />

(SCA); Van Eeden v Minister of Safety and Security (Women’s Legal Centre as<br />

Amicus Curiae) 2003 1 SA 389 (SCA); Minister of Safety and Security v Van<br />

Duivenboden 2003 1 SA 389 (SCA)<br />

18 Woolman (n 2 above) 31-13, n1 and Woolman (n 3 above) n 19.


144 Chapter 9<br />

Provisions of the<br />

Constitution<br />

8(1): The Bill of Rights<br />

applies to all law, and<br />

binds the legislature,<br />

the executive, the judiciary<br />

and all organs of<br />

state<br />

8(2): A provision of the<br />

Bill of Rights binds a<br />

natural or a juristic person<br />

if, and to the extent<br />

that, it is applicable,<br />

taking into account the<br />

nature of the right and<br />

the nature of any duty<br />

imposed by the right.<br />

8(3): When applying a<br />

provision of the Bill of<br />

Rights to a natural or juristic<br />

person in terms of<br />

subsection (2), a court:<br />

(a) in order to give effect<br />

to a right in the<br />

Bill, must apply, or if<br />

necessary develop, the<br />

common law to the extent<br />

that legislation<br />

does not give effect to<br />

that right; and<br />

(b) may develop rules of<br />

the common law to limit<br />

the right, provided that<br />

the limitation is in accordance<br />

with section<br />

36(1).<br />

The ‘black letter’<br />

reading<br />

The Bill of Rights applies<br />

directly to (a) all law<br />

governing disputes between<br />

the state and individuals<br />

(b) state<br />

conduct giving rise to a<br />

dispute between the<br />

state and an individual.<br />

In the case of disputes<br />

between individuals<br />

(horizontal disputes)<br />

see s 8(2).<br />

Disputes between individuals<br />

may be subject<br />

to the direct application<br />

of the Bill of Rights. This<br />

depends on the ‘the intensity<br />

of the constitutional<br />

right in question’.<br />

In disputes governed by<br />

s 8(2), a court must<br />

remedy infringements<br />

of constitutional rights<br />

by developing the law.<br />

The Woolmanian<br />

‘preferred reading’<br />

The Bill of Rights applies<br />

directly to all<br />

law. It also applies<br />

directly to all state<br />

conduct.<br />

This applies to horizontal<br />

disputes over<br />

conduct ‘not “adequately”<br />

governed’<br />

by a rule of law. ‘FC s<br />

8(2) calls attention to<br />

the potential gap between<br />

extant rules of<br />

law and the prescriptive<br />

content of the<br />

Bill of Rights, and,<br />

where necessary, requires<br />

the courts to<br />

bridge that gap by<br />

bringing the law into<br />

line with the demands<br />

of the particular<br />

constitutional<br />

right or rights<br />

deemed to apply’.<br />

The same.


Reply - Iain Currie 145<br />

39(2): When interpreting<br />

any legislation, and<br />

when developing the<br />

common law or customary<br />

law, every court,<br />

tribunal or forum must<br />

promote the spirit, purport<br />

and objects of the<br />

Bill of Rights.<br />

In horizontal disputes This applies where s 8<br />

where sec 8(2) does not does not: in cases<br />

apply the Bill of Rights where ‘the prescriptive<br />

content of the<br />

must be indirectly applied.<br />

substantive provision<br />

of the Bill of Rights<br />

does not engage the<br />

and<br />

rule of law or conduct<br />

at issue’. b Even<br />

though no specific<br />

‘Even where a right is right can be relied on<br />

asserted directly, the by a party challenging<br />

a rule or the ex-<br />

court may still speak as<br />

if a finding of inconsistency<br />

or invalidity re-<br />

if a rule of law, the<br />

isting interpretation<br />

quires that a new rule of courts must interpret<br />

common law be developed<br />

in terms of FC op the law in light of<br />

legislation and devel-<br />

section 39(2)’. a the general objects<br />

of the Bill of Rights.<br />

a. See Woolman (n 2 above) 31-45 n 1. I think the ‘black-letter’ authority for <strong>this</strong> is<br />

Thebus (n 6 above) and K (n 7 above).<br />

b. Woolman (n 2 above) 31-46 and Woolman (n 3 above) 13.<br />

So the reconstructive aspects of the Woolmanian reading are:<br />

giving section 8(1) a far greater role to play in horizontal disputes —<br />

indeed it, and not section 8(2) is the default basis for application;<br />

confining section 8(2) to (rare) cases of a ‘gap’ in the law not<br />

adequately governing private conduct; similarly demoting section<br />

39(2) to apply only in instances where section 8 does not apply. The<br />

attractions of <strong>this</strong> reading are numerous: It coheres with the doctrine<br />

of objective constitutionality (which makes the form of a dispute (ie,<br />

who the parties happen to be) irrelevant to the objective<br />

constitutional issues it raises); it provides a nice solution to the<br />

problems raised by the SCA’s doctrine of stare decisis in Afrox; 19 it<br />

gives the central role to direct application that the drafters of section<br />

8 probably had in mind, while reducing section 8(2) and all its opaque<br />

qualifiers to a minor role. But it remains, as Stu admits, a theoretical<br />

reading that faces two practical difficulties: It is not what the<br />

Constitutional Court said in Khumalo; it is not what the courts post-<br />

Khumalo seem to be making of the application issue.<br />

19 Afrox Healthcare Bpk v Strydom 2002 6 SA 21 (SCA), [2002] 4 All SA 125 (SCA).


146 Chapter 9<br />

5 Theory v practice<br />

Why is there <strong>this</strong> gap between theory and practice? Why are the<br />

theoreticians so vexed about <strong>this</strong> aspect of application while the<br />

courts go about the business of indirect horizontal application with no<br />

trace of vexation and as though Du Plessis was still the law? I think<br />

much is explained by the widespread conviction that the form of<br />

application makes no difference: That indirect and direct application<br />

of the Bill of Rights to the common law are just different ways, as Stu<br />

puts it, of singing the same song. In addition, whereas under the<br />

Interim Constitution there were important jurisdictional consequences<br />

that followed the form of application, those consequences<br />

are of greatly diminished importance under the unitary jurisdictional<br />

scheme of the Final Constitution. 20 If that is so then there really is not<br />

much worth fussing about in the application issue. The Final<br />

Constitution applies to the law and, in the case of the common law<br />

(‘the courts’ own law’ as Moseneke J puts it in Thebus), 21 the correct<br />

approach is to assess its constitutionality and to change it where<br />

necessary. The only reason these days to go to all the trouble of<br />

deploying direct horizontal application (which requires grappling with<br />

Khumalo and with section 8(2)) would be to take advantage of the<br />

holding of the SCA in Afrox that courts in direct application cases are<br />

not bound by pre-1994 decisions. 22<br />

So, despite its theoretical attractions, why bother with the<br />

Woolmanian approach at all? Much turns on the correctness of the<br />

conviction that, when it comes to the common law, the form of<br />

application — whether direct or indirect — makes no practical<br />

difference since the outcome of the use of either form of application<br />

is the same. Robert Alexy, writing about the theories used to explain<br />

the horizontal effect of the German Constitution, calls <strong>this</strong> outcomeneutrality.<br />

23 Are direct and indirect horizontal application under the<br />

South African Constitution outcome-neutral? If they are not, then the<br />

courts’ indirect-application-by-default approach will have to be<br />

20 Under the Interim Constitution only direct application was within the<br />

Constitutional Court’s jurisdiction. Indirect application was not.<br />

21<br />

Thebus (n 6 above) para 31.<br />

22 This is why Khumalo (n 4 above) was pitched as a direct application case — to<br />

bypass the SCA’s negative holding on the issue of the plaintiff’s onus in National<br />

Media Ltd & Others v Bogoshi 1998 4 SA 1196 (SCA), 1999 1 BCLR 1 (SCA), [1998] 4<br />

All SA 347 (SCA) (which was, sort of, an indirect application case).<br />

23 R Alexy A theory of constitutional rights trans J Rivers (2002) 357: ‘Two juridical<br />

constructions are outcome-neutral if every outcome which could be achieved in<br />

the context of one could also achieved in the context of the other’. There are,<br />

according to Alexy, theoretical reasons for arriving at the correct account of the<br />

effect of constitutional norms on private relations but no practical implications:<br />

‘Each theory [indirect effect, direct effect, mediation by rights against the state]<br />

expresses an aspect of the same matter. Which is chosen in the process of legal<br />

justification is a question of utility. None of them can claim primacy over the<br />

others’.


Reply - Iain Currie 147<br />

revisited and replaced with something more theoretically sound. Stu<br />

clearly thinks the two forms are different and that the direct/indirect<br />

distinction makes a difference. But I could not immediately find in the<br />

text a convincing explanation of why (but it is, as I may have<br />

mentioned, a lengthy text and I have to confess that I have postponed<br />

reading that famous Appendix until my next sabbatical). So <strong>this</strong> is my<br />

opportunity to ask him in person and is the point of these remarks. Is<br />

direct horizontality necessary? Is there any reason other than the<br />

beauty of our theories to bother with it?


10<br />

LIMITATIONS:<br />

SHARED CONSTITUTIONAL<br />

INTERPRETATION, AN<br />

APPROPRIATE NORMATIVE<br />

FRAMEWORK & HARD CHOICES<br />

Stu Woolman & Henk Botha<br />

1 Introduction<br />

Let us begin with three rather unassailable assumptions. First, the<br />

general limitation clause articulates standards for the justification of<br />

restrictions placed by law upon the exercise of fundamental rights.<br />

Second, these standards are expressed in rather rarefied rules that<br />

courts make concrete through their application to discrete cases.<br />

Third, limitations analysis allows for open and candid consideration of<br />

competing interests. Taken together, these three statements give<br />

expression to what the Constitutional Court has taken to be one of the<br />

most basic principles in the Final Constitution: That every exercise of<br />

public power derives its force from basic law, needs to be justified by<br />

reference to the basic law, 1 and that only open and public processes<br />

of rational deliberation produce acceptable forms of justification. 2<br />

Despite the fact that these standards are produced openly and<br />

publicly, or perhaps because of it, they are often hotly contested.<br />

Courts cannot, and do not, simply apply the requirements of the text<br />

of the limitation clause mechanically. Courts need to explain how<br />

they understand the demands of the text and why those demands<br />

have certain consequences for the disposition of a case. As a result,<br />

1 See Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA: In Re Ex Parte President of<br />

the Republic of South Africa 2000 2 SA 674 (CC), 2000 3 BCLR 241 (CC).<br />

2 See K v Minister of Safety and Security 2005 6 SA 419 (CC), 2005 9 BCLR 835 (CC).<br />

149


150 Chapter 10<br />

judges themselves are subject to the demand for justification. They<br />

must be able to explain why they have given the standards the<br />

content that they have, and why they have applied them in a given<br />

fashion. By doing so, they signal their respect for the parties before<br />

them, provide guidance to legislators, fellow judges and prospective<br />

litigants, and, perhaps most importantly of all, model rational<br />

political discourse through participation in an ongoing debate about<br />

the meaning of constitutional norms. 3<br />

These initial observations suggest that Bill of Rights litigation,<br />

rightly conceived, reflects an ongoing dialogue about the meaning of<br />

fundamental rights and the cogency of the justifications offered for<br />

their limitation. 4 From <strong>this</strong> perspective, the courts’ exercise of<br />

powers of judicial review is best understood as part of a shared<br />

project of constitutional interpretation. This project requires that the<br />

courts, through thoroughly reasoned engagement with the<br />

constitutional text, produce a normative framework of sufficient<br />

density to guide other political actors, organs of state and social<br />

agents. At the same time, a doctrine of shared constitutional<br />

interpretation encourages other actors to place their own gloss on<br />

constitutional norms and to experiment with different policy options<br />

consistent with the basic law.<br />

Put slightly differently, powers of judicial review are best<br />

understood not as part of a battle for ascendancy between courts and<br />

legislatures (though they may turn into that) nor a means of<br />

frustrating the will of the political majority, but rather as a<br />

commitment of our basic law to shared constitutional interpretation.<br />

This commitment to shared constitutional interpretation supplants<br />

the traditional notion of judicial supremacy with respect to<br />

constitutional interpretation — all branches of government have a<br />

relatively equal stake in giving our basic law content. While courts<br />

retain the power to determine the content of any given provision, a<br />

commitment to shared constitutional interpretation means that a<br />

court ought to limit consciously the reach of its holding regarding the<br />

meaning of a given provision and to invite the political branches of<br />

government, organs of state, civil society associations and individual<br />

citizens to come up with their own alternative, but ultimately<br />

3<br />

See S v Steyn 2001 1 SA 1146 (CC), 2001 1 BCLR 52 (CC) (Previous findings of the<br />

Constitutional Court do not absolve legislatures from the duty to deliberate about<br />

the constitutionality of bills before them, or to justify limitations of fundamental<br />

rights.)<br />

4 See S v Mhlungu 1995 3 SA 867 (CC), 1995 7 BCLR 793 (CC) para 129<br />

(Constitutional interpretation takes the form of ‘a principled judicial dialogue, in<br />

the first place between members of <strong>this</strong> Court, then between our Court and other<br />

courts, the legal profession, law schools, Parliament, and, indirectly, with the<br />

public at large’.) See also H Botha ‘Rights, limitations, and the (im)possibility of<br />

self-government’ in H Botha, A van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and<br />

democracy in a transformative constitution (2003) 13 24-25.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 151<br />

consistent, gloss on the text. Shared constitutional interpretation<br />

married to a rather open-ended or provisional understanding of the<br />

content of the basic law means that the Constitutional Court’s<br />

limitations analysis might be best understood in terms of norm-setting<br />

behaviour that provides guidance to other state actors and interested<br />

parties without foreclosing the possibility of other effective<br />

safeguards for rights or other useful methods for their realisation.<br />

Shared constitutional interpretation within experimentalist framework<br />

ought to reveal ‘best practices’ with respect to the realisation<br />

of constitutional objectives and should offer us regular opportunities<br />

to rethink the meaning — and the constraints — of our basic law. 5<br />

In the pages that follow, we assess the ability of the Constitutional<br />

Court to delineate clearly rights analysis and limitations analysis, to<br />

‘balance’ rights, to distinguish the core of a right from its penumbra,<br />

and to construct a framework for limitations analysis that both (a)<br />

enables the parties before the court to make arguments that fully<br />

ventilate the issues raised and (b) reinforces our democratic lawmaking<br />

processes so that they take adequate account of the<br />

constitutional imperative to create ‘an open and democratic society’<br />

based upon the democratic values of ‘human dignity, equality and<br />

freedom’. After a critical appraisal of the Court’s efforts in <strong>this</strong><br />

regard, we offer our own thick(er) conception of what limitations<br />

analysis ought to look like. We offer <strong>this</strong> thicker conception not<br />

because we think that it is, in the abstract, to be preferred. We<br />

proffer the thicker conception because we think that the Court’s<br />

current approach to rights interpretation and limitations analysis<br />

lacks analytical rigour.<br />

That thicker conception begins with an appropriate standard of<br />

review for limitations analysis. This standard of review takes the form<br />

of, what we called above, a doctrine of shared constitutional<br />

interpretation. This doctrine mediates between the doctrine of<br />

constitutional supremacy (a doctrine that does not shy away from the<br />

necessity of judicial law-making) and the doctrine of separation of<br />

powers (a doctrine that often justifies the ‘need’ for judicial<br />

deference). That said, the courts must still articulate a general<br />

normative framework that gives the standard of review real purchase<br />

5<br />

See S Woolman The selfless constitution: Experimentation and flourishing as the<br />

foundations of South Africa’s basic law (forthcoming 2008); M Dorf & B Friedman<br />

‘Shared constitutional interpretation’ (2000) Supreme Court Review 61; National<br />

Education Health and Allied Workers Union v University of Cape Town & Others<br />

2003 3 SA 1 (CC), 2003 2 BCLR 154 (CC) para 14 (‘Where the Legislature enacts<br />

legislation in the effort to meet its constitutional obligations, and does so within<br />

constitutional limits, courts must give full effect to the legislative purpose.<br />

Moreover, the proper interpretation of such legislation will ensure the protection,<br />

promotion and fulfilment of constitutional rights and as such will be a<br />

constitutional matter. In <strong>this</strong> way, the courts and the Legislature act in<br />

partnership to give life to constitutional rights.’)


152 Chapter 10<br />

and which thereby guides the behaviour of political actors and<br />

citizens alike. In the Final Constitution, and in FC section 36 in<br />

particular, the creation of a normative framework adequate to the<br />

task of limitations analysis turns on giving adequate content to the<br />

phrase ‘open and democratic society based on human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom’. This task requires that we do something which<br />

the courts themselves have only gotten half-right: We offer a<br />

description of how the value of dignity and the principle of democracy<br />

work — in tandem — to produce, in Theunis Roux’s words, a political<br />

system in which ‘rights ... lie at the very heart of South African<br />

democracy’. 6 Thus, whereas the Court has privileged the value of<br />

dignity over the other four values found in the Final Constitution’s<br />

favourite catchphrase, we reassert the priority of democracy. That<br />

reassertion does not, of course, provide an easy algorithm for<br />

resolving conflicts between various rights, values and other pressing,<br />

constitutionally-mandated, imperatives. Even if, as we have argued<br />

previously, and Professor Roux himself notes, fundamental rights<br />

analysis and limitations analysis are both driven by a commitment to<br />

rights and democracy, courts are still left with the decidedly difficult<br />

task of harmonising constitutionally-permissible, but conflicting,<br />

ends. As we suggest in our critique of balancing, the goods reflected<br />

in rights and in laws are often incommensurable. Conflict resolution<br />

in the face of value incommensurability requires substantially more<br />

than the invocation of such pat metaphors as the ‘scales of justice’.<br />

In our final, highly speculative section, we defend the use of a<br />

particular form of judicial narrative-making — storytelling. The<br />

difference between story-telling as the preferred form of judicial<br />

narrative-making in hard cases and the reliance on cryptic<br />

justifications for hard choices is the difference between a good<br />

explanation and a bad explanation for the decisions that courts take<br />

in terms of FC section 36. The better the explanation, the more<br />

persuasive it will be. For those who need persuading, the more<br />

persuasive the decision, the more legitimate it will be deemed to be.<br />

Storytelling, properly understood, is a rhetorical form that enables<br />

judges, in Sachs J’s words, to challenge the ‘hydraulic insistence on<br />

conformity to majoritarian standards’ and to consider a range of<br />

possible outcomes that might not otherwise have occurred to judges<br />

or their public. 7<br />

6 T Roux ‘Democracy’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa<br />

(2nd Edition, OS, 2006) §10.3, available at www.westlaw.com.<br />

7<br />

Prince v President of the Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope 2001 2 SA 388<br />

(CC), 2001 2 BCLR 133 (CC) para 156.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 153<br />

2 Delineating rights analysis and limitations analysis<br />

This section attempts to answer a basic question in Bill of Rights<br />

analysis: How does fundamental rights analysis relate to limitation<br />

clause analysis? That is, what happens in the first stage of analysis,<br />

what remains to be done in the second stage, why do we allocate<br />

certain analytical tasks to one stage and not the other, and how do<br />

we justify our overall approach to constitutional interpretation?<br />

FC section 39 tells us that the content and the scope of the rights<br />

enshrined in Chapter 2 should be determined in the light of the five<br />

fundamental values which animate the entire constitutional enterprise:<br />

openness, democracy, human dignity, freedom, and equality.<br />

FC section 39 thereby confirms that the determination of a right’s<br />

scope is a value-based exercise. However, the scope-determinative<br />

values are not limited to the five identified in FC section 39. For each<br />

right there are specific values that can be said to have led to its<br />

constitutionalisation. The specific values that animate each right,<br />

along with FC section 39’s more general concerns, determine the<br />

right’s sphere of protected activity. On <strong>this</strong> account, if an applicant<br />

can show that the exercise of constitutionally protected activity has<br />

been impaired, then she has made a prima facie showing of a<br />

constitutional infringement. If the infringement was authorised by<br />

law, then the state or the party relying upon <strong>this</strong> law will have an<br />

opportunity to justify its prima facie infringement of the right under<br />

the limitation clause.<br />

There is of course another way to go. That approach, quite often<br />

adopted by the Constitutional Court, suggests that any activity which<br />

could notionally fall within the ambit of a right is protected. It<br />

remains then to show that the law — as opposed to mere conduct —<br />

actually limits the exercise of the right before moving on to the heart<br />

of FC section 36 analysis. 8<br />

8<br />

8<br />

See Coetzee v Government of the Republic of South Africa; Matiso & Others v<br />

Commanding Officer, Port Elizabeth Prison 1995 4 SA 631 (CC), 1995 10 BCLR 1382<br />

(CC) paras 46-47 (Sachs J concludes that, in his view, ‘faithfulness to the<br />

Constitution is best achieved by locating the two-stage balancing process within a<br />

holistic, value-based and case-oriented framework’. There are several potential<br />

problems with Sachs J’s intervention on <strong>this</strong> subject. First, a two-stage approach<br />

is not necessarily ‘formal’ or ‘academic’. The quality of the inquiry depends on<br />

the nature of the questions asked, not on their number or their order. Secondly, it<br />

is impossible to know what Sachs J means by a ‘synergetic relationship’ between<br />

the two stages of analysis or by the ‘exercise ... of a structured and disciplined<br />

value judgment’ when he gives neither examples nor further description of these<br />

processes. Thirdly, and most disturbing, is Sachs J’s vision of a ‘two-stage<br />

balancing process within a holistic, value-based and case-oriented framework’.<br />

Sachs J’s apparent vision of balancing at both stages ignores the clear intention<br />

and the structure of a Bill of Rights which possesses both fundamental rights and a<br />

general limitations clause: That different forms of analysis will take place at


154 Chapter 10<br />

There are several reasons to prefer the first approach to the<br />

Court’s approach. First, it is consistent with the text’s admonition<br />

that provisions of the Bill of Rights be interpreted in light of the<br />

‘values which underlie an open and democratic society based on<br />

human dignity, equality and freedom’. The Final Constitution was not<br />

meant to protect certain forms of behaviour and a value-based<br />

approach permits us to screen out those forms of behaviour which do<br />

not merit constitutional protection. 9 Secondly, high value-based<br />

barriers for the first stage of analysis mean that only genuine and<br />

serious violations of a constitutional right make it through to FC<br />

section 36. If only serious infringements make it through, then the<br />

court can take a fairly rigorous approach with respect to the<br />

justification for the impairment. It could then be fairly confident that<br />

when it nullified law or conduct there would be something worth<br />

protecting. Thirdly, the valued-based approach is consistent with the<br />

notion that a ‘unity of values’ underlies both the rights-infringement<br />

determination and the limitation-justification analysis. The language<br />

of the interpretation clause and the limitation clause strongly<br />

suggests that both inquiries are driven by a desire to serve the five<br />

values underlying our entire constitutional enterprise: openness,<br />

democracy, human dignity, freedom and equality.<br />

The desirability of the value-based approach is perhaps clearer<br />

when compared with the consequences of the notional or the<br />

expansive approach to rights interpretation. First, the notional<br />

approach suggests that certain forms of behaviour which we believe<br />

do not merit constitutional protection will in fact receive prima facie<br />

protection. Secondly, the notional approach expands the number of<br />

claims that make it to the second stage of analysis. The result is that<br />

different stages of analysis. The first stage of analysis is generally understood to<br />

require the judge to determine the ambit of the right. The determination is made<br />

by asking what values underlie the right and then, in turn, what practices serve<br />

those values. The judge is not required to compare the importance of the values<br />

underlying the right allegedly being infringed with the values said to underlie the<br />

policy or right or interest said to support the alleged infringement. This<br />

comparison is left for the second stage of analysis under the limitations clause. It<br />

is under the limitations clause that we ask whether a party’s interest in having a<br />

challenged law upheld is of sufficient import to justify the infringement of a<br />

right.) For good examples of the Court’s notional approach to rights analysis, see<br />

Beinash v Ernst & Young 1999 2 SA 116 (CC), 1999 2 BCLR 125 (CC); Christian<br />

Education South Africa v Minister of Education 2000 4 SA 757 (CC), 2000 4 BCLR<br />

1051 (CC) (Constitutional Court simply assumed that the exercise of FC secs 15<br />

and 31 had been impaired by the South African Schools Acts. The rights<br />

interpretation was not even notional. It was non-existent.) See also Prince (n 7<br />

above) (Court assumes that criminal proscription of dagga use violates FC s 15’s<br />

right to freedom of religion.)<br />

9 See Justice O’Regan ‘On the reach of the Constitution and the nature of<br />

constitutional jurisdiction: A reply to F Michelman’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds)<br />

Constitutional conversations (2008) Chapter 5.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 155<br />

if the courts wish to curtail their findings of unconstitutionality, their<br />

criteria for the justification of government limitations on rights have<br />

to become more flexible. The further possibility exists that in order<br />

to make their justificatory criteria more flexible, the courts will<br />

expand the kinds of objectives which justify limitations on<br />

constitutional rights. This result would seem to stand in direct conflict<br />

with the textual demand that both rights interpretation and<br />

limitations analysis be undertaken in the light of the needs of an open<br />

and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and<br />

freedom. Finally, by pushing all of the Chapter 2 analysis into the<br />

limitation clause, and forcing themselves to be more flexible with<br />

respect to the grounds for justification of a limitation, the courts<br />

undercut their ability to articulate analytically rigorous conceptions<br />

of rights at the first stage of analysis and useful standards of<br />

justification for limitations at the second stage of analysis.<br />

3 Balancing as a bad metaphor<br />

One of the most noteworthy features of the Constitutional Court’s<br />

limitations jurisprudence is the way it conceives of the relationship<br />

between the different factors that FC section 36 suggests that one<br />

consider. The Court understands these factors — FC section 36(1)(a)-<br />

FC section 36(1)(e) — to be closely interrelated. Far from representing<br />

a ‘sequential check-list’ that can be adhered to ‘mechanically’, the<br />

factors are to be considered within the broader context of a<br />

‘balancing exercise’ and a ‘global judgment on proportionality’.<br />

This approach has taken many commentators by surprise. Prior to<br />

the judgment in Makwanyane, 10 it was widely expected that the Court<br />

would model its analysis of the reasonableness and justifiability of<br />

fundamental-rights limitations on the approach adopted by the<br />

Canadian Supreme Court in R v Oakes. 11 However, the approach of the<br />

Makwanyane Court represents a significant departure from the Oakes<br />

test. The Oakes test proceeds in distinct stages: first, it is asked<br />

whether the limitation serves a sufficiently important objective;<br />

second, whether the limitation is rationally connected to the said<br />

objective; third, whether the limitation impairs the right as little as<br />

possible; and fourth, whether the actual benefits of the limitation are<br />

proportionate to its deleterious consequences for the rights-holder.<br />

The need to consider the second question arises only once the first leg<br />

of the test has been satisfied; the third question is addressed only<br />

once the first and second questions have been answered in the<br />

10 S v Makwanyane 1995 3 SA 391 (CC), 1995 6 BCLR 665 (CC), 1995 2 SACR 1 (CC).<br />

11 See S Woolman ‘Riding-the push-me-pull-you: Constructing a test that reconciles<br />

the conflicting interests which animate the limitation clause’ (1994) 10 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 60 84–90.


156 Chapter 10<br />

affirmative, and so on. This sequential exercise is substantially<br />

different from an approach grounded in balancing and proportionality.<br />

12 Not only is it more structured, but a ‘balancing<br />

exercise’ is undertaken only at the very end of the inquiry, once it has<br />

been established that the limitation does serve an important<br />

objective, that it is rationally connected to such an objective, and<br />

that it impairs the right as little as possible. If the limitation fails any<br />

of the first three legs, the court need not engage in cost-benefit<br />

analysis.<br />

That the Oakes test should be seen as worthy of emulation in<br />

South Africa after 1994 is hardly surprising. The test represents a bold<br />

attempt to come to terms with the sometimes conflicting doctrines of<br />

constitutional supremacy and separation of powers. The Oakes test<br />

subjects fundamental-rights limitations to rigorous scrutiny, refuses<br />

to lend legitimacy to the limitation of rights in the name of a crass<br />

utilitarian calculus, links conceptually the grounds for finding a rights<br />

infringement to the grounds for finding that such a limitation is<br />

justified, and offers a sophisticated understanding of the proper<br />

degree of deference the courts owe the legislature. Finally, the Oakes<br />

test promotes analytically rigorous and politically candid judicial<br />

reasoning.<br />

But that is not the direction that we have chosen to go. In the end,<br />

the Constitutional Court has opted for balancing. The metaphor of<br />

balancing is so deeply embedded in our constitutional discourse that<br />

we often use it without giving the actual meaning of the metaphor a<br />

second thought. Our purpose in <strong>this</strong> section is to offer (a) several<br />

definitions of balancing and (b) a number of trenchant critiques of the<br />

practice. 13 This exercise is meant to clear the space for our preferred<br />

reading of FC section 36.<br />

3.1 Definitions of balancing<br />

Balancing means the ‘head-to-head’ comparison of competing rights,<br />

values or interests. It takes two basic forms.<br />

Sometimes balancing means that one right (or interest or value)<br />

will simply ‘outweigh’ another right (or interest or value). For<br />

example, in Makwanyane, the Court held that the applicant’s right<br />

not to be subject to cruel, inhuman and degrading punishment<br />

(informed by the right to life and the right to human dignity)<br />

12<br />

Cf P Hogg ‘Canadian law in the Constitutional Court of South Africa’ (1998) 13<br />

South African Public Law 1 7.<br />

13 For a good faith reconstruction and critique of the Court’s doctrines of balancing<br />

and proportionality, see S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations’ in S Woolman et al (n<br />

6 above) Chapter 34.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 157<br />

outweighed the state’s interest in the death penalty for the sake of<br />

retribution and communal catharsis. In purely clinical terms, the<br />

death penalty impaired the right not to be subject to cruel, inhuman<br />

and degrading punishment and could not be justified in terms of IC<br />

section 33.<br />

Sometimes balancing means ‘the striking of a balance’ between<br />

competing rights or interests. No right is asked to pay the ultimate<br />

price. In Minister of Home Affairs v Fourie, same-sex life partners<br />

contended that their rights to equality and to human dignity were<br />

impaired by laws that prevented them from entering into civillysanctioned<br />

marriages. 14 Leaders of religious and traditional<br />

communities contended that the state and the Court had no business<br />

demanding that they alter their beliefs or practices to accommodate<br />

gay and lesbian unions. The Court split the baby and engaged in <strong>this</strong><br />

second form of balancing. While acknowledging that the rights of<br />

same-sex life partners to equality and to dignity were unjustifiably<br />

limited by rules of common law and statutory provisions that<br />

prevented them from entering civilly-sanctioned marriages, the<br />

Fourie Court went out of its way to note that religious prohibitions on<br />

gay and lesbian marriage did not constitute an unjustifiable<br />

infringement and that religious officials could legitimately refuse to<br />

consecrate a marriage between members of a same-sex life<br />

partnership.<br />

3.2 Critiques of balancing<br />

3.2.1 Pluralism, incommensurability and complexity<br />

Some critiques suggest that the discourse of balancing of<br />

constitutional rights, values or interests involves terminological<br />

confusion. Other critiques contend that ‘balancing’, in either of the<br />

two forms identified above, is an impossible undertaking. Our critique<br />

targets both the terminological and the theoretical confusion<br />

associated with balancing talk. 15<br />

We do not solely value things in quantitative terms: intensity or<br />

utility. We value things in qualitatively different ways. Furthermore,<br />

human beings generally do not value just one thing in life. Human<br />

14<br />

15<br />

Minister of Home Affairs & Another v Fourie & Another (Doctors for Life<br />

International & Others, Amici Curiae); Lesbian and Gay Equality Project & Others<br />

v Minister of Home Affairs & Others 2006 1 SA 524 (CC), 2006 3 BCLR 355 (CC).<br />

See, eg, M Tushnet ‘An essay on rights’ (1984) 62 Texas Law Review 1363 1372–73;<br />

T Aleinikoff ‘Constitutional law in the age of balancing’ (1987) 96 Yale Law<br />

Journal 943 972-76; S Woolman ‘Out of order? Out of balance? The limitation<br />

clause of the Final Constitution’ (1997) 13 South African Journal on Human Rights<br />

102 114–119.


158 Chapter 10<br />

beings value a vast array of goods. And we value each good in our own<br />

and its own particular way. This first claim about pluralism and the<br />

qualitatively different ways in which we value goods suggests a second<br />

claim. Human goods are often incommensurable. It is fair to say that<br />

the things we value most in life — friends, lovers, work, beauty,<br />

nature, and yes, money — cannot be compared with one another. Put<br />

differently, while we may be able to compare the virtues of friends<br />

with friends, the virtues of lovers with lovers, the virtues of work with<br />

work, the virtues of certain objects of beauty with other objects of<br />

beauty, and certainly the virtues of more money with less money,<br />

there is no single template against which we can measure claims of<br />

friendship, love, work, beauty, nature and money. They may compete<br />

with one another. But they compete in a way not easily assessed.<br />

Indeed, justice may require us to refrain, in so far as it is possible,<br />

from attempts to measure these competing goods by a single<br />

yardstick. Michael Walzer puts our second complex claim thus:<br />

There has never been a universal medium of exchange. ... [T]here has<br />

never been a single criterion, or a single set of interconnected criteria<br />

for all distributions. Desert, qualification, birth and blood, friendship,<br />

need, free exchange, political loyalty, democratic decision: each has<br />

had its place, along with many others, uneasily coexisting, invoked by<br />

competing groups, confused with one another. 16<br />

From these observations, Walzer draws the following conclusions.<br />

First, goods, like people, have shared meanings in a society, because<br />

goods, like people, are a product of social, political, economic,<br />

educational, religious and linguistic practices which generate<br />

meaning. Second, it is the shared meaning of a good which<br />

determines, or should determine, its distribution. Third, and perhaps<br />

most importantly for Walzer, when the meanings of social goods are<br />

distinct, their distributions must be autonomous. That is, for each<br />

good there exists a set of criteria and procedures deemed to be<br />

appropriate for its distribution.<br />

Walzer’s view may need to be qualified. The demands of justice<br />

— even in a world of plural and incommensurable goods — are, in fact,<br />

far more complex than Walzer’s account allows. First, spheres of<br />

human activity do overlap and thereby complicate the criteria for the<br />

distribution of any particular social good. Second, to the extent that<br />

some spheres of activity are inextricably linked, it is inevitable that<br />

the distribution of one good will influence the distribution of another.<br />

Third, given the spontaneous, evolutionary manner in which most<br />

spheres of activity have come into being — meaning they are never the<br />

product of a single agent — the criteria for the distribution of a social<br />

good are rarely going to be clear or conflict-free. The criteria for<br />

16 Spheres of Justice (1985) 4.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 159<br />

distribution are also rarely going to conform to a simple lexical<br />

ordering. Fourth, not only will criteria within spheres conflict, the<br />

individual criteria within the same sphere may be so indeterminate as<br />

not to yield a clear result in a given instance. Fifth, different goods<br />

can sometimes be measured along the same metric. We discover on<br />

closer analysis, for example, that friendship and military honour share<br />

a common value — loyalty — or we find that two different<br />

constitutional norms — equality and expression — undergird a third<br />

constitutional commitment — democratic participation. Sixth,<br />

spheres will not only overlap with one another, and through the<br />

domination of a party or group in one sphere effect the unjust<br />

distribution of some good in another sphere, but the criteria for<br />

distribution of a good in two different spheres may conflict directly<br />

with one another. The internal criteria of two spheres of activity may<br />

be such that it is impossible in a given situation to do justice to both.<br />

For instance, a commitment to a pristine environment may be<br />

completely at odds with a commitment to life, equality and economic<br />

development.<br />

Although <strong>this</strong> account of the relationship between spheres of<br />

activity and various goods is somewhat more complex than a pure<br />

pluralist account, the fact remains that, in innumerable instances,<br />

goods are incommensurable. Hard choices as to which good — and<br />

which goods — we pursue have to be made. 17 How should the Court<br />

handle hard choices?<br />

First, the Court must be candid and recognise that there will be<br />

situations in which constitutional goods will urge independent and<br />

irreconcilable claims upon us: In such situations, we will have to<br />

choose between incommensurable goods. 18 Second, the Court must<br />

acknowledge that it lacks a set of second-order rules which might tell<br />

us how to reconcile competing goods with one another. Most<br />

importantly, the Court must not view the choice of one good over<br />

another good in hard cases as arbitrary. Instead, it must be candid<br />

about the reasons for its choices and hope that its candour about the<br />

reasons for its choices ultimately reflects the exercise of good<br />

judgment: for only such candour will allow the litigants to become full<br />

citizens through their participation in the process of giving the basic<br />

law meaning. This recognition, in turn, holds out the promise that the<br />

17 See J Finnis ‘On reason and authority in Law’s Empire’ (1987) 6 Law & Philosophy<br />

357, 375 (‘A case is hard, in the sense which interests lawyers, when there is<br />

more than one right, ie not wrong, answer.’)<br />

18 See C Larmore Patterns of Moral Complexity (1986).


160 Chapter 10<br />

basic law will come to possess the normative legitimacy associated<br />

with a just legal order. 19<br />

3.3 Subjectivity and arbitrariness<br />

Some critics of balancing point out that the Final Constitution — like<br />

most constitutional texts — provides little or no guidance as to how a<br />

court should determine the relative weight to be attached to<br />

conflicting rights and interests. One possible result is that the<br />

weighting and the ranking of interests are not grounded in<br />

constitutional interpretation — and extended and reflected engagement<br />

with the meaning of the constitutional text — but based,<br />

instead, on the subjective preferences of individual judges.<br />

The charge that balancing reinforces non-interpretative<br />

tendencies in a bench already loath to make the normative<br />

pronouncements that every constitution requires, and creates a<br />

mechanism that enables judges to substitute their personal political<br />

preferences for the preferences of the democratically-elected<br />

branches, inevitably raises important questions about the separation<br />

of powers between the legislature and the judiciary. If the mediation<br />

of conflicting social interests is understood to be an essentially<br />

legislative function, judges ought not to be placed in a position that<br />

short-circuits the hurly-burly of the political process. Realists about<br />

the legal process may counter that <strong>this</strong> argument rests upon a<br />

formalist distinction between law and politics (and thus between the<br />

legislative function and the judicial function) that never was and<br />

never will be an accurate account of what happens in all modern<br />

constitutional democracies. What happens, on the realist account, is<br />

that politics becomes law, law becomes politics, and politics becomes<br />

law in a never-ending cycle of conflict and resolution. 20 But even<br />

realists, among whom we count ourselves, must contend with the<br />

spectre of judicial arbitrariness raised by balancing. And, it must be<br />

said, we are concerned that <strong>this</strong> approach to limitations analysis<br />

enables judges to skirt the demands that attach to difficult and<br />

controversial value-choices by employing the ostensibly neutral,<br />

objective or scientific language of balancing.<br />

19 On various notions of legitimacy and the response to those notions by the<br />

Constitutional Court, see T Roux ‘Principle and pragmatism on the South African<br />

Constitutional Court’ (2008) International Journal of Constitutional Law<br />

(forthcoming).<br />

20<br />

The current Chief Justice has said extra-curially that the Constitution ‘requires an<br />

acceptance of the politics of law. There is no longer place for assertions that the<br />

law can be kept isolated from politics. While they are not the same, they are<br />

inherently and necessarily linked.’ P Langa ‘Transformative constitutionalism’<br />

(2007) 17 Stellenbosch Law Review 351 353.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 161<br />

3.4 Incrementalism and conservatism<br />

Balancing is also sometimes associated with a conservative bench. In<br />

the United States, balancing got a bad reputation during the McCarthy<br />

era, when courts used the language of balancing to validate serious<br />

infringements of freedom of expression. Such an account seems to<br />

oversimplify the historical record. Balancing has, at various times in<br />

history, also been associated with liberal and progressive causes and<br />

the extension of constitutional rights and freedoms. But even if<br />

balancing does not necessarily translate into a readiness to sacrifice<br />

individual rights and freedoms in the name of collective interests,<br />

there may still be something conservative about it. Balancing is, we<br />

think, legitimately associated with a cautious, incrementalist<br />

approach to constitutionality inspired judicial law-making. The<br />

balancer is inclined to restrict her finding to the case at hand, as the<br />

next case may, ostensibly, require that a different balance be struck.<br />

While there may be advantages to such a judicious approach, which<br />

was indeed a hallmark of the Chaskalson Court, there is a growing<br />

concern within the academy that the case-by-case approach to<br />

constitutional analysis, in general, and limitations analysis, in<br />

particular, blunts the transformative potential of the Final<br />

Constitution. 21<br />

3.5 Science and silence<br />

Balancing, some critics suggest, encourages judges to resort to<br />

‘scientific’ language — ie, cost-benefit analysis. The fear here is that<br />

such talk invites a new type of formalism which, like all formalist<br />

doctrines, tends to eschew dialogue about important moral and<br />

political issues. As Aleinikoff puts it:<br />

Scientifically styled opinions, written to answer charges of subjectivity,<br />

make us spectators as the Court places the various interests on the<br />

scales. The weighing mechanism remains a mystery, and the result is<br />

simply read off the machine. Scientific balancing decisions are neither<br />

opinions nor arguments that can engage us; they are demonstrations. 22<br />

A related critique is that balancing rests upon the assumption that the<br />

primary aim of constitutional law is to mediate pre-existing interests.<br />

21 For a critique of the incrementalist approach to the development of the common<br />

law, see generally R Nagel ‘Liberals and balancing’ (1992) 63 University of<br />

Colorado Law Review 319. See also A van der Walt ‘Tradition on trial: A critical<br />

analysis of the civil-law tradition in South African property law’ (1995) 11 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 169; A van der Walt ‘Dancing with codes —<br />

Protecting, developing and deconstructing property rights in a constitutional<br />

state’ (2000) 18 South African Law Journal 258; S Woolman ‘The amazing,<br />

vanishing Bill of Rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 762.<br />

22 Aleinikoff (n 15 above) 993.


162 Chapter 10<br />

These interests are thought to be exogenous to the legal process. Such<br />

an approach to constitutional conflicts presupposes an underlying<br />

coherence in the law and in society that in heterogeneous polities —<br />

such as our own — simply does not exist. Moreover, an underlying<br />

assumption of value homogeneity tends to work against the belief of<br />

many an honest citizen — and quite a few academics — that political<br />

truths are more likely to arise out of dialogic modulation and not the<br />

reinforcement of their own subjective preferences. 23 The judge’s role<br />

in <strong>this</strong> account of balancing is akin to that of a grocer when, in fact,<br />

it should be that of a facilitator of and a participant in a normative<br />

dialogue with other political actors and the citizens of a constitutional<br />

order. 24<br />

4 A thick(er) conception of limitations analysis<br />

In <strong>this</strong> section, we offer a preferred reading of FC section 36 — one<br />

which we believe will help courts to think more clearly about the<br />

demands that limitations analysis places on various actors in our<br />

constitutional democracy. This preferred reading does not proffer a<br />

‘grand unified theory’. Our account begins, instead, by addressing<br />

serious concerns about institutional comity in a constitutional<br />

democracy and by articulating what we, and others, have described<br />

as the Final Constitution’s call for ‘shared constitutional<br />

interpretation’. After suggesting the contours of a doctrine that<br />

would enable the courts to share ‘constitutional competence’ with<br />

other political actors — and thus mediate the competing doctrinal<br />

claims of constitutional supremacy and of separation of powers — we<br />

ask whether the Constitutional Court’s extant jurisprudence provides<br />

sufficient normative content to guide lower courts and other actors<br />

interested in participating in <strong>this</strong> shared interpretive endeavour.<br />

What we currently see is, on the one hand, a rather cursory<br />

attempt to reconcile the primary values that underlie fundamental<br />

rights analysis and limitations analysis — openness, democracy,<br />

human dignity, equality and freedom — and a more deeply entrenched<br />

privileging of the value of human dignity, on the other. We do not<br />

deny the centrality of dignity to our constitutional project — our<br />

dignity jurisprudence may even be, with the principle of legality, one<br />

of our two most important contributions to the larger world of<br />

international or comparative constitutional law. We do, however,<br />

take issue with the Court’s tendency to reduce the other four values<br />

to manifestations of dignity, and its record of having little to say<br />

23 See K Sullivan ‘Post-liberal judging: The roles of categorisation and balancing’<br />

24<br />

(1992) 63 University Colorado of Law Review 293.<br />

Nagel (n 21 above); Van der Walt ‘Tradition on trial’ (n 21 above); Van der Walt<br />

‘Dancing with codes (n 21 above).


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 163<br />

about the meaning of ‘democracy’ or ‘openness’ or ‘freedom’ in our<br />

basic law — something of a surprise given the success of South Africa’s<br />

transition from fascism to democracy. Having established that our five<br />

basic values may well be incommensurable in some sets of<br />

circumstances and that balancing does little to address such<br />

incommensurability, we end our discussion by suggesting a<br />

methodology for constructing judicial narratives that may be of some<br />

use to courts faced with cases that challenge our ability to<br />

accommodate marginal groups or that require hard choices.<br />

4.1 Shared constitutional interpretation<br />

Our approach to limitations analysis, in particular, and to<br />

constitutional interpretation, generally, suggests that Bill of Rights<br />

litigation, rightly conceived, ought to reflect a dialogue about the<br />

meaning of fundamental rights and the cogency of justifications<br />

offered for their limitation. 25 From <strong>this</strong> perspective, powers of<br />

judicial review are best understood, not as part of a battle for<br />

ascendancy between courts and legislatures (though they may turn<br />

into that) or a means of frustrating the will of the political majority<br />

but, rather, as a shared project of constitutional interpretation. What<br />

is ‘shared constitutional interpretation’ exactly? In short, shared<br />

constitutional interpretation stands for five basic propositions.<br />

First. It supplants the notion of judicial supremacy with respect to<br />

constitutional interpretation. All branches of government have a<br />

relatively equal stake in giving our basic law content. Second. It draws<br />

attention to a shift in the status of court-driven constitutional<br />

doctrine. While courts retain the power to determine the content of<br />

any given provision, a commitment to shared constitutional<br />

interpretation means that a court’s reading of the constitutional text<br />

is not meant to exhaust all possible readings. To the extent that a<br />

court consciously limits the reach of its holding regarding the meaning<br />

of a given provision, the rest of the judgment should read as an<br />

invitation to the co-ordinate branches or other organs of state to<br />

come up with their own alternative, but ultimately consistent, gloss<br />

on the text. Third. Shared constitutional competence married to a<br />

rather open-ended or provisional understanding of the content of the<br />

basic law is meant to increase the opportunities to see how different<br />

doctrines operate in practice and maintain the space necessary to<br />

make revision of constitutional doctrines possible in light of new<br />

experience and novel demands. In <strong>this</strong> regard, the Constitutional<br />

25 See Mhlungu (n 4 above) para 129 (Constitutional interpretation takes the form of<br />

‘a principled judicial dialogue, in the first place between members of <strong>this</strong> Court,<br />

then between our Court and other courts, the legal profession, law schools,<br />

Parliament, and, indirectly, with the public at large.’)


164 Chapter 10<br />

Court might be understood to engage in norm-setting behaviour that<br />

provides guidance to other state actors without foreclosing the<br />

possibility of other effective safeguards for rights or other useful<br />

methods for their realisation. Fourth. A commitment to shared<br />

interpretation ratchets down the conflict between co-ordinate<br />

branches and levels of government. Instead of an arid commitment to<br />

separation of powers — and empty rhetorical flourishes about courts<br />

engaging in legal interpretation not politics — courts are freed of the<br />

burden of having to provide a theory of everything and can set about<br />

articulating a general framework within 26 which different understandings<br />

of the basic text can co-exist. The courts and all other<br />

actors have more to gain from seeing how variations on a given<br />

constitutional norm work in practice. Fifth. This experimentalist<br />

framework ought to reveal ‘best practices’ with respect to the<br />

realisation of constitutional objectives. These ‘best practices’ should,<br />

in turn, offer the courts, the political branches and the citizenry<br />

regular opportunities to re-think the meaning — and the constraints —<br />

of our basic law. 27<br />

Justice Ackermann, in National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian<br />

Equality v Minister of Home Affairs, gives expression to just the sort<br />

of institutional comity we have in mind when he writes that:<br />

It should also be borne in mind that whether the remedy a Court grants<br />

is one striking down, wholly or in part; or reading into or extending the<br />

text, its choice is not final. Legislatures are able, within constitutional<br />

limits, to amend the remedy, whether by re-enacting equal benefits,<br />

further extending benefits, reducing them, amending them, ‘finetuning’<br />

them or abolishing them. 28<br />

Shared responsibility for interpreting the Final Constitution does have<br />

its limits. The legislature must make a good faith attempt to revisit<br />

an issue in a new and constitutionally permissible way. Where, as in<br />

Satchwell I and II, Parliament refuses to take seriously a previous<br />

finding of constitutional invalidity, the courts are well within their<br />

rights to rebuff subsequent attempts to re-enact, in modified form,<br />

the offending statutory and regulatory framework. 29<br />

How then does shared constitutional interpretation inform our<br />

general approach to limitations analysis? The two-part structure of<br />

Bill of Rights analysis contains an invitation to non-judicial actors to<br />

26<br />

See F Michelman ‘Constitutional supremacy and appellate jurisdiction in South<br />

Africa’ S Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations (2008) Chapter<br />

4.<br />

27<br />

See Woolman (n 5 above). See also Dorf & Friedman (n 5 above).<br />

28 2000 2 SA 1 (CC), 2000 1 BCLR 39 (CC) para 76.<br />

29 Satchwell v President of the Republic of South Africa 2002 (6) SA 1 (CC), 2002 9<br />

BCLR 986 (CC)(‘Satchwell I’); Satchwell v President of the Republic of South<br />

Africa 2003 4 SA 266 (CC), 2004 1 BCLR 1 (CC).


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 165<br />

alter the Constitutional Court’s take on the basic law. By explicitly<br />

separating out the process of defining the ambit of a right and the<br />

process of determining the appropriateness of any limitation, the Bill<br />

of Rights avoids creating a binary world where the outcome of the<br />

dispute is tied entirely to rights definition. For example, in American<br />

constitutional law, once a particular type of conduct is deemed to fall<br />

within the protected ambit of a fundamental right, any law limiting<br />

the exercise of the conduct concerned is highly likely to be<br />

invalidated under a strict scrutiny standard. 30 The two-part structure<br />

of Bill of Rights analysis has enabled the Constitutional Court to avoid<br />

rigid categories and expressly acknowledge the role of other state<br />

institutions in interpreting the provisions of the Final Constitution.<br />

The two-part structure of Bill of Rights analysis has two further<br />

benefits when viewed through the lens of shared constitutional<br />

interpretation. First, a relatively precise, if nuanced, approach to<br />

limitations analysis creates the space for a fairly fastidious treatment<br />

of rights interpretation. Second, the Court is at its best, and its most<br />

comfortable, when it speaks to the parameters of the ‘constitutional’<br />

and is not asked to become an oracle of the ‘optimal’. 31<br />

However, the promise of shared constitutional interpretation will<br />

not be fulfilled if the courts continue to rely exclusively on the<br />

metaphor of balancing. Balancing blocks meaningful analysis of the<br />

facts in difficult cases because it substitutes an empty image for the<br />

more difficult task of information-gathering, norm-setting and<br />

remedy creation. Balancing thereby carries the potential for<br />

increased judicial deference to existing practices and, consequently,<br />

the systematic under-enforcement of important rights. Actions<br />

challenging public or private institutional practices typically pose the<br />

following problems for traditional adjudication: (1) epistemic hurdles<br />

in adapting the legal language to render faithfully important facts and<br />

ideas from particular communities and contexts; 32 (2) evaluative<br />

obstacles when courts need to weigh conflicting values against a<br />

background of norms grounded in particular contexts; and (3) the<br />

complexity of structuring suitable institutional remedies. 33<br />

30 For a compelling account of the dilemmas posed by one-stage fundamental rights<br />

analysis, see L Tribe & M Dorf ‘Levels of generality in the definition of rights’<br />

(1990) 57 University of Chicago Law Review 1057.<br />

31 See, especially, Ex parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In re<br />

Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 4 SA<br />

744 (CC), 1996 10 BCLR 1253 (CC) para 27.<br />

32 See R Cover ‘1982 term foreword: Nomos and narrative’ (1983) 97 Harvard Law<br />

Review 4 28 citing Bob Jones University v United States (1983) 461 US 574.<br />

33<br />

See M Dorf ‘The domain of reflexive law’ (2003) 103 Columbia Law Review 384<br />

399 (Noting the dynamic nature of deliberation and implementation may create<br />

novel solutions to seemingly intractable conflicts because ‘reflexivity goes both<br />

up and down, local participation always has ingredient in it the prospect of<br />

changing the principal norm.’)


166 Chapter 10<br />

To overcome the poverty of the existing approach to limitations<br />

analysis, South African courts might be well-served by embracing a<br />

more ‘experimentalist’ approach. Indeed, the open-ended, factdriven<br />

framework of limitations analysis invites litigants — and other<br />

stakeholders — to participate more directly in the vetting of possible<br />

solutions to the legal problem confronting the court. Such an<br />

invitation to the parties to get their hands dirty enables the courts to<br />

overcome both their own limited administrative capacity and their<br />

often enervating reliance on the good faith of the various parties.<br />

More importantly, the invitation to the parties to expand their legal<br />

strategies from competing claims with zero-sum outcomes to more<br />

optimal solutions grounded in compromises from which all parties<br />

believe they may benefit enables the courts to reap the problemsolving<br />

potential inherent in collective deliberation.<br />

An experimentalist perspective on limitations analysis proceeds<br />

from the recognition that the determination of the ‘reasonableness’<br />

of a limitation and the identification of the best of all possible<br />

remedies are interdependent processes. This experimentalist perspective<br />

also recognises how exceedingly difficult it is to discover the<br />

‘right’ answer — or remedy — from an outsider’s perspective. 34<br />

Indeed, the notion of a single ‘right’ answer in such a complex context<br />

— in advance of any attempt to mediate the competing positions — is<br />

itself suspect. As Susan Sturm has observed in connection with<br />

workplace discrimination, changes in legal doctrines reshape people’s<br />

expectations. 35 The new legal doctrine thereby reconstructs their<br />

identities, beliefs and behaviour. Such an evolutionary process — a<br />

function of the law as an experimental feedback mechanism — can<br />

gradually transform the nature of the problem as originally<br />

perceived. 36<br />

Confronted with such complexity, the task for the courts is not to<br />

undertake Herculean quests for perfect theoretical answers or to<br />

retreat into the quietism of deference to administrative decisions and<br />

private ordering. Our preferred experimentalist perspective possesses<br />

two important advantages. First, by acknowledging the difficulty of<br />

finding the ‘right’ answer, ex ante, courts with a problem-solving<br />

perspective must create mechanisms (including legal doctrines) that<br />

gather relevant information, generate proposed reforms and relay<br />

feedback quickly. Second, given the potential for unintended<br />

consequences that flows from adaptive processes triggered by shifting<br />

34 See M Dorf ‘1997 Supreme Court term foreword: The limits of socratic<br />

35<br />

deliberation’ (1998) 112 Harvard Law Review 4 (1998).<br />

See S Sturm ‘The promise of participation’ (1993) 78 Iowa Law Review 981<br />

(Argues that participation of stakeholders in the negotiation process initiated by a<br />

36<br />

structural injunction offers important benefits.)<br />

See Dorf (n 33 above) 399-400.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 167<br />

legal principles, a problem-solving perspective implements each set<br />

of solutions tentatively and is ready to modify these rolling normative<br />

guidelines on the basis of empirical evidence. 37 The experimentalist<br />

approach calls for mechanisms that compare the information<br />

generated by different proposals and that allow for the adoption of<br />

successful solutions.<br />

Of course, courts called upon to perform limitations analysis<br />

cannot avoid conflicts that are not susceptible to deliberative<br />

solutions. Here again experimental constitutionalism offers the<br />

additional idea of provisional adjudication. Provisional adjudication<br />

puts alternative possible remedies to the test of experience without<br />

necessarily elevating such remedies to the level of established<br />

doctrine. Provisional adjudication promises two additional benefits.<br />

First. It may facilitate compromise. 38 Affected parties may learn from<br />

practical experience and adjust their beliefs and conduct accordingly.<br />

Second. It gives parties that may have been aggrieved with a final<br />

non-provisional outcome the opportunity to experiment with a<br />

remedy of their own making.<br />

But suppose that such provisional space fails to yield a desirable<br />

— let us say, from the view of the state — outcome. A finding of<br />

unconstitutionality generally still leaves the legislature free to pursue<br />

the same objectives, but requires it to use means that better fit — are<br />

more narrowly tailored to — constitutional imperatives. It is,<br />

therefore, clear that the courts do not have the final word on the<br />

meaning of the constitutional text in two very important respects.<br />

First, just as the legislature must pay heed to the Court’s reasons for<br />

a finding of unconstitutionality when offering a new formulation of a<br />

law, so too must the Court demonstrate discernible deference to the<br />

legislature’s reformulation. The very fact of a limitations clause in our<br />

Bill of Rights demands that the courts give the coordinate branches of<br />

37 See M Dorf ‘Legal indeterminism and institutional design’ (2004) 78 New York<br />

University Law Review 875 920-935 and 960-70.<br />

38<br />

See eg Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road Berea Township and 197 Main Street<br />

Johannesburg v City of Johannesburg 2008 3 SA 208 (CC). Prior to handing down<br />

its decision, the Constitutional Court issued an order requiring the parties to the<br />

dispute to engage meaningfully with each other with a view to addressing the<br />

possibilities of short-term steps to improve current living conditions and of<br />

alternative accommodation for those who would be rendered homeless. As a<br />

result of <strong>this</strong> interim order, the parties reached a consensus that the City of<br />

Johannesburg would not eject the occupiers, that it would upgrade the buildings<br />

and that it would provide temporary accommodation. In addition, the parties<br />

agreed to meet and discuss permanent housing solutions. This agreement was<br />

then ratified by an order of the Constitutional Court. That consensus decision<br />

about the optimal remedy left the Court free to articulate general norms about<br />

the right to access to adequate housing: (1) evictions cannot occur in the absence<br />

of meaningful engagement; (2) the potential for homelessness must be considered<br />

prior to any decision by a state actor to eliminate unsafe buildings. While<br />

an experimental constitutionalist could generally ask for little more, one problem<br />

with the judgment is its failure to provide ‘new’ rolling norms with teeth.


168 Chapter 10<br />

government ample opportunity to demonstrate that a new and<br />

improved law can achieve the desired objectives within the<br />

framework established by the Final Constitution. Second, the ability<br />

of our elected representatives to amend the basic law itself — so long<br />

as they follow the appropriate procedures and do not violate its basic<br />

structure — means that the people always have the final word.<br />

5 Norms: ‘an open and democratic society based upon<br />

human dignity, equality and freedom’<br />

5.1 Intersection, convergence, and conflict amongst<br />

constitutional values<br />

We have described in the preceding pages an approach to limitations<br />

analysis that simultaneously answers ‘deep’ questions about<br />

institutional comity in a constitutional democracy and adumbrates an<br />

analytical framework that responds to concerns about judicial<br />

usurpation of legislative prerogatives and the alleged inability of<br />

courts to resolve polycentric social problems. What we have not<br />

described, in even the most superficial way, is how the courts go<br />

about determining the ‘normative’ content of limitations analysis.<br />

That normative content for limitations analysis turns on the<br />

phrase ‘an open and democratic society based on human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom’. Determining the meaning of <strong>this</strong> phrase is<br />

fraught with interpretive difficulties as old as political theory itself.<br />

There are, for starters, the tensions between democracy and rights,<br />

between equality and freedom, and the deeply contested nature of<br />

each of these terms.<br />

Before turning to the ways in which our courts have attempted to<br />

make sense of <strong>this</strong> complex phrase, a few observations are in order.<br />

First of all, FC section 36 — unlike limitations clauses in many<br />

international human rights instruments and national constitutions —<br />

avoids references to national security, the public interest, public<br />

order, decency or morality as criteria for the limitation of<br />

fundamental rights. Such silence is not surprising given the myriad<br />

ways in which notions of national security, the public interest and<br />

public morals were used to suppress opposition to the apartheid state.<br />

FC section 36 redefines ‘the public interest’ (from the constellation<br />

of interests that served white, male, straight, and Christian South<br />

Africans under apartheid) in terms of the values underlying an open<br />

and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and<br />

freedom. No longer can sectarian notions of the public interest be<br />

allowed to ride roughshod over fundamental rights. A limitation of a<br />

fundamental right that negates plurality or difference in the name of<br />

the common good is, generally, unlikely to be deemed reasonable and


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 169<br />

justifiable in an open and democratic society based on human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom.<br />

Second, FC section 36 requires us to reconsider traditional<br />

understandings of the relationship between constitutional rights and<br />

the public interest. If the public interest in terms of which<br />

fundamental rights may be limited is underpinned by the same values<br />

that inform our interpretation of those rights, it makes no sense to<br />

view rights and the public interest as being diametrically opposed, the<br />

first representing private entitlements and the second state interests.<br />

Rather than fitting our two-stage analysis into the traditional, but<br />

ultimately facile, public/private dichotomy, the Final Constitution<br />

requires us to develop a substantive vision of the norms and values<br />

enshrined in the Bill of Rights that, as we argued above, must guide<br />

both rights interpretation and limitations analysis. The result is likely<br />

to be both a more realistic understanding of the ‘private sphere’,<br />

which recognises the legitimate role of the state in ordering ‘private’<br />

relations, and a richer conception of the public interest, which<br />

neither equates it with the interests of the governing elite nor<br />

reduces it to the sum of private interests.<br />

Third, the Final Constitution does not envisage a neat division of<br />

interpretive tasks, in terms of which certain values (say, human<br />

dignity, equality and freedom) are considered only or primarily during<br />

the first stage of the fundamental rights inquiry, whereas others (say,<br />

democracy) feature only during the second stage. Instead,<br />

constitutional interpreters must engage with all five values — to the<br />

extent that they are relevant — during both fundamental rights<br />

interpretation and limitations analysis. Indeed, FC section 39(1), like<br />

FC section 36(1), recognises that a particular right may be<br />

underpinned by more than one value. For instance, while freedom of<br />

expression certainly serves democracy and freedom, the<br />

Constitutional Court jurisprudence also demonstrates how it serves<br />

the interests of human dignity and equality. 39 Both FC section 36 and<br />

FC section 39 invite us to consider the complex ways in which the<br />

values of democracy, openness, human dignity, equality and freedom<br />

overlap, converge, intersect, mutually support each other, and clash.<br />

Lastly, the Final Constitution does not view these values as<br />

invariably incommensurable. It requires us to first attempt to<br />

39<br />

See eg South African National Defence Union v Minister of Defence & Another<br />

1999 4 SA 469 (CC), 1999 6 BCLR 615 (CC) para 7 (‘Freedom of expression lies at<br />

the heart of a democracy. It is valuable for many reasons, including its<br />

instrumental function as a guarantor of democracy, its implicit recognition and<br />

protection of the moral agency of individuals in our society and its facilitation of<br />

the search for truth by individuals and society generally’.) See also S Woolman<br />

‘Dignity’ in Woolman et al (n 6 above) Chapter 36 (On dignity interests served by<br />

freedom of expression.)


170 Chapter 10<br />

harmonise them. 40 If <strong>this</strong> were not the case, then the quintet of<br />

values enshrined in FC section 36 and FC section 39 would generate a<br />

cacophony of judgments, rather than a recurring set of themes that<br />

hold our Court’s jurisprudence together. As Sachs J wrote in his<br />

dissenting judgment in Prince:<br />

[L]imitations analysis under section 36 is antithetical to extreme<br />

positions which end up setting the irresistible force of democracy and<br />

general law enforcement, against the immovable object of<br />

constitutionalism and protection of fundamental rights. What it requires<br />

is the maximum harmonisation of all the competing interests, on a<br />

principled yet nuanced and flexible case-by-case basis, located in South<br />

African reality yet guided by international experience, articulated with<br />

appropriate candour and accomplished without losing sight of the<br />

ultimate values highlighted by our Constitution. 41<br />

The attempt to harmonise conflicting interests also coheres with our<br />

commitment to shared constitutional interpretation. It creates room<br />

for an inter-institutional dialogue about the best way of resolving the<br />

tension, if not out-right conflict, between various constitutional<br />

goods. 42<br />

Again. The Final Constitution does not require us to resolve these<br />

conflicts, once and for all, or to measure the Court’s fidelity to all five<br />

values along a single metric. The tensions inherent in the formulation<br />

of FC section 36 and FC section 39 are constitutive of the South<br />

African constitutional order. 43 They reflect the complexity and<br />

plurality of South African society, the fault-lines and frayed edges of<br />

the political traditions embraced by the Final Constitution and the<br />

fragility of the political compromise that it represents. Any attempt<br />

to eradicate these conflicts and to deny the distinctive meaning of<br />

each of these values would do real violence to the constitutional text<br />

and deny the commitment to openness and to plurality upon which it<br />

is premised.<br />

40<br />

See K Hesse Grundzüge des Verfassungsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland 20<br />

ed (1999) 28 142-143 and 146.<br />

41 n 7 above, para 155.<br />

42<br />

n 7 above, para 156 (Sachs J) (‘The search for an appropriate accommodation ...<br />

imposes a particularly heavy responsibility on the courts to be sensitive to<br />

considerations of institutional competence and the separation of powers. Undue<br />

judicial adventurism can be as damaging as excessive judicial timidity.’)<br />

43 See J van der Walt & H Botha ‘Democracy and rights in South Africa: Beyond a<br />

constitutional culture of justification’ (2000) Constellations 341; H Botha<br />

‘Democracy and rights: Constitutional interpretation in a post-realist world’<br />

(2000) 63 Tydskrif vir die Hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse Reg 561 581.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 171<br />

5.2 Dignity and democracy<br />

5.2.1 Primacy of dignity<br />

As we have seen above, the Constitutional Court regards human<br />

dignity as the most important human right and constitutional value.<br />

In the view of the Court,<br />

Human ... dignity informs constitutional adjudication and interpretation<br />

at a range of levels. It is a value that informs the interpretation of many,<br />

possibly all, other rights. ... Human dignity is also a constitutional value<br />

that is of central significance in the limitations analysis. Section 10,<br />

however, makes it plain that dignity is not only a value fundamental to<br />

our Constitution, it is a justiciable and enforceable right that must be<br />

respected and protected. In many cases however, where the value of<br />

human dignity is offended, the primary constitutional breach occasioned<br />

may be of a more specific right such as the right to bodily integrity, the<br />

right to equality or the right not to be subjected to slavery, servitude or<br />

forced labour. 44<br />

Given that both the text and the Court tell us that dignity plays a<br />

‘central’ role in limitations analysis, two questions arise. What role<br />

does dignity play? How central is it to our constitutional project?<br />

The basis for the Court’s recognition of dignity as, perhaps, the<br />

master concept in the Bill of Rights range from the direct manner in<br />

which dignity answers the ‘problem’ of apartheid, 45 to the centrality<br />

of dignity to the post-war constitutional tradition, 46 to the ability of<br />

dignity to answer, in a coherent manner, the Court’s call for a transformative<br />

jurisprudence; 47 to the place dignity occupies in Roman-<br />

44 Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v<br />

Minister of Home Affairs 2000 3 SA 936 (CC), 2000 8 BCLR 837 (CC) para 35. For a<br />

detailed discussion of how each of the rights in the Bill of Rights has been<br />

refracted through the prism of human dignity, see Woolman (n 39 above).<br />

45 See S Liebenberg ‘The value of human dignity in interpreting socio-economic<br />

rights’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 1 (Respect for human<br />

dignity requires society to respect the equal worth of the poor by marshalling its<br />

resources to redress the conditions that perpetuate their marginalisation).<br />

46<br />

See L Weinrib ‘Constitutional conceptions and constitutional comparativism’ in V<br />

Jackson & M Tushnet (eds) Defining the field of comparative constitutional law<br />

(2002) 3. See also A Chaskalson ‘Human dignity as a foundational value of our<br />

constitutional order’ (2000) 16 South African Journal on Human Rights 193 196<br />

(‘The affirmation of human dignity as a foundational value of the constitutional<br />

order places our legal order firmly in line with the development of<br />

constitutionalism in the aftermath of the Second World War.’)<br />

47 See Woolman (n 39 above) 36-6 — 36-19.


172 Chapter 10<br />

Dutch law, 48 in traditional understandings of ubuntu 49 and in<br />

contemporary discourse on the politics of capability; 50 and, finally, to<br />

the manner in which dignity assists courts faced with the practical<br />

difficulties of reconciling such ‘complementary’ values as freedom<br />

and equality.<br />

The reason of most immediate import for making sense of<br />

limitations analysis is, perhaps, the last. Writing in his personal<br />

capacity, Justice Laurie Ackermann claims that the Court’s dignitybased<br />

equality jurisprudence enables it to adjudicate conflicts<br />

between equality and freedom in a neutrally-principled manner. 51<br />

Ackermann offers a number of clashes between equality and freedom<br />

that, he believes, can be resolved by reference to a neutral<br />

conception of dignity. For example, a restrictive condition attached<br />

to a property that prevents future sale of the property to a black<br />

person constitutes a deep affront to the dignity of prospective black<br />

buyers. At the same time, a finding that the provision is<br />

constitutionally infirm ‘would constitute a mere abstract limitation’ 52<br />

of the contractual freedom of the contracting parties and of the right<br />

of the original owner to dispose of his property as she pleases.<br />

Ackermann contrasts <strong>this</strong> first scenario with another: The owner of a<br />

residential property, for racist reasons, wishes to have someone<br />

trespassing on his property ejected. In <strong>this</strong> case, Ackermann argues,<br />

the owner can rely on constitutional rights such as privacy and<br />

freedom of association, while the trespasser only ‘suffers a minor<br />

limitation and a limited and unpublic indignity.’ 53<br />

Ackermann’s analysis of the mediating role of dignity in conflicts<br />

between equality and freedom sheds new light on the perceived role<br />

of dignity in proportionality analysis. In his view, a dignity-based<br />

approach enables judges to make a principled distinction between<br />

instances of private discrimination that constitute a violation of<br />

somebody’s equal worth and legitimate exercises of personal and<br />

associational freedom. Dignity, he seems to suggest, is ideally suited<br />

to playing such a mediating role because it provides a measure of<br />

48 See LWH Ackermann ‘The significance of human dignity for constitutional<br />

jurisprudence’ Lecture, Stellenbosch Law Faculty, 15 August 2005 (Manuscript on<br />

file with authors) § 6. See also LWH Ackermann ‘Equality and non-discrimination:<br />

Some analytical thoughts’ (2006) 22 South African Journal on Human Rights 597<br />

602.<br />

49 See Y Mokgoro ‘Ubuntu and the law in South Africa’ (1998) 4 Buffalo Human<br />

Rights Law Review 15; M Pieterse ‘“Traditional” African jurisprudence’ in C<br />

Roederer & D Moellendorf (eds) Jurisprudence (2004) 441. See also Makwanyane<br />

(n 9 above) paras 224-225.<br />

50 See A Sen Development as Freedom (1999).<br />

51<br />

See L Ackermann ‘Equality and the South African constitution: The role of dignity’<br />

(2000) 63 Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht 537.<br />

52 n 51 above, 552.<br />

53<br />

n 51 above, 553 quoting L Henkin ‘Shelley v Kraemer: Notes for a revised opinion’<br />

(1962) 110 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 473 498.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 173<br />

value that is common to the frequently conflicting imperatives of<br />

equality and freedom.<br />

The purpose of Ackermann’s two intuition pumps is to convince us<br />

that the stronger the dignity interest is on one side of the equality/<br />

freedom divide, the weaker it is likely to be on the other. In the<br />

example of the restrictive condition, the discrimination strikes at the<br />

heart of the dignity interests of a prospective black buyer, while only<br />

marginally disturbing the dignity interests of the property owner. But<br />

these — on Ackermann’s account — are easy cases. One could well<br />

imagine cases in which there are strong dignity/equality interests and<br />

dignity/freedom interests on both sides. Consider, for example, a<br />

clash between the rights of women who wish to participate equally in<br />

traditional or religious communities and the ‘autonomy’ rights of such<br />

religious or cultural communities. 54 In such cases, the discrimination<br />

constitutes a serious impairment of the fundamental human dignity of<br />

women while, at the same time, the religious or cultural practice in<br />

question is so fundamental to the worldview and customs of its<br />

adherents that a ruling of unconstitutionality would strike at the heart<br />

of that community’s sense of dignity. Dignity does not, in such cases,<br />

offer a neutral or a principled way of striking a balance between<br />

equality and freedom.<br />

The second problem with dignity as a neutral, mediating principle<br />

is that it assumes that a dignity-based reading of the limitations<br />

clause adequately captures the various interests served by rights as<br />

varied as equality, privacy and association. A number of<br />

commentators have argued that something is likely to get lost in the<br />

process of translating the right to equality into the language of human<br />

dignity. 55 One of their concerns has been that a dignity-based<br />

approach to equality focuses primarily on individual moral harm,<br />

rather than material disadvantage and structural power. While some<br />

forms of disadvantage can be expressed quite easily in moral terms,<br />

others may not be so readily recognised. This difference may explain<br />

why the transformative vision of the Constitutional Court’s<br />

jurisprudence in the field of sexual orientation has easily outpaced its<br />

jurisprudence on discrimination on the grounds of sex and gender.<br />

While discrimination against gays and lesbians is usually rooted in<br />

moral disapproval and results directly in an affront to their dignity<br />

54 See eg Bhe & Others v Magistrate, Khayelitsha & Others 2005 1 SA 580 (CC), 2005<br />

1 BCLR 449 (CC).<br />

55 C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Facing the challenge of transformation: difficulties in<br />

the development of an indigenous jurisprudence of equality’ (1998) 14 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 248; DM Davis ‘Equality: The majesty of<br />

legoland jurisprudence’ (1999) 116 South African Law Journal 398; H Botha<br />

‘Equality, dignity, and the politics of interpretation’ (2004) 19 South African<br />

Public Law 724. But see S Cowen ‘Can “dignity” guide South Africa’s equality<br />

jurisprudence?’ (2001) 17 South African Journal on Human Rights 34.


174 Chapter 10<br />

and identity, discrimination on the grounds of sex and gender is often<br />

more closely bound up with material disadvantage and systemic<br />

discrimination, and is, therefore, more difficult to capture in the<br />

language of dignity. 56<br />

The Court has, in recent years taken some of the sting out of <strong>this</strong><br />

critique by embracing an understanding of dignity that recognises our<br />

collective responsibility for creating the material conditions for the<br />

actual exercise of agency by all South Africans. Cases such as Bhe, 57<br />

Daniels, 58 Grootboom 59 and Khosa 60 demonstrate that dignity can be<br />

used to defend the rights of women, the poor and other vulnerable<br />

groups that suffer from material disadvantage and systemic<br />

discrimination.<br />

These cases buttress our contention that a dignity-based approach<br />

to limitations is capable of addressing at least some of the structural<br />

problems associated with poverty and gender. At the same time,<br />

however, we must express doubt about the ability of dignity to rescue<br />

marginal groups — Rastafarians, 61 prostitutes, 62 and unmarried<br />

cohabitants 63 — whose ways of being in the world challenge the<br />

Court’s own assumptions about what is normal and socially<br />

acceptable. Indeed, the Court often relies on dignity to justify legal<br />

limitations that appear to flow from very traditional, conservative<br />

and sectarian concerns.<br />

For example, in De Reuck, the Court found that a total ban on<br />

child pornography was justified because child pornography impairs<br />

the dignity of all children and, thus, of all members of any society that<br />

condones it. 64 By appealing to the dignity of society as a whole, rather<br />

than focusing solely on the dignity of those real children who were<br />

harmed in the making of pornography, the De Reuck Court was able to<br />

fend off the argument that the limitation — which also extended to<br />

depictions of imaginary persons — was overbroad and that less<br />

restrictive means were available. 65 Invoking the ‘dignity’ of an entire<br />

society can be dangerous when used to justify the restriction of<br />

unpopular views or forms of expression. The ‘dignity’ of the<br />

community can easily become shorthand for the institutionalisation of<br />

56 See Botha (n 55 above) 748.<br />

57<br />

n 54 above.<br />

58 Daniels v Campbell 2004 5 SA 331 (CC), 2004 7 BCLR 35 (CC).<br />

59 Government of the Republic of South Africa & Others v Grootboom & Others 2001<br />

1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC).<br />

60 Khosa v Minister of Social Development 2004 6 SA 505 (CC), 2004 5 BCLR 569 (CC).<br />

61 Prince (n 7 above).<br />

62<br />

S v Jordan & Others 2002 6 SA 642 (CC), 2002 11 BCLR 1117 (CC).<br />

63 Volks NO v Robinson 2005 5 BCLR 446 (CC).<br />

64 De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions (Witwatersrand. Local Division) &<br />

Others 2004 1 SA 406 (CC), 2003 12 BCLR 1333 (CC) para 63.<br />

65 n 64 above paras 68-70.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 175<br />

the moral views of the majority and the negation of plurality and<br />

difference.<br />

On other occasions, judges underestimate the extent to which a<br />

limitation of a fundamental right impairs the dignity of members of<br />

out-groups. Consider, for example, the insistence in Jordan that the<br />

stigma associated with prostitution is the result of personal choice<br />

and is unrelated to the role of law in apportioning blame and<br />

sustaining structural inequality. 66 Or ponder the majority’s finding in<br />

Volks that the exclusion of the surviving partner of a permanent life<br />

partnership from the right of surviving spouses to claim maintenance<br />

from the estates of their deceased spouses does not constitute unfair<br />

discrimination because the law never prevented them from getting<br />

married. 67 These findings — grounded both in traditional mores and<br />

rather outré metaphysical views about ‘individual freedom’ — cast<br />

something of a pall over the place of dignity in our limitations<br />

jurisprudence.<br />

Do these cases really indicate fundamental problems inherent in<br />

a dignity-based approach? Do they suggest that values other than<br />

dignity might assist the Courts in making better sense of the Final<br />

Constitution’s commitment to pluralism and the eradication of<br />

structural disadvantage?<br />

On the one hand, we are not convinced that a dignity-based<br />

approach must of necessity result in the reinforcement of traditional<br />

moral views, the continued marginalisation of certain out-groups, or<br />

the suppression of unpopular views. On the contrary, as Denise<br />

Meyerson has persuasively argued, and as the case law largely<br />

confirms, dignity can be used to invalidate limitations which seek to<br />

impose a particular conception of the good upon autonomous human<br />

beings. 68<br />

On the other hand, we need to ask why, despite its adherence to<br />

definitions of dignity that take our capacity for self-actualisation and<br />

self-governance seriously, the Constitutional Court failed to give<br />

adequate effect to dignity in the cases canvassed above. One reason<br />

could be that the private-law conception of dignity as dignitas still<br />

exerts a powerful hold on the legal imagination. This ‘conservative’<br />

pre-disposition may explain why dignity qua self-governance is not<br />

always given sufficient weight, and why the discourse of dignity<br />

sometimes slips into sermons about dignified behaviour. 69<br />

66 See Jordan (n 62 above) para 16.<br />

67 Volks (n 63 above) para 91.<br />

68<br />

See D Meyerson Rights Limited (1997).<br />

69 See Woolman (n 39 above) 36-14 — 36-17.


176 Chapter 10<br />

5.3 Democracy and openness<br />

5.3.1 Principle of democracy<br />

Cases such as Khosa 70 — which stressed the political community’s<br />

responsibility to provide non-citizens who find themselves on the<br />

margins of that community with the material conditions for agency —<br />

and Fourie 71 — which recognised that gays and lesbians have an<br />

entitlement to public recognition of their intimate relationships —<br />

evince the Court’s transformation of its dignity-based approach to<br />

fundamental rights interpretation and limitations analysis from<br />

dignitas and a narrow conception of the public interest to something<br />

far more expansive, if not all-embracing. This far more substantive<br />

vision of dignity allows us to make sense of a variety of other<br />

constitutional values precisely because <strong>this</strong> conception of dignity<br />

embraces such notions as equal concern and equal respect, selfactualisation,<br />

self-governance, and collective responsibility for the<br />

material means required for agency.<br />

But what the Court has still not done is give distinctive content to<br />

each of the five values enshrined in FC section 36. For the most part,<br />

the Court has viewed the four other values through the lens of human<br />

dignity. According to the Court, dignity provides a common measure<br />

of value which can help bridge the division between equality and<br />

freedom, or between negative and positive rights, or between the<br />

individual and collective aspects of our autonomy. However, we have<br />

also seen that dignity does not adequately address all conflicts nor<br />

does a reliance on dignity appear to do adequate justice to those outgroups<br />

whose participation in our social and political life remains<br />

marginal at best.<br />

It is particularly surprising that the Constitutional Court has not<br />

done more to develop the meaning of ‘openness’ and ‘democracy’ —<br />

two features of our society that clearly demarcate the boundary<br />

between apartheid South Africa and post-apartheid South Africa. In<br />

our view, a greater elaboration of the meaning of ‘an open and<br />

democratic society’, and a closer connection of these values to<br />

dignity (especially dignity qua self-governance), might result in a<br />

jurisprudence more inclined to accommodate plurality and<br />

difference. Similarly, an engagement with ‘democracy’ might<br />

strengthen our commitment to securing spaces in which ‘counterpublics’<br />

can challenge dominant ideas and engage in alternative<br />

discourses. In <strong>this</strong> section, we consider the possibility of a<br />

complementary understanding of the values underlying the Bill of<br />

70<br />

Khosa (n 60 above).<br />

71 Fourie (n 14 above).


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 177<br />

Rights that flows from a greater appreciation for the kind of<br />

‘democratic’ society to which the Final Constitution commits us.<br />

In United Democratic Movement v President of the Republic of<br />

South Africa, the Constitutional Court issued a challenge of sorts to<br />

the academic community: Tell us what ‘democracy’ means, and more<br />

importantly, tell us how it ought to inform, in a principled manner,<br />

our understanding of various provisions in the text of the Final<br />

Constitution. 72 Some South African academics, and in particular,<br />

Theunis Roux, have begun to do just that. 73 Roux pulls together the<br />

political theory out of which our particular South African conception<br />

of democracy arises, the textual provisions of the Final Constitution<br />

that shape that conception, and the extant case law of our own courts<br />

to generate a ‘principle of democracy’. 74 We will not rehearse Roux’s<br />

arguments in support of that principle here. We will, however, draw<br />

down on several of his arguments, especially those that serve part (2)<br />

of his ‘principle of democracy’.<br />

The argument that lends the greatest force to our general theory<br />

of limitations analysis is Roux’s contention that, read together, FC<br />

72 United Democratic Movement v President of the Republic of South Africa &<br />

Others (African Christian Democratic Party & Others Intervening; Institute for<br />

Democracy in South Africa & Another as Amici Curiae) (No 2) 2003 1 SA 495 (CC),<br />

2002 11 BCLR 1179 (CC) para 25.<br />

73<br />

Roux (n 6 above).<br />

74 This principle stated in its clearest form holds:<br />

Government in South Africa must be so arranged that the people, through<br />

the medium of political parties and regular elections, in which all adult<br />

citizens are entitled to participate, exert sufficient control over their<br />

elected representatives to ensure that: (a) representatives are held to<br />

account for their actions, (b) government listens and responds to the<br />

needs of the people, in appropriate cases directly, (c) collective decisions<br />

are taken by majority vote after due consideration of the views of<br />

minority parties, and (d) the reasons for all collective decisions are<br />

publicly explained. (2) The rights necessary to maintain such a form of<br />

government must be enshrined in a supreme-law Bill of Rights, enforced<br />

by an independent judiciary, whose task it shall be to ensure that,<br />

whenever the will of the majority, expressed in the form of a law of<br />

general application, runs counter to a right in the Bill of Rights, the<br />

resolution of that tension promotes the values of human dignity, equality<br />

and freedom.<br />

Roux (n 6 above) § 10.5(b) (emphasis removed). Roux offers an additional gloss on<br />

the second part of his principle that may be worth bearing in mind:<br />

The rights necessary to maintain such a form of government, including<br />

the right to freedom of expression, the right to form political parties, the<br />

right to vote, and the right to the minimum standard of welfare necessary<br />

to participate in the democratic process, must be enshrined in a supremelaw<br />

Bill of Rights, enforced by an independent judiciary, whose task it<br />

shall be to ensure that, whenever the will of the majority, expressed in<br />

the form of a law of general application, runs counter to a right in the Bill<br />

of Rights, the resolution of that tension promotes the values of human<br />

dignity, equality and freedom.<br />

As above (emphasis removed).


178 Chapter 10<br />

sections 7(1), 36(1), and 39(1) ‘structure the way in which the tension<br />

between rights and democracy is to be managed in South African<br />

constitutional law.’ 75 We have argued, over the course of <strong>this</strong><br />

chapter, that FC section 36(1) and FC section 39(1) require a valuebased<br />

approach to fundamental rights analysis and limitations analysis<br />

in part because they invoke the same set of values, the same linguistic<br />

trope, ‘an open and democratic society based upon human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom’. However, Roux’s connection of the oftignored<br />

FC section 7(1) to both fundamental rights interpretation (FC<br />

section 39) and limitations analysis (FC section 36) enables us to make<br />

four new critical points in <strong>this</strong> chapter.<br />

First, FC section 7(1) reads: ‘The Bill of Rights is a cornerstone of<br />

democracy in South Africa. It enshrines the rights of all people in our<br />

country and affirms the democratic values of human dignity, equality<br />

and freedom.’ Notice that democracy is treated as an independent<br />

value. Notice that the values of human dignity, equality and freedom<br />

are ‘democratic’ values. At a minimum, the language of FC section<br />

7(1) should give pause to those interpreters of the basic law who<br />

privilege, reflexively, the value of human dignity. One can press <strong>this</strong><br />

point further and argue that FC section 7(1), in fact, reverses the spin<br />

placed by the Constitutional Court on the phrase ‘an open and<br />

democratic society based upon human dignity, equality and freedom’.<br />

It makes a democratic society, and not dignity, foundational.<br />

Second, it is, we think, unnecessary to read the language of FC<br />

section 7(1) in a manner that privileges democracy over dignity.<br />

Indeed, FC section 7(1) and Professor Roux suggest that we should be<br />

just as wary of such overly simplistic reductions (rights service<br />

democracy) as we are chary of claims that rights and democracy stand<br />

in irreconcilable tension with one another (the counter-majoritarian<br />

dilemma). We think that it is enough to suggest, as Professor Roux<br />

does, that FC section 7(1) delinks the phrase ‘an open and democratic<br />

society’ from ‘human dignity, equality and freedom’. That is, whereas<br />

the phrase ‘open and democratic society based upon human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom’ suggests a miasma of ‘big’ ideas that, if read<br />

jointly and severally, could exhaust the entire universe of modern<br />

political theory, delinking the two phrases forces the reader of FC<br />

section 36(1) and FC section 39(1) to stop and to attend — for a<br />

moment — to the meaning, as well as the desiderata, of an ‘open and<br />

democratic society’. Even if it does nothing else, by reading FC<br />

section 7(1) together with FC section 36(1), we are forced to concede<br />

that the principle of democracy is, at least, of equal weight as the<br />

value of dignity when it comes to the justification of a limitation of a<br />

fundamental right.<br />

75 Roux (n 6 above) § 10.3(c).


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 179<br />

Third, Roux’s arguments support our contention that scales and<br />

balancing are inapt metaphors for limitations analysis. Such<br />

metaphors block one from drawing the conclusion to which FC section<br />

7(1) has already alerted us: Namely, that rights stand not in<br />

opposition to democracy, but that they are, instead, constitutive of<br />

it. That is to say, without the rights to equality, dignity, life, belief,<br />

expression, assembly, association, vote, political party membership,<br />

citizenship, access to information, access to courts, and just<br />

administrative action, we would not have a meaningful democracy.<br />

These rights are themselves the preconditions for an ‘open and<br />

democratic society’.<br />

Fourth, the principle of democracy, when taken seriously, gets<br />

read back into these rights. And by that we mean that the virtues of<br />

belonging, deliberating and participating, identified first and<br />

foremost with democracy, attach not just to the political realm, but<br />

to an array of associational forms — religious, traditional, linguistic,<br />

commercial, labour, intimate, cultural — that are part of, but not<br />

identical to the political. So although Professor Roux does not make<br />

<strong>this</strong> claim, we do. Indeed, it is an appreciation for these ‘democratic’<br />

values of membership, deliberation and participation that underwrites<br />

our defense of pluralism, marginal social groups and<br />

‘oppositional counterpublics’. 76 And we value pluralism, and thus<br />

marginal social groups and ‘oppositional counterpublics’, not simply<br />

because they serve as reminders of the emancipatory potential of<br />

robust democratic discourse, but because these groups, and others<br />

like them, are where democracy takes place everyday for the vast<br />

majority of us.<br />

Finally, we agree with Professor Roux that ‘no South African<br />

political system claiming to be democratic would be worthy of that<br />

name unless it respected the democratic values which the Bill of<br />

Rights affirms.’ 77 This view firmly reinforces our own views about the<br />

relationship between courts and legislatures in a regime of ‘shared<br />

constitutional interpretation’. In such a regime, as in the political<br />

system contemplated by FC sections 7(1), 36(1) and 39(1), neither the<br />

courts nor the political branches of government have a privileged<br />

position with regard to the making and re-making of our basic law.<br />

5.3.2 Principle of openness<br />

The dissenting judgment of Sachs J in Prince resonates with Roux’s<br />

understanding of democracy, and sounds themes similar to our own<br />

76 K Thomas ‘Racial justice’ in A Sarat, G Bryant & R Kagan (eds) Looking back at<br />

77<br />

law’s century (2002) 78 87.<br />

Roux (n 6 above) § 10.3(c).


180 Chapter 10<br />

thoughts about the relationship between democracy and the other<br />

values that ought to inform limitations analysis. In his dissent in<br />

Prince, Sachs J stressed the need in an ‘open and democratic society’<br />

faced with seemingly intractable conflicts — between the state and<br />

religious communities — for a ‘reasonable accommodation’ of<br />

interests. 78 This accommodation requires mutual recognition and ‘a<br />

reasonable measure of give-and-take from all sides’. 79 Sachs J, not<br />

surprisingly, finds that the majority’s refusal to carve out an<br />

exemption for bona fide religious use of cannabis offends <strong>this</strong> very<br />

principle. The majority judgment, he writes, ‘puts a thumb on the<br />

scales in favour of ease of law-enforcement, and gives insufficient<br />

weight to the impact the measure will have, not only on the<br />

fundamental rights of the appellant and his religious community, but<br />

on the basic notion of tolerance and respect for diversity that our<br />

Constitution demands for and from all in our society’. 80 The<br />

majority’s suppression of cultural and religious differences harms not<br />

only the individuals and the communities concerned, but society as a<br />

whole. He continues:<br />

[F]aith and public interest overlap and intertwine in the need to protect<br />

tolerance as a constitutional virtue and respect for diversity and<br />

openness as a constitutional principle. Religious tolerance is accordingly<br />

not only important to those individuals who are saved from having to<br />

make excruciating choices between their beliefs and the law. It is deeply<br />

meaningful to all of us because religion and belief matter, and because<br />

living in an open society matters. 81<br />

For Sachs J, freedom of belief and the freedom to express such belief<br />

are fundamental not only to the freedom and dignity of the believers<br />

concerned, but also to the diversity and openness that are the<br />

lifeblood of a democracy. Democracy, Sachs J seems to be saying,<br />

presupposes the ability of marginalised and vulnerable minorities to<br />

challenge the normative closure into which political communities<br />

tend to lapse. A political community can only remain free if it values<br />

plurality and difference, and allows out-groups to disturb and to<br />

challenge deeply held majoritarian beliefs and practices. 82 For <strong>this</strong><br />

reason, the critical challenge for our constitutional ‘democracy’<br />

consists ‘not in accepting what is familiar and easily accommodated,<br />

78 See Prince (n 7 above) paras 146 155-156 and 170.<br />

79 n 7 above, para 161.<br />

80<br />

n 7 above, para 147.<br />

81 n 7 above, para 170.<br />

82 n 7 above, para 147 (‘[P]ractical inconvenience and disturbance of established<br />

majoritarian mind-sets are the price that constitutionalism exacts from<br />

government.’)


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 181<br />

but in giving reasonable space to what is “unusual, bizarre or even<br />

threatening”’. 83<br />

Nowhere in his judgment does Sachs J renounce the language of<br />

dignity, or question its centrality to the Final Constitution. In fact, his<br />

judgment can be read as an endorsement of the constitutional<br />

commitment to dignity, and a celebration of dignity’s con-comitant<br />

commitment to self-worth, self-actualisation and self-governance. 84<br />

What is significant about his judgment, however, is the manner in<br />

which the language of dignity is supplemented by a more nuanced<br />

account of democracy — a Whitmanian vision of democracy that ties<br />

the ability of individuals to re-imagine their own identities to the<br />

capacity of the political community for transformation. 85<br />

Underlying Sachs’ radically democratic vision is an equally<br />

egalitarian concern — the demand for equal recognition, as Charles<br />

Taylor puts it 86 — for marginal cultures, worldviews and lifestyles.<br />

Sachs emphasises the political powerlessness of the Rastafari in a<br />

manner that recalls the concerns of representation-reinforcing<br />

process theory. 87 The continuing disempowerment of the Rastafari<br />

unmasks the power relations lurking beneath a veneer of formally<br />

equal treatment, and shows how facially neutral laws are conditioned<br />

by background assumptions that define ‘normality’ in terms of<br />

conformity to the tenets of mainstream religions. At the same time,<br />

it presents the political community with an opportunity to reconsider<br />

the ways in which the boundaries of citizenship are being drawn. Of<br />

the relationship between the ‘romantic-liberal’ view of<br />

constitutionalism and the struggle of out-groups for recognition,<br />

Frank Michelman writes:<br />

A chief aim of the romantic-liberal constitution must be to free ‘the lifechances<br />

of the individual ... from the tyranny of social categories’ of<br />

‘classes, sexes, and nations’. The benefit accrues not only to the<br />

emancipated: it is structural and systemic, and accrues to everyone.<br />

Everyone, in the romantic view, has reason to welcome confrontation<br />

and challenge of his or her accustomed or habitual ways and values,<br />

from all quarters known and unknown. Democracy accordingly becomes<br />

83 n 7 above, para 172. The remaining judges of the Constitutional Court have<br />

recently explicitly endorsed a similar conception of reasonable accommodation of<br />

marginalised individuals and groups. KwaZulu-Natal MEC for Education & Others v<br />

Pillay 2008 2 BCLR 99 (CC).<br />

84 n 7 above, paras 148, 151. Moreover, the dissenting judgment of Ngcobo J, in<br />

which Sachs J concurred, made much of the way the general prohibition<br />

stigmatises Rastafari, and thus ‘strikes at the very core of their human dignity.’ n<br />

7 above, paras 48-51.<br />

85<br />

For a fuller elaboration of <strong>this</strong> understanding of democracy, see F Michelman<br />

‘Law’s republic’ (1988) 97 Yale Law Journal 1493; F Michelman Brennan and<br />

democracy (1999) 68-89.<br />

86<br />

C Taylor The ethics of authenticity (1992).<br />

87 JH Ely Democracy and distrust (1981).


182 Chapter 10<br />

not just a procedural but a substantive ideal — a commitment to<br />

empower the disempowered and reconnect the alienated. Likewise,<br />

freedom of expression figures for the romantic constitutionalist as both<br />

an individual right of self-presentation — of efficacious participation or<br />

citizenship — and a social-structural provision for imbuing social life with<br />

the enrichment, and politics with the knowledge, sparked by frictional<br />

contact with human outlooks and sensibilities other than those to which<br />

one has grown accustomed. 88<br />

This constitutional vision is attractive for our account of limitations<br />

analysis for a number of reasons. First, it calls for a form of limitations<br />

analysis under FC section 36 which does not privilege a single value —<br />

say dignity. Our non-reductionist account of the values at play in<br />

limitations analysis — and our emphasis on democracy and openness<br />

— may counter the tendency to overlook forms of group-based<br />

disadvantage not easily captured by the language of dignity. 89 Put<br />

slightly differently, FC section 36’s commitment to openness ought to<br />

underwrite an approach to limitations analysis that challenges any<br />

unitary conception of the good. Second, a commitment to openness<br />

recognises that some conflicts may be intractable — just as some<br />

values are, in given contexts, incommensurable. This commitment, to<br />

plurality and to difference, should serve to counter naïve attempts to<br />

‘balance’ conflicting interests in terms of FC section 36. Third, a<br />

commitment to openness helps us to make further sense of FC section<br />

7(1)’s statement that the Bill of Rights ‘is a cornerstone of democracy<br />

in South Africa’. FC section 7(1)’s vision of democracy presupposes<br />

public processes of deliberation and participation that enhance<br />

openness, plurality and difference. 90 Although <strong>this</strong> vision does not<br />

resolve the tension between democracy and rights, it enables us to<br />

explore the potential of rights litigation to strengthen democracy.<br />

Finally, the commitment to a principle of openness in FC section 36<br />

alerts us to the ways in which the lack of access of certain groups to<br />

the levers of political power is re-inforced by apparently neutral laws<br />

that privilege certain worldviews over others. It reminds us of the<br />

emancipatory potential of robust democratic discourse, and the<br />

capacity of marginal social groups or ‘oppositional counterpublics’ 91<br />

to contest dominant notions of normality 92 and to challenge the<br />

tendency of the political community to assume its own moral<br />

completion. 93<br />

88 Michelman Brennan and democracy (n 85 above) 70-71.<br />

89<br />

See Botha (n 55 above) 746-751.<br />

90 See Prince (n 7 above) paras 170-171.<br />

91 Thomas (n 76 above) 87.<br />

92<br />

See Botha (n 55 above) 745-746 (Argues that the majority judgment in Jordan<br />

rested upon a highly conventional understanding of what constitutes normal<br />

sexual relations, and prevented oppositional discourses of sexuality from entering<br />

mainstream public discourse.)<br />

93 Michelman Brennan and democracy (n 85 above) 71.


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 183<br />

5.4 Judicial Narratives<br />

In the previous two sections, we tried to develop limitations analysis<br />

in a manner that makes greater sense both from an institutional<br />

perspective and from a normative perspective. However, just as<br />

shared constitutional interpretation does not provide a simple answer<br />

to the inevitable political conflicts that arise out of the dual<br />

commitment to the doctrines of constitutional supremacy and<br />

separation of powers, even a normative framework that takes<br />

adequate account of both democracy and dignity is not going to<br />

resolve — in an unproblematic fashion — the kinds of conflicts<br />

between incommensurable goods that arise in constitutional disputes.<br />

How then are judges engaged in limitations analysis to arrive at an<br />

optimal decision when neither considerations of institutional comity<br />

nor normative coherence yield a univocal conclusion? A number of<br />

authors have, of late, suggested that storytelling may yield significant<br />

benefits for hard cases, in general, and hard cases in terms of<br />

limitations analysis, in particular.<br />

That said, the following account of judicial narrative-making is<br />

not meant to supplant conventional limitations analysis undertaken by<br />

the Court in terms of conventional morality. However, the virtues of<br />

<strong>this</strong> approach are visible in a number of hard cases. The requirements<br />

of storytelling may force decision-makers to consider a range of<br />

possibilities that would not have otherwise occurred to them and thus<br />

to alter the conclusions they ultimately reach. In addition, the<br />

difference between storytelling in hard cases and cryptic<br />

justifications for hard choices — in terms of FC section 36 — is the<br />

difference between a good explanation and a bad explanation for the<br />

decisions that we take: The better the explanation, the more<br />

persuasive it will be — for those who need persuading; the more<br />

persuasive the decision, the more legitimate it will be deemed to<br />

be. 94 Denser judicial narratives thus serve a good that we have argued<br />

is essential in fundamental rights interpretation and limitations<br />

analysis: analytical rigour.<br />

The following two case studies do not prove that storytelling<br />

invariably works for limitations analysis in hard cases. No approach to<br />

limitations analysis could carry such a burden. They serve a rather<br />

more mundane purpose: To show that judges doing constitutional law,<br />

94 See P Gewirtz ‘On I know it when I see it’ (1996) 105 Yale Law Journal 1023 1042-<br />

1043. See also P Gewirtz ‘Narrative and rhetoric in the law’ in P Brooks & P<br />

Gewirtz (eds) Law’s stories: Narrative and rhetoric in the Law (1996) 2 11 (‘[An]<br />

opinion usually ends with the words “It is so ordered”, emphasising the coercive<br />

force that judges wield. But the written justification in the body of the judicial<br />

opinion is what gives the order its authority.’)


184 Chapter 10<br />

who might otherwise be sceptical of storytelling, not only have the<br />

capacity to tell stories, but to do so to brilliant effect.<br />

5.4.1 Prince<br />

Consider the dissenting judgment of Justice Sachs in Prince. In Sachs<br />

J’s view, the idea that the religious freedom of Rastafari must simply<br />

give way to the state’s interest in law enforcement rests on what he<br />

calls the ‘hydraulic insistence on conformity to majoritarian<br />

standards’. 95 Justice Sachs challenges the supposed neutrality of <strong>this</strong><br />

dominant mindset by choosing a narrative perspective that differs<br />

fundamentally from that of the majority. Instead of emphasising lawenforcement,<br />

Sachs J tells us a bit about the history of the Rastafari,<br />

the centrality of cannabis in their religion, the marginality of the<br />

Rastafari in South African life, and their inability to exercise any<br />

meaningful influence on the political process. By relocating the<br />

limitations inquiry in the ‘lived and experienced’ reality of the<br />

Rastafari, Sachs J’s story challenges dominant assumptions about the<br />

alleged dangers that certain ‘controlled’ substances pose for the<br />

common good of the commonweal. 96<br />

The minority’s stated preference for crafting an exemption for<br />

Rastafari ritual use of cannabis also dovetails rather neatly with our<br />

description of shared constitutional interpretation. For while the<br />

Court would, quite naturally, retain the power to set out very<br />

generally normative guidelines for the religious use of cannabis by<br />

Rastafari, it would remain up to the legislature, law enforcement<br />

officials and representatives of the Rastafari community to work out<br />

the details of an exemption that met the needs of all parties<br />

concerned.<br />

5.4.2 Jordan & Khosa<br />

As one of the authors has noted elsewhere, 97 the Constitutional Court<br />

in S v Jordan & Others falls into an ‘autonomy trap’ and that leads to<br />

a failure in legal imagination that actually drives the South African<br />

market in sexual slavery. In Jordan, the Constitutional Court rejected<br />

equality, dignity, privacy and freedom of profession challenges to<br />

those sections of the Sexual Offences Act that criminalise<br />

95 Prince (n 7 above) para 156.<br />

96 n 7 above, para 151.<br />

97<br />

See S Woolman & M Bishop ‘State as pimp: Sexual slavery in South Africa’ (2006)<br />

Development Southern Africa 385. See also S Woolman ‘Freedom of association’<br />

in S Woolman et al (n 6 above) Chapter 44; S Woolman & M Bishop ‘Slavery<br />

servitude and forced labour’ in S Woolman et al (n 6 above) Chapter 64; Woolman<br />

(n 35 above).


Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 185<br />

prostitution. 98 The majority reasoned as follows:<br />

If the public sees the recipient of reward as being ‘more to blame’ than<br />

the ‘client’, and a conviction carries a greater stigma on the ‘prostitute’<br />

for that reason, that is a social attitude and not the result of the law.<br />

The stigma that attaches to prostitutes attaches to them, not by virtue<br />

of their gender, but by virtue of the conduct they engage in. That stigma<br />

attaches to female and male prostitutes alike. I am not persuaded by the<br />

argument that gender discrimination exists simply because there are<br />

more female prostitutes than male prostitutes, just as I would not be<br />

persuaded if the same argument were to be advanced by males accused<br />

of certain crimes, the great majority of which are committed by men. 99<br />

The Court’s commitment to a very strong form of metaphysical<br />

autonomy — a form of autonomy that makes all individuals morally<br />

and legally culpable for actions that issue ineluctably from their<br />

circumstances — fails dramatically the large number of prostitutes<br />

who are victims of sexual trafficking. The Jordan Court continues:<br />

It was accepted that they have a choice, but it was contended that the<br />

choice is limited or ‘constrained’. Once it is accepted that [the<br />

criminalisation of prostitution] is gender-neutral and that by engaging in<br />

commercial sex work prostitutes knowingly attract the stigma associated<br />

with prostitution, it can hardly be contended that female prostitutes are<br />

discriminated against. 100<br />

First, sexual trafficking is about the sale and exploitation of women<br />

for prostitution. It is about women who have little chance, and no<br />

choice, in life’s wheel of fortune. Second, how ‘knowing’ that stigma<br />

attaches to an event that takes place under conditions of compulsion<br />

makes a prostitute culpable remains unclear. The Jordan Court’s<br />

approach may hold in the context of some ‘voluntary’ forms of<br />

prostitution. But the Jordan Court’s views regarding ‘autonomy’<br />

makes the manumission of most sexual slaves inconceivable.<br />

A more recent judgment, written by Justice Mokgoro, hints at a<br />

way out of <strong>this</strong> kind of ‘autonomy trap’. In Khosa v Minister of Social<br />

Development; Mahlaule v Minister of Social Development, the<br />

Constitutional Court found unconstitutional, as a violation of both FC<br />

section 9 and FC section 27(1), the exclusion of permanent residents<br />

from the class of persons entitled to a variety of social security grants:<br />

old age, disability, veterans, child-support and foster care. Mokgoro J<br />

writes:<br />

The exclusion of permanent residents in need of social-security<br />

programmes forces them into relationships of dependency upon families,<br />

98 See s 20(1)(aA) of the Sexual Offences Act 23 of 1957.<br />

99<br />

Jordan (n 62 above) paras 16-17.<br />

100 n 62 above, para 16.


186 Chapter 10<br />

friends and the community in which they live, none of whom may have<br />

agreed to sponsor the immigration of such persons to South Africa. ...<br />

Apart from the undue burden that <strong>this</strong> places on those who take on <strong>this</strong><br />

responsibility, it is likely to have a serious impact on the dignity of the<br />

permanent residents concerned who are cast in the role of<br />

supplicants. 101<br />

Mokgoro J could well have added that permanent residents are, as<br />

supplicants, not merely dependent on family members, but quite<br />

literally at their mercy.<br />

The same story could well be told of the sexual slaves that Jordan<br />

necessarily, though never directly, addresses. Many sex slaves would<br />

consider themselves fortunate to be supplicants. They are not just<br />

excluded from the protection of the law. Many sex slaves do not speak<br />

the language, do not know the law of the land, do not have the<br />

resources to engage corrupt immigration officials or to escape<br />

criminal syndicates. Many are enslaved by their own families.<br />

By depicting the permanent residents in Khosa as supplicants,<br />

Justice Mokgoro is able to get us to see that FC section 7(2), read with<br />

FC section 9 and FC section 27, places the state under an obligation<br />

to protect and to fulfil the rights of all persons in South Africa. By<br />

hammering home the point about turning our neighbours into beggars,<br />

Justice Mokgoro shows us that legal regimes that offer incentives to<br />

become members of the political community but then punish persons<br />

who cannot act on such incentives — by withholding benefits or by<br />

threatening incarceration — are perverse. Justice Mokgoro then<br />

demonstrates that the state’s denial of various social security grants<br />

to permanent residents extinguishes the material conditions for<br />

genuine agency. And, in the end, it is <strong>this</strong> depiction of Khosa’s<br />

permanent residents as supplicants — as beggars — that convinces a<br />

majority of the Court that the children, the aged and the disabled<br />

permanently resident in South Africa are entitled to their claim for<br />

state support. Had a similar story been told in Jordan about the lives<br />

of sex slaves, the outcome might well have been different.<br />

101 Khosa (n 60 above) para 76.


11 Reply<br />

Sharing interpretation: A reply to<br />

Stu Woolman & Henk Botha<br />

Johan van der Walt<br />

1 Introduction<br />

In <strong>this</strong> response I have taken my cue from a crucial line in Woolman<br />

and Botha’s text. ‘Powers of judicial review’, they write, ‘are best<br />

understood ... as a shared project of constitutional interpretation.’ 1<br />

And then they ask: ‘What is shared constitutional interpretation?’ It is<br />

not an over-simplification or an exaggeration to say that their<br />

detailed analyses of the Constitutional Court’s jurisprudence with<br />

regard to section 36 of the Constitution are in all respects aimed at<br />

answering just <strong>this</strong> question. Nor is it an over-simplification or<br />

exaggeration to say that these analyses ultimately lead them to<br />

rephrase the question in terms of the need to ‘harmonis[e] [the]<br />

conflicting ends’ of the legislature, executive and judiciary. 2 Some<br />

kind of harmonisation of conflicting interests is certainly what is at<br />

issue from the very beginning of their text, as becomes abundantly<br />

clear when we look at the whole passage regarding ‘shared<br />

constitutional interpretation’ that I have begun to quote above.<br />

From <strong>this</strong> perspective, powers of judicial review are best understood,<br />

not as a part of a battle for ascendancy between courts and legislatures<br />

1 S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations: Shared constitutional interpretation, an<br />

appropriate normative framework & hard choices’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds)<br />

Constitutional conversations (2008) 150.<br />

2 Woolman & Botha (n 1 above) 152.<br />

187


188 Chapter 11<br />

... or a means of frustrating the will of the political majority but, rather,<br />

as a shared project of constitutional interpretation. 3<br />

Woolman and Botha then commence to explain <strong>this</strong> shared project of<br />

constitutional interpretation with reference to four points that show<br />

that the relation of sharing involved here is one of more or less mutual<br />

deference: The legislature must allow the judiciary to declare a<br />

specific aspect of legislation unconstitutional, but the judiciary must<br />

from their side leave as much scope as possible to the legislature to<br />

select one of the many ways in which a legislative goal can be pursued<br />

without falling foul of the Constitution.<br />

One must nevertheless push <strong>this</strong> sophisticated understanding of<br />

shared constitutional interpretation to its limits in order to begin to<br />

explore that which lurks at and beyond these limits. What are the<br />

limits at issue here? Having invoked Sachs J’s notion of the maximum<br />

harmonisation of conflicting interests of the legislature and judiciary,<br />

Woolman and Botha also pay passing attention to Sachs J’s<br />

acknowledgment of the possibility of intractable conflicts between<br />

the judiciary and legislature in which the project of shared<br />

interpretation would sadly come to falter. This is however not the<br />

first invocation of the limits of interpretation in their text. In the<br />

rather optimistic passage on the notion of shared interpretation that<br />

I have quoted twice now, they also slip in between parentheses, as if<br />

it is a self-evident matter that only warrants a brief reminder, a<br />

reference to the possibility of the impossibility of <strong>this</strong> sharing. Let me<br />

quote <strong>this</strong> passage again, <strong>this</strong> time, fully in full:<br />

From <strong>this</strong> perspective, powers of judicial review are best understood,<br />

not as a part of a battle for ascendancy between courts and legislatures<br />

(though they may turn into that) or a means of frustrating the will of the<br />

political majority but, rather, as a shared project of constitutional<br />

interpretation. 4<br />

I would like to suggest that their whole text turns on an endeavour to<br />

indeed keep <strong>this</strong> ‘though they may turn into that’ in the<br />

unthreatening zone between these parentheses. The unproblematic<br />

and almost in passing fashion in which they later pay a little more<br />

attention to Sachs J’s reference to intractable conflicts between<br />

legislature and judiciary, 5 gives the whole invocation of<br />

‘intractability’ the quality of an aside. Here again, the almost in<br />

passing reference to intractability has the effect of diminishing its<br />

purport. This later invocation of Sachs J’s acknowledgement of<br />

intractability does not appear between parentheses as it does in the<br />

3 Woolman & Botha (n 1 above) 150.<br />

4<br />

As above.<br />

5 Woolman & Botha (n 1 above) 180.


Reply - Johan van der Walt 189<br />

passage above. However, one feels tempted to insert or read into <strong>this</strong><br />

part of their text another set of parentheses to mark <strong>this</strong> in-passing<br />

nature of their invocation of potential intractability. A set of<br />

parentheses appears to have been omitted here ‘inadvertently’.<br />

However, I wish to suggest, to the contrary, that a realistic regard<br />

for the potential of intractable conflicts between judiciary and<br />

executive actually beckons one to remove the first set of parentheses<br />

in the passage quoted above, and to decline the invitation to<br />

interpretively add another set in the later discussion of intractability.<br />

The first set of parentheses should be removed so that that which<br />

figures between them can spill more constructively and destructively,<br />

‘deconstructively’ one can say, into the rest of their text. For ‘here is<br />

the rose’. ‘It is here that we must dance’, to use Hegel’s immortal<br />

words regarding mortality in the Grundlinien der Philosophie des<br />

Rechts. 6<br />

It is here that we must pause to reflect deeply, because it is here<br />

that the notion of shared constitutional interpretation runs headlong<br />

into the question of the possibility or impossibility of sharing that has<br />

involved two great philosophers of our time in what may well become<br />

an epoch making debate. Existence is as such a matter of sharing,<br />

argues Jean-Luc Nancy in his scintillating work L’Expérience de la<br />

liberté. 7 Existence is a function of the impossibility of sharing,<br />

responds Derrida in Voyous. 8 I think our responsibility lies not in trying<br />

to determine which of these two philosophers are conclusively<br />

correct, but in drawing from their debate the insight that we, mortal,<br />

finite and fallible beings that we are, have hitherto always seemed to<br />

be entangled and caught up in the irreducible tensions between<br />

possibilities and impossibilities of sharing. We should draw from their<br />

debate the insight that human beings are always caught up in what<br />

Botha elsewhere, in the context of the question of the possibility or<br />

impossibility of constitutional democracy, calls an ‘(im)possibility’,<br />

that is, the irreducible and irreducibly enigmatic concomitance of the<br />

possible and impossible in all things human. 9 It is in <strong>this</strong> regard that I<br />

wish to question Woolman and Botha’s optimistic understanding of<br />

shared interpretation as a crucial element of the life of a living law in<br />

which the harmony or harmoniously shared roles between common<br />

and constitutional law will allow the Constitution to grow creatively.<br />

I would like to ask whether one should not spare the precariousness<br />

and fragility of the life of <strong>this</strong> living law a little more thought.<br />

6<br />

G Hegel Werke in Zwanzig Bänden, Band 7 (1971) 26-27.<br />

7 Nancy L’Expérience de la liberté (1988) 91-107.<br />

8 Derrida Voyous (2003) 74.<br />

9<br />

H Botha ‘Rights, limitations and the (im)possibility of self-government’ in H Botha<br />

et al (eds) Rights and democracy in a transformative constitution (2004).


190 Chapter 11<br />

This inseparable concomitance between the possible and the<br />

impossible (nothing is possible unless it is, at least at first, impossible)<br />

derives from the structure of language and linguistic statements that<br />

determines all shared interpretations and the sharing of all<br />

interpretations, a structure that one can describe by the neologistic<br />

conjunction immimanence, that is, the neologistic conjunction of the<br />

words immanence and imminence. Language is not only immanent to<br />

itself as Wittgenstein taught us. Language is always also imminent.<br />

Language does not only allow one to say what has hitherto been<br />

sayable, it also allows one and indeed requires one to say also what<br />

has hitherto remained unsayable. 10 It requires us to say the unsayable<br />

for the sake of the existential significance of the linguistic utterance,<br />

an existential significance that often goes by the name of justice.<br />

The tension between the already sayable and the as yet unsayable<br />

that always waits to be said for the sake of justice, the tension<br />

between immanence and imminence, is the mark or scar of all<br />

language and all linguistic utterances. This mark or scar informs all<br />

levels of ‘shared’ interpretation. Shared interpretation is scarred<br />

interpretation. There is no sharing without slicing or cutting. Indeed,<br />

shared interpretation is scarred interpretation to the extent that it<br />

heals somewhat and does not remain a gaping wound. The latter, one<br />

should add without the consoling assistance of parentheses, always<br />

remains a scary possibility.<br />

The relation between the legislature and the judiciary is the locus<br />

of the encounter between existing law and new law, of law that has<br />

been said and law that has hitherto remained unsaid and unsayable.<br />

As such, the relation between the legislature and the judiciary is one<br />

of immanence and imminence. An old formalist understanding of the<br />

liberal distinction between law and politics would have us simplify<br />

<strong>this</strong> relation as one of absolute constitutional immanence and relative<br />

legislative imminence. According to <strong>this</strong> formalist understanding,<br />

parliament can make (relatively) new law, provided it essentially<br />

remains subject or reconcilable with the unchanging essence of<br />

constitutional norms. The post-formalist understanding of the<br />

distinction between law and politics and of the relation between<br />

legislatures and judiciaries that is current today requires a more<br />

complex understanding of the relation between the immanence and<br />

imminence that is at issue here.<br />

No realist or realistic lawyer or legal scholar would deny today the<br />

irreducible imminence of constitutional interpretation and<br />

constitutional review. Constitutional review often brings new law into<br />

10<br />

For a further discussion of <strong>this</strong> point, see J van der Walt ‘Immimanence: Law’s<br />

language lesson’ (2006) Law Culture and the Humanities 2.


Reply - Johan van der Walt 191<br />

existence. Only old-style formalists will insist on always describing<br />

<strong>this</strong> advent of new law in the course of constitutional review in terms<br />

of ‘judicial activism’. They will only be correct in cases where the<br />

judiciary fails to access and articulate the intrinsic and truly<br />

existential imminence of language that calls for new law. Only in<br />

these cases do judges resort to the degenerate or secondary and<br />

blatantly transparent language of ‘making law’ and of ‘judicial<br />

activism’.<br />

Constitutional law, however, is not as such the abode of<br />

imminence. In the relation between constitutional rights and<br />

legislation, constitutional law and legislation take turns in saying the<br />

unsaid or saying what urgently waits to be said. They take turns in the<br />

always imminent disruption of immanence, the always imminent<br />

disruption of the other’s immanence. They take turns in unsaying one<br />

another. This relation between constitutional law and legislation is<br />

hardly ever a happy or easy one. In fact, to the extent that something<br />

significant comes to pass in <strong>this</strong> relation, the relation is invariably<br />

deeply destructive and deeply sacrificial. As the ancients knew well,<br />

it is through sacrifices that we create and maintain the worlds we live<br />

in, often all too cruelly so. 11 The critical and destructive moment of<br />

traversing the abyssal divide between the immanence and imminence<br />

of law and language, that is, between the already sayable and the as<br />

yet unsayable that beckons to be said in law and language, is the<br />

moment of sacrifice.<br />

It is <strong>this</strong> sacrificial moment that affords the notions of shared<br />

interpretation its grave significance for the daily praxis of<br />

constitutional interpretation. It is <strong>this</strong> sacrificial moment that renders<br />

all instances of shared interpretation fundamentally scarred and scary<br />

— scarred by the time they are indeed shared, if there ever is such a<br />

time; scary during all times that they are not.<br />

11 J van der Walt Law and sacrifice (2005) 190-233.


12<br />

THE WIDENING<br />

GYRE OF<br />

DIGNITY<br />

Stu Woolman<br />

Turning and turning in the widening gyre,<br />

The falcon cannot hear the falconer.<br />

WB Yeats The second coming<br />

As essentially a court lawyer, with no formal training in philosophy, I<br />

dare to take my stand on Kant because his imperatives encapsulate for<br />

me, by way of contrast and in the rationally most compelling manner<br />

that I have been able to discover, what was so obscene about apartheid.<br />

It serves as a constant reminder of our very ugly recent past. As a<br />

reforming Constitution, it is right that human dignity should be so highly<br />

valued.<br />

LWH Ackermann ‘The nature of the South African legal revolution’ 1<br />

Nobody crowds you, and nobody goes it alone.<br />

B Springsteen Long walk home<br />

1<br />

LWH Ackermann ‘The legal nature of the South African constitutional revolution’<br />

(2004) 4 New Zealand Law Review 650.<br />

193


194 Chapter 12<br />

1 Introduction<br />

Late one Saturday night, as I rode the rails underground Manhattan up<br />

its west side, I had a very un-New York-like experience. I ran into<br />

people I knew. I was then a first year graduate student in philosophy<br />

at Columbia, and my pleasant bubble of anonymity was burst by two<br />

of my betters — more senior graduate students already at work on<br />

their PhDs. The One (the subway line, not Neo from The Matrix) was<br />

hardly the place for chit-chat, crowded as it was, at midnight. So my<br />

betters carried on their conversation, the subject of which was The<br />

Second Coming.<br />

One of the lovely things about graduate school is that one has all<br />

the time in the world to read. And one of the lovely things about<br />

graduate school at Columbia in the 1980s was the university’s<br />

proximity to innumerable bookstores. During one of my forays into<br />

those long extinct independent shops, I picked up a collection of<br />

Yeats’ poems. Never having read Yeats before, I stumbled across The<br />

Second Coming as I might any other poem. I dog-eared page 116, and<br />

kept turning back to it because the poem had struck me with all the<br />

force of a revelation. Well-schooled in literature, but unschooled in<br />

the more recondite vocabulary of modern poetry, I couldn’t claim to<br />

understand more than it offered at a both a literal and visceral level.<br />

But that seemed more than enough reason for me to commit it to<br />

memory.<br />

So when my betters just happened to take up The Second Coming<br />

as a topic of conversation, I couldn’t have been more eager, more<br />

open to the wisdom that they might dispense. It came then as<br />

something of a shock to hear that they considered The Second Coming<br />

to be something of a cliché. Over-anthologised. Over-quoted. Overcited.<br />

Ubiquitous. As overplayed in middle-brow literary fora as<br />

Vivalidi’s The Four Seasons is on classical music stations. (Their<br />

churlish dismissal still manages to take a wee bit of pleasure out of<br />

<strong>this</strong> great poem — much like the doctors in Clockwork Orange were<br />

able to eliminate most (but not all) of the immense pleasure that<br />

Beethoven’s Ninth gave the book’s protagonist.) But the poem<br />

remains beautiful and powerful. Yeats had something profound to say<br />

about modernity; and no one can gainsay the prescience of the poem<br />

with regard to the violence and the anarchy of the century that<br />

followed.<br />

It seems to me that some of my betters have offered a similar<br />

conclusion about dignity. Over-used. Over-cited. Over-indulged.<br />

Ubiquitous. A cliché. What I will suggest in the pages that follow is<br />

that although dignity has been deployed again and again by<br />

philosophers ever since Kant placed dignity at the centre of modern


Stu Woolman 195<br />

moral philosophy, and has been employed again and again by<br />

Constitutional Courts in Germany, in Canada and in South Africa from<br />

the very inception of their respective constitutional projects, that<br />

constant return does not turn the right to dignity into a right that<br />

means anything and everything, and therefore nothing. As we shall<br />

see, the right to dignity, like The Second Coming, speaks powerfully<br />

to the violence and the anarchy of the 20th and 21st Centuries. More<br />

importantly, however, dignity, as a rule-generating right (and value)<br />

in South African constitutional law, moves in an ever widening gyre<br />

that speaks not just to our past but to our future, and denotes an ever<br />

widening gyre of constitutional obligations to our fellow citizens.<br />

2 History<br />

South Africa boasts one of the world’s most developed bodies of<br />

dignity jurisprudence. Only the Federal Constitutional Court’s gloss on<br />

the meaning of dignity in Germany’s Basic Law can match the richness<br />

of our Constitutional Court’s account.<br />

As the epigram from Justice Ackermann suggests, the richness of<br />

<strong>this</strong> jurisprudence flows, in part, from South African history. The<br />

Truth and Reconciliation Commission (‘TRC’), for example,<br />

recognised that dignity has its roots in the simple idea that justice<br />

consists of the refusal to turn away from suffering. The TRC’s<br />

unflinching commitment to the provisional provision of a historical<br />

record of such suffering under apartheid was the first step in our<br />

moral re-awakening. However, dignity traces an arc that extends<br />

beyond the narrow duty to refuse to turn away from suffering to a<br />

broader duty to recognise our fellow citizens as agents capable of<br />

governing themselves. The granting of a truly universal franchise, and<br />

its exercise in the election of Nelson Mandela in 1994 (and in every<br />

other subsequent election), constitutes formal recognition of the<br />

capacity of each person to legislate for him or her self. The history of<br />

dignity in South Africa does not end there. The formal recognition of<br />

our compatriots as autonomous moral agents underwrites an even<br />

wider obligation to convert their innate talents into capabilities that<br />

will, in turn, enable them to realise their preferred way of being in<br />

the world. When refracted through the prism of dignity, the Final<br />

Constitution extends our obligations, beyond the franchise and those<br />

civil liberties that permit us to legislate for ourselves, to socioeconomic<br />

rights that guarantee the material transformation of the<br />

lives of each and every South African. 2 This brief history of our new-<br />

2 See S Liebenberg ‘The value of human dignity in interpreting socio-economic<br />

rights’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 1. See S Woolman<br />

‘Dignity’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd<br />

Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 36, available at www.westlaw.com.


196 Chapter 12<br />

found ability to recognise the inherent dignity of our fellow South<br />

Africans is meant to suggest how the extension of <strong>this</strong> right progresses<br />

from mere duties of justice to duties of virtue that have as their aim<br />

the qualitative perfection of humanity. 3<br />

Despite its deep and profound resonance with South African<br />

history, dignity is manifestly not like Auden’s valley cheese — ‘local,<br />

but prized everywhere’. The Constitutional Court quite consciously<br />

draws upon two exogenous sources, both a part of modern western<br />

thought.<br />

First, the Court traces dignity’s place in the pantheon of political<br />

thought back to Immanuel Kant. The existing corpus of South Africa’s<br />

dignity jurisprudence tracks, in a surprisingly direct manner, the<br />

trajectory of Kant’s ethical thought, and, in particular, his various<br />

formulations of the categorical imperative. The Court’s jurisprudence<br />

turns, as we shall see, in an ever widening gyre of obligation: moving<br />

outward from ‘the refusal to turn away’ as manifest in the death<br />

penalty and corporal punishment judgments, to ‘the equal respect’<br />

accorded non-traditional forms of intimate association in the gay and<br />

lesbian rights cases, to ‘the collective responsibility for the material<br />

conditions required for agency’ contemplated in recent socioeconomic<br />

rights decisions.<br />

Second, the Court recognises that the history of dignity is a history<br />

3<br />

Any meaningful historical account of dignity’s South African roots must take note<br />

of other endogenous sources: first, the Roman-Dutch law of personality. See LWH<br />

Ackermann ‘The significance of human dignity for constitutional jurisprudence’<br />

(Lecture, Stellenbosch Law Faculty, 15 August 2005)(Manuscript on file with<br />

author) § 6 (Personality rights include the rights to dignity.) See also J Neethling,<br />

JM Potgieter & PJ Visser Neethling’s Law of personality (2005) 24-38; Universiteit<br />

van Pretoria v Tommie Meyer Films (Edms) Bpk 1977 4 SA 376 381 (T); National<br />

Media Ltd v Jooste 1996 3 SA 262 272 (A). Other authors have suggested that the<br />

African concept of ‘ubuntu’ and dignity draw on quite similar moral intuitions.<br />

See Y Mokgoro ‘Ubuntu and the law in South Africa’ (1998) 4 Buffalo Human<br />

Rights Law Review 15; D Cornell ‘A call for a nuanced jurisprudence’ (2004) 19<br />

South African Public Law 661; M Pieterse ‘“Traditional” African jurisprudence’ in<br />

C Roederer & D Moellendorf (eds) Jurisprudence (2004) 441. See also S v<br />

Makwanyane 1995 3 SA 391 (CC), 1995 6 BCLR 665 (CC), 1995 2 SACR 1 (CC) at<br />

paras 224-225 (Langa J) (Ubuntu captures, conceptually, ‘a culture which places<br />

some emphasis on communality and on the interdependence of the members of a<br />

community. It recognises a person’s status as a human being, entitled to<br />

unconditional respect, dignity, value and acceptance from the members of the<br />

community such a person happens to be part of. It also entails the converse,<br />

however. The person has a corresponding duty to give the same respect, dignity,<br />

value and acceptance to each member of that community. More importantly, it<br />

regulates the exercise of rights by the emphasis it lays on sharing and coresponsibility<br />

and the mutual enjoyment of rights by all.’ (Emphasis added).)


Stu Woolman 197<br />

of the world after World War II. 4 It is no accident that dignity occupies<br />

a central place in German constitutional jurisprudence: for ‘dignity’<br />

is the flip-side of ‘never again’. And just as the Germans have<br />

promised not to shovel people into stoves, so too have South Africans<br />

promised never again to treat people like cattle to be packed off to<br />

bantustans or to be slaughtered in the middle of the night. Dignity,<br />

like the words ‘never again’, may now have a new and deeper<br />

meaning post-Third Reich and post-apartheid. But ‘dignity’, like<br />

‘never again’, writes Alan Ryan, has, in fact, ‘been the watchword all<br />

along.’ 5 Ultimately, that watchword always returns us to first<br />

principles: the refusal to turn away.<br />

3 Definitions of dignity<br />

One can identify five primary definitions of dignity in the Court’s<br />

jurisprudence. One aim of the following taxonomy is to demonstrate<br />

how these five definitions draw down on the same basic insight: That<br />

we recognise all individuals as ends-in-themselves capable of selfgovernance.<br />

(Put pithily, each definition of dignity emphasises a<br />

different dimension of our status as relatively autonomous moral<br />

agents.) I suggest how these definitions build upon <strong>this</strong> common<br />

insight and interpenetrate one another to yield a theory of ‘dignity’. 6<br />

4<br />

See A Chaskalson ‘Human dignity as a foundational value of our constitutional<br />

order’ (2000) 16 South African Journal on Human Rights 193 196 (‘The affirmation<br />

of human dignity as a foundational value of the constitutional order places our<br />

legal order firmly in line with the development of constitutionalism in the<br />

aftermath of the second world war.’)<br />

5<br />

A Ryan ‘After the fall: Judt’s Postwar: A history of Europe since 1945’ New York<br />

Review of Books 3 November 2005 16 19.<br />

6<br />

I stand accused — well, mildly criticised — by Justice Ackermann and others of<br />

engaging in a rather benighted Hartian attempt to reduce ‘dignity’ to a series of<br />

definitions or rules. I remain somewhat perplexed by <strong>this</strong> charge — since I and<br />

most other lawyers take law to be a rule-governed exercise, and that to<br />

understand a phenomenon as rule-governed does not entail a commitment to a<br />

Hartian view of law or language. That said, a word or two of explanation about<br />

<strong>this</strong> chapter’s method appears to be in order before I set out my taxonomy of<br />

dignity and some of the black letter law FC section 10 has generated below. First,<br />

neither the emphasis on the actual manner in which the courts have used and<br />

defined dignity, nor the effort to distinguish first order rules from second order<br />

rules should lead the reader to conclude that I aim to offer a purely positivist<br />

account of <strong>this</strong> body of law. See HLA Hart The concept of law (1961) (Not even<br />

HLA Hart, with whom the nomenclature of primary rules and secondary rules is<br />

most often associated, assumes that such rules exhaust the universe of<br />

obligations.) Second, if the point of a positivist account (shorn of more<br />

controversial jurisprudential baggage) is to construct a taxonomy of all the rules<br />

that constitute the law of dignity — made up of the primary rules that impose<br />

4 See<br />

legal<br />

A<br />

obligations<br />

Chaskalson<br />

and<br />

‘Human<br />

the secondary<br />

dignity as<br />

rules<br />

a foundational<br />

that govern<br />

value<br />

the<br />

of<br />

application<br />

our constitutional<br />

and the<br />

order’<br />

interpretation<br />

(2000) 16<br />

of<br />

South<br />

primary<br />

African<br />

rules<br />

Journal<br />

— then<br />

on<br />

my<br />

Human<br />

account<br />

Rights<br />

does<br />

193<br />

do<br />

196<br />

something<br />

(‘The affirmation<br />

like that.<br />

of<br />

But<br />

human<br />

it does<br />

dignity<br />

so only<br />

as<br />

because<br />

a foundational<br />

all lawyers<br />

value<br />

and<br />

of<br />

academics<br />

the constitutional<br />

attempting<br />

order<br />

to understand<br />

places our<br />

legal<br />

dignity<br />

order<br />

require<br />

firmly<br />

a Baedeker<br />

in line<br />

of<br />

with<br />

<strong>this</strong><br />

the<br />

sort to<br />

development<br />

make their way<br />

of constitutionalism<br />

through a complex<br />

in<br />

body<br />

the<br />

aftermath<br />

of jurisprudence.<br />

of the second<br />

Third,<br />

world<br />

such<br />

war.’)<br />

a Baedeker alone is insufficient to the task of<br />

5<br />

A<br />

explanation.<br />

Ryan ‘After<br />

In<br />

the<br />

the<br />

fall:<br />

first<br />

Judt’s<br />

place,<br />

Postwar:<br />

legal<br />

A<br />

rules<br />

history<br />

often<br />

of<br />

perform<br />

Europe since<br />

more<br />

1945’<br />

than<br />

New<br />

a single<br />

York<br />

Review<br />

function.<br />

of<br />

See<br />

Books<br />

JW<br />

3 November<br />

Harris Legal<br />

2005<br />

Philosophies<br />

16 19.<br />

(1980) 105-109 (In the accepted


198 Chapter 12<br />

3.1 Dignity 1: Individual as an end-in-herself<br />

Justice Ackermann, the Court’s original exponent of dignity, grounds<br />

the first definition of dignity in two sources that we have already<br />

identified: apartheid and the work of Immanuel Kant:<br />

[I]t is permissible and indeed necessary to look at the ills of the past<br />

which [the Constitution] seeks to rectify and in <strong>this</strong> way try to establish<br />

what equality and dignity mean. ... What lay at the heart of the<br />

apartheid pathology was the extensive and sustained attempt to deny to<br />

the majority of the South African population the right of selfidentification<br />

and self-determination. ... Who you were, where you<br />

could live, what schools and universities you could attend, what you<br />

could do and aspire to, and with whom you could form intimate personal<br />

relationship was determined for you by the state. ... That state did its<br />

best to deny to blacks that which is definitional to being human, namely<br />

the ability to understand or at least define oneself through ones own<br />

powers and to act freely as a moral agent pursuant to such<br />

understanding of self-definition. Blacks were treated as means to an end<br />

and hardly ever as an end in themselves; an almost complete reversal of<br />

the Kantian imperative and concept of priceless inner worth and<br />

dignity. 7<br />

For Kant, as for Ackermann, the recognition of every human being’s<br />

inherent dignity takes the form of a variation on the golden rule, the<br />

categorical imperative: ‘Act in such a way that you always treat<br />

6 explanation. In the first place, legal rules often perform more than a single<br />

function. See JW Harris Legal Philosophies (1980) 105 - 109 (In the accepted<br />

parlance of legal positivism, primary rules are generally understood to impose<br />

duties and obligations, while secondary rules, which are parasitic on the<br />

existence of primary rules, determine how primary rules are to be applied or to<br />

be altered). See also Hart (supra) at 77–96. However, I use ‘first order rule’ and<br />

‘second order rule’ in a technical sense not meant to evoke passionate debate<br />

about the virtues and vices of legal positivism. First order rules resolve disputes;<br />

second order rules assist in the interpretation of—though they do not necessarily<br />

determine— the content of first order rules in a manner that permits resolution of<br />

disputes. See S Woolman ‘Review of Corder and Du Plessis Understanding South<br />

Africa’s Transitional Bill of Rights’ (1996) 112 South African Law Journal 711, 715.<br />

See also T Morawetz ‘Understanding Disagreement, the Root Issue of<br />

Jurisprudence: Applying Wittgenstein to Positivism, Critical Theory and Judging’<br />

(1992) 141 University of Pennsylvania LR 371. Not only do different denotations of<br />

dignity operate as different kinds of rules, the very same definition of ‘dignity’<br />

may operate as both a primary rule and a secondary rule. In the second place,<br />

while the word ‘dignity’ may not be so open-textured as to be the basic unit in a<br />

jurisprudential ‘Lego-land’, its multiple uses confound all attempts to reduce the<br />

courts’ jurisprudence to a finite number of rules. Fourth, two distinct dangers<br />

attach to a purely positivist account of dignity: (a) formally fair rules may mask<br />

substantially unjust arrangements; (b) once a constitutional norm such as dignity<br />

is reduced to rules, obedience to the law tends to supplant considerations of<br />

justice as the primary end of our political community. We need to be regularly<br />

reminded that the legal rules that the right to dignity produces are only as good<br />

as the everyday ethical practices that inform, and regularly transform, those<br />

rules.<br />

7 Ackermann ‘Legal Nature’ (n 1 above) 650.


Stu Woolman 199<br />

humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of another,<br />

never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end.’ 8<br />

Stated in Kant’s uncompromising terms, such an ethical algorithm<br />

might seem impossible to enact. 9 We all know that, even with the<br />

best of intentions, many of the myriad interactions we have with our<br />

fellow human beings will be almost entirely instrumental. We know<br />

that whether we are taking decisions for a family, a classroom of<br />

students, a neighbourhood, a town, a province or a nation, some form<br />

of a utilitarian calculus — the greatest good for the greatest number<br />

— will enter into our considerations. And we know that the relational<br />

or communitarian quality of ethics is such that we will often privilege<br />

the claims of family, kin, neighbourhood or nation over more general<br />

or universal claims. 10<br />

8<br />

I Kant Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals trans AW Wood (ed) (2002) 45-<br />

46. See also D Meyerson Rights limited (1997) 12. That Kant should be identified<br />

as a source for constitutional doctrine in South Africa is not as outlandish a<br />

proposition as it may initially sound. In his commentary on German constitutional<br />

law and its dignity jurisprudence, Donald Kommers identifies three ‘politically<br />

significant sources of ethical theory’: Christian natural law, Kantian thought and<br />

social democratic thought. D Kommers The constitutional jurisprudence of the<br />

Federal Republic of Germany 2 ed (1997) 304. The above variation of the<br />

categorical imperative is, in fact, Kant’s second formulation. See Rawls Lectures<br />

on the history of moral philosophy (2000) 181. The second formulation turns our<br />

attention to the nature of other moral agents as rational beings, who, like our<br />

own selves, are entitled to treatment as ends in themselves. The second<br />

formulation also makes what is, for Kant and for us moderns, a crucial distinction<br />

between things which have a price — and are therefore fungible — and things<br />

which have no price — and thus have no replacement. Most of us think of our<br />

selves and those we care about as priceless. Kant asks us to extend that<br />

recognition to all human beings: for they, like us, view themselves and their<br />

significant others as irreplaceable. See AW Wood ‘Humanity as an end in itself’ in<br />

P Guyer (ed) Critical essays on Kant’s groundwork of the metaphysics of morals<br />

(1998) 165 170 (Wood defines the term ‘individual as an end-in-itself’ as ‘an end<br />

with absolute worth or (as Kant also says) dignity, something whose value cannot<br />

be compared to, traded off against, or compensated for or replaced by any other<br />

value.’) Pace L Ackermann, it is important here to note that Rawls speaks about<br />

multiple variations of the categorical imperative — and not just one. L Ackermann<br />

‘The soul of dignity: A reply to Stu Woolman’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds)<br />

Constitutional conversations (2008).<br />

9<br />

Kant did not view <strong>this</strong> principle as impossible to enact. Indeed, as Rawls notes,<br />

Kant found moral pietism offensive and conceived of the categorical imperative<br />

as a ‘mode of reflection that could order and moderate the scrutiny of our<br />

motives in a reasonable way.’ Rawls (n 8 above) 149. Perhaps the best way to<br />

characterise Kant’s categorical imperative is as a reflective check — albeit a<br />

demanding one — on our moral intuitions. A contemporary example of such a<br />

reflective check — and one that continues to do a great deal of heavy lifting — is<br />

Rawls’ own ‘veil of ignorance’. See J Rawls A theory of justice (1972). See also<br />

TW Pogge ‘The categorical imperative’ in Guyer (n 8 above) 189 206 (‘The<br />

categorical imperative is ... a general procedure for constructing morally<br />

relevant thought experiments ... [T]he categorical imperative amplifies my<br />

conscience by transforming the decision from one of marginal significance into<br />

one concerning the world at large, and also isolates my conscience by screening<br />

out personal considerations that might affect my choice of maxims but are<br />

irrelevant to my decisions about how through legislation to specify a realm of<br />

ends.’)<br />

10 See C Lamore Patterns of moral complexity (1986).


200 Chapter 12<br />

How then to understand Kant in a way that is neither sentimental<br />

nor woolly? Consider Oscar Schachter’s gloss on the categorical<br />

imperative: ‘Respect for the intrinsic worth of every person should<br />

mean that individuals are not to be perceived or treated merely as<br />

instruments or objects of the will of others.’ 11 Dignity, on <strong>this</strong><br />

account, sets a floor below which ethical — and legal — behaviour may<br />

not fall. Although some relationships will be purely instrumental, no<br />

individual person can be treated as a mere instrument over the entire<br />

domain of her social interactions. This floor supports — as the Dawood<br />

Court suggests — Chapter 2’s express prohibitions on slavery,<br />

servitude and forced labour. 12 This definition of dignity also bars punishments<br />

that either extinguish the humanity of another entirely —<br />

say, the death penalty 13 — or through their disproportionality reduce<br />

a human being to a mere signal — a warning, a disincentive — within<br />

a large and impersonal system of social control. 14<br />

3.2 Dignity 2: Equal concern and equal respect<br />

Another version of Kant’s moral law — more accurately described as a<br />

principle of justice — yields another dimension of dignity: ‘Any action<br />

is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with<br />

a universal law, or if on its maxim the freedom of choice of each can<br />

coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal<br />

law.’ 15 This primarily negative obligation not to treat another merely<br />

as a means and to recognise in that Other the freedom to act as an<br />

end in itself — the ability to act as an autonomous moral agent —<br />

underwrites a conception of dignity as a formal entitlement to equal<br />

concern and to equal respect. 16 From <strong>this</strong> conception, the Constitutional<br />

Court has constructed two different, though not entirely<br />

distinct, tests in terms of FC section 9 (the right to equality): (1) a<br />

right to equal treatment which ensures (a) that the law does not<br />

irrationally differentiate between classes of person and (b) that the<br />

11 O Schachter ‘Human dignity as a normative concept’ (1983) 77 American Journal<br />

of International Law 848 849.<br />

12 Dawood & Another v Minister of Home Affairs & Others 2000 3 SA 936 (CC), 2000<br />

8 BCLR 837 (CC) para 35.<br />

13<br />

See Makwanyane (n 3 above).<br />

14 See S v Dodo 2001 3 SA 382 (CC), 2001 5 BCLR 423 (CC).<br />

15 See I Kant Metaphysics of morals trans M Gregor (1991) 56 231 395.<br />

16<br />

Kant offers a more accessible, and less rarefied, account of dignity qua equal<br />

concern and equal respect in the Metaphysics of morals, when he writes:<br />

[A] human being regarded as a person ... is exalted above any price; for<br />

as a person ... he is not merely to be valued merely as a means to the<br />

ends of others or even to his own ends, but as an end in itself, that is, he<br />

possesses a dignity (an absolute inner worth) by which he exacts respect<br />

for himself from all other rational beings in the world. He can measure<br />

himself with every other being of <strong>this</strong> kind and value himself on a footing<br />

of equality with them.<br />

Kant (n 15 above) 557 (my emphasis).


Stu Woolman 201<br />

law does not reflect the ‘naked preferences’ of government; and (2)<br />

a right to equal treatment that guarantees that individuals are not<br />

subject to unfair discrimination on the basis of largely ascriptive<br />

characteristics. 17 Of <strong>this</strong> demand for equal concern and equal<br />

respect, Justice Ackermann writes:<br />

[A]t the heart of the prohibition of unfair discrimination lies the<br />

recognition that the purpose of our new constitutional and democratic<br />

order is the establishment of a society in which all human beings will be<br />

accorded equal dignity and respect regardless of their membership in<br />

particular groups. The achievement of such a society in the context of<br />

our deeply inegalitarian past will not be easy, but that that is the goal of<br />

the Constitution should not be forgotten or overlooked. 18<br />

3.3 Dignity 3: Self-actualisation<br />

Another formulation of the categorical imperative shapes a third<br />

strand of the Court’s dignity jurisprudence. Kant writes: ‘Act only on<br />

the maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should<br />

become a universal law.’ 19 Here, the term that warrants the closest<br />

scrutiny is ‘will’. For Kant, the hallmark of humanity is its ability to<br />

‘will’ or to shape its ends through ‘reason’. But when Kant writes that<br />

our humanity consists, at least in part, in our power to rationally set<br />

and will an end, he is not speaking solely of an individual’s capacity<br />

to adopt an end for purely moral reasons. While Kant certainly<br />

contends that the defining feature of humanity is our capacity to<br />

overcome our instincts and that we are only truly free when we are<br />

moral, he maintains that we define ourselves — and our humanity —<br />

through the rational choice of all of our ends and not just those that<br />

are explicitly moral. This broader capacity to create meaning — to<br />

‘will’ value into the world — gives rise to the modern political and<br />

ethical pre-occupation with ‘self-actualisation’. An individual’s<br />

capacity to create meaning generates an entitlement to respect for<br />

the unique set of ends that the individual pursues. In Ferreira v Levin,<br />

Justice Ackermann writes:<br />

Human dignity cannot be fully valued or respected unless individuals are<br />

able to develop their humanity, their ‘humanness’ to the full extent of<br />

its potential. Each human being is uniquely talented. Part of the dignity<br />

of every human being is the fact and awareness of <strong>this</strong> uniqueness. An<br />

17 See President of the Republic of South Africa v Hugo 1997 4 SA 1 (CC), 1997 6<br />

BCLR 708 (CC) para 41 (‘[T]he purpose of our new constitutional and democratic<br />

order is the establishment of a society in which all human beings will be accorded<br />

equal respect regardless of their membership in particular groups.’ (My<br />

emphasis.))<br />

18 LWH Ackermann ‘Equality under the 1996 South African Constitution’ in Wolfrem<br />

(ed) Gleichheit und Nichtdiskriminierung im Nationalen und Internationalen<br />

Mesenchenrechtssschutz (2003) 547.<br />

19 Kant (n 8 above) 37-38.


202 Chapter 12<br />

individual’s human dignity cannot be fully respected or valued unless the<br />

individual is permitted to develop his or her unique talents optimally.<br />

Human dignity has little value without freedom; for without freedom<br />

personal development and fulfilment are not possible. Without freedom,<br />

human dignity is little more than an abstraction. Freedom and dignity<br />

are inseparably linked. To deny people their freedom is to deny them<br />

their dignity. 20<br />

Dignity, properly understood, secures the space for selfactualisation.<br />

21 That said, dignity qua self-actualisation describes<br />

only a political, and not a metaphysical, state. 22<br />

3.4 Dignity 4: Self-governance<br />

A third formulation of the categorical imperative helps us to identify<br />

a fourth dimension of dignity. 23 An essential feature of the constitutional<br />

politics that issues from the categorical imperative is the<br />

recognition of the ability of (almost) all human beings — through their<br />

capacity to reason — to legislate for themselves. Indeed, as we have<br />

just noted, it is our capacity for self-governance, and the fact that we<br />

are not simply slaves to our passions, that distinguishes man from<br />

beast. (Whether Kant is correct to make reason the sine qua non of<br />

humanity is another matter.) 24 Our capacity for self-governance — the<br />

capacity of (almost) all human beings to reason their way to the ends<br />

that give their lives meaning — is largely what makes democracy the<br />

only acceptable secular form of political organisation in modernity.<br />

For if we are capable of shaping our own ends as individuals, equal<br />

treatment demands that we be able to shape them as citizens. At a<br />

minimum, it means we must be able to participate in the collective-<br />

20 Ferreira v Levin NO & Others 1996 1 SA 984 (CC), 1996 4 BCLR 1 (CC) para 49.<br />

21<br />

See eg Hugo (n 17 above) para 41 (‘[D]ignity is at the heart of individual rights in<br />

a free and democratic society’ (my emphasis)); Prinsloo v Van der Linde 1997 3 SA<br />

1012 (CC), 1997 6 BCLR 759 (CC); National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality<br />

v Minister of Justice 1999 1 SA 6 (CC), 1998 12 BCLR 1517 (CC).<br />

22 See S Woolman The selfless constitution: Experimentation and flourishing as the<br />

foundations of the South Africa’s basic law (forthcoming 2008)(Self-actualisation<br />

is not contingent upon the ability to will freely or to choose freely one’s ends.<br />

Such a conception of freedom is a form of folk psychology. Rather, freedom<br />

consists primarily of having the capacity to participate in ways of being in the<br />

world that already give one’s life the better part of its meaning.) See also AW<br />

Wood ‘What is Kantian ethics?’ in Kant (n 8 above) 176 (‘I doubt that Kant’s<br />

extravagant metaphysics is the best we can do with <strong>this</strong> problem. The basic point,<br />

however, is that Kantian ethics is no more hostage to the free will problem than<br />

any other ethical theory would be that regards us as reasonable and selfgoverning<br />

beings.’)<br />

23<br />

See Rawls (n 8 above) 183 (‘In the third formulation (that of autonomy) we come<br />

back again to the agent’s point of view, but <strong>this</strong> time not as someone subject to<br />

moral requirements, but as someone who is, as it were, legislating universal law:<br />

here the [categorical imperative] procedure is seen as that procedure the<br />

adherence to which with a full grasp of its meaning enables us to regard ourselves<br />

as making law for a possible realm of ends.’)<br />

24<br />

See B Williams ‘The idea of equality’ in P Laslett & WG Runciman (eds)<br />

Philosophy, politics and society (1962) 111.


Stu Woolman 203<br />

decision making processes that determine the ends of our community.<br />

As Justice Sachs notes in August v Electoral Commission:<br />

The universality of the franchise is important not only for nationhood<br />

and democracy. The vote of each and every citizen is a badge of dignity<br />

and of personhood. Quite literally, it says that everybody counts. 25<br />

3.5 Dignity 5: Collective responsibility for the material<br />

conditions for agency<br />

The fifth and final strand of the Court’s dignity jurisprudence widens<br />

our constitutional frame beyond individual ends and asks that we<br />

consider what it means for South Africa to be, as Kant would put it, a<br />

‘realm of ends’. 26 In a series of unfair discrimination and socioeconomic<br />

rights cases, the Constitutional Court has made it clear that<br />

our commitment to dignity does not flow entirely from, or is not<br />

limited to, the inalienable rights of individuals. Whether it has<br />

engaged the stigma associated with HIV/AIDS, 27 the urgent need for<br />

shelter, 28 or the desperation associated with summary evictions, 29<br />

the Constitutional Court has, over the past several years, repeatedly<br />

emphasised the fact that<br />

[i]t is not only the dignity of the poor that is assailed when homeless<br />

people are driven from pillar to post in a desperate quest for a place<br />

where they and their families can rest their heads. Our society as a<br />

25 See August v Electoral Commission 1999 3 SA 1 (CC), 1999 4 BCLR 363 (CC) para<br />

17. See also Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention<br />

2005 3 SA 280 (CC), 2004 5 BCLR 445 (CC); New National Party of South Africa v<br />

Government of the Republic of South Africa 1999 3 SA 191 (CC), 1999 4 BCLR 457<br />

(CC). This commitment to dignity qua self-governance is rather straightforward in<br />

the franchise cases. However, dignity qua self-governance is, in fact, where the<br />

Constitutional Court falters most conspicuously. Dignity qua self-governance<br />

ought to promote the Court’s commitment to representation reinforcing<br />

processes — most notably where our democratic processes cannot be profitably<br />

exploited by vulnerable minorities and out-groups. But Prince, Jordan, Robinson<br />

and De Reuck sound cautionary notes about the extent to which the Court will<br />

extend itself on behalf of non-traditional associations, vocations or professions. In<br />

these cases, the Court reinforces a traditional morality supported by a majority of<br />

South Africans and effectively undermines the efforts of these out-groups to<br />

determine the ends of their own lives. See Prince v President, Cape Law Society &<br />

Others 2002 2 SA 794 (CC), 2002 3 BCLR 231 (CC); S v Jordan & Others (Sex<br />

Workers Education and Advocacy Task Force & Others as Amici Curiae) 2002 6 SA<br />

642 (CC), 2002 11 BCLR 1117 (CC); De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions,<br />

Witwatersrand Local Division 2004 1 SA 406 (CC), 2003 12 BCLR 1333 (CC); Volks<br />

NO v Robinson 2005 5 BCLR 466 (CC).<br />

26 See Kant (n 8 above) 51.<br />

27<br />

See Hoffman v South African Airways 2001 1 SA 1 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1211 (CC).<br />

28 See Government of the Republic of South Africa & Others v Grootboom & Others<br />

2001 1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1164 (CC).<br />

29<br />

See Occupiers of 51 Olivia Rd & Others v City of Johannesburg & Others 2008 3 SA<br />

208 (CC).


204 Chapter 12<br />

whole is demeaned when state action intensifies rather than mitigates<br />

their marginalisation. 30<br />

Dignity, on <strong>this</strong> account, is not simply a constellation of negative<br />

duties owed by the state to each human subject, or a set of positive<br />

entitlements that can be claimed by each member of the polity.<br />

Dignity is that which binds us together as a community, and it occurs<br />

only under conditions of mutual recognition. Moreover, such mutual<br />

recognition is not merely formal. The Court in Khosa notes that the<br />

Final Constitution commits us to an understanding of dignity in which<br />

wealthier members of the community view the minimal well-being of<br />

the poor as connected with their personal well-being and the well-being<br />

of the community as a whole. 31<br />

The Court’s account of dignity, which has, heretofore, offered various<br />

desiderata for individual moral agency, now appears to describe<br />

dignity as a collective good. The case law even features a small<br />

number of disputes in which the dignity interests of the collective are<br />

said to trump the dignity interests of an individual.<br />

But with the exception of a few apercu in socio-economic rights<br />

cases, and an aside or two in a handful of other disputes, the Court<br />

rarely refers to our collective dignity. The Court’s circumspection, in<br />

<strong>this</strong> regard, suggests that it does not have in mind some romantic<br />

conception of the political community.<br />

How then to comprehend dignity as a collective concern? What the<br />

Court wishes us to understand is that for dignity to be meaningful in<br />

South Africa, the political community as a whole must provide that<br />

basket of goods — including such primary goods as civil and political<br />

rights — which each member of the community requires in order to<br />

exercise some basic level of agency. This conception of dignity<br />

possesses striking similarities to Amartya Sen’s politics of capability.<br />

For Sen, as for our Constitutional Court, the primary concern of<br />

the polity is not with wealth maximisation. ‘Wealth’ as Aristotle<br />

wrote, ‘is evidently not the good we are seeking; for it is merely<br />

useful and for the sake of something else.’ 32 That something else, as<br />

Sen writes, is<br />

[t]he expansion of the ‘capabilities’ of persons to lead the kinds of lives<br />

they value — and have reason to value. ... Having freedom to do the<br />

30<br />

See Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 1 SA 217 (CC), 2004 12<br />

31<br />

BCLR 1268 (CC) para 18 (my emphasis).<br />

Khosa v Minister of Social Development 2004 6 SA 505 (CC), 2004 6 BCLR 569 (CC)<br />

32<br />

para 74.<br />

See Aristotle Nichomachean ethics D Ross trans (1980) Bk I, §§ 5 7.


Stu Woolman 205<br />

things one has reason to value is (1) significant in itself for the person’s<br />

overall freedom, and (2) important in fostering the person’s opportunity<br />

to have valuable outcomes. 33<br />

However, Sen’s aims are not limited to fostering the agency of the<br />

individual. Individual agents should be understood both as ends-inthemselves<br />

and as the ‘basic building blocks’ of aggregate social<br />

development. The ‘greater freedom’ of individuals not only ‘enhances<br />

the ability of people to help themselves and ... to influence the<br />

world,’ it is essential for the development of society as a whole. 34 For<br />

Sen, the link between individual capabilities and development is part<br />

of a virtuous circle. Enhancement of individual freedom — by both<br />

political and material means — leads to greater social development,<br />

which, in turn, further enhances the possibilities for individual<br />

capabilities and the freedom to lead the kinds of lives we have reason<br />

to value.<br />

This virtuous circle would appear to be what the Constitutional<br />

Court in Khosa has in mind when it ties the well-being of the worst off<br />

to the well-being of the wealthy. The enhancement of individual<br />

capabilities of the poorest members of our political community<br />

enhances the development of South Africa as a whole. Or put slightly<br />

differently, the greater the ‘agency’ of the least well-off members of<br />

our society, the greater the ‘agency’ of ‘all’ the members of our<br />

society. This gloss on Khosa emphasises not the subjective sense of<br />

well-being that the well-off might experience by tying their wellbeing<br />

to that of the poor. Rather it emphasises an increase in the<br />

objective sense of well-being that flows from the enhancement of the<br />

agency of each individual member of our society.<br />

3.6 The creation of a realm of ends<br />

We may be able to see, now, how dignity builds upon a simple<br />

premise, the refusal to turn away from suffering, and yields,<br />

ultimately, a realm of ends. The refusal to turn away marks the very<br />

beginning of our moral awareness — the first time we come to<br />

understand that others are not mere instruments for the realisation<br />

of our desires, but beings who are ends in themselves. This moral<br />

awakening leads, almost ineluctably, to two further insights: (a) that<br />

others are entitled to the same degree of concern and respect that we<br />

would demand for ourselves; and (b) that others are entitled to that<br />

equal respect and equal concern because they, like us, are possessed<br />

of faculties and talents that enable them to pursue ends which give<br />

their lives meaning.<br />

33<br />

A Sen Development as freedom (1999) 18.<br />

34 As above.


206 Chapter 12<br />

The ability to give our lives meaning and to determine the course<br />

by which we give our lives meaning, leads to the recognition that we<br />

are able to govern our selves. At a minimum, <strong>this</strong> recognition of our<br />

ability to govern our selves supports the more formal political<br />

recognition that just as each one of us is capable of and entitled to<br />

govern our individual self, so too each one of us is equally capable of<br />

legislating on behalf of the broader community of which we are a<br />

part. This mutual recognition of one another as rational beings<br />

capable of ordering the ends both of our own lives and of the larger<br />

community underwrites the final insight: That we not only live in a<br />

realm of ends, but that if such a realm is to have real meaning, we<br />

must be willing to order our community in a manner that enables each<br />

individual to realise their status as an end. It is simply not enough to<br />

(a) not turn away from suffering, (b) end discrimination and (c) grant<br />

all citizens the franchise. Once we recognise others as ends we must<br />

be committed — at some level — to the provision of those material<br />

means necessary to live as ends. To refuse them such means might<br />

render meaningless the more formal guarantees found in the Final<br />

Constitution. As the Court itself notes in Grootboom:<br />

The Constitution will be worth infinitely less than its paper if the<br />

reasonableness of state action concerned with housing is determined<br />

without regard to the fundamental constitutional value of human<br />

dignity. Section 26, read in the context of the Bill of Rights as a whole,<br />

must mean that the respondents have a right to reasonable action by the<br />

state in all circumstances and with particular regard to human dignity. In<br />

short, I emphasise that human beings are required to be treated as<br />

human beings. 35<br />

4 Uses of dignity<br />

The word ‘dignity’ is sprinkled about the text of the Final<br />

Constitution. It is a founding value: FC section 1(a). It acts as a<br />

cornerstone of both democracy and the Bill of Rights: FC section 7(1).<br />

It informs both our interpretation of the ambit of the specific<br />

substantive provisions of the Bill of Rights — FC section 39(1) — and<br />

our analysis of the justification of any limitation of a right or freedom<br />

— FC section 36. It governs the behaviour of our courts, other tribunals<br />

and state institutions supporting constitutional democracy: FC<br />

sections 165, 181, 196. It is, perhaps most importantly, the second<br />

substantive right identified in the Bill of Rights: FC section 10. That<br />

dignity operates as a first order rule, a second order rule, a<br />

correlative right, a value and a grundnorm — and sometimes all in a<br />

single case — is confirmed by Justice O’ Regan’s oft quoted dictum in<br />

Dawood:<br />

35 Grootboom (n 28 above) para 83 (my emphasis).


Stu Woolman 207<br />

Human ... dignity informs constitutional adjudication and interpretation<br />

at a range of levels. It is a value that informs the interpretation of many,<br />

possibly all, other rights ... Human dignity is also a constitutional value<br />

that is of central significance in the limitations analysis. Section 10,<br />

however, makes it plain that dignity is not only a value fundamental to<br />

our Constitution, it is a justiciable and enforceable right that must be<br />

respected and protected. In many cases however, where the value of<br />

human dignity is offended, the primary constitutional breach occasioned<br />

may be of a more specific right such as the right to bodily integrity, the<br />

right to equality or the right not to be subjected to slavery, servitude or<br />

forced labour. 36<br />

So, just as dignity denotes at least five different kinds of obligation,<br />

so too does dignity operate within our legal system in four sundry<br />

ways.<br />

4.1 Dignity as a first order rule<br />

The right to dignity rarely operates a first order rule. That is, the right<br />

to dignity alone is rarely dispositive of a constitutional matter. The<br />

first rule of South African dignity jurisprudence is that where a court<br />

can identify the infringement of a more specific right, FC section 10<br />

will (ostensibly) not add to the enquiry. That said, dignity has<br />

operated as a first order rule in a number of important corporal<br />

punishment and intimate association matters.<br />

In corporal punishment or capital punishment cases such as<br />

Williams 37 and Makwanyane, 38 the Constitutional Court has found<br />

that the punishment reduces the individual to a mere cipher and fails<br />

to recognise the individual as an end-in-herself. In Dawood and<br />

Booysen, the Constitutional Court found that no other specific<br />

substantive right would protect the co-habitation interests of the<br />

married couples or life partners in question and that the failure to<br />

protect such intimate associations failed to recognise both the<br />

individual as an end-in herself and the individual as capable of selfactualisation.<br />

39<br />

36 Dawood (n 12 above) para 35.<br />

37 S v Williams & Others 1995 3 SA 632 (CC), 1995 7 BCLR 861 (CC).<br />

38<br />

S v Makwanyane (n 3 above).<br />

39 See Dawood (n 12 above); Booysen v Minister of Home Affairs & Another 2001 4<br />

SA 485 (CC), 2001 7 BCLR 645 (CC). See also Daniels v Campbell 2004 5 SA 331<br />

(CC), 2004 6 BCLR 735 (CC) (Moseneke J dissenting). High Courts have extended<br />

the protection that FC section 10 affords intimate association beyond the<br />

confines of marriage or life partnerships to relationships between grandparents<br />

and grandchildren. See Petersen v Maintenance Officer, Simon’s Town 2004 2 SA<br />

56 (C), 2004 2 BCLR 205 (C). High Courts have also deployed dignity as an<br />

operational rule when no other right would protect the linguistic interests of a<br />

party before the court. See S v Pienaar 2000 7 BCLR 800 (NC) para 10; Advance<br />

Mining Hydraulics v Botes NO 2000 1 SA 815 (T), 2000 2 BCLR 119 (T) 127.


208 Chapter 12<br />

4.2 Dignity as a second order rule<br />

Dignity often operates as a second order rule. That is, dignity either<br />

informs or determines how a first order rule disposes of a given<br />

matter. Dignity, as a second order rule, features most prominently in<br />

equality (FC section 9) cases. It does so in two ways. First, an<br />

impairment of human dignity may determine whether mere<br />

differentiation amounts to actual discrimination. Second, when<br />

attempting to determine whether discrimination amounts to unfair<br />

discrimination, the Constitutional Court will ask to what extent the<br />

law or the conduct in question impairs the dignity of the complainant<br />

and whether the law or the conduct in question re-inscribes systemic<br />

patterns of disadvantage for — and thus impairs the dignity of — a<br />

specific class of persons. Similarly, dignity, as a second order rule,<br />

determines: (a) whether punishments are disproportionate (FC<br />

section 12); (b) whether the state has a duty of care with respect to<br />

the physical security of its citizens (FC sections 11 and 12); (c) the<br />

extent of the state’s interest in foetal life (FC section 11); (d) the<br />

parameters of contractual autonomy (FC section 22); (e) the<br />

circumstances under which an individual may legitimately claim that<br />

his or her home is an impregnable castle (FC section 14); (f) when the<br />

conditions of existence amount to slavery (FC section 13); and (g)<br />

when expressive conduct constitutes hate speech (FC section 16).<br />

4.3 Dignity as a correlative 40 right<br />

The Constitutional Court often deploys rights simultaneously in the<br />

service of its arguments. It likes to describe rights as interdependent<br />

and symbiotic. This talk of ‘interdependence’ is especially evident in<br />

challenges to law or to conduct grounded in the right to dignity.<br />

However, for my immediate purpose — to distinguish dignity as a<br />

correlative right from dignity as a first order rule, dignity as a second<br />

order rule or dignity as a value — I must show that dignity functions,<br />

in some respects, independently of other rights in constitutional<br />

challenges that rely upon multiple rights.<br />

S v Jordan provides a paradigmatic instance of dignity deployed<br />

as a correlative right. Justices O’Regan and Sachs note that although<br />

the rights to dignity, privacy, and freedom of the person intersect and<br />

overlap, the challenges brought in terms of each of these rights<br />

cannot be consolidated into a single challenge grounded in some<br />

‘unenumerated’ right to autonomy. Each challenge based upon a<br />

40 Pace L Ackermann ‘correlative’ does indeed mean a ‘complementary, parallel or<br />

reciprocal relationship, especially a structural, functional or qualitative<br />

correspondence.’ See www.answers.com (accessed 13 July 2008).


Stu Woolman 209<br />

specific right must, they say, be considered individually. 41<br />

The Court has adopted <strong>this</strong> multiple challenge approach in a wide<br />

variety of cases. In Bhe, customary law rules of primogeniture were<br />

found to violate both the right to equality and the right to dignity. 42<br />

In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of<br />

Justice, the Court, in finding that the common law criminalisation of<br />

consensual sodomy constituted a violation of the right to dignity, as<br />

well as a violation of the rights to equality and to privacy, wrote ‘[i]t<br />

is clear that the constitutional protection of dignity requires us to<br />

acknowledge the value and the worth of all individuals as members of<br />

society’ 43 and that ‘the rights of equality and dignity are closely<br />

related, as are the rights of dignity and privacy.’ 44<br />

4.4 Dignity as a value or a grundnorm<br />

Dignity is invoked most often as a value. Part of the reason for <strong>this</strong><br />

preference for deploying dignity as a value flows from the Court’s<br />

stated preference for ‘developing’ the law rather than making it. The<br />

result of <strong>this</strong> preference, however, is a certain lack of precision. For<br />

example, in Williams, the Court writes that:<br />

The Constitution has allocated to the State and its organs a role as the<br />

protectors and guarantors of those rights to ensure that they are<br />

available to all. In the process, it sets the State up as a model for society<br />

as it endeavours to move away from a violent past. It is therefore<br />

reasonable to expect that the State must be foremost in upholding those<br />

values which are the guiding light of civilised societies. Respect for<br />

human dignity is one such value; acknowledging it includes an<br />

acceptance by society that ‘... even the vilest criminal remains a human<br />

being possessed of common human dignity.’ 45<br />

Dignity, in <strong>this</strong> paragraph, appears to operate as a value. However,<br />

the Williams Court held that juvenile whipping constitutes a violation<br />

of the right to dignity and the right to be free from cruel, inhuman<br />

and degrading treatment.<br />

Whatever the reason for <strong>this</strong> particular instance of analytical<br />

confusion, as a matter of doctrine, the Constitutional Court is on<br />

record as having little time for the putative collapse of the rule/value<br />

distinction. In Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime<br />

Prevention, Chaskalson CJ writes:<br />

41<br />

2002 6 SA 642 (CC), 2002 6 BCLR 759 (CC) paras 52-53.<br />

42 Bhe v Magistrate, Khayelitsha 2005 1 SA 580 (CC), 2005 1 BCLR 1 (CC).<br />

43 1999 1 SA 6 (CC), 1998 12 BCLR 1517 (CC) para 28.<br />

44<br />

n 42 above, para 30.<br />

45 Williams (n 37 above) para 77.


210 Chapter 12<br />

The values enunciated in section 1 of the Constitution are of<br />

fundamental importance. They inform and give substance to all the<br />

provisions of the Constitution. They do not, however, give rise to<br />

discrete and enforceable rights in themselves. This is clear not only from<br />

the language of section 1 itself, but also from the way the Constitution is<br />

structured and in particular the provisions of Chapter 2 which contains<br />

the Bill of Rights. 46<br />

Values are one thing, the NICRO Court appears to be saying, rules<br />

another. While it is certainly true that the fundamental values<br />

articulated in the Final Constitution will shape the rules expressed<br />

therein, and that the rules will have a reciprocal effect with respect<br />

to our understanding of those fundamental values, there remains a<br />

distinction with a difference. Rights give rise to rules and to<br />

enforceable claims. Values do not.<br />

And so it is with dignity. The right to dignity — as a first order rule<br />

and as a correlative right — gives rise to enforceable claims. Dignity,<br />

as a value, does not.<br />

The first reason that dignity is invoked more often as a value than<br />

as a rule is that FC section 39 states that the various substantive<br />

provisions in the Bill of Rights, and the Bill of Rights as a whole, must<br />

be interpreted so as to ‘promote the values that underlie an open and<br />

democratic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom.’<br />

The second reason is that when a law is found to have infringed a<br />

fundamental right, the question raised, FC section 36 tells us, is<br />

whether the limitation in question ‘is reasonable and justifiable in an<br />

open and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and<br />

freedom.’ The third reason is that the ubiquity of dignity has led the<br />

Court to adhere to a relatively restrictive rule regarding the use of<br />

dignity as a first order rule: Where a court can identify the<br />

infringement of a more specific right, FC section 10 should not be<br />

added to the enquiry. Because some rights are understood,<br />

immediately, to be expressions of the commitment to dignity — say,<br />

the prohibitions on torture (FC section 12) and slavery, servitude or<br />

forced labour (FC section 13) — and many other rights, once refracted<br />

through the value of dignity, become expressions of the more basic<br />

(non–justiciable) commitment to dignity — say the right to equality<br />

and the right not to be subject to cruel, inhuman or degrading<br />

punishment — the need for dignity to function as a rule that disposes<br />

of cases directly is less pronounced than it might otherwise be.<br />

In the first class of ‘dignity as value’ cases, dignity guides our<br />

interpretation of the right and, in so doing, shapes our understanding<br />

of the ambit of a right. In Coetzee v Comitis, the Cape High Court<br />

46 NICRO (n 25 above).


Stu Woolman 211<br />

finds that the restraint of trade provision at issue ‘strips the player of<br />

his human dignity’ and therefore constitutes an unjustifiable<br />

limitation of his freedom, under FC section 22, of trade, occupation<br />

and profession. 47 In Khosa, the Constitutional Court’s conclusion that<br />

‘the exclusion of permanent residents in need ... [from] socialsecurity<br />

programmes’ has ‘a serious impact on [their] dignity’<br />

supports a finding that the Social Assistance Act violates both the right<br />

to equality and the right to social security of permanent residents. 48<br />

In the second class of cases, dignity may be used to justify a<br />

limitation on a right. In Khumalo v Holomisa, the Constitutional Court<br />

twins the privacy and the dignity rights that ground the interest in a<br />

good reputation to turn back a freedom of expression challenge to the<br />

constitutionality of the law of defamation. 49 In De Reuck, the<br />

Constitutional Court finds that the state’s interest in protecting the<br />

dignity of all children justifies the limitation of the freedom of<br />

expression that the Films and Publications Act imposes upon the<br />

producers and the possessors of child pornography. 50 In Christian<br />

Education, the mutually reinforcing rights of religion and culture said<br />

to sanction corporal punishment in private schools were deemed to be<br />

in conflict with, and ultimately subordinate to, a constellation of<br />

rights that included dignity, equality, and freedom and security of the<br />

person. 51<br />

In the third class of cases, those cases in which the Bill of Rights<br />

does not apply directly, the Court will often speak of dignity as a value<br />

that informs the development of the common law or the<br />

interpretation of a statute. In Carmichele v Minister of Safety and<br />

Security, the Constitutional Court found that the value of dignity, as<br />

well as the values that animate freedom and security of the person,<br />

required that the duty of care imposed on the state in delictual<br />

actions be expanded so as to ensure that the state did not permit<br />

known and dangerous felons to imperil the lives of its citizens. 52<br />

Similarly, in K v Minister of Safety and Security, the Constitutional<br />

Court found that that these same values required a significant<br />

alteration in the common law understanding of vicarious liability and<br />

ensured that the state remained responsible for police officers, acting<br />

under the colour of law, who abused their authority and violated the<br />

physical integrity of the very people they are duty bound to protect. 53<br />

In Rail Commuters, the Constitutional Court interpreted the Legal<br />

47<br />

2001 1 SA 1254 (C), 2001 4 BCLR 323 (C) para 34.<br />

48 n 31 above, para 76 (my emphasis).<br />

49 2002 5 SA 401 (CC), 2002 8 BCLR 771 (CC).<br />

50<br />

n 25 above, paras 62-63.<br />

51 Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education 1999 2 SA 83 (CC); 1998<br />

12 BCLR 1449 (CC) para 51.<br />

52<br />

2001 4 SA 938 (CC), 2001 10 BCLR 995 (CC).<br />

53 2005 6 SA 419 (CC), 2005 (9) BCLR 835 (CC).


212 Chapter 12<br />

Succession of the South African Transport Act in light of the values<br />

that inspire the rights to dignity, life and freedom and security of the<br />

person and found that the Act, properly construed, required that the<br />

state actors responsible for rail travel take affirmative steps to ensure<br />

the safety of their commuters. 54<br />

5 Dignity and the politics of capability<br />

5.1 First restitution<br />

Various members of the Constitutional Court, over its first ten years,<br />

have explained the presence of dignity in our Final Constitution by<br />

reference to the denial of dignity under apartheid. As Justice O’Regan<br />

writes:<br />

The Constitution asserts dignity to contradict our past in which human<br />

dignity for black South Africans was routinely and cruelly denied. It<br />

asserts it to inform the future, to invest in our democracy respect for<br />

the intrinsic worth of all human beings. 55<br />

The Constitutional Court reacts to the particular ways in which dignity<br />

was denied under apartheid (the imposition of the death penalty to<br />

blunt political opposition, the implementation of pass laws to control<br />

both the intimate and economic lives of black South Africans, the use<br />

of corporal punishment as a form of social control) by finding<br />

unconstitutional those laws that continue to re-inscribe these affronts<br />

to dignity. But as Justice O’Regan observes above, and Justice<br />

Ackermann has written here and elsewhere, the Final Constitution<br />

does not simply ask us to react to, and to reverse, past indignities. It<br />

demands that we transform our society into one that will ultimately<br />

recognise the intrinsic worth of each individual.<br />

5.2 Dignity and transformation<br />

We can trace that process of transformation in the equality<br />

jurisprudence on sexual orientation. Our courts begin slowly,<br />

dispatching laws proscribing sodomy as a violation of intimate or<br />

private space. 56 The courts go on to reject laws that impair the ability<br />

of same-sex partners to live private lives within South Africa. 57 They<br />

then abolish laws that refuse to extend ‘public’ benefits to the<br />

54 Rail Commuters Action Group & Others v Transnet LTD t/a Metrorail & Others<br />

2005 2 SA 359 (CC), 2005 4 BCLR 301 (CC).<br />

55 Dawood (n 12 above) para 35.<br />

56 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice & Others (n<br />

21 above).<br />

57 Dawood (n 12 above) and Booysen (n 39 above).


Stu Woolman 213<br />

surviving same-sex life partner of a judicial officer. 58 Until finally, the<br />

dignity of same-sex partners is understood to be as important a public<br />

matter as it is private, and the public institution of marriage sanctions<br />

heterosexual and homosexual unions alike. 59<br />

The public recognition of same-sex life partnerships as marriages<br />

takes dignity beyond the merely restitutional, and articulates an<br />

understanding of dignity that is fundamentally transformative of our<br />

politics. That <strong>this</strong> holding is transformative, and not merely reactive,<br />

can be understood through the prism of the state’s response to the<br />

various challenges mounted against anti-gay and anti-lesbian<br />

enactments. The early challenges to sodomy laws and immigration<br />

laws met with little resistance. However, as the challenges to the law<br />

required public recognition of the equality of gays and lesbians — as<br />

opposed to mere sufferance of the homosexuals in our midst — the<br />

state’s resistance stiffened. In Satchwell II, the Constitutional Court<br />

had to take the unusual and uncomfortable step of invalidating a<br />

piece of legislation virtually identical to the legislation that it had<br />

found unconstitutional in Satchwell I. 60 It is hard to read Parliament’s<br />

response to Satchwell I as anything but a refusal to recognise that<br />

same-sex partnerships are entitled to equal concern and equal<br />

respect. In Fourie, the state actively sought to block the recognition<br />

of same-sex unions as marriages. Again, it is hard to read the state’s<br />

response as anything other than a refusal to accord same-sex life<br />

partnerships the same public recognition as opposite-sex life<br />

partnerships. The Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court of<br />

Appeal have reached beyond mere restitutionary forms of justice to a<br />

vision of dignity that forces all South Africans to reconsider their<br />

previous understandings of marriage. The transformative power of<br />

dignity thus forces all South Africans to acknowledge publicly the<br />

variety of legitimate and valuable life partnerships within our society.<br />

5.3 Beyond negative liberty to means and capability<br />

It seems reasonable to ask, at <strong>this</strong> juncture, whether the Court’s<br />

jurisprudence on equality and sexual orientation reflects genuine<br />

transformation or the mere logical extension of the Court’s liberal<br />

commitment to state non-intervention and the actual pressures of the<br />

text. The question arises because some critics of the Court’s early<br />

dignity jurisprudence, such as Dennis Davis, suggested correctly that<br />

58<br />

59<br />

60<br />

Satchwell v President of the Republic of South Africa 2003 4 SA 266 (CC), 2004 1<br />

BCLR 1 (CC)(‘Satchwell II’); Satchwell v President of the Republic of South Africa<br />

2002 6 SA 1 (CC), 2002 9 BCLR 986 (CC)(‘Satchwell I’).<br />

See Minister of Home Affairs & Another v Fourie & Another; Lesbian and Gay<br />

Equality Project & Others v Minister of Home Affairs & Others 2006 1 SA 524<br />

(CC), 2006 3 BCLR 355 (CC).<br />

See Satchwell I (n 58 above) and Satchwell II (n 58 above). The legislation<br />

concerned the benefits to be paid to judges’ spouses.


214 Chapter 12<br />

the Constitutional Court permitted a Berlian understanding of<br />

negative liberty to slip into the Court’s equality jurisprudence<br />

through the backdoor of dignity. 61 The Ferreira Court rejected<br />

Justice Ackermann’s view that IC section 11(1) and FC section 12(1)<br />

required that ‘freedom’ and ‘security of the person’ should be read<br />

disjunctively and that IC section 11(1) and FC section 12(1) contained<br />

a robust freedom right. 62 However, in a number of cases decided<br />

shortly after Ferreira, the Court appeared to accept Justice<br />

Ackermann’s contention that there exists an inextricable link<br />

between dignity and the need for individual freedom from state<br />

intervention. In Hugo, the Court places ‘dignity ... at the heart of<br />

individual rights in a free and democratic society.’ 63 In National<br />

Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice, the Court<br />

states that ‘it is clear that the constitutional protection of dignity<br />

requires us to acknowledge the value and the worth of all individuals<br />

as members of society.’ 64 Thus, over the course of several cases and<br />

the space of a couple of years, individual freedom qua negative<br />

liberty becomes the foundation for dignity, and dignity, in turn,<br />

becomes the basis for equality.<br />

One can accept the truth of the proposition that the<br />

Constitutional Court accepted the link between dignity and the need<br />

for individual freedom from state intervention without accepting the<br />

proposition that dignity is only about the need for individual freedom<br />

from state intervention. For example, Amartya Sen ties his notion of<br />

‘development as freedom’ to the provision of a basic basket of goods<br />

— both real and figurative — that enable human beings to develop<br />

those ‘capabilities’ necessary for each individual to achieve those<br />

ends that each has reason to value. 65 Sen contends that dignity and<br />

freedom and equality, rightly understood, are meant neither to<br />

achieve definitive outcomes nor to prescribe a univocal understanding<br />

of the good. 66 What these covalent values do require is a level of<br />

61 D Davis ‘Equality: The majesty of legoland jurisprudence’ (1999) 116 South<br />

African Law Journal 398.<br />

62 Ferreira (n 20 above).<br />

63 Hugo (n 17 above) para 41.<br />

64 n 21 above, para 28.<br />

65 61<br />

See D Davis Sen (n‘Equality: 33 above); The A Sen majesty Inequality of legoland re-examined jurisprudence’ (1992). (1999) 116 South<br />

66 Sen African asks Law us Journal to take 398. account, in any theory of distributive justice, of how the<br />

62<br />

heterogeneity Ferreira (n 20 above). amongst individuals (both within societies and across societies)<br />

63<br />

shapes Hugo (n the 16 meaning above) para of primary 41. goods and incomes. For example, the meaning of a<br />

64<br />

primary n 21 above, political para good 28. like freedom of assembly will have demonstrably different<br />

65<br />

meanings See Sen (n for 33 a above); prson who A Sen is Inequality ambulatory re-examined and for a person (1992). who is not ambulatory,<br />

66<br />

but such housebound. primary goods Similarly, as income the or civil utility liberties of an into income the capability of R200 ‘to 000 choose will a have life<br />

demonstrably one has reason different to value’ value — or for in a simpler person who terms, is ambulatory the ability and to pursue for a person one’s own who<br />

is ends. not ambulatory, Sen (n 27 above) but housebound. 75. The virtue At a of minimum, Sen’s approach says Sen, is that quoting it recognises Adam Smith, (a)<br />

our the heterogeneity primary concern of capacity ought to that be providing people possess individuals by virtue with of those biology, necessities custom, or of<br />

life class; that (b) will, the in heterogeneity fact, give them of ‘“the critical ability functions to appear — from in public nourishment without shame”.’ to civic<br />

Sen participation (n 27 above) — that 73 quoting may be required A Smith The to live wealth a life of one nations has reason (1776) to RH value; Campbell and (c) &<br />

AS the Skinner heterogeneity (ed) (1976) of 469-471. capabilities That, that in just people a few will well-chosen possess words, — different sounds<br />

very combinations much like of South more African basic functions discourse — on which dignity. will, Sen in contends turn, enable that them best to<br />

measure pursue different of equality visions or freedom of the good. or dignity is the ability of individuals to convert


Stu Woolman 215<br />

material support (eg, food) and immaterial support (eg, civil liberties)<br />

that enables individuals to pursue a meaningful and comprehensive<br />

vision of the good — as they understand it. 67<br />

As recent case law suggests, the Court has moved beyond a<br />

minimalist understanding of dignity, and a negative conception of<br />

freedom, to something richer and more substantial. In Grootboom the<br />

Constitutional Court announced: ‘A society must seek to ensure that<br />

the basic necessities of life are provided to all if it is to be a society<br />

based on dignity, equality, and freedom.’ 68 In Khosa v Minister of<br />

Social Development, the Court commits the state to the provision of<br />

actual resources, social assistance, to an identifiable class of persons<br />

— permanent residents. In so doing, the Court moves well beyond<br />

dignity as negative liberty to a vision of dignity in which ‘wealthier<br />

members of the community view the minimal well-being of the poor<br />

as connected with their personal well-being and the well-being of the<br />

community as a whole.’ 69<br />

Dignity qua collective responsibility for material agency moves us<br />

towards a Sen-like capabilities model. Moreover, it does so without<br />

being susceptible to the critique of dignity qua negative liberty<br />

levelled by exponents of substantive equality. The capabilities model<br />

defines equal treatment in terms of the provision of differently<br />

situated persons with the material and immaterial means that they,<br />

in particular, require to pursue some specific vision of the good. So,<br />

for example, Sen argues that pregnant women need more nutrition<br />

than men and that any basic food program is obliged to recognise <strong>this</strong><br />

difference in a basic nutritional package. 70<br />

Dignity modelled on a Sen-like capabilities model also appears to<br />

answer the charge that a commitment to substantive autonomy reinscribes<br />

the disadvantage of those persons who find themselves in a<br />

state of injury. A capabilities model does not underscore the lack of<br />

such primary goods as income or civil liberties into the capability ‘to choose a life<br />

one has reason to value’ — or in simpler terms, the ability to pursue one’s own<br />

ends. Sen (n 33 above) 75. The virtue of Sen’s approach is that it recognises (a)<br />

the heterogeneity of capacity that people possess by virtue of biology, custom, or<br />

class; (b) the heterogeneity of critical functions — from nourishment to civic<br />

participation — that may be required to live a life one has reason to value; and (c)<br />

the heterogeneity of capabilities that people will possess — different combinations<br />

of more basic functions — which will, in turn, enable them to pursue<br />

different visions of the good.<br />

67 Sen (n 33 above) 75. See also K van Marle ‘No last word: Reflections on the<br />

imaginary domain, dignity and intrinsic worth’ (2002) 13 Stellenbosch Law Review<br />

299 306<br />

68 n 29 above, para 83.<br />

69<br />

n 25 above, para 74.<br />

70 Sen (n 33 above) 189–203.


216 Chapter 12<br />

freedom of our fellow citizens, nor call undue attention to their<br />

injury. Rather it demands that we recognise that all of us require a<br />

certain basket of goods in order to pursue our preferred way of being<br />

in the world. 71<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

I hope that I have, over the previous pages, shown that the right to<br />

dignity is neither, over-used, over-cited, over-indulged, ubiquitous or<br />

a cliché. It possesses at least five discrete denotations — but all five<br />

denotations turn around and around a basic conception of the<br />

individual as an end in herself, as of priceless worth, and as a being<br />

that may not be used merely as a means for another’s or society’s<br />

ends. It serves four distinct functions: first-order rule, second orderrule,<br />

correlative right and value. It is by taking great care to keep<br />

these definitions and uses relatively discrete and distinct, however,<br />

that the Constitutional Court has been able to build a solid body of<br />

dignity jurisprudence. Indeed, so solid, so clear is <strong>this</strong> new<br />

contribution to global constitutional law, that at least in South African<br />

courts of law, the falcon can still hear the falconer, and the centre<br />

still holds.<br />

71 See D Cornell Just cause: Freedom, identity and rights (2000); D Cornell ‘A call<br />

for a nuanced constitutional jurisprudence: Ubuntu, dignity and reconciliation’<br />

(2004) 19 South African Public Law 666; D Cornell Defending ideals (2004). See<br />

also D Cornell ‘On Dignity’ (Unpublished memorandum on file with author) (2005)<br />

(I am deeply indebted to both Professor Cornell and Justice Ackermann for the<br />

framing of dignity in Kantian terms with idealist twist.)


13 Reply<br />

The soul of dignity: A reply to Stu Woolman<br />

Justice Laurie Ackermann<br />

‘In the kingdom of ends everything has either a price or a dignity [fn<br />

Würde]. What has a price can be replaced by something else as its<br />

equivalent; what on the other hand is raised above all price and<br />

therefore admits of no equivalent has a dignity ... that which constitutes<br />

the condition under which alone something can be an end in itself has<br />

not merely a relative worth, that is, a price, but an inner worth, that is,<br />

dignity.’<br />

Immanuel Kant Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals 1<br />

1 Introduction<br />

If one believes in the idea of truth, or in approximations to the truth,<br />

the process of ‘conversation’ — which the title of <strong>this</strong> collection<br />

invites — is more likely to lead to such a desired end; but only if one<br />

upholds an essential component of conversation, namely the true<br />

‘exchange of ideas’. Moreover, if one is disposed to think that<br />

knowledge only advances through the elimination of error, then bold<br />

hypotheses are called for, which in turn invite challenge and<br />

refutation.<br />

1<br />

[AK 4:434-435] as translated in MJ Gregor (ed) Immanuel Kant: Practical<br />

philosophy (1996) 84.<br />

217


218 Chapter 13<br />

For someone, like myself, who agrees with Prof Allen Wood 2 that<br />

in our age too many ‘choose ... to apologise for the rationally<br />

indefensible’ and others ‘are caught up in the fashionable mood of<br />

irony, absurdity, and self-destruction’ because ‘they have lost<br />

confidence in the mind’s authority over human life and its power to<br />

find better ways for people to live’, and that the age therefore needs<br />

‘Kant’s sober, principled hope for a more rational, cosmopolitan<br />

future,’ I heartily endorse any attempt to explain human dignity<br />

(worth) 3 and its central position in our Constitution in terms of<br />

Kantian concepts. Kant, to my mind, musters the most powerful and<br />

convincing secular arguments in support of human dignity being a<br />

worth beyond price, and hence equal in and for all persons. I am<br />

consequently in broad and fundamental agreement with Stu<br />

Woolman’s Kantian approach to dignity under our Constitution. It is<br />

within the context of such hearty agreement that I offer some ideas<br />

in exchange, exposing these ideas themselves to critical refutation.<br />

2 Whence dignity?<br />

My first joust, offered as a playful opening to discussion, relates to<br />

Woolman’s title ‘The widening gyre of dignity.’ I would suggest that<br />

the falcon’s widening gyrations evoked by the title relates more<br />

properly to the broadening of our understanding of human worth,<br />

rather than to the nature and content of human worth itself.<br />

Whatever lofty aspirations the falcon’s soaring may invoke, and such<br />

aspirations are very important, I think we should also look downwards<br />

and inwards, in an attempt to fathom what <strong>this</strong> uniqueness of human<br />

personhood is. What is it about humans that raises them ‘above all<br />

price and therefore admits of no equivalent,’ that projects them<br />

beyond ‘merely a relative worth’ and sees them as having ‘inner<br />

worth’?<br />

I have previously offered the following tentative definition of<br />

human worth (dignity):<br />

[T]he human dignity (worth) of each and every person is the capacity for<br />

and the right to respect as a human being that arise from all those<br />

aspects of the human personality that flow from human intellectual and<br />

moral capacity; which in turn separate humans from the impersonality of<br />

nature, enables them to exercise their own judgment, to have self-<br />

2<br />

AW Wood Kant’s ethical thought (1999) xv.<br />

3 It is clear that word ‘dignity’ is used in the Constitution as meaning ‘human<br />

worth’. The Afrikaans text uses the word ‘menswaardigheid’ which means,<br />

literally, ‘human worthiness’ and is also the exact equivalent of ‘Menschenwürde’<br />

the word used in the German Basic Law. I say that it means ‘human worth’<br />

because it is obviously something quite different from ‘dignity’ in the context of<br />

social standing, rank, position or privilege. ‘Human worth’ clearly accords with<br />

the Constitutional Court’s exposition of dignity.


Reply - Justice Laurie Ackermann 219<br />

awareness and a sense of self-worth, to exercise self-determination, to<br />

shape themselves and nature, to develop their personalities and to strive<br />

for self-fulfillment in their lives. 4<br />

Looking downwards and inwards, I point to the powerful teachings in<br />

the so-called Abrahamic religions that found the dignity (and equality)<br />

of all humans on the imago dei (image of God) concept, namely, that<br />

all humans are created in the image of God, based on the creation<br />

narrative in Genesis 1: 26-27. 5 Verse 27 reads: ‘So God created<br />

humankind in his image, in the image of God he created them; male<br />

and female he created them.’ Every human being therefore has<br />

priceless worth (dignity) and for <strong>this</strong> reason is in essence equal to<br />

every other human being. These and similar theological concepts have<br />

influenced the development of closely related secular ideas<br />

concerning human dignity, and the latter’s role in giving context and<br />

meaning to the development of equality and other fundamental<br />

rights. The Dutch jurist (and theologian) Hugo de Groot (Grotius), who<br />

was himself a Christian believer, contended that fundamental<br />

principles of law and morality would have binding force etsi Deus non<br />

daretur — as if (even if) God did not exist. In his challenging work, On<br />

human worth: A Christian vindication of equality, Professor Duncan<br />

Forrester points out, with regard to these views, that:<br />

4<br />

5<br />

See LWH Ackermann ‘Equality and non-discrimination: Some analytical thoughts’<br />

(2006) 22 South African Journal on Human Rights 597 602. I have, with some<br />

additions of my own, modeled <strong>this</strong> definition closely on the widely accepted<br />

German formulation by the distinguished scholar Professor Günther Dürig in the<br />

1950’s in ‘Der Grundrechtssatz von der Menschenwürde’ (1956) 81 Archiv des<br />

öffentlichen Rechts 117125:<br />

Jeder Mensch ist Mensch kraft seines Geistes, der ihn abhet von der<br />

unpersönlichen Natur und ihn aus eigner Entscheidung dazu befähigt,<br />

seiner selbst bewußt zu werden, sich selbst zu bestimmen und sich und<br />

die Umwelt zu gestalten.<br />

(Each and every human being is a human being by virtue of his or her<br />

intellect [‘kraft seine Geistes’] which serves to separate them from the<br />

impersonality of nature and enables them to exercise their own<br />

judgment, to have self-awareness, to exercise self-determination and to<br />

shape themselves and nature. (my translation))<br />

According to JD Douglas et al (eds) The new Bible dictionary (1962) 7 Judaism,<br />

Christianity and Islam all perceive Abraham as playing a unique roll as a great<br />

prophet and recipient of the divine covenant. BM Metzger & MD Coogan (eds) The<br />

Oxford companion to the Bible (1993) 5, express the view that ‘Abraham is to be<br />

looked to as a source of unity and harmony rather than dissent among Jews,<br />

Christians and Muslims.’ For Judaism see, eg, D Polish ‘Judaism and human rights’<br />

in L Swidler (ed) Human rights in religious traditions (1982) 40; E Rackman<br />

‘Judaism and Equality’ in JR Pennock & JW Chapman (eds) Equality (being Nomos<br />

IX: Yearbook of the American Society for Political and Legal Philosophy) (1967)<br />

154; and Y Arieli ‘On the necessary and sufficient conditions for the emergence of<br />

the doctrine of the dignity of man and his rights’ in D Kretzmer & E Klein (eds)<br />

The concept of human dignity in human rights discourse (2002) 1. For Christian<br />

theology see, eg, J Moltmann On Human Dignity Douglass Meeks trans (1984) and<br />

D Forrester On human worth: A Christian vindication of equality (2001). Finally,<br />

for Islam see, eg, AE Mayer Islam and human rights: Traditions and politics<br />

(1991); AS Moussalli The Islamic quest for democracy, pluralism, and human<br />

rights (2001); and MH Kamali The dignity of man: An Islamic perspective (2002).


220 Chapter 13<br />

[t]his is not atheism, or even what has more recently been called<br />

‘methodological atheism’. It is rather the simple recognition that a<br />

common morality is necessary for people to flourish together in<br />

community, and <strong>this</strong> cannot rest any longer on the foundation of<br />

Christian theology because of the bitter religious fragmentation in<br />

Europe ... But natural law continued, according to Grotius, to rest on<br />

the existence of an objective cosmic moral order. 6<br />

Theology cannot simply be ignored in our inward search, and in<br />

tracing the history of secular ideas. At the same time, and to avoid<br />

any misunderstanding, I must explain clearly for what purposes I refer<br />

to theological concepts, in the context of a secular Constitution. I do<br />

not, in a secular argument, use them because of any higher authority<br />

I claim for them (expressly or impliedly) by reasons of their<br />

theological origin. I refer to them as sociological and historical<br />

phenomena in the course of the human race’s intellectual and ethical<br />

development. I cite them as ethical values that have featured in<br />

human self-reflection for many ages and are open to rational enquiry.<br />

In <strong>this</strong> regard I think the following passage from the last pages of<br />

John Locke’s The reasonableness of Christianity, as quoted by Roger<br />

Ruston is particularly apt:<br />

He that travels the roads now, applauds his own strength and legs that<br />

have carried him so far in such a scantling of time, and ascribes all to his<br />

own vigour, little considering how much he owes to their pains, who<br />

cleared the woods, drained the bogs, built the bridges, and made the<br />

ways passable; without which he might have toiled much with little<br />

progress. A great many things which we have been bred up in the belief<br />

of, from our cradles ... we take for unquestionable truths obvious truths,<br />

and easily demonstrable; without considering how long we might have<br />

been in doubt or ignorance of them, had revelation been silent. And<br />

many are beholden to revelation, who do not acknowledge it. It is no<br />

diminishing to revelation, that reason gives its suffrage too to the<br />

truths revelation has discovered. But it is our mistake to think that<br />

because reason confirms them to us, we had the first certain knowledge<br />

of them from thence; and in that clear evidence we now possess them. 7<br />

The Islamic scholar An-Na’im, who is concerned with the fact that<br />

large-scale human rights violations continue to occur throughout the<br />

world, considers it imperative to ‘investigate ways of resolving the<br />

present crisis and revitalise the international human rights<br />

movement,’ and is of the view that ‘culturally rooted norms stand the<br />

best chance of compliance.’ 8 He considers that the implementation<br />

of the international human right standards will improve ‘if they can<br />

6 n 5 above, 51.<br />

7 Human rights and the image of God (2004) 287 (my emphasis).<br />

8<br />

‘Religious minorities under Islamic law and the limits of cultural relativism’<br />

(1987) 9 Human Rights Quarterly 1 2-3.


Reply - Justice Laurie Ackermann 221<br />

be shown to be the natural and legitimate evolution of the cultural<br />

tradition of the particular community.’ Although cultural norms have<br />

complex origins, An-Na’im argues that ‘the religious factor seems to<br />

be a major formative force.’ 9<br />

John Rawls, in A theory of justice, develops a concept of<br />

‘overlapping consensus’ which, although expressed in the context of<br />

civil disobedience, is of general import and relevant to the use of<br />

theological ethics:<br />

In [certain previous] remarks I have assumed that in a nearly just society<br />

there is a public acceptance of the same principles of justice.<br />

Fortunately <strong>this</strong> assumption is stronger than is necessary. There can, in<br />

fact, be considerable difference in citizens’ conception of justice<br />

provided that these conceptions lead to similar political judgments. All<br />

<strong>this</strong> is possible, since different premises can yield the same conclusion.<br />

In <strong>this</strong> case there exists what we may refer to as overlapping rather then<br />

strict consensus. 10<br />

This idea is discussed more fully by Rawls in Political liberalism, 11<br />

where he places the following gloss on the notion of an ‘overlapping<br />

consensus’:<br />

All those who affirm the political conception start from within their own<br />

comprehensive view and draw on the religious, philosophical, and moral<br />

grounds it provides. The fact that people affirm the same political<br />

conception on these grounds does not make their affirming it less<br />

religious, philosophical, or moral, as the case may be, since the grounds<br />

sincerely held determine the nature of their affirmation. 12<br />

9<br />

n 8 above, 9. Lest I unwittingly do an injustice to An-Na’im, I must point out that<br />

the whole thrust of his article, see eg pp. 17-18, is to the effect that:<br />

(1) The status of non-Muslim religious minorities under Shari’ah is not<br />

consistent with current universal human rights. (2) The current state of<br />

affairs cannot be justified under claims of Islamic cultural relativism.<br />

(3) It is not only possible, but also imperative, that the status of non-<br />

Muslims under Shari’ah be reformed from within the fundamental sources<br />

of Islam, namely the Qu’rn and Sunnah. Such reform would be at once<br />

both Islamic and fully consistent with universal human rights standards.<br />

Very broadly stated his argument (9-11) is that the Shari’ah is ‘not the totality of<br />

the word of God.’ According to Muslim belief, ‘the Qu’rn is the literal and final<br />

word of God while Sunnah is the record of what the Prophet is believed to have<br />

said.’ While conceding (17) that not all aspects of Shari’ah are open to<br />

restatement and reinterpretation, he does contend (10) that Shari’ah is no more<br />

than the ‘understanding of the early Muslims of the sources of Islam’ influenced<br />

by their historical context and ‘experience and perception of the world’. It<br />

developed under the conditions and influenced by the problems of an Islamic<br />

state in seventh century Arabia. Since these problems have altered and the<br />

historical answers are no longer valid, An-Na’im argues (11) that ‘new answers<br />

must be developed out of the Qu’rn and Sunnah ... [For] the Islamic Shari’ah for<br />

today.’<br />

10 (1973) 387.<br />

11<br />

(1993) 133-172.<br />

12 n 11 above, 147.


222 Chapter 13<br />

It is generally uncontested that one of the pressing goals in our<br />

young democracy is to strengthen the commitment by all South<br />

Africans to constitutionalism generally, but also to the rights and<br />

values guaranteed by the Constitution. I sense, however, that there<br />

are, for example, mono-theists who feel uncomfortable with<br />

committing themselves personally to a secular Constitution whose<br />

rights and values are expressed in secular form. Such discomfort is not<br />

limited to conservatives or fundamentalist mono-theists, but is shared<br />

by those who understand and accept the reasons why a Constitution<br />

must be secular. It is for such persons important to realise that the<br />

secular form of the Constitution and its values, are not in conflict with<br />

theological ethics, at least not the most fundamental values of the<br />

Constitution such as, for example, priceless and equal human worth.<br />

For them, the concept and the legitimacy of an overlapping<br />

consensus, — which honours a personal ‘correct conclusion’, despite<br />

the fact that such a conclusion is reached by a different line of<br />

argument — may be helpful. By referring specifically to mono-theists<br />

I do not mean to exclude other deists or those confessing non-deistic<br />

faiths. My omission is due entirely to ignorance on my part. I certainly<br />

do not exclude the possibility that such other faiths have their own<br />

justification for the constitutional values of human worth and<br />

equality.<br />

In its preamble, the American Declaration of Independence of<br />

1776 unselfconsciously proclaims that:<br />

We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal,<br />

and that they are endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable<br />

rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the Pursuit of Happiness.<br />

As Duncan Forrester points out, the Declaration at <strong>this</strong> point is<br />

‘saturated with theological language’ and suggests that the ‘ultimate<br />

and only ground for equality ... lies in the will of the creator God.’ 13<br />

Jeremy Waldron argues that in a number of ways the Christian<br />

conception out of which modern liberalism originated remains richer<br />

and deeper than their secular offspring’ and that ‘[w]e might<br />

reasonably expect to find further clues to a rich and adequate<br />

conception of persons, equality, justice, and rights in what is<br />

currently made of the Christian-centred tradition by those who<br />

remain centred in Christ.’ 14<br />

It is in the context of Rawls’ concept of the ‘overlapping<br />

consensus’ that Kant’s ethical thought again plays an important role.<br />

13<br />

n 5 above, 56.<br />

14 ‘Religious Contributions in Public deliberation’ (1993) 30 San Diego Law Review 817<br />

846-7. See also J Waldron God, Locke and equality: Christian foundations in<br />

Locke’s political thought (2002) (an in-depth treatment of the Christian<br />

foundations in John Locke’s political thought.)


Reply - Justice Laurie Ackermann 223<br />

As Bernard Williams has pointed out: ‘[t]he ground of respect owed to<br />

each man thus emerges in the Kantian theory as a kind of secular<br />

analogue of the Christian conception of the respect owed to all men<br />

as equally children of God.’ 15<br />

Some might say that <strong>this</strong> philosophical and theological digging<br />

down into the meaning of constitutional human dignity (worth) is an<br />

intellectual irrelevance, that has nothing to contribute to the<br />

‘practical’ ‘realities’ of daily life and the running of a modern state.<br />

I would argue that such a view is gravely misconceived. After the<br />

tragedies of World War II, the 1948 Universal Declaration of Human<br />

Rights placed inherent human dignity (worth), together with equality<br />

and freedom at the heart of practical measures to prevent a<br />

repetition of the barbaric acts of the recent past that ‘have outraged<br />

the conscience of mankind’. To prevent rebellion against tyranny and<br />

oppression, the Preamble to the Universal Declaration regards it as<br />

essential that human rights ‘be protected by the rule of law.’ The<br />

Declaration also proclaims that ‘every individual and every organ of<br />

society ... shall strive by teaching and education to promote respect<br />

for [human rights and freedoms] and by progressive measures ... to<br />

secure their universal and effective recognition and observance.’ At<br />

the heart of Article 1 is the categorical statement that all human<br />

beings are ‘born free and equal in dignity and rights’ and are<br />

‘endowed with reason and conscience.’ Yet, in the nearly 60 years<br />

since the Declaration, barbaric acts, which continue to outrage the<br />

conscience of humankind, have continued to occur with painful<br />

regularity. The continued exploration, at the deepest level, of the<br />

meaning and implications of human dignity (worth) continues to be an<br />

imperative and not a luxury. I am not certain that material progress<br />

will be made until we realise that in the act of infringing the dignity<br />

of others, we are rejecting and harming our own human worth.<br />

Having paraded above my own definition of human dignity<br />

(worth), let me readily concede that it is probably not possible to<br />

capture the full meaning of human worth in so simple a definition. We<br />

still have much to learn about it, and its delineations will no doubt be<br />

developed (prudently) on a case by case basis by our courts. Even the<br />

German Federal Constitutional Court (‘BVerfG’) has not attempted to<br />

give a comprehensive definition of the personality rights, which form<br />

an integral part of the German concept of human dignity<br />

(‘Menschenwürde’) as it does in South Africa. Instead it has followed<br />

15<br />

B Williams ‘The idea of equality’ in P Laslett & WG Runciman (eds) Philosophy,<br />

politics and society (1967) 116.


224 Chapter 13<br />

a case-by-case approach, reminiscent of the empirical Anglo-Saxon<br />

tradition, in the light of current or developing social conditions. 16<br />

I feel some disquiet with Woolman’s taxonomic approach to<br />

human worth and his reference to five primary ‘definitions’ of dignity<br />

allegedly given by the Constitutional Court; and I would prefer to<br />

refer to ‘aspects’ of dignity, or ‘dimensions’ of dignity as Woolman<br />

himself seems later to suggest. These aspects of human worth should<br />

also not be regarded as a closed list, but open to future expansion. It<br />

is likely, in my view, that considerable time will still pass before we<br />

have ‘captured’ a complete view of what human worth means. I<br />

believe that Woolman is mistaken when he relays all these five<br />

aspects back to ‘our status as rational moral agents capable of selfactualisation<br />

and self-governance’. While freedom is indispensable<br />

for dignity, it does not encapsulate it, if we are talking about freedom<br />

and moral autonomy in a constitutional context, as I believe we are.<br />

There are other components such as self-awareness and a sense of<br />

self-worth that are important aspects of human worth itself. I do not<br />

pretend to be a Kantian scholar myself, but I am not sure that<br />

contemporary Kantian scholars would agree that there is only one<br />

categorical imperative, as opposed to three formulas. 17<br />

3 Dignity as ‘attribute’ in equality<br />

I also find myself constrained to disagree with Woolman’s suggestion<br />

that one of the ‘definitions’ or even ‘attributes’ of dignity is that of<br />

‘equal concern and equal respect.’ The latter lies at the heart of the<br />

equality clause. It is true that dignity (human worth) is the attribute<br />

in respect whereof all humans are equal. 18 But it is the unequal<br />

treatment of persons with respect to their human dignity that<br />

infringes equality, according to the system of our Constitution. One<br />

should also remind oneself that mere equal treatment does not<br />

guarantee constitutional conformity; because treatment that is equal<br />

may infringe the dignity of all concerned, and <strong>this</strong> too would be<br />

inconsistent with the Constitution. I also believe Woolman to be<br />

mistaken when he suggests that the Constitutional Court has<br />

constructed two ‘different’ tests in terms of the right to equality.<br />

There is only one test, but it deals with different parts of FC section<br />

9. The first part of the same test deals with subsection (1), and might<br />

be termed the prohibition against arbitrariness. The other test deals<br />

16 See the Eppler case 54 BVerfGE 148 153 (1980), and also DP Kommers The<br />

constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany 2 ed (1997) 320-<br />

323 and EJ Eberle Dignity and liberty: Constitutional visions in Germany and the<br />

United States (2002) 62f.<br />

17 See, eg, Wood (n 2 above) 17-18.<br />

18<br />

For a full discussion of what is meant by attribute in <strong>this</strong> context see Ackermann<br />

(n 4 above) particularly 597 and 608-612.


Reply - Justice Laurie Ackermann 225<br />

with unfair discrimination under section 9(3). The fact that there is<br />

only one test emerges clearly, I suggest, from the Constitutional<br />

Court’s first two judgments on equality, 19 and from the subsequent<br />

tabulation of <strong>this</strong> test in Harksen v Lane. 20 Although the formulation<br />

was in regard to section 8 of the Interim Constitution, it is equally<br />

applicable to section 9 of the Final Constitution:<br />

At the costs of repetition, it may be as well to tabulate the stages of<br />

enquiry which become necessary where an attack is made on a provision<br />

in reliance on section 8 of the Interim Constitution. They are:<br />

(a) Does the provision differentiate between people or categories of<br />

people? If so, does the differentiation bear a rational connection to a<br />

legitimate government purpose? If it does not then there is violation of<br />

section 8(1). Even if it does bear a rational connection, it might<br />

nevertheless amount to discrimination.<br />

(b) Does the differentiation amount to unfair discrimination? This<br />

requires a two stage analysis:<br />

(i) Firstly, does the differentiation amount to ‘discrimination’? If it is<br />

on a specified ground, then discrimination will have been<br />

established. If it is not on a specified ground, then whether or not<br />

there is discrimination will depend upon whether, objectively, the<br />

ground is based on attributes and characteristics which have the<br />

potential to impair the fundamental human dignity of persons as<br />

human beings or to affect them adversely in a comparably serious<br />

manner.<br />

(ii) If the differentiation amounts to ‘discrimination’, does it amount<br />

to ‘unfair discrimination’? If it has been found to have been on a<br />

specified ground, then unfairness will be presumed. If on an<br />

unspecified ground, unfairness will have to be established by the<br />

complainant. The test of unfairness focuses primarily on the impact<br />

of the discrimination on the complainant and others in his or her<br />

situation.<br />

If, at the end of <strong>this</strong> stage of the enquiry, the differentiation is found not<br />

to be unfair, then there will be no violation of section 8(2).<br />

(c) If the discrimination is found to be unfair then a determination will<br />

have to be made as to whether the provision can be justified under the<br />

limitations clause (section 33 of the Interim Constitution). 21<br />

I also find myself in disagreement with Woolman’s proposition that<br />

dignity, properly understood, ‘secures the space for selfactualisation.’<br />

It is freedom, and not dignity, that secures <strong>this</strong> space,<br />

19<br />

Prinsloo v Van Der Linde & Another 1997 3 SA 1012 (CC), 1997 6 BCLR 759 (CC);<br />

and President of the Republic of South Africa & Another v Hugo 1997 4 SA 1 (CC),<br />

1997 6 BCLR 708 (CC). Prinsloo was argued some time prior to Hugo. The two<br />

judgments were delivered on the same day. The two judgments should therefore<br />

be viewed as a simultaneous precedent and be read as one, in the same way as<br />

one would read a single judgment disposing of two cases.<br />

20<br />

Harksen v Lane NO & Others 1998 1 SA 300 (CC), 1997 11 BCLR 1489 (CC).<br />

21 n 20 above, para 53.


226 Chapter 13<br />

but freedom to enable self-actualisation is of course essential for<br />

human dignity. Art 2 of the German Basic Law, deals with personal<br />

freedoms and Art 2(1) specifically with the free development of<br />

everyone’s personality (‘die freie Entfaltung seiner Persönlichkeit’).<br />

Article 2(1) is universally regarded as relating back also to Art 1 and<br />

as establishing, with Art 1, a general personality right. 22 However,<br />

Woolman’s statement in footnote 22 that ‘dignity qua self-governance<br />

is, in fact, where the Constitutional Court falters most conspicuously’<br />

seems to me a broad criticism with shaky support. One would have<br />

thought that the Court’s judgments on the human worth (dignity)<br />

rights of gays and lesbians — which he later correctly identifies as one<br />

of the most transformative areas of the Court’s jurisprudence — point<br />

firmly in the opposite direction. Woolman’s criticism, for example, of<br />

Prince in <strong>this</strong> regard simply ignores the crucial fact that the<br />

constitutional validity of South Africa’s drug legislation (which inter<br />

alia proscribes the possession and use of dagga, the substance whose<br />

use was in issue in the case) was not generally challenged by the<br />

complainant. 23 The Court was accordingly obliged to have regard to<br />

the disastrous effect that permitting the religious use of dagga (which<br />

religious use was, on the complainant’s own case, virtually unlimited<br />

as to time and place) would have on the enforcement of the<br />

legislation in question.<br />

4 Collective dignity?<br />

The way that Woolman presents the idea of ‘collective responsibility<br />

for the material conditions for agency’ is a welcome addition to our<br />

local debate on dignity and equality, as is his reference to Amartya<br />

Sen’s idea of capability equality. 24 I would also readily agree that<br />

when the state harms the dignity of one person <strong>this</strong>, in a certain<br />

manner of speaking, diminishes the dignity of us all. But the ‘us’ in<br />

<strong>this</strong> proposition refers to the totality of our individual dignities. It is,<br />

however, a far cry from <strong>this</strong> understanding to extrapolate from the<br />

Court’s jurisprudence postulate a ‘collective notion of dignity.’<br />

(Woolman does, it must be noted, acknowledge that that ‘notion’<br />

allegedly implicit in the Court’s judgments refers not to some<br />

romantic idea of the ‘volk’, but to a commitment to providing all<br />

individuals with the material means necessary to create a Kantian<br />

‘kingdom of ends’.) There are serious potential objections and<br />

dangers to attributing dignity to a group which does not otherwise<br />

enjoy legal personality, as there are fundamental objections and<br />

22 See, eg, I von Münch P Kunig (eds) Grundgesetz-Kommentar 4 ed (1992) vol 1, Art 2<br />

23<br />

Rn 30.<br />

Prince v President, Cape Law Society & Others 2002 2 SA 794 (CC), 2002 3 BCLR<br />

24<br />

231 (CC).<br />

In <strong>this</strong> regard, see also S Cowen ‘Can “dignity” guide South Africa’s Equality<br />

Jurisprudence’ (2001) 17 South African Journal on Human Rights 34.


Reply - Justice Laurie Ackermann 227<br />

dangers to attributing rights to such a group. Apart from the<br />

conceptual legal problem of attributing rights generally, and dignity<br />

in particular, to an unincorporated group, it can have serious political<br />

consequences. Just as the identity and individual responsibility of the<br />

individual can be sucked up into the identity of the nation or some<br />

other collective, and thereby destroyed, as was the case with German<br />

fascism and Russian communism, so too the idea of the dignity of the<br />

collective could become destructive of individual dignity. I am not<br />

suggesting that <strong>this</strong> is Woolman’s aim or strategy; in fact I am sure<br />

that his purpose is quite the opposite. I merely point to the<br />

conceptual and con-sequential difficulties and dangers. Nor do I, for<br />

one moment, see individuals and their dignity as existing in isolation<br />

from society. It is vitally important that the associational individual<br />

rights of individuals be recognised and protected as, inter alia, FC<br />

sections 17-19 and 29-31 do, because without such recognition and<br />

protection it is not possible for humans to develop their individual<br />

personalities fully. Nor do I deny the obligation of society generally,<br />

whether <strong>this</strong> be a legal, ethical or moral one, to facilitate the<br />

capabilities of the poor and the weak. But <strong>this</strong> is all a far cry from<br />

attributing dignity (human worth) to an unincorporated group or<br />

collective, or to a nation.<br />

5 Kelsen rather than Hart<br />

I must furthermore join issue with Woolman’s presentation of dignity<br />

as something that ‘operates as a first order rule, a second order rule,<br />

a correlative right, a value and a Grundnorm.’ Woolman is using, in<br />

my view mistakenly, the language and concepts of HLA Hart where our<br />

Constitution cries out for a Kelsenian approach. In <strong>this</strong> regard I would<br />

invoke the support of Ronald Dworkin who rejects such an approach<br />

as:<br />

a taxonomic concept of law: it supposes that any political community<br />

that has law in the sociological sense also has a collection of discrete<br />

rules and other kinds of standards that are legal standards as opposed to<br />

moral or customary or some other kinds of standards. Legal philosophers<br />

use <strong>this</strong> taxonomic concept when they ask whether certain moral<br />

principles are also principles of law. The idea of law as a set of discrete<br />

standards, which we might in principle individuate and count, seems to<br />

me a scholastic fiction. 25<br />

What occurred in 1994, and was continued in 1996, was a revolution<br />

in the fully substantive sense that Kelsen uses, but it was not a<br />

revolution in the procedural sense, because there was ‘no discon-<br />

25 Justice in robes (2006) 4.


228 Chapter 13<br />

tinuous legal fracture with the old legal order.’ 26 The Final<br />

Constitution established itself as a grundnorm in the very fullest<br />

continental sense of the word. All law, whether it be common law or<br />

statute law, depends on the Constitution and is derived from the<br />

Constitution; it has no life apart from the Constitution. This was<br />

expressly articulated by a unanimous Constitutional Court in the<br />

Pharmaceutical case:<br />

I cannot accept <strong>this</strong> contention which treats the common law as a body<br />

of law separate and distinct from the Constitution. ... There is only one<br />

system of law. It is shaped by the Constitution which is the supreme law,<br />

and all law, including the common law, derives its force from the<br />

Constitution and is subject to constitutional control. 27<br />

It was later confirmed, also by a unanimous Court, per O’Regan J in<br />

Bato Star:<br />

There are not two systems of law regulating administrative action — the<br />

common law and the Constitution — but only one system of law grounded<br />

in the Constitution. ... The grundnorm of administrative law is now to be<br />

found in the first place not in the doctrine of ultra vires, nor in the<br />

doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty, nor in the common law itself, but<br />

in the principles of our Constitution. The common law informs the<br />

provisions of PAJA and the Constitution, and derives its force from the<br />

latter. 28<br />

Conflicts or tensions between positive law and non-positive law no<br />

longer exist in South Africa and debates about them have become<br />

arcane. It is in my view sufficient to refer to ‘dignity’ as a<br />

constitutional categorical imperative, 29 as a right, and as a value<br />

which, inter alia, informs other rights (such as equality and nondiscrimination)<br />

and helps resolve tensions between rights. 30 I do not<br />

believe that anything more was intended by O’Regan J in the passage<br />

from Dawood quoted by Woolman. 31 I would emphasise that my<br />

challenge to Woolman’s use of positivist language and concepts is not<br />

simply a semantic one. The language employed by Hart has acquired<br />

a well-settled meaning in a particular context. The danger of using<br />

26<br />

Ackermann ‘The legal nature of the South African constitutional revolution’<br />

(2004) 4 New Zealand Law Review 633 645-6; H Kelsen General theory of law and<br />

state trans A Wedberg (1945) 117; Makanete v Lekhanya [1993] LRC 13 (Les CA)<br />

38g-39h, and the authorities cited therein.<br />

27 Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of SA in re: the Ex Parte Application<br />

of the President of the RSA & Others 2000 2 SA 674 (CC), 2000 3 BCLR 241 (CC)<br />

para 44 (my emphasis).<br />

28 Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v The Minister of Environmental Affairs and Tourism &<br />

Others 2004 4 SA 490 (CC), 2004 7 BCLR 687 (CC) para 22.<br />

29<br />

Because sec 10 postulates that ‘[e]veryone has inherent dignity’ (my emphasis).<br />

30 Such as will occur with the horizontal operation of the Bill of Rights under secs<br />

8(2), 8(3) and 9(4) of the Constitution.<br />

31<br />

Dawood & Another v Minister of Home Affairs & Others 2000 3 SA 436 (CC), 2000<br />

8 BCLR 837 (CC) para 35.


Reply - Justice Laurie Ackermann 229<br />

positivist language and concepts in our context lies in the fact that the<br />

assumptions and context underlying such expressions willy-nilly follow<br />

their grammatical use, and are inconsistent with the fundamental<br />

grundnorm nature of our Constitution.<br />

Tony Honoré correctly points out that the law, even in the time of<br />

Ulpian, was — in a broad sense — a philosophical discipline. 32 The<br />

purpose, nature, and structure of our Constitution — quite apart from<br />

the broad formulation of rights (and values) such as, for example,<br />

dignity, equality, and freedom — has greatly strengthened <strong>this</strong> view.<br />

Nevertheless we must all, I believe, heed Honoré’s accompanying<br />

warning 33 that ‘[i]t is a mistake to attribute to a lawyer a system of<br />

philosophy rather than a set of values.’ I make <strong>this</strong> comment with full<br />

awareness of the following holding in Carmichele:<br />

Our Constitution is not merely a formal document regulating public<br />

power. It also embodies, like the German Constitution, an objective,<br />

normative value system. As was stated by the German Federal<br />

Constitutional Court:<br />

‘The jurisprudence of the Federal Constitutional Court is<br />

consistently to the effect that the basic right norms contain not only<br />

defensive subjective rights for the individual but embody at the<br />

same time an objective value system which, as a fundamental<br />

constitutional value for all areas of the law, acts as a guiding<br />

principle and stimulus for the legislature, executive and judiciary.’<br />

The same is true of our Constitution. The influence of the fundamental<br />

constitutional values on the common law is mandated by section 39(2) of<br />

the Constitution. It is within the matrix of <strong>this</strong> objective normative value<br />

system that the common law must be developed. 34<br />

What has to be appreciated is that the purpose and scope of the<br />

values within <strong>this</strong> ‘normative value system’ has in the first place to be<br />

found within the Constitution itself. Of course one cannot understand<br />

these values properly without the help of appropriate philosophical<br />

ideas or values, but <strong>this</strong> must take place from within the Constitution<br />

outwards, and not the other way around. 35 In passing, may I say that<br />

on occasion one gets the impression that some lawyers — seemingly<br />

taken by surprise by what they see as the unacceptably radical nature<br />

of the development of the common law as enunciated in the<br />

paragraph from Carmichele quoted above — fail to read the next<br />

32 Ulpian: Pioneer of human rights 2 ed (2002) 78-80.<br />

33 As above.<br />

34<br />

Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security & Another 2001 4 SA 938 (CC), 2001<br />

10 BCLR 995 (CC) para 54.<br />

35 See the cautionary remarks in Dodo v The State 2001 3 SA 382 (CC), 2001 5 BCLR<br />

423 (CC) para 17, against the importation of ‘abstract theories of separation of<br />

powers’ into our Constitution.


230 Chapter 13<br />

paragraph. 36 This stresses the importance of expert knowledge of the<br />

common law, and respect for the common law’s own paradigm, when<br />

applying section 39(2).<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

Despite my disagreements with certain aspects of Woolman’s<br />

approach, I can only applaud the depth and the breadth of his<br />

endeavours and confirm from my perspective that he has clearly<br />

demonstrated what he asserts in his conclusion: namely, that ‘the<br />

right to dignity is neither over-used, over-cited, over-indulged,<br />

ubiquitous or a cliché.’ It is distressing that even so distinguished an<br />

Anglo-Saxon constitutional scholar as Prof Peter Hogg is sceptical<br />

about the concept and the use of dignity. 37 One may well pose the<br />

rhetorical question whether dignity is any more ‘vague and<br />

unpredictable in its application’ than the concept of the ‘reasonable<br />

person’ (whether in its continental guise of the ‘bonus paterfamilias’<br />

or in its Anglo-Saxon garb of ‘the man on the Clapham omnibus.’) The<br />

concept of ‘Menschenwürde’ (human worth) stands at the very core<br />

of the German Basic Law and over the past nearly sixty years the<br />

German Federal Constitutional Court has developed a body of<br />

jurisprudence on human dignity that can, I believe, stand up to the<br />

most rigorous critical appraisal. South Africa ignores <strong>this</strong><br />

jurisprudence at its peril.<br />

36<br />

n 34 above, para 55 reads:<br />

This requires not only a proper appreciation of the Constitution and its<br />

objective, normative value system, but also a proper understanding of<br />

the common law. We have previously cautioned against overzealous<br />

judicial reform. The proper development of the common law under<br />

section 39(2) requires close and sensitive interaction between, on the one<br />

hand, the High Courts and the Supreme Court of Appeal which have<br />

particular expertise and experience in <strong>this</strong> area of the law and, on the<br />

other hand, <strong>this</strong> Court. Not only must the common law be developed in a<br />

way which meets the needs of section 39(2) objectives, but it must be<br />

done in a way most appropriate for the development of the common law<br />

within its own paradigm.<br />

37 See Constitutional Law of Canada 3 ed, Loose-leaf (1992) § 52.7(b). Hogg<br />

criticises the judgment of the Canadian Supreme Court in Law v Minister of<br />

Human Resources Development [1999] 170 DLR (4th) 1, for its use of dignity as<br />

comparator in establishing discrimination, in the following terms:<br />

The element of human dignity that has now been injected into the s 15<br />

jurisprudence is, in my view, vague, confusing and burdensome to<br />

equality claimants. Although various ‘contextual factors’ were listed in<br />

Law to assist in the task of determining whether a distinction impairs<br />

human dignity, the factors are not very helpful and the concept of human<br />

dignity is inherently vague and unpredictable in its application.


14<br />

TOWARDS A<br />

SUBSTANTIVE RIGHT<br />

TO EQUALITY<br />

Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt<br />

1 Introduction<br />

This paper examines the development of the Constitutional Court’s<br />

equality jurisprudence over the last decade — a fascinating journey<br />

that has established South Africa as a leading jurisdiction in <strong>this</strong><br />

domain. The first cases adumbrated a detailed equality test that<br />

reflects a mature approach to <strong>this</strong> complex right. A large number of<br />

cases have reached the Court: most rationality review challenges<br />

under FC section 9(1) have failed; and most unfair discrimination<br />

challenges under FC section 9(3) have succeeded.<br />

As more and more disadvantaged claimants and groups are<br />

reaching court, FC section 9(3)’s value-based fairness analysis is<br />

becoming more historically and contextually sophisticated. There are,<br />

of course, some notable exceptions. This chapter will focus on the<br />

following key areas of equality jurisprudence: the role of<br />

constitutional values in interpreting the equality right; an evaluation<br />

of the unfair discrimination jurisprudence; and the nature and<br />

relationship of the different components of the equality right, as well<br />

as the limitations clause.<br />

231


232 Chapter 14<br />

2 Values and the equality right<br />

2.1 Equality as substantive equality<br />

Race, gender, class and many other forms of inequality structure<br />

access to basic needs and material resources in South Africa and result<br />

in: limited opportunities and economic marginalisation; social<br />

exclusion, stigmatisation and stereotyping; vulnerability to physical<br />

and psychological violence; and political vulnerability. The causes of<br />

inequality are manifold and usually deeply entrenched in social and<br />

economic structures, systems and institutions. Inequalities often arise<br />

out of group-based disparities and relationships of privilege and<br />

subordination.<br />

Addressing these inequalities is an important part of the<br />

constitutional project of transformation. 1 To do so using law requires<br />

both a strong concept of equality and an idea of law that does not<br />

preserve the status quo. For many in academia and the Constitutional<br />

Court, <strong>this</strong> conception is captured in the idea of substantive equality.<br />

In a 2006 address at Stellenbosch University, Chief Justice Langa<br />

identified substantive equality as one of the key measures of<br />

transformation in our society. Here he was referring to the<br />

aspirational value of substantive equality: ‘a social and economic<br />

revolution in which all enjoy equal access to the resources and<br />

amenities of life, and are able to develop to their full human<br />

potential’. 2 This vision requires the dismantling of systemic<br />

inequalities, the eradication of poverty and disadvantage (economic<br />

equality) and the affirmation of human identity and capabilities<br />

1 See K Klare ‘Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 146. The idea of transformative<br />

constitutionalism has characterised many writings on equality. See, eg, C Albertyn<br />

& B Goldblatt ‘Facing the challenge of transformation: Difficulties in the<br />

development of an indigenous jurisprudence of equality’ (1998) 14 South African<br />

Journal on Human Rights 248; S Liebenberg & M O’Sullivan ‘South Africa’s new<br />

equality legislation: A tool for advancing women’s socio-economic equality?’ in S<br />

Jagwanth & E Kalula (eds) Equality Law: Reflections from South Africa and<br />

elsewhere (2001) 70; P de Vos ‘Grootboom, The right of access to housing and<br />

substantive equality as contextual fairness’ (2001) 17 South African Journal on<br />

Human Rights 258; A van der Walt ‘A South African reading of Frank Michelman’s<br />

theory of justice’ in H Botha et al (eds) Rights and democracy in a transformative<br />

constitution (2003); S Jagwanth ‘Expanding equality’ in C Murray & M O’Sullivan<br />

(eds) Advancing women’s rights (2005) 131; S Jagwanth & C Murray ‘No nation can<br />

be free when one half of it is enslaved: Constitutional equality for women in<br />

South Africa’ in B Baines & R Rubio-Marin (eds) The gender of constitutional<br />

jurisprudence (2005) 230. See also P Langa ‘Transformative constitutionalism’<br />

(2006) 17 Stellenbosch Law Review 351.<br />

2 Langa (n 1 above) 352-353, citing Albertyn & Goldblatt (n 1 above).


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 233<br />

(social equality). It confirms a strong relationship between<br />

substantive equality and the achievement of socio-economic rights. 3<br />

The value of substantive equality does not provide a definitive<br />

answer to the question, ‘equality of what?’ However, it does suggest<br />

that the constitutional answer is, at least, a social democratic vision<br />

that entails equality of opportunities and outcomes, including the<br />

idea of redistribution (of power and resources) and the remedying of<br />

material disadvantage. Here the aspirational value of achieving<br />

equality is capable of an expansive meaning: It is largely unencumbered<br />

by more practical considerations of the separation of<br />

powers and institutional competence. However, constitutional rights,<br />

as legal entitlements, are enforced through the courts and it is in FC<br />

section 9, discussed below, that the idea of substantive equality is<br />

captured in law.<br />

2.2 The values underlying the equality right<br />

As with any other right, the equality right should be interpreted in the<br />

light of underlying constitutional values, as well as the interests —<br />

that that right is meant to protect. This interrogation of purpose and<br />

values provides the equality right with its substantive content, and<br />

provides an answer to the question: ‘equality of what?’ The judicial<br />

determination of values and purpose thus involves choices about<br />

whom or what the right can and should protect. In the equality right,<br />

<strong>this</strong> determination mostly takes place in terms of an assessment of<br />

fairness. In <strong>this</strong> assessment, dignity has been the dominant and<br />

determinative value.<br />

2.2.1 Dignity<br />

The Constitutional Court emphasised the relationship between<br />

equality and the value of dignity early in its jurisprudential<br />

development of the right. In President of the Republic of South Africa<br />

v Hugo Goldstone J said:<br />

At the heart of the prohibition of unfair discrimination lies a recognition<br />

that the purpose of our new constitutional and democratic order is the<br />

establishment of a society in which all human beings will be accorded<br />

equal dignity and respect regardless of their membership of particular<br />

groups. The achievement of such a society in the context of our deeply<br />

3 For a discussion on the relationship between equality and socio-economic rights<br />

see B Goldblatt & S Liebenberg ‘Achieving substantive equality in South Africa:<br />

The relationship between equality and socio-economic rights’ (2007) 23 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 335.


234 Chapter 14<br />

inegalitarian past will not be easy, but that that is the goal of the<br />

Constitution should not be forgotten or overlooked. 4<br />

The idea of dignity as meaning equal moral worth — the right to be<br />

treated with equal concern and respect — derives from the Kantian<br />

notion of the equal moral worth of all human beings. 5 Here dignity is<br />

closely related to ideas of equality. Amaryta Sen admits that a<br />

common feature of being egalitarian ‘in some significant way relates<br />

to the need to have equal concern, at some level, for all persons<br />

involved’. 6 However, equal concern is not necessarily related to our<br />

conception of substantive equality. ‘Equal concern and respect’ based<br />

on ‘equal moral worth’ is a fairly abstract concept that requires<br />

greater content in order for persons and institutions to determine<br />

when a failure to equally recognise people’s moral worth contravenes<br />

the equality right.<br />

In both South African and Canadian jurisprudence, the use of<br />

‘dignity’ in equality jurisprudence has been criticised for its<br />

indeterminism 7 and for its potential to narrow the right. 8 The narrow<br />

definition of dignity in Harksen v Lane 9 — which turned on the way the<br />

applicant felt about the impugned law (did she feel less worthy of<br />

respect?) — generated concerns that the use of dignity might reinforce<br />

an individualised and abstract conception of equality divorced from<br />

actual social and economic disadvantage and the systemic nature of<br />

inequality. We would suggest that additional content be given to the<br />

value of equality in order to address structural disadvantage and<br />

inequalities. 10 That said many other legal scholars have argued that<br />

dignity can, and should, be interpreted differently to deal with<br />

systemic inequality. 11<br />

4 President of the Republic of South Africa & Another v Hugo 1997 4 SA 1 (CC),<br />

1997 6 BCLR 708 (CC) para 41.<br />

5 For an account of how Kant’s variations on the categorical imperative that inform<br />

both our dignity and our equality jurisprudence, see S Woolman ‘Dignity’ in<br />

S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS,<br />

2006) § 36.2.<br />

6 A Sen Inequality re-examined (2007).<br />

7<br />

Dennis Davis has argued that the indeterminate meaning of dignity meant that it<br />

was inappropriate as the dominant conceptual tool for interpreting the equality<br />

right. ‘Equality: The majesty of Legoland jurisprudence’ (1999) 15 South African<br />

Law Journal 398. See also D Davis Democracy and deliberation (1999) 69–95. For a<br />

critique of Davis’ position, see Woolman (n 5 above) §36.6<br />

8 See Albertyn & Goldblatt (n 1 above).<br />

9<br />

Harksen v Lane NO 1998 1 SA 300 (CC), 1997 11 BCLR 1489 (CC).<br />

10 Albertyn & Goldblatt (n 1 above).<br />

11 S Cowen ‘Can dignity guide our equality jurisprudence?’ (2001) 17 South African<br />

Journal on Human Rights 34; S Liebenberg ‘The value of human dignity in<br />

interpreting socio-economic rights’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human<br />

Rights 1 (in relation to socio-economic rights); S Liebenberg ‘The interpretation<br />

of socio-economic rights’ in Woolman et al (n 5 above) Chapter 33; Woolman (n 5<br />

above) § 36.3.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 235<br />

The latter view has been partly borne out by the Court’s recent<br />

development of the concept of dignity to include a more systemic<br />

understanding of individual and group-based material inequalities. 12<br />

This development has been explicit in relation to socio-economic<br />

rights, where the Court has linked dignity (together with freedom and<br />

equality) to the achievement of basic needs. 13 In Khosa v Minister of<br />

Social Development, 14 the equality analysis was bolstered by the<br />

concurrent presence of the right to adequate social assistance. Here<br />

the Khosa Court found the exclusion of permanent residents from<br />

social assistance to be ‘intentional, statutorily sanctioned unequal<br />

treatment’ that affected the material and social well-being of the<br />

applicants. The Court noted that ‘decisions about the allocation of<br />

public benefits represent the extent to which poor people are treated<br />

as equal members of society’. Where they are excluded from such<br />

benefits, the applicants were forced into ‘relationships of<br />

dependency upon families, friends and community’, ‘relegated to the<br />

margins of society’ and ‘cast in the role of supplicants’. 15 In Khosa,<br />

the exacerbation of material disadvantage, even destitution,<br />

reflected an absence of equal concern and respect. This absence was<br />

not merely a concern of the state, but of society as a whole.<br />

However, the Constitutional Court has connected the value of<br />

dignity and the commitment to equal concern and respect to the idea<br />

of group-based material disadvantage in only a small number of<br />

cases. 16 It has, however, found an absence of ‘equal concern and<br />

respect’ and a denial of self-worth in relation to laws that result in<br />

12<br />

This approach was, arguably, implicit in cases such as National Coalition for Gay<br />

and Lesbian Equality & Another v Minister of Justice & Others 1999 1 SA 6 (CC),<br />

1998 12 BCLR 1517 (CC) para 24 and Hoffmann v South African Airways 2001 1 SA<br />

1 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1211 (CC) para 38. However there have also been notable<br />

exceptions to <strong>this</strong> trend, see Jordan & Others v The State (Sex Workers Education<br />

and Advocacy Task Force & Others as Amici Curiae) 2002 6 SA 642 (CC), 2002 11<br />

BCLR 1117 (CC).<br />

13 Government of the Republic of South Africa & Others v Grootboom & Others 2001<br />

1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC) para 23: ‘There can be no doubt that human<br />

dignity, freedom and equality, the foundational values of our society, are denied<br />

those who have not food, clothing and shelter’. At para 44, the Court states: ‘A<br />

society must seek to ensure that the basic necessities of life are provided to all if<br />

it is to be a society based on human dignity, freedom and equality’. See also A<br />

Chaskalson ‘The third Bram Fischer lecture: Human dignity as a foundational<br />

value of our constitutional order’ (2000) 16 South African Journal on Human<br />

Rights 193 203.<br />

14 2004 6 SA 505 (CC), 2004 6 BCLR 569 (CC).<br />

15 n 14 above, paras 74, 76, 77.<br />

16<br />

See C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Equality’ in Woolman et al (n 5 above) 35-10—35-<br />

12, available at www.westlaw.com.


236 Chapter 14<br />

social exclusion, 17 the perpetuation of harmful stereotypes, 18 and<br />

political vulnerability. 19<br />

In the end, the value of dignity — manifest in the notion of equal<br />

moral worth and the requirement that all persons be treated with<br />

equal concern and respect — is a malleable concept. It easily<br />

embraces ideas of status or recognition that are implicated in the<br />

majority of equality (unfair discrimination) cases. Here the value of<br />

dignity evinces a constitutional concern with the equal moral worth<br />

of persons and groups, with their inclusion and participation within<br />

society as equals, without stereotyping, prejudice and isolation. The<br />

relationship of the value of dignity to ideas of material disadvantage<br />

is apparent, although, as we noted above, thus far limited in its<br />

application to concrete cases. In equality cases, <strong>this</strong> conception of<br />

dignity has only been employed where the underlying inequality is<br />

supported by a violation of a socio-economic right. 20 The cases<br />

demonstrate that while dignity is capable of supporting a substantive<br />

understanding of equality that explores and seeks to remedy systemic<br />

inequalities and disadvantage, other uses of dignity, often combined<br />

with legal formalism, prevent a substantive understanding of<br />

equality. 21<br />

Rather trenchant criticisms of dignity — and its relationship to<br />

equality — have been made with regard to Canadian jurisprudence.<br />

Canadian scholars have shown that the courts’ reliance on dignity<br />

focuses on whether a person or group has been treated with ‘equal<br />

concern and respect’, and fails to test whether particular goals of<br />

substantive equality have been achieved. 22<br />

17 Bhe & Others v Magistrate, Khayelitsha & Others; Shibi v Sithole & Others;<br />

SAHRC & Another v President v President of the RSA & Another 2005 1 SA 580<br />

(CC), 2005 1 BCLR 1 (CC) in relation to the customary rule of primogeniture. See<br />

further Albertyn & Goldblatt (n 16 above) 35-10—35-12.<br />

18 National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 2<br />

SA 1 (CC), 2000 1 BCLR 39 (CC) paras 45–53.<br />

19 Larbi-Odam & Others v Member of the Executive Council for Education (North-<br />

West Province) & Another 1998 1 SA 745 (CC), 1997 12 BCLR 1655 (CC) in respect<br />

of access to economic opportunities (teaching posts).<br />

20 For a discussion of <strong>this</strong> idea of dignity in relation to socio-economic rights, see S<br />

Liebenberg ‘The value of human dignity’ (n 11 above). For a discussion of the<br />

relationship between equality and socio-economic rights, see S Fredman<br />

‘Providing equality: Substantive equality and the positive duty to provide’ (2005)<br />

21 South African Journal on Human Rights 163; Goldblatt & Liebenberg (n 3<br />

above).<br />

21 See C Albertyn ‘Substantive equality and transformation in South Africa’ (2007) 23<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 253; Woolman (n 5 above) § 36.4<br />

22<br />

See, eg, C Sheppard ‘Inclusive equality and new forms of social governance’<br />

(2004) 24 Supreme Court Law Review (2d) 45; S Moreau ‘The wrongs of unequal<br />

treatment’ (2004) 54 University of Toronto Law Journal 291; J Fudge ‘Substantive<br />

equality, the Supreme Court of Canada and the limits to redistribution’ (2007) 23<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 235.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 237<br />

2.2.2 Equality<br />

The Constitutional Court has recently begun to engage more fully with<br />

the value of equality, especially in cases concerning FC section 9(2)<br />

and the positive aspects of the equality right. In these cases, the court<br />

has developed its understanding of equality’s role in remedying<br />

historical disadvantage and material inequalities. In Brink v Kitshoff<br />

NO when O’Regan J wrote that the equality clause in the Interim<br />

Constitution was adopted<br />

[in the] recognition that discrimination against people who are members<br />

of disfavoured groups can lead to patterns of group disadvantage and<br />

harm. Such discrimination is unfair: it builds and entrenches inequality<br />

amongst different groups in our society. ... The need to prohibit such<br />

patterns of discrimination and remedy their results are the primary<br />

purposes of section 8. 23<br />

Although dignity became more central to the equality jurisprudence<br />

after Brink, the Constitutional Court has regularly emphasised the<br />

remedial and restitutionary aspects of substantive equality 24 and<br />

linked equality to the enjoyment of all rights and freedoms. 25 The<br />

value of substantive equality, so understood, encompasses a notion of<br />

redistributive justice, 26 and suggests that the right to be free from<br />

unfair discrimination must be understood against our legacy of deep<br />

social inequality. 27 However, with the exception of City Council of<br />

Pretoria v Walker, 28 the Court has not had to address equality claims<br />

that necessarily and directly related to material disadvantage or<br />

economic redistribution until the cases of Bannatyne v Bannatyne; 29<br />

Khosa v Minister of Social Development; 30 and Minister of Finance v<br />

Van Heerden. 31 In Khosa, a case dealing with a claim of unfair<br />

discrimination in the allocation of social grants, the Court deployed<br />

dignity as the driving force in its development of the connection<br />

between poverty and self-worth. In Van Heerden, the Court linked the<br />

achievement of equality with the achievement of a society based on<br />

‘social justice’. However, <strong>this</strong> objective could only be realised if there<br />

was a ‘positive commitment progressively to eradicate socially<br />

constructed barriers to equality’ and to root out systematic or<br />

23 1996 4 SA 197 (CC), 1996 6 BCLR 752 (CC) para 42.<br />

24 City Council of Pretoria v Walker 1998 2 SA 363 (CC), 1998 3 BCLR 257 (CC) paras<br />

45–48; NCGLE v Minister of Justice (n 12 above) paras 60–62.<br />

25 FC sec 9(2).<br />

26 The recognition that the value of equality encompasses an idea of material<br />

equality and economic redistribution has also been expressed by former Chief<br />

Justice Chaskalson. Chaskalson (n 13 above).<br />

27 See, eg, Brink v Kitshoff (n 23 above) and Prinsloo v Van der Linde & Another<br />

1997 3 SA 1012 (CC), 1997 6 BCLR 759 (CC).<br />

28 n 24 above.<br />

29 2003 2 SA 363 (CC), 2003 2 BCLR 111 (CC).<br />

30<br />

n 14 above.<br />

31 2004 6 SA 121 (CC), 2004 11 BCLR 1125 (CC) para 31.


238 Chapter 14<br />

institutionalised under-privilege’. 32 This commitment required remedial<br />

or restitutionary equality. 33 Although the Van Heerden Court does<br />

not use the term ‘redistribution’, its interpretation of the value of<br />

equality clearly envisages a degree of economic redistribution and the<br />

removal of material disparities.<br />

2.2.3 Values, purpose and the parameters of the equality right<br />

Read across a series of cases, and in the context of our history, the<br />

purpose of the equality right can be seen to promote a society where<br />

each person is accorded equal moral worth, and in which systemic<br />

inequality and disadvantage are eradicated and substantive equality<br />

is actively promoted. The value of dignity continues to play the<br />

central role in relation to unfair discrimination and its meaning has<br />

(sometimes) been broadened to include issues of group disadvantage<br />

and material well-being. The value of equality is more dominant in<br />

the Court’s interpretation of the positive aspects of the right under<br />

FC section 9(2). In relation to both unfair discrimination and positive<br />

measures, the Court’s embrace of the redistributive aspects of<br />

equality has been supported by the presence of underlying rights in<br />

the Final Constitution (the right to social assistance in Khosa) or in<br />

legislation (the Maintenance Act in Bannatyne and the Political Office<br />

Bearers Pension Fund in Van Heerden).<br />

However, a redistributive function does not always fit<br />

comfortably with the institutional role of courts and with the<br />

distinction the courts seek to draw between issues of social policy and<br />

issues of law. 34 It is perhaps for <strong>this</strong> reason that the Constitutional<br />

Court initially turned to the more comfortable terrain of dignity to<br />

define and to guide the application of the equality right. However, it<br />

is through giving substantive meaning to the values of dignity and<br />

equality that the Court has begun to develop an equality<br />

jurisprudence that is flexible in its response to different kinds of<br />

claims, and that is able to address questions of individual moral worth<br />

and group-based social and economic disadvantage.<br />

3 Evaluation of unfair discrimination jurisprudence<br />

The early cases of unfair discrimination involved the gradual<br />

development of the jurisprudence and led to the crystallisation of a<br />

comprehensive test for unfair discrimination in Harksen. 35<br />

32 n 31 above, para 31.<br />

33<br />

n 31 above, para 30 and paras 73-74 (Mokgoro J).<br />

34 See, eg, NCGLE v Minister of Justice (n 12 above) para 123 (Sachs J expressed<br />

concerns in his minority judgement in relation to ‘over-intrusive judicial<br />

intervention in matters of broad social policy’.)<br />

35 n 9 above.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 239<br />

The Harksen test was initially followed in quite a formulaic<br />

manner by the Court (Larbi-Odam, 36 Walker, 37 NCGLE v Minister of<br />

Justice). 38 Later, the Court stopped restating the test and began to<br />

take a more sophisticated and integrated approach towards unfair<br />

discrimination determinations (Hoffman, 39 Moseneke, 40 Bhe, 41<br />

Zondi 42 ). The increasing number of FC section 9(3) cases has thrown<br />

up a number of interesting issues. For the purpose of <strong>this</strong> discussion,<br />

we will look only at some of these issues: first, issues of proof of<br />

discrimination in the first step of the FC section 9(3) test; second, the<br />

use of the listed grounds and the development of new grounds; third,<br />

the application of the contextual approach; and, finally, the use of<br />

fairness.<br />

3.1 Proving discrimination in the first step of the Harksen<br />

test<br />

In South African constitutional jurisprudence, there has been little<br />

dispute over the issue of discrimination: whether there is<br />

differentiation, or whether the differentiation is based on a<br />

prohibited ground. In discrimination law more widely understood (in<br />

both labour law in South Africa and in discrimination claims in other<br />

jurisdictions) these issues have been strongly contested. Although<br />

most claims have concerned overt legislative and executive<br />

distinctions, or clear cases of indirect discrimination on largely<br />

undisputed grounds, the Constitutional Court has confronted a couple<br />

of cases in which these issues have been contested. These cases<br />

provide some clues as to how disputes about discrimination, including<br />

the nature of the causal relationship between the distinction and the<br />

ground, may be addressed.<br />

In Jordan v The State the fact of the legislative distinction was<br />

disputed. Did the provision that criminalised sex work differentiate<br />

between sex worker and client? It was argued by the state that it did<br />

not but rather that it criminalised both sex worker and client. 43 The<br />

majority accepted that there may be a distinction, but found against<br />

the complainant on the relationship of the distinction to the ground.<br />

The minority judgment addressed the criteria for the proper<br />

36<br />

n 19 above.<br />

37 n 24 above.<br />

38 n 12 above.<br />

39<br />

n 12 above.<br />

40 Moseneke & Others v Master of the High Court 2001 2 SA 18 (CC), 2001 2 BCLR<br />

103 (CC).<br />

41<br />

n 17 above.<br />

42 Zondi v MEC for Traditional and Local Government Affairs & Others 2005 3 SA 589<br />

(CC), 2005 4 BCLR 347 (CC).<br />

43<br />

Jordan (n 12 above) paras 8 and 40 (Jordan was decided under sec 8(1) of the<br />

Interim Constitution.)


240 Chapter 14<br />

interpretation of the provision. Their starting point was to ‘consider<br />

whether there is a constitutionally compatible interpretation of the<br />

section’ that the provision is ‘reasonably capable of bearing’. 44<br />

The majority took a more staid approach. It looked at what had<br />

been generally accepted in our law; the natural reading of the<br />

section; and the context of the enactment of the provision. 45 In<br />

finding that the provision did differentiate between sex worker and<br />

client, the Court also sought to avoid a broadening of the definition<br />

of the crime (so as to include the client in its ambit), a task that<br />

ordinarily fell to the legislature and not the Court. The Court<br />

concluded that it would be contrary to constitutional values, including<br />

the principle of legality, to accept the extended definition. 46<br />

In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of<br />

Home Affairs, 47 the state contended that the exclusion of gay and<br />

lesbian partners from benefits was not discrimination based on sexual<br />

orientation but on the fact that these partners were ‘non-spouses’. In<br />

response to <strong>this</strong> line of argument, the Court said that the question of<br />

whether there has been differentiation on a specified or unspecified<br />

ground has to be determined objectively 48 and contextually, and with<br />

the experience of those affected by it in mind. 49 In <strong>this</strong> case the<br />

enquiry was a substantive one that went beyond the form of the<br />

disputed law to determine its impact on the complainants. This closer<br />

inspection involves an interrogation of the assumptions and stereotypes<br />

about ‘spouse’ and ‘family’ that underpinned the respondent’s<br />

challenge, as well as how these affected gay and lesbian people.<br />

Before <strong>this</strong> case, the stage of proving discrimination was a relatively<br />

mechanical one in the Court. This case suggests that the stage of<br />

proving discrimination could yet become a far more substantive<br />

enquiry than has, thus far, been the case.<br />

In contrast, Jordan v The State demonstrates the difference<br />

between a mechanical and more substantial approach to<br />

understanding the relationship between differentiation/discrimination<br />

and the stated ground. Unlike the enquiry in National Coalition<br />

for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Home Affairs, the Jordan<br />

majority fails to interrogate the relationship between the<br />

differentiation in section 20(1)(aA) and ‘gender’ and finds no<br />

discrimination on the basis of gender. 50 The more substantial and<br />

detailed enquiry of the minority, which is more faithful to the<br />

44 Jordan (n 12 above) para 40.<br />

45 Jordan (n 12 above) paras 41–44.<br />

46<br />

Jordan (n 12 above) para 45–46.<br />

47 NCGLE v Minister of Home Affairs (n 18 above).<br />

48 Harksen (n 9 above) para 48.<br />

49<br />

See NCGLE v Minister of Home Affairs (n 18 above) para 35.<br />

50 Jordan (n 12 above) paras 8-14.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 241<br />

approach adopted in National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality<br />

arrives at the opposite conclusion. 51<br />

It is likely that these issues will be more contested in the future<br />

as more complicated claims of intersectional or indirect<br />

discrimination are brought to the Court, or where direct<br />

discrimination is alleged against state functionaries or private<br />

individuals, whose behaviour is often covert and less susceptible to<br />

easy proof. 52 It will be interesting to see whether the Court adopts a<br />

substantive or a mechanical test to these issues.<br />

3.2 Grounds of discrimination<br />

Most of the cases that have come to the Constitutional Court have<br />

been decided on the basis of a small number of listed grounds: race,<br />

colour and ethnic origin (Walker, 53 Moseneke, 54 Mabaso 55 and<br />

Zondi 56 ); sex and gender (Brink, 57 Fraser 58 (also marital status),<br />

Hugo, 59 Jordan, 60 Bhe, 61 Volks, 62 Masiya 63 ) and sexual orientation<br />

and marital status (NCGLE v Justice, 64 NCGLE v Home Affairs, 65<br />

Satchwell, 66 Du Toit, 67 J, 68 Fourie, 69 Gory 70 and Harksen 71 ). Equality<br />

challenges have also been raised in three citizenship cases (Larbi-<br />

51 Jordan (n 12 above) paras 59-65.<br />

52<br />

Much of <strong>this</strong> will not occur under the Constitution, but is more likely to be tested<br />

under the Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of<br />

2000.<br />

53<br />

n 24 above.<br />

54 n 40 above.<br />

55 Mabaso v Law Society of the Northern Provinces & Another 2005 2 SA 117 (CC),<br />

2005 2 BCLR 129 (CC).<br />

56 n 42 above.<br />

57<br />

n 23 above.<br />

58 Fraser v Children’s Court, Pretoria North & Others 1997 2 SA 218 (CC), 1997 (2)<br />

BCLR 153 (CC).<br />

59<br />

n 4 above.<br />

60 n 12 above.<br />

61 n 17 above.<br />

62<br />

Volks NO v Robinson & Others 2005 5 BCLR 446 (CC).<br />

63 Masiya v Director of Public Prosecutions, Pretoria & Another 2007 5 SA 30 (CC),<br />

2007 8 BCLR 827 (CC).<br />

64<br />

n 12 above.<br />

65 n 18 above.<br />

66 Satchwell v President of the RSA & Another 2002 6 SA 1 (CC), 2002 9 BCLR 986<br />

(CC) and Satchwell v President of RSA & Others 2003 4 SA 266 (CC), 2004 1 BCLR 1<br />

(CC).<br />

67 Du Toit & Another v Minister for Welfare and Population Development & Others<br />

2003 2 SA 198 (CC), 2002 10 BCLR 1006 (CC).<br />

68 J & Another v Director-General, Department of Home Affairs & Others 2003 5 SA<br />

621 (CC), 2003 5 BCLR 463 (CC).<br />

69<br />

Minister of Home Affairs & Another v Fourie & Another; Lesbian and Gay Equality<br />

Project & Others v Minister of Home Affairs 2006 1 SA 524 (CC), 2006 3 BCLR 355<br />

(CC).<br />

70<br />

Gory v Kolver NO & Others (Starke & Others intervening) 2007 4 SA 97 (CC).<br />

71 n 9 above. O’Regan J in her minority judgment relied only on marital status.


242 Chapter 14<br />

Odam, 72 Khosa, 73 and Union of Refugee Women 74 ), two religion and<br />

culture disputes (Daniels 75 and Pillay 76 ) and one matter that turned<br />

on HIV status (Hoffmann 77 ).<br />

One would expect in post-Apartheid South Africa, that race discrimination<br />

challenges would abound. The challenges based on<br />

gender and sexual orientation reflect, to some extent, the role of two<br />

key social movements — the women’s movement and the gay and<br />

lesbian equality campaign. Each have used the courts actively in their<br />

struggles. We will look briefly at each of the three categories.<br />

3.2.1 Race<br />

The history of our country makes <strong>this</strong> ascriptive characteristic a likely<br />

source for constitutional challenges — and one would have predicted<br />

an even greater numbers of cases. Some of these cases arose because<br />

the legislature, although intending to remove apartheid laws and<br />

racist legislation, had not been able to manage <strong>this</strong> quickly enough.<br />

Mabaso, for example, found there to be unfair discrimination on the<br />

basis of the unlisted ground of those persons still subject to former<br />

‘homeland’ legislation. 78 Zondi found there to be unfair<br />

discrimination on the basis of landlessness as well as race. 79 Walker<br />

famously found there to be indirect race discrimination in the<br />

application of usage charges for predominantly white homeowners<br />

and a lower, flat rate in a former black area of Pretoria: However, the<br />

Court still held that, under the given conditions, such discrimination<br />

was not unfair. 80 The cases reflect a sensitive historical and<br />

contextual approach by the Court. As the number of problematic legal<br />

remnants of apartheid dwindle, fewer anti-apartheid cases are likely<br />

to reach the courts. At the same time, affirmative action cases under<br />

FC section 9(2) may well increase. It is also likely that a number of<br />

race discrimination cases will be brought under the Promotion of<br />

Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act (PEPUDA). 81<br />

PEPUDA covers a broad array of inequality issues in the private domain<br />

and offers a range of remedies that outstrip those remedies commonly<br />

offered under the common law or the Constitution.<br />

72<br />

n 19 above.<br />

73 n 14 above.<br />

74 Union of Refugee Women v The Director: The Private Security Regulatory<br />

Authority 2007 4 SA 395 (CC).<br />

75 Daniels v Campbell NO & Others 2004 5 SA 331 (CC), 2004 7 BCLR 735 (CC).<br />

76 MEC for Education: KwaZulu-Natal & Others v Pillay 2008 2 BCLR 99 (CC).<br />

77<br />

n 12 above.<br />

78 n 55 above.<br />

79 n 42 above.<br />

80<br />

n 24 above.<br />

81 Act 4 of 2000.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 243<br />

3.2.2 Sexual orientation<br />

These cases reflect the importance of the inclusion of <strong>this</strong> ground of<br />

discrimination, itself a product of the struggle by gay and lesbian<br />

activists in the constitution-writing process. 82 They also reflect the<br />

success of a systematic litigation strategy, carefully formulated as<br />

part of a broader campaign for gay and lesbian rights. 83 The strategy<br />

began with challenges to the criminal law (NCGLE v Minister of<br />

Justice) 84 and moved to challenges to the status of gay and lesbian<br />

relationships (NCGLE v Home Affairs). 85 Satchwell, 86 Du Toit 87 and<br />

J, 88 although brought by individuals rather than the movement, fitted<br />

well into the strategy of affording same-sex relationships the benefits<br />

afforded to heterosexual spouses. Fourie, 89 which required the state<br />

to legislate for same sex marriage, was the culmination of a careful<br />

building block approach that has placed South African law on the same<br />

advanced footing as a handful of other countries in the world. 90<br />

These cases were relatively straightforward formal equality<br />

decisions because the impugned legislative discrimination was so<br />

overtly unfair. It is clear that the gay and lesbian movement was<br />

correct to challenge these laws through litigation rather than through<br />

attempting to convince the state to alter discriminatory legislation.<br />

Despite favourable statements from government, little has been done<br />

in the last 13 years to rewrite these laws. In fact the Court, in J &<br />

Another v D-G, Home Affairs, called for ‘[c]omprehensive legislation<br />

regularising relationships between gay and lesbian persons’. 91<br />

Goldstone J said:<br />

It is unsatisfactory for the courts to grant piecemeal relief to members<br />

of the gay and lesbian community as and when aspects of their<br />

relationships are found to be prejudiced by unconstitutional legislation.<br />

The executive and legislature are therefore obliged to deal<br />

comprehensively and timeously with existing unfair discrimination<br />

against gays and lesbians. 92<br />

82<br />

See Stychin ‘Constituting sexuality: The struggle for sexual orientation in the<br />

South African Bill of Rights’ (1996) 23(4) Journal of Law and Society 455-483; S<br />

Croucher ‘South Africa’s democratisation and the politics of gay liberation’ (2002)<br />

28(2) Journal of Southern African Studies 315-330; R Louw ‘A decade of gay and<br />

lesbian equality litigation’ in M du Plessis & S Pete (eds) Constitutional<br />

Democracy in South Africa 1994-2004 (2004) 65-79.<br />

83<br />

Louw (n 82 above).<br />

84 n 12 above.<br />

85 n 18 above.<br />

86<br />

n 66 above.<br />

87 n 67 above.<br />

88 n 68 above.<br />

89<br />

n 69 above.<br />

90 B Goldblatt ‘Case note: Same-Sex marriage in South Africa — The Constitutional<br />

Court’s judgment’ (2006) 14 Feminist Legal Studies 261; M Judge et al (eds) To<br />

have and to hold: The making of same-sex marriage in South Africa.<br />

91 n 69 above, para 23.


244 Chapter 14<br />

Following Fourie, Parliament passed the Civil Union Act 17 of 2006 and<br />

created the option of a civil partnership or marriage for same-sex<br />

couples.<br />

The sexual orientation series of cases can be described as<br />

inclusive, rather than transformatory, since they allow gays and<br />

lesbians into the protected social institution of marriage without<br />

challenging its position within the broader concerns of family law. 93<br />

However, that inclusion does not preclude future transformation and<br />

may in fact ‘assist in setting democratic norms that may eventually<br />

shift the social norms’. 94<br />

3.2.3 Sex/gender<br />

These cases have been less systematically the product of a conscious<br />

litigation strategy by the women’s movement, although women’s<br />

organisations have been a party to all but one of them (Hugo). 95 The<br />

first case, Brink, 96 concerned provisions affecting a life insurance<br />

policy, and was thus not of great assistance to the majority of women<br />

in South Africa. Fraser 97 and Hugo, both brought by men, resulted in<br />

important substantive equality decisions that looked carefully at the<br />

context of women’s lives and the reasons why the law should take<br />

account of the unequal roles that men and women fulfil in relation to<br />

children in our society. (Fraser, it should be noted, was decided on<br />

the basis of marital status, not sex/gender discrimination. Similarly,<br />

the minority judgment of O’Regan J in Harksen contains important<br />

discussion of the gender issues in South African society while finding<br />

that discrimination was based on marital status.) The Court has<br />

incorporated critical concerns of feminist theory into its jurisprudence.<br />

In its discussion of the public/private divide, it recognises<br />

that the ‘private’ domain is often the site of efforts to silence<br />

92 As above. Similar remarks were made in Satchwell (n 66 above) paras 28-31; Du<br />

Toit (n 67 above) para 36; and Gory (n 70 above) para 65.<br />

93 C Albertyn ‘Defending and securing rights through law: Feminism, law and the<br />

courts in South Africa’ Politikon 32(2) 217 233. But see Woolman (n 5 above) §<br />

36.6 (Contends that the sexual orientation cases — when viewed against the<br />

background of state and social resistance to the recognition of sexual orientation<br />

equality — have been a challenge to the dominant heterosexual view of sexuality<br />

and forced the other branches of government and society to view such<br />

relationships differently.)<br />

94 C Albertyn (n 93 above) 233. See also P de Vos ‘The “inevitability” of same-sex<br />

marriage in South Africa’s post-apartheid state’ (2007) South African Journal on<br />

Human Rights 23 432.<br />

95 n 4 above.<br />

96<br />

n 27 above.<br />

97 n 58 above.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 245<br />

women’s claims in the home and other spheres of life, (Baloyi); 98 and<br />

it acknowledges a sexual division of labour that burdens women with<br />

child care and household responsibilities (Hugo). 99<br />

Jordan, 100 Bhe 101 and Volks 102 were all claims supported by the<br />

organised women’s movement in an effort to challenge legislative<br />

restrictions on different groups of women. 103 Bhe found the<br />

customary law rule of primogeniture to be unfair discrimination on<br />

the basis of gender. The minority decision considered whether there<br />

was discrimination based on age and birth but found that <strong>this</strong> was<br />

justifiable while the discrimination based on gender could not be<br />

justified. In both decisions, while it was relatively easy to reach <strong>this</strong><br />

conclusion on the basis of a formal equality reading of the law, the<br />

case delved into the subtleties of history and context in reaching its<br />

finding. The willingness of the Court to ‘interrogate the private<br />

sphere’ and determine the issue rather than defer to the legislature<br />

are positive developments. As one of the authors has noted<br />

elsewhere:<br />

Most significantly, the judgment has both normative value in setting the<br />

terms of the relationship between custom and gender equality, and<br />

practical value in extending inheritance rights to all women married in<br />

customary law. 104<br />

While Bhe was able to take account of context and history in<br />

addressing the plight of women under customary inheritance laws,<br />

there was a disappointing failure by the majority of the Court in<br />

Jordan and Volks to understand the situation of and to assist<br />

disadvantaged women. Ultimately, a deferential approach flowed<br />

from the assessment that the legislature was seen as ‘knowing what<br />

it was doing’ (Jordan) or ‘needing to improve the situation’ (Volks).<br />

In Jordan, the majority failed to heed the Court’s own<br />

jurisprudence by not looking into the private sphere of sexuality — it<br />

ignored the context of <strong>this</strong> form of sex and thereby reinforced harmful<br />

stereotypes. 105 In Volks (discussed further below) the majority again<br />

resorted to a formal equality approach grounded in a conservative<br />

majority. 106<br />

98 S v Baloyi 2000 1 BCLR 86 (CC), 2000 2 SA 425 (CC).<br />

99 Albertyn (n 94 above) 225-6.<br />

100<br />

n 12 above.<br />

101 n 17 above.<br />

102 n 62 above.<br />

103<br />

In addition, the Women’s Legal Centre was an amicus in Moseneke (n 40 above). It<br />

raised issues of discrimination particular to African widows.<br />

104 Albertyn (n 93 above) 231.<br />

105<br />

Albertyn (n 93 above) 228-9.<br />

106 Albertyn (n 93 above) 229-30.


246 Chapter 14<br />

These decisions point to the possibility that despite the stated<br />

recognition of feminist theories, many of the judges are not able to<br />

apply these in practice or to confront their discomfort with the<br />

implications of <strong>this</strong> approach. Gender issues seem to test many ideas<br />

around prejudice and stereotyping that seem less complex when seen<br />

through the prism of race. Interestingly, neither of the two women<br />

judges on the Court placed themselves with the majority in Volks and<br />

Jordan. 107<br />

3.3 Unlisted/new grounds of discrimination<br />

FC section 9(3) prohibits unfair discrimination on a list of grounds but<br />

also says ‘including’ before listing these grounds. This term clearly<br />

indicates that the list of grounds is not closed and that other grounds<br />

are possible. The Constitutional Court has acknowledged a range of<br />

unlisted grounds: citizenship, HIV status and marital status (which was<br />

not included in the list of grounds in the Interim Constitution).<br />

3.3.1 Citizenship<br />

The ground of citizenship has been given particular attention in three<br />

Constitutional Court cases. Non-citizens are a classic vulnerable group<br />

who face xenophobia and violence in the battle for scarce resources<br />

in our country. This situation is likely to worsen as the number of<br />

immigrants increase and the desperation of those South Africans<br />

waiting for services grows. The equality right becomes a critical<br />

mechanism for <strong>this</strong> group to assert its entitlement to the promise of<br />

(most rights in) the Constitution. Both Larbi-Odam 108 and Khosa 109<br />

are positive examples of the Court’s support for non-citizens. In Larbi-<br />

Odam, the Court recognised the ground of citizenship as an additional<br />

ground of unfair discrimination. In Khosa, the majority went quite far<br />

in affirming the rights of the permanent resident applicants. It is<br />

important to note, however, as does Lucy Williams, that courts must<br />

take care not to reinforce hierarchies of entitlement within the group<br />

of non-citizens ie: permanent residents, legal immigrants, refugees<br />

and illegal immigrants, in a way that deepens the vulnerability of the<br />

worst off. 110 In Union of Refugee Women 111 a case that turned on the<br />

rights of refugees to work as security guards, the majority of the<br />

Constitutional Court was less welcoming of <strong>this</strong> excluded group. 112<br />

107<br />

Jagwanth (n 1 above) and Jagwanth & Murray (n 1 above).<br />

108 n 19 above.<br />

109 n 14 above.<br />

110<br />

L Williams ‘Issues and challenges in addressing poverty and legal rights: A<br />

comparative United States/South Africa analysis’ (2005) 21 South African Journal<br />

on Human Rights 436 468.<br />

111<br />

n 74 above.<br />

112 This case is discussed in more detail in 3.4 below.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 247<br />

3.3.2 The Poor<br />

Interestingly, one of the most marginal groups in our society, the<br />

poor, have not approached courts with equality cases requiring<br />

positive state action to meet their basic needs. The majority of unfair<br />

discrimination cases have been brought by middle class applicants.<br />

(Although some of the cases have argued for improved benefits that<br />

would assist the poor within that disadvantaged group (Jordan 113 and<br />

Volks).) 114 As discussed above, 115 Khosa 116 concerned the rights of<br />

non-citizens living in poverty to state support. But thus far, no-one<br />

has come to court to argue that they are unfairly treated by virtue of<br />

their membership of a disadvantaged group of poor people. PEPUDA<br />

includes socio-economic status as a ground to be considered for<br />

inclusion in the list of prohibited grounds of discrimination. One would<br />

hope that the next decade will witness cases brought by or on behalf<br />

of people who have been left behind during the sustained period of<br />

growth over the past decade. 117 Our equality right seems capable of<br />

assisting them if the Court’s jurisprudence is properly applied.<br />

3.3.3 Intersectionality<br />

Other jurisdictions have struggled with the development of a method<br />

for dealing with claims based on a range of different grounds.<br />

Crenshaw has explained the problems of an unsophisticated approach<br />

by what she terms ‘intersectionality’ and shows how disadvantage<br />

suffered by a black woman constitutes a separate category of<br />

discrimination that is greater than, and different from, the individual<br />

claims of race or gender discrimination made on behalf of white<br />

women or black men. 118 A contextual approach requires that<br />

different layers of disadvantage be unpacked and addressed in their<br />

full complexity. Our Constitutional Court has not properly dealt with<br />

<strong>this</strong> issue (NCGLE v Home Affairs 119 and Moseneke). 120 Still, it has<br />

managed to assist groups where a number of possible grounds exist.<br />

The Court has correctly adopted the expansive view that as long as<br />

113 n 12 above.<br />

114 n 62 above.<br />

115<br />

See 2.1.1 above.<br />

116 n 14 above.<br />

117 See S Liebenberg & B Goldblatt ‘The interrelationship between equality and<br />

socio-economic rights under South Africa’s transformative constitution’ (2007) 23<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 335. for a discussion of poverty/class as a<br />

ground of unfair discrimination.<br />

118<br />

K Crenshaw ‘Demarginalising the intersection of race and sex: A black feminist<br />

critique of antidiscrimination doctrine, feminist theory and antiracist politics’<br />

(1989) University of Chicago Legal Forum 139. See also N Iyer ‘Categorical<br />

denials: Equality rights and the shaping of social identity’ (1993) 19 Queen’s Law<br />

Journal 179.<br />

119 n 18 above, para 40. Sachs J gave more detailed attention to the issue in his<br />

separate concurring judgment, paras 112-113.<br />

120 n 40 above, para 30.


248 Chapter 14<br />

one can succeed on one ground, the existence of other possible<br />

grounds for unfair discrimination do not have to be proved. No case<br />

has yet raised the type of intersectional issues that might lead a court<br />

astray. However, it seems probable that the Constitutional Court will<br />

follow its own contextual approach to equality and thereby avoid<br />

unjust outcomes.<br />

3.4 The application of the contextual approach<br />

Most cases that have reached the Constitutional Court have resulted<br />

in a finding of unfair discrimination in favour of the complainant. The<br />

Court has repeatedly protected the rights of marginal groups such as<br />

gays and lesbians, and at times, the rights of poverty-stricken noncitizens<br />

in a number of thoroughly contextual enquiries. Notable<br />

exceptions where the (male and white) complainants were largely<br />

unsuccessful include Hugo 121 and Walker. 122 These two cases,<br />

brought in terms of the Interim Constitution, concerned positive<br />

measures that might well have been challenged in terms of FC section<br />

9(2) following Van Heerden. 123 Other unsuccessful claims were<br />

brought in Harksen, 124 Jordan, 125 Volks 126 and Union of Refugee<br />

Women. 127 The first three concerned claims on the ground of gender<br />

discrimination (Harksen and Volks also raised issues of marital status<br />

discrimination). In all three cases, the Constitutional Court was<br />

divided. The dissents reflected the views of the same judges (O’Regan<br />

J and Sachs J in all three cases and Mokgoro J in Volks and Harksen —<br />

she did not sit in Jordan). This division in the Court seems to reflect<br />

a significant difference in the application of the FC section 9(3) test:<br />

The majority adopted a formal approach rather than a substantive<br />

approach in all three decisions.<br />

In Union of Refugee Women, which concerned the right of<br />

refugees to work as security guards, the majority (6 judges), while<br />

taking care to look at the context of refugees’ lives, found that<br />

discrimination against them (as opposed to permanent residents and<br />

citizens) was not unfair. Again, Mokgoro and O’Regan JJ in a minority<br />

judgment (4 judges) differed, finding that refugees had been unfairly<br />

discriminated against in relation to permanent residents. Their<br />

reading of the impugned legislation was that it contained an unstated<br />

stereotype that refugees are less trustworthy than South Africans.<br />

The minority’s consideration of the impact of the legislation on<br />

121 n 4 above.<br />

122 n 24 above. Walker was partially successful.<br />

123<br />

n 31 above.<br />

124 n 9 above.<br />

125 n 12 above.<br />

126<br />

n 62 above.<br />

127 n 74 above.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 249<br />

refugees took account of a wider range of contextual issues than did<br />

the majority and reflects a deeper understanding of vulnerability.<br />

In Jordan, the majority failed to appreciate the gendered nature<br />

of the sex work industry and chose to focus formalistically on the fact<br />

that the male customer and the female sex worker (as well as both<br />

male and female sex workers) were equally criminalised by the<br />

challenged legislation. The minority (the Court was divided 6:5)<br />

interpreted the Act to mean that sex workers faced greater sanctions<br />

as the primary offender than did their clients as accomplices and that<br />

since sex workers were generally women and clients men, indirect<br />

discrimination had occurred. The minority was thus able to see <strong>this</strong><br />

distinction as ‘mattering’ by exploring and unpacking the perception<br />

of sex workers as social outcasts, deviants and temptresses. 128<br />

Volks concerned a claim by a surviving domestic partner to<br />

maintenance in terms of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act.<br />

The majority had little sympathy for the middle class complainant —<br />

although it acknowledged the vulnerability of a group of poor women<br />

who find themselves in unregulated domestic partnerships. Although<br />

there was a seeming attention to context, the judgment foundered on<br />

its inability to look at the matter historically. The focus on the special<br />

place of marriage blocked any willingness to shift dominant<br />

traditional and conservative ideas about the nature of the family.<br />

Moreover, the focus on a person’s choice to marry or not was at odds<br />

with an understanding of constraints on women’s choices within<br />

intimate relationships, particularly when they are already<br />

disadvantaged and poor. 129<br />

4 An overview of the right and its relationship with FC<br />

section 36<br />

The equality right in FC section 9 is quite detailed. Five provisions set<br />

out different aspects of the right, and different ‘levels’ of equality<br />

protection (what the US courts call scrutiny). The Constitutional Court<br />

has argued that ‘[a] comprehensive understanding of the<br />

Constitution’s conception of equality requires a harmonious reading<br />

of the provisions of section 9’. 130 This reading also requires the right<br />

to be approached holistically rather than formulaically, so that the<br />

right, as a whole, produces an approach to achieving equality which<br />

is ‘cumulative, interrelated and indivisible’. 131<br />

128<br />

Jordan (n 12 above) para 64.<br />

129 See also Albertyn (n 93 above) 229-30; C Lind ‘Domestic Partnerships and Marital<br />

Status Discrimination’ in Murray & O’Sullivan (n 1 above) 108-130.<br />

130<br />

Van Heerden (n 31 above) para 28.<br />

131 Van Heerden (n 31 above) para 135 (Sachs J).


250 Chapter 14<br />

4.1 FC section 9(1) (rationality)<br />

FC section 9(1) provides constitutional protection against any<br />

irrational or arbitrary classifications (on any basis) made by the state.<br />

This constitutes a weak rationality constraint on the state that<br />

renders such classifications irretrievably unconstitutional. Failure at<br />

<strong>this</strong> stage does not require further assessment under FC section 9(3),<br />

and cannot be saved by the higher standards of reasonableness and<br />

proportionality found in section 36. The rationality test in FC section<br />

9(1) — on all differentiations that do not occur on a prohibited ground<br />

— is thus minimal and extremely deferrential to the legislature (as is<br />

reflected in the low success rate in such cases). 132<br />

4.2 FC section 9(2) (a defence to unfair discrimination)<br />

FC sections 9(3) and (4) provide the main substantive protection of<br />

the right by prohibiting unfair discrimination on an open-ended list of<br />

grounds. However, if the discrimination complained of relates to a<br />

positive measure to promote equality, then the respondent (usually<br />

the state) is able raise a defence to the claim under FC section 9(2).<br />

In terms of FC sections 9(2), the impugned action is not ‘unfair discrimination’,<br />

but a measure ‘designed to protect or advance persons,<br />

or categories of persons, disadvantaged by unfair discrimination’. Van<br />

Heerden v Minister of Finance confirmed that FC section 9(2) provides<br />

a complete defence to a claim of unfair discrimination if the following<br />

questions are answered in the affirmative:<br />

• Does the measure target persons or categories of persons who have<br />

been disadvantaged by unfair discrimination?<br />

• Is the measure designed to protect persons or categories of persons<br />

who have been disadvantaged by unfair discrimination?<br />

• Does the measure promote the achievement of equality? 133<br />

Compliance with FC section 9(2) does not make positive measures<br />

‘exempt’ from attack as unfair discrimination. It simply means that<br />

the measures are fair. 134 In general, the Court has suggested that in<br />

determining compliance with these conditions, courts should exercise<br />

some restraint, leaving space for government and parliament to<br />

address the patterns of subordination and disadvantage in our society.<br />

132<br />

It has been successfully employed only once, in Van der Merwe v Road Accident<br />

Fund 2006 4 SA 230 (CC), 2006 6 BCLR 682 (CC). The Court held that legislation<br />

rules preventing spouses married in community from claiming delictual damages<br />

for bodily injury from their spouse violated FC s 9(1).<br />

133 Van Heerden (n 31 above) para 37. Note that all judges agree with <strong>this</strong> test,<br />

although Mokgoro J and Ngcobo J each come to different conclusions in applying<br />

the test.<br />

134 Van Heerden (n 31 above) para 140.


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 251<br />

In <strong>this</strong> respect, ‘presumptive unfairness would unduly require the<br />

judiciary to second guess the legislature and the executive concerning<br />

the appropriate measures to overcome the effect of unfair<br />

discrimination’. 135 The level of scrutiny of positive measures is<br />

therefore lower than that which applies to unfair discrimination. 136 In<br />

particular, it places less emphasis on the negative impact of the<br />

measure (which would generally be on an advantaged group). The<br />

heart of the enquiry is on the promotional aspects of the measure,<br />

and the group that is to be advanced. 137<br />

If the impugned measure is not saved under FC section 9(2) then<br />

it can be assessed in terms of FC section 9(3). If it fails there, then it<br />

could still (notionally) be justified under FC section 36.<br />

4.3 FC section 9(3) (fairness) and FC section 36<br />

FC sections 9(3) and (4) provide the main substantive protection of<br />

the right by prohibiting unfair discrimination on an open-ended list of<br />

grounds. As discussed above, the test for fairness sets a high standard,<br />

with few cases passing constitutional muster.<br />

The Constitutional Court has not maintained a clear theoretical<br />

distinction between the enquiry into fairness in the unfair<br />

discrimination test set out in FC section 9(3) and the enquiry into<br />

justification in FC section 36. The lines between these two enquiries<br />

become particularly blurred when the impugned conduct does not<br />

arise from a law of general application and the Court is left with no<br />

vehicle for exploring economic and administrative considerations.<br />

In President of the RSA v Hugo, for example, the Court looked at<br />

questions of the state’s administrative capacity and public reactions<br />

to the release of so many prisoners within the enquiry into fairness. 138<br />

This case concerned an exercise of presidential prerogative that was<br />

not found to be a law of general application. 139 Economic<br />

considerations were addressed in Hoffmann v South African Airways.<br />

The case turned on the refusal by South African Airways (an organ of<br />

state) 140 to employ people living with HIV as cabin attendants.<br />

135 Van Heerden (n 31 above) para 33. See also para 152 (Sachs J).<br />

136<br />

Van Heerden (n 31 above) para 34.<br />

137 Van Heerden (n 31 above) paras 78-80 (Mokgoro J).<br />

138 n 4 above, para 46. See the criticism of the majority in the dissenting judgment of<br />

Kriegler J (para 78).<br />

139 Mokgoro J disagreed. She found that the prerogative was a law of general<br />

application and that it justified the unfair discrimination. Hugo (n 4 above) paras<br />

96-104.<br />

140 n 12 above, para 23. SAA was an organ of state in so far as it is a business unit of<br />

Transnet, a statutory body under the control of the state which has public powers<br />

and performs public functions. S Woolman ‘Application’ in S Woolman et al (n 5<br />

above).


252 Chapter 14<br />

However, the judgment suggests that, at least in relation to alleged<br />

unfair discrimination by the state, ‘legitimate commercial requirements’<br />

cannot trump the ‘greater interests of society’.<br />

Legitimate commercial requirements have been deemed an<br />

important consideration. However, the Court has warned against<br />

allowing stereotyping and prejudice to creep in under the guise of<br />

commercial interests. The greater interests of society require the<br />

recognition of the inherent dignity of every human being, and the<br />

elimination of all forms of discrimination. Our Constitution protects<br />

the weak, the marginalised, the socially outcast, and the victims of<br />

prejudice and stereotyping. It is only when these groups are protected<br />

that we, the better off, can be sure that our own rights are<br />

protected. 141<br />

Two conceptions of fairness are thus emerging in the equality<br />

jurisprudence of the Constitutional Court. The first applies when the<br />

unfair discrimination emerges from a law of general application and<br />

retains its ‘purity’ as a moral enquiry. The second applies to other<br />

forms of state action and to unfair discrimination in the private sphere<br />

and seeks to balance moral concerns with more prudential concerns<br />

within the meaning of fairness. 142<br />

4.4 Can unfairness ever be justified?<br />

If discrimination is found to be unfair, the question of justification<br />

arises, 143 but only if it relates to a law of general application. Given<br />

that the determination of inequality inevitably involves questions of<br />

justifying classifications on the basis of rationality 144 or fairness, 145<br />

the Court has not always drawn a clear line between those issues<br />

involved in determining whether the right has been violated and those<br />

issues involved in justifying that violation.<br />

In theory, the enquiry into fairness is largely a moral enquiry that<br />

measures government action against the litmus test of treating<br />

everyone with equal concern and respect and with equal moral or<br />

human worth. The enquiry is also concerned with remedying social<br />

and economic disadvantage. It thus has a particular focus on the<br />

141 Hoffmann (n 12 above) para 34. Economic considerations also formed part of the<br />

fairness enquiry when assessing a redistributive measure in Bel Porto School<br />

Governing Body v The Premier of the Province, Western Cape 2002 3 SA 265 (CC),<br />

2002 9 BCLR 891 (CC) paras 65-68.<br />

142 This idea of fairness is also found in the legislation that seeks to regulate unfair<br />

discrimination: PEPUDA and the Employment Equity Act 55 of 1998.<br />

143 This is the third stage of the test for unfair discrimination set out in Harksen v<br />

Lane (n 9 above) para 38.<br />

144<br />

FC sec 9(1).<br />

145 FC sec 9(3) or (4).


Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt 253<br />

social, economic and political context in which the impugned action<br />

occurs, and on its impact on the complainant.<br />

FC section 36 embraces a different type of enquiry. It measures<br />

the finding of fairness against a range of defences and justifications<br />

offered by the state, within a balancing of rights and values. 146<br />

Despite the failure of the Court to distinguish unfair discrimination<br />

analysis from proportionality analysis, we believe that a relatively<br />

clear distinction between FC section 9(3) and FC section 36 exists. In<br />

particular, questions of resources, administrative capacity or<br />

alternative mechanisms of achieving the same end should only enter<br />

the Court’s enquiry under FC section 36.<br />

In practice, the Court has yet to find an incident of unfair<br />

discrimination in terms of FC section 9 justifiable in terms of FC<br />

section 36. 147 Nevertheless, FC section 36 remains a critical part of<br />

the new constitutional culture of accountability and justification. In<br />

Khosa v Minister of Social Development, 148 the Constitutional Court<br />

found that the denial of social assistance constituted unfair<br />

discrimination that was not justified under FC section 36. In doing so,<br />

it demonstrated that it would carefully scrutinise the justifications<br />

offered by government and measure these against the nature of the<br />

right. Two points stand out. Firstly, the significance that the Court<br />

attached to the right: the denial of social assistance constituted a<br />

total deprivation of ‘what may be essential to enable [the applicants]<br />

to enjoy other rights vested in them in the Constitution’, by<br />

implication finding the nature of the right to be foundational. 149<br />

Secondly, the fact that the discrimination was not justified even<br />

though it would impose an additional cost burden on the state. In<br />

weighing up the government’s financial justifications, the Court found<br />

that although there was no definitive evidence of the cost, the<br />

available evidence revealed that the inclusion of the category of<br />

persons represented by the applicants would not incur more than a<br />

two percent increase over current costs. Given that a seventy percent<br />

146 FC sec 36 reads as follows:<br />

The rights in the Bill of Rights may be limited only in terms of law of<br />

general application to the extent that the limitation is reasonable and<br />

justifiable in an open and democratic society based on human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom, taking into account all relevant factors, including:<br />

(a)the nature of the right;<br />

(b)the importance of the purpose of the limitation;<br />

(c)the nature and extent of the limitation;<br />

(d)the relation between the limitation and its purpose; and<br />

(e)less restrictive means to achieve the purpose.<br />

147<br />

But see the minority judgment of Ngcobo J in Bhe (n 17 above).<br />

148 n 14 above. In <strong>this</strong> case the justification enquiry was woven into the overall set of<br />

considerations before the Court. This summary extracts what appears to have<br />

been applicable to the finding that the unfair discrimination was not justified.<br />

149 Khosa (n 14 above) para 77.


254 Chapter 14<br />

increase had been budgeted over the next three years, the cost did<br />

not justify the limitation of the right. 150<br />

Although it is difficult to imagine a case in which unfair<br />

discrimination would be justified, cost might well be the critical<br />

factor when it comes to scarce government resources. Khosa suggests<br />

that the Court will nevertheless demand, and scrutinise,<br />

comprehensive cost justifications by the respondent. This justification<br />

might be the only vehicle by which a court could reach the<br />

paradoxical conclusion that a violation of equality is justified in a<br />

‘democratic society based on ... equality’. 151<br />

150 Khosa (n 14 above) paras 60-62. However, the Court also noted that it would not<br />

be drawn into academic disputes over <strong>this</strong> issue, and seemed content to rehearse,<br />

briefly, the very same arguments regarding justification as it did for unfair<br />

discrimination.<br />

151<br />

For a comprehensive discussion of the relationship between FC sec 9 and FC sec<br />

36, see S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations’ in Woolman et al (n 5 above) Chapter<br />

34 (The authors strongly challenge the notion — articulated here — that any<br />

meaningful analysis can take place under FC sec 36 once unfair discrimination has<br />

been found in terms of FC sec 9.)


15 Reply<br />

A cautionary note regarding substantive equality:<br />

A reply to Cathi Albertyn & Beth Goldblatt<br />

Karthy Govender<br />

1 Caution with respect to expansive approaches to<br />

equality<br />

The equality jurisprudence has been developed incrementally — with<br />

dignity and fairness as its central themes. In the process, a fairly<br />

unique jurisprudence has developed around the right. Professors<br />

Albertyn and Goldblatt (‘the authors’) correctly point out that the<br />

initial cautious and stricter application of the Harksen 1 test has been<br />

supplemented by a more expansive and value-laden approach<br />

reflected in such recent decisions as Van Heerden 2 and Fourie. 3<br />

An approach that was both cautious, but faithful to core values,<br />

within the context of an expansive bill of rights, was to be expected.<br />

The drafters of the Interim Constitution and the Final Constitution<br />

were required to draft a bill of rights that protected and entrenched<br />

all universally accepted fundamental rights and freedoms. Thus<br />

various different visions have been fused into our Bill of Rights. The<br />

constraining vision prevents state action which unreasonably and<br />

1 Harksen v Lane NO 1998 1 SA 300 (CC), 1997 11 BCLR 1489 (CC).<br />

2<br />

Minister of Finance & Another v Van Heerden 2004 6 SA 121 (CC), 2004 11 BCLR<br />

1125 (CC).<br />

3 Minister of Home Affairs & Another v Fourie & Another; Lesbian and Gay Equality<br />

Project & Others v Minister of Home Affairs 2006 1 SA 524 (CC), 2006 3 BCLR 355<br />

(CC).<br />

255


256 Chapter 15<br />

unjustifiably infringes rights while the egalitarian vision compels<br />

calculated and measured steps by the state towards the attainment<br />

of a fairer and more compassionate society. The right to equality had<br />

to be construed in a manner that did not intrude into and inhibit the<br />

enforcement of socio-economic and other rights. When the process of<br />

interpreting the Interim Constitution started, we could not be entirely<br />

sure as to which vehicle would be best suited to achieve the object of<br />

improving the quality of life of all persons and freeing the potential<br />

of each person. Hence it made sense to allow each right and cluster<br />

to which it belonged to develop incrementally and not to engage<br />

prematurely in expansive reflection that might have retarded the<br />

development of perhaps more relevant and directly applicable rights.<br />

With the growth, development and interpretation of all rights, the<br />

vista is much clearer now and thus it is now more appropriate for<br />

expansive development of egalitarian principles.<br />

The ‘cautious’ equality was able to yield the far reaching and<br />

radical result of moving <strong>this</strong> society within a period of just over ten<br />

years from a legal context in which it was a criminal offence for<br />

consenting males to engage in sexual conduct to one where the state<br />

is obliged to regulate gay and lesbian marriages in a materially<br />

comparable manner to that which applies to opposite sex marriages.<br />

Other momentous journeys in the history of constitutional law were a<br />

lot more protracted and incremental. In the US, the validation of the<br />

segregationist ‘separate but equal’ doctrine in Plessy v Ferguson 4 was<br />

overturned almost 58 years later in Brown v Board of Education. 5 The<br />

major rapid change in South Africa that affirmed gays and lesbians as<br />

persons of equal worth took place through litigation — based on the<br />

rights to equality and to dignity — and involved minimal legislative<br />

inter-vention.<br />

Constitutional space exists for individuals and organisations to<br />

achieve far reaching, almost revolutionary, changes. While the<br />

organised gay and lesbian community contributed to <strong>this</strong><br />

development, it would be unjustifiably benevolent to attribute these<br />

profound changes in the law to an organised and carefully thought out<br />

systematic pattern of litigation. The courts were primarily responsible<br />

for these changes. In National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality<br />

v Minister of Justice (‘NCGLE’), 6 the Court set aside laws that<br />

criminalised consensual sexual conduct (sodomy) between male<br />

adults. Rather than relying on the directly applicable right to privacy,<br />

the matter was decided primarily on the basis of equality and dignity.<br />

The tracks laid down, ultimately led to the decision in Fourie. Our<br />

4 Plessy v Ferguson 163 US 537 (1896).<br />

5 Brown v Board of Education 347 US 483 (1954)<br />

6<br />

National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality & Another v Minister of Justice &<br />

Others 1999 1 SA 6 (CC), 1998 12 BCLR 1517 (CC).


Reply - Karthy Govender 257<br />

equality jurisprudence, by effectively protecting the right to be<br />

treated equally and by re-affirming the dignity of gays and lesbians<br />

has delivered a legal regime that is amongst the most progressive in<br />

the world. Entrenched rights thus achieved major social changes<br />

notwithstanding an indifferent government.<br />

2 Concerns about equality<br />

There were concerns that the insistence on equal treatment in section<br />

FC section 9(1) may be used to frustrate the developmental state’s<br />

programmes aimed at the attainment of substantive social and<br />

economic equality. FC section 9(1) had to be interpreted in a manner<br />

that did not frustrate the realisation of substantive equality under FC<br />

section 9(2) and did not detract from the development and growth of<br />

FC section 9(3). The High Court in Walker appeared to adopt a<br />

formalistic approach that could have frustrated or seriously retarded<br />

developmental initiatives. 7 In order to avert <strong>this</strong> problem, the<br />

Constitutional Court reaffirmed that differentiations that did not<br />

impact on dignity were constitutionally permissible if the<br />

categorisations were rationally related to a legitimate state<br />

objective. This non-exacting standard of rationality afforded the<br />

state significant latitude in advancing its developmental priorities.<br />

This concern — about the potential dangers of a formalistic<br />

approach to our equality jurisprudence — was articulated, in a slightly<br />

different context, in Sachs J’s spirited dissent in Walker. He<br />

cautioned that the undue enlargement of the concept of indirect<br />

unfair discrimination would mean that<br />

every tax burden, every licensing or town planning regulation ... would<br />

be challengeable simply because it impacted disproportionately on<br />

blacks or whites or men or women or gays or straights or able-bodied or<br />

disabled people. 8<br />

His main concern was that the courts would be interminably tied up<br />

with issues that had nothing to do with the real achievement of<br />

equality. To the extent that challenges of <strong>this</strong> nature occurred in Bel<br />

Porto 9 and Van Heerden, 10 the courts are now able, with the solid<br />

doctrinal foundation that has been laid, to develop and to enhance<br />

the notion of substantive equality.<br />

7 Walker v Stadsraad van Pretoria 1997 4 SA 189 (T), 1997 8 BCLR 416 (T).<br />

8<br />

City Council of Pretoria v Walker 1998 2 SA 363 (CC), 1998 3 BCLR 257 (CC) para<br />

117.<br />

9 Bel Porto School Governing Body v The Premier of the Province, Western Cape<br />

2002 3 SA 265 (CC), 2002 9 BCLR 891 (CC).<br />

10 n 2 above.


258 Chapter 15<br />

Interestingly, Justice Sachs’ preferred response was to amend the<br />

Harksen test and, in cases of indirect discrimination, to require a<br />

showing of prejudice before a claim of discrimination could be<br />

sustained. The majority view had found discrimination to occur<br />

wherever there was differentiation, either directly or indirectly, on a<br />

listed ground. The net effect of Justice Sachs’ proposal would have<br />

been to place a further hurdle in the path of those seeking an answer<br />

to the question of whether the law or conduct in question amounted<br />

to fair or unfair discrimination. The structure of the right — as<br />

elucidated by the majority — was found to arrive at <strong>this</strong> substantive<br />

inquiry without the need for Sachs J’s intermediary step.<br />

2.1 Van Heerden — a flexible approach<br />

By way of contrast, the Court in Van Heerden dealt with challenges to<br />

measures aimed at redressing existing inequalities by developing the<br />

concept of substantive equality within the framework of FC section<br />

9(2). 11 In the words of the Court, remedial and restitutionary equality<br />

are integral to the reach of our equality protection. In other words, the<br />

provisions of section 9(1) and section 9(2) are complimentary; both<br />

contribute to the constitutional goal of achieving equality to ensure ‘full<br />

and equal enjoyment of all rights.’ 12<br />

In the USA, the ground or category of differentiation determines the<br />

level of scrutiny to which the conduct or law is subject. These range<br />

from a rational basis test, to an intermediate level of scrutiny and,<br />

finally, to strict scrutiny analysis. The ground or category of<br />

differentiation is often determinative of the outcome of the matter.<br />

We have adopted a more nuanced approach. Categorisations that<br />

do not impact on dignity are dealt with under the mere differentiation<br />

standard or rationality standard of FC section 9(1). Categorisations<br />

that allegedly impair dignity are dealt with through the Harksen test<br />

— and FC sections 9(3) and 9(4). The assessment of remedial and<br />

affirmative action measures are assessed through the criteria laid<br />

down in Van Heerden and its gloss on FC section 9(2). For a<br />

categorisation to amount to a constitutionally permissible affirmative<br />

action measure in terms of FC section 9(2), it must target persons or<br />

categories of persons who have been disadvantaged by unfair<br />

discrimination, be designed to protect or advance such persons and<br />

promote the achievement of equality.<br />

The inherent flexibility of these criteria and the need to be<br />

context and situation sensitive could mean that the rigour and<br />

11<br />

n 2 above, para 31.<br />

12 Van Heerden (n 2 above) para 30.


Reply - Karthy Govender 259<br />

robustness with which these criteria are applied will depend upon the<br />

extent to which the right to dignity has been affected by the<br />

categorisation. In all probability, a university rule which, say,<br />

effectively restricts the number of Indian students admitted to a<br />

medical programme 13 will be subject to closer scrutiny to determine<br />

whether FC section 9(2) criteria are satisfied than were the<br />

pensioners in Van Heerden. I would describe the level of scrutiny to<br />

determine whether measures fall within FC section 9(2) as being<br />

flexible — as opposed to being an intermediate standard between the<br />

non-exacting requirements of FC section 9(1) and the more exacting<br />

requirements of FC section 9(3). As pointed out in Van Heerden, if a<br />

measure satisfies the requirements of FC section 9(2), it cannot be<br />

viewed as a form of unfair discrimination. It would be incoherent to<br />

have a measure sanctioned in one section of the Final Constitution<br />

and prohibited in the next.<br />

The ease with which the Court found the criteria satisfied in Van<br />

Heerden had a lot to do with the facts of that particular case. The<br />

striking feature of the facts of Van Heerden is that the differential<br />

pension schemes did not adversely impact on dignity — hence the<br />

looser application of FC section 9(2)’s underlying principles. Had facts<br />

similar to the facts in Motala 14 been at issue — and there was a direct<br />

impact of the affirmative action programme on the dignity of the<br />

complainant — then closer scrutiny would have been warranted. As<br />

Justice Mokgoro’s judgment suggests, all three of FC section 9(2)’s<br />

criteria are capable of being applied more robustly. The extent to<br />

which FC section 9(2) provides a ‘safe harbour’ will depend on the<br />

context and the impact the measure has on the dignity of the<br />

complainant and similarly situated persons.<br />

As the authors correctly point out, Van Heerden not only<br />

embraces the concept of substantive equality, but also encompasses<br />

measures designed to redress existing inequalities and to realise more<br />

egalitarian notions of redistributive justice. A broader notion of<br />

substantive equality will not only enable government to defend<br />

restitutionary measures, but could also be used to compel more<br />

urgent action on the part of government to seek out and eradicate<br />

systemic discrimination that perpetuates past patterns of<br />

disadvantage. Chapter 5 of the Promotion of Equality and Prevention<br />

of Unfair Discrimination (PEPUDA), 15 for example, imposes a duty on<br />

the State to promote substantive equality.<br />

13 See Motala v University of Natal 1995 3 BCLR 374 (D).<br />

14<br />

n 13 above.<br />

15 Act 4 of 2000.


260 Chapter 15<br />

2.2 Van Heerden — a positive obligation<br />

One of the consequences of Van Heerden may be that there is now a<br />

constitutional obligation ‘to progressively eradicate socially<br />

constructed barriers and root out systemic or institutionalised underprivilege’.<br />

16 If that is the case, then the core obligations and duties<br />

of section 25 of PEPUDA are activated without the section being<br />

brought into effect. If so, the genie is out of the bottle. No further<br />

reason exists for bringing <strong>this</strong> provision into effect than to ensure that<br />

the statute’s provisions for auditing, remedying and reporting are<br />

carried out. That said, an operational section 25 of PEPUDA may<br />

provide a better means of addressing systemic patterns of discrimination.<br />

Clearly such a provision would directly benefit<br />

marginalised and minority groups. The government would likely find<br />

itself under a greater legal onus to be pro-active in respect of laws<br />

and conduct which discriminate unfairly against such historically and<br />

systemically disadvantaged groups.<br />

The notion that substantive equality embraces a more egalitarian<br />

form of redistributive justice may have important consequences —<br />

and not just with respect to the application of FC section 9. It may<br />

also affect the interpretation of other rights: Individual rights may be<br />

required to yield before broader societal upliftment programmes. In<br />

Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers, the Court refused an<br />

order for the eviction of unlawful occupiers of land on the basis that<br />

the occupiers had been on the land for many years, only cursory steps<br />

had been taken by the municipality to determine the circumstances<br />

of the occupiers and the land was not needed for immediate use by<br />

the owners. 17 The common-law right to property had to be<br />

interpreted to recognise that the normal ownership rights of<br />

possession, use and occupation had to be ‘counterposed’ with the<br />

right not to be arbitrarily deprived of a home. FC section 26<br />

specifically sought to balance the rights and interests of owners with<br />

those persons in dire need of accommodation and shelter.<br />

3 FC section 9 fairness and FC section 36 justification<br />

Judgments of the Constitutional Court, as Albertyn and Goldblatt<br />

note, have not been clear in distinguishing between the criteria to<br />

establish unfairness from those required to prove justifiability as<br />

required by FC section 36. 18 The consequence of the decision in Hugo,<br />

16<br />

Van Heerden (n 2 above) para 31<br />

17 2005 1 SA 217 (CC), 2004 12 BCLR 1268 (CC).<br />

18 The coherence of <strong>this</strong> distinction is assessed at length in S Woolman & H Botha<br />

‘Limitations’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd<br />

Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 34.


Reply - Karthy Govender 261<br />

that the unfairness analysis requires an assessment of the nature of<br />

the provision or power and the purpose sought to be achieved by it, is<br />

that the proportionality analysis, which is the essence of the<br />

limitation clause, is now important in deciding whether the right has<br />

been violated. Based upon the facts of Hugo — which turned on<br />

conduct and not law — the Court was not able to rely on the limitation<br />

clause and hence the concept of ‘unfairness’ was expanded. Section<br />

14 of PEPUDA, in recognition of <strong>this</strong> difficulty, has further extended<br />

the definition of unfairness to incorporate the limitation clause<br />

enquiry. 19<br />

3.1 Minister of Education v Harris<br />

In Minister of Education v Harris, a regulation increasing the school<br />

admission age to 7 was challenged on the basis that it unfairly<br />

discriminated on the prohibited ground of age against a learner<br />

attending an independent school who was prepared and ready for<br />

school at the age of 6, which was the previous age for admission. 20<br />

The regulation sought to bring the age admission requirements of<br />

private schools in line with that of state schools. From the perspective<br />

of the applicant learner and the independent school that she<br />

attended, there were no sound reasons for not allowing her to start<br />

school when she was ready to do so. Denying her admission would,<br />

according to expert testimony, adversely affect her. The school had<br />

no reason, other than the departmental regulation, for refusing her<br />

admission until she turned 7. As the unfairness enquiry focuses on the<br />

impact of the regulation on the complainant, the Department of<br />

Education in Harris would have had serious difficulties in<br />

demonstrating that the discrimination was fair, even if regard is had<br />

to the objectives of the regulations. 21<br />

Given the circumstances of <strong>this</strong> case, the national Department of<br />

Education was more likely to justify their regulation under the general<br />

limitation clause than prove that it did not unfairly discriminate<br />

against <strong>this</strong> particular learner. Having different age admission<br />

requirements in independent and state schools would give learners<br />

from independent schools a distinct advance and accentuate the<br />

differences between the two systems. Thus, under the limitation<br />

19 Whether the inclusion of justification criteria at the fairness stage is good law<br />

was recently questioned by the Constitutional Court in MEC for Education:<br />

KwaZulu-Natal & Others v Pillay 2008 2 BCLR 99 (CC) para 70.<br />

20 Harris v Minister of Education 2001 8 BCLR 796 (T). The Constitutional Court<br />

decided the case without considering the equality question. Minister of Education<br />

v Harris 2001 4 SA 1297 (CC), 2001 11 BCLR 1157 (CC).<br />

21 However, as Stu Woolman notes, one of the myriad problems in Harris was that<br />

the DoE failed to provide any evidence that would justify the discrimination. See<br />

S Woolman ‘Freedom of Association’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law<br />

of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2003) Chapter 44.


262 Chapter 15<br />

clause enquiry, the shortcomings and challenges of the state school<br />

education system which necessitated the regulation being introduced<br />

becomes a relevant and important consideration in determining<br />

whether the infringement of the applicant’s rights are reasonable and<br />

justifiable.<br />

One of the challenges that faced the Department was that<br />

learners in public school were entering the schooling system underprepared<br />

at the age of 6 and remaining in the system much longer as<br />

a consequence. The state sought to utilise its resources more<br />

effectively by raising its admission age to 7. Given the broader<br />

objectives of narrowing inequality in educational opportunities, the<br />

Department of Education could not reasonably adopt a rule which<br />

would allow children from private institutions to leave school a year<br />

earlier than state schools. 22 If there were important justifications for<br />

the adoption of the rule in public education, then FC section 36 offers<br />

another opportunity for the successful defence of the rule with regard<br />

to independent schools. The State could have also relied on the need,<br />

identified in Van Heerden, to dismantle practices that perpetuate<br />

systemic disadvantage and promote substantive equality.<br />

3.2 Volks v Robinson<br />

Albertyn and Goldblatt’s critique of Volks 23 employs three lines of<br />

argument: it resorts to formal equality, endorses a moral<br />

conservatism and fails to understand the constraints on women’s<br />

choices within intimate relationships. Volks, in my opinion, is a much<br />

more difficult case than Jordan. 24 The right to choose, particularly in<br />

the private sphere of one’s life, is often central to one’s happiness in<br />

a society such as ours. There must be a substantial state interest to<br />

justify the setting aside of conscious decisions made by individuals<br />

within the private domain.<br />

The question is whether such intervention is justified in a life<br />

partnership, where one or both partners consciously chose not to<br />

marry. Volks was about being able to access adequate maintenance<br />

from the estate of a partner. Given the nature of <strong>this</strong> case, the<br />

exclusion of vulnerable partners could amount to unfair<br />

discrimination. However I would leave it to the legislature to<br />

determine the criteria that would have to be established to<br />

demonstrate vulnerability or need. If vulnerability is not established,<br />

then there may be another adequate justification to interfere with a<br />

22<br />

It must be noted that the High Court found that the State had failed to provide<br />

any compelling evidence in favour of justification of <strong>this</strong> regulation.<br />

23 Volks NO v Robinson & Others 2005 5 BCLR 446 (CC).<br />

24<br />

Jordan & Others v The State (Sex Workers Education and Advocacy Task Force &<br />

Others as Amici Curiae) 2002 6 SA 642 (CC), 2002 11 BCLR 1117 (CC).


Reply - Karthy Govender 263<br />

conscious choice. The legislature must now determine the broader<br />

question of how to regulate life partnerships as an institution existing<br />

independent of marriage.<br />

4 Conclusion<br />

As fascinating as the development of the equality jurisprudence has<br />

been thus far, it promises so much more. With judicial acceptance<br />

that the notion of substantive equality embraces a more egalitarian<br />

form of redistributive justice coupled with the developing<br />

jurisprudence on socio-economic rights, the stage is set for greater<br />

assertiveness on the part of the poor and marginalised to challenge<br />

and rectify measures that continue to oppress them. The Court in Van<br />

Heerden has signaled that the courts are an effective and viable<br />

forum within which to exercise the rights of the poor to meaningful<br />

participation in our democracy and to ensure effective delivery by the<br />

developmental state.


16<br />

THE ‘ARBITRARY<br />

DEPRIVATION’<br />

VORTEX:<br />

CONSTITUTIONAL<br />

PROPERTY LAW<br />

AFTER FNB<br />

Theunis Roux<br />

1 Introduction<br />

When I wrote the chapter in CLoSA on the constitutional property<br />

clause, I was not yet one of the editors. Stu Woolman’s response on<br />

receiving my chapter was to say: ‘This is not a chapter on<br />

constitutional property. This is an extended case note on a single<br />

decision — FNB. 1 And you don’t cite enough foreign law!’ I replied:<br />

‘But it has to be <strong>this</strong> way, because FNB sets out the framework for all<br />

future constitutional property cases, and in so doing renders foreign<br />

law largely irrelevant.’ In <strong>this</strong> presentation I want to record my<br />

reasons for that reply — to explain why I thought that the only way to<br />

write a chapter on constitutional property law in the immediate<br />

aftermath of FNB was to write an extended case note on that<br />

decision, and why it is that FNB, which is itself heavily reliant on<br />

foreign law, renders foreign law largely irrelevant to the resolution of<br />

future constitutional property cases.<br />

The letters ‘FNB’ stand for First National Bank — the claimant in<br />

the first case to come to the Constitutional Court under FC section 25,<br />

the property clause of the Final Constitution. The opening gambit in<br />

1<br />

First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner, South African<br />

Revenue Service & Another; First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Minister<br />

of Finance 2002 4 SA 768 (CC), 2002 7 BCLR 702 (CC). See T Roux ‘Property’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2004)<br />

Chapter 46, available at www.westlaw.com.<br />

265


266 Chapter 16<br />

Ackermann J’s judgment for a unanimous court was to assert that the<br />

primary function of the clause is to strike ‘a proportionate balance’<br />

between the public interest and individual property rights. 2 This is, of<br />

course, the traditional function performed by constitutional property<br />

clauses. The significance of the FNB decision, however, was that it<br />

purported to decide precisely how <strong>this</strong> balance should be struck in<br />

South Africa. Not only that, but the answer the Constitutional Court<br />

gave was one that none of the academic commentators on FC section<br />

25 had predicted.<br />

2 Six points<br />

If one disregards FNB for the moment, there are theoretically six<br />

points in the South African constitutional property clause inquiry at<br />

which the competing interests of the public in a just and socially<br />

beneficial distribution of property rights, and the interests of<br />

individuals in the protection of their acquired property rights, can be<br />

resolved. The first point concerns the definition of constitutional<br />

property. If the court decides that the interest that the claimant is<br />

alleging ought to be protected is not the sort of interest that FC<br />

section 25 was designed to protect, 3 then that interest receives no<br />

protection, at least under the property clause, and the competition is<br />

resolved in favour of the state. In foreign law, categorical exclusions<br />

of <strong>this</strong> kind have played an important role in constitutional property<br />

cases, particularly those relating to novel forms of property. 4 This<br />

issue has also arisen in the American ‘conceptual severance’ debate.<br />

Penn Central Transportation Co v City of New York 5 provides the best<br />

example of the divergent outcomes that may follow from judicial<br />

disagreement over whether or not to accept a particular interest as<br />

constitutionally protected property. 6<br />

2 FNB (n 1 above) para 50.<br />

3 The phrase ‘designed to protect’ covers a number of different ways in which the<br />

judicial determination of constitutional property may be undertaken, from a<br />

search for the intention of the framers to a value-based inquiry into the purposes<br />

underlying the constitutional protection of property. The latter method is more in<br />

2<br />

FNB keeping (n 1 with above) the para South 50. African approach to constitutional interpretation.<br />

34<br />

The phrase two most ‘designed oft-cited to Commonwealth protect’ covers a cases number in <strong>this</strong> of different regard are ways Government in which the of<br />

Malaysia judicial determination v Selangor Pilot of Association constitutional [1978] property AC 337 (PC) may and be Societé undertaken, United from Docks a<br />

v search Government for the intention of Mauritius of the (1985) framers LRC to (Const) a value-based 801 (PC). inquiry In Germany, into the the purposes extent<br />

to underlying which a the property constitutional interest protection is regarded of property. as being The inherently latter method subject is to more social in<br />

keeping control will with affect the South the likelihood African approach of its being to constitutional protected under interpretation.<br />

the property clause,<br />

4<br />

The art 14 two of the most German oft-cited Basic Commonwealth Law. See BVerfGE cases 58 in 300 <strong>this</strong> (1981) regard (the are Nassauskiesung Government or of<br />

Malaysia Groundwater v Selangor Case). Pilot Association [1978] AC 337 (PC) and Societé United Docks<br />

5 v 438 Government US 104 (1978). of Mauritius (1985) LRC (Const) 801 (PC). In Germany, the extent<br />

6 to The which term ‘conceptual a property interest severance’ is regarded was coined as by being MJ Radin inherently ‘The liberal subject conception to social<br />

control of property: will affect Cross the currents likelihood in the of jurisprudence its being protected of takings’ under the (1988) property 88 Columbia clause,<br />

art Law 14 Review of the 1667. German The Basic term Law. refers See to BVerfGE the possibility 58 300 (1981) that the (the court Nassauskiesung might isolate, or<br />

Groundwater for purposes of Case). analysing the property interest at stake, just that stick in the<br />

5 438 bundle, US 104 or topographical (1978). unit (in the case of land) or time period (in the case of


Theunis Roux 267<br />

The second opportunity for resolving competing public and private<br />

interests in property is provided by the court’s approach to the<br />

concept of deprivation. A very strict approach would define out of the<br />

ambit of constitutional concern certain types of regulation, and<br />

thereby resolve the competition in respect of these sorts of regulation<br />

entirely in favour of the state. 7 Conversely, a generous approach<br />

would tend to admit into the constitutional property clause inquiry a<br />

broader range of types of regulation, leaving it to other parts of the<br />

inquiry to resolve the competition. In between these two extremes, a<br />

more cautious court — one that wanted to make <strong>this</strong> stage of the<br />

property clause inquiry do real analytic work — might approach the<br />

matter casuistically, offering no general definition of the term<br />

deprivation, but instead assessing on a case-by-case basis whether the<br />

regulation at issue was the sort of regulation that should be held to<br />

the standard imposed by FC section 25(1).<br />

The third opportunity for resolving competing public and private<br />

interests in property concerns the application of the test for arbitrary<br />

deprivation in FC section 25(1). Since <strong>this</strong> was the primary focus of the<br />

FNB decision, I am not going to say any more about it for the moment.<br />

The fourth opportunity is provided by the distinction drawn in FC<br />

sections 25(1) and (2) between the deprivation and expropriation of<br />

property. Under FC section 25(1), deprivation of property must occur<br />

in terms of law of general application, and ‘no law may permit<br />

arbitrary deprivation of property’. Under FC section 25(2), the<br />

expropriation of property is permitted where it occurs in terms of law<br />

of general application, ‘for a public purpose or in the public interest’,<br />

and just and equitable compensation is paid. Since two different<br />

standards are prescribed, the text requires the interpreter to<br />

distinguish between the deprivation and expropriation of property.<br />

And, since the obligations attaching to the expropriation of property<br />

are more onerous from the state’s perspective than those attaching<br />

to the deprivation of property, the way in which <strong>this</strong> distinction is<br />

drawn will affect the balance struck between the public interest and<br />

6 The term ‘conceptual severance’ was coined by MJ Radin ‘The liberal conception<br />

of property: Cross currents in the jurisprudence of takings’ (1988) 88 Columbia<br />

Law Review 1667. The term refers to the possibility that the court might isolate,<br />

for purposes of analysing the property interest at stake, just that stick in the<br />

bundle, or topographical unit (in the case of land) or time period (in the case of<br />

temporary restrictions on use) actually affected by the regulation. After<br />

seemingly endorsing <strong>this</strong> approach in Hodel v Irving 481 US 704 (1987) and First<br />

Evangelical Lutheran Church v County of Los Angeles 482 US 304 (1987), the US<br />

Supreme Court has not since decided a case on <strong>this</strong> basis. See GS Alexander The<br />

global debate over constitutional property: Lessons for American takings<br />

jurisprudence (2006) 78-80.<br />

7<br />

See Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality; Bissett & Others v<br />

Buffalo City Municipality; Transfer Rights Action Campaign & Others v Member of<br />

the Executive Council for Local Government and Housing, Gauteng & Others 2005<br />

1 SA 530 (CC), 2005 2 BCLR 150 (CC).


268 Chapter 16<br />

individual property rights. A distinction that gathered more types of<br />

conceivable state action under the rubric of expropriation than an<br />

alternative distinction, would put a thumb on the individual side of<br />

the scales, and vice versa.<br />

As with the definition of deprivation, the distinction between<br />

deprivation and expropriation is a conceptual one that could be drawn<br />

in a more or less categorical way. A purely categorical approach might<br />

reserve the term ‘expropriation’ for situations where the state forced<br />

the transfer of a (constitutionally valued) property right to itself or to<br />

a third party. A less categorical approach might seek to develop some<br />

or other test for determining the circumstances under which the<br />

impact of a regulation on the property rights holder was so severe as<br />

to require formal justification under FC section 25(2)(a) and the<br />

payment of just and equitable compensation. 8 Either way, the rules<br />

developed would need to resolve competing public and private<br />

interests in property by defining a legal act, or legally ascertainable<br />

tipping point, at which the obligations specified in FC section 25(2)<br />

and (3) would arise.<br />

The fifth opportunity for resolving competing public and private<br />

interests occurs once the court has decided that <strong>this</strong> legal act has<br />

occurred, or <strong>this</strong> tipping point has been reached, and consists in the<br />

determination of the ‘amount’, and ‘time and manner’ of any<br />

compensation that may be due. 9 The determination of these issues<br />

allows for a very fine-grained solution since the court is empowered<br />

to apportion the cost in monetary terms of the collective interest<br />

being pursued between the public (meaning the taxpayers as a whole)<br />

and the individual property rights holder. In <strong>this</strong> case, the South<br />

African compensation clause, FC section 25(3), expressly enjoins the<br />

court to determine these issues by using a multi-factor balancing test<br />

in which the court is required to strike ‘an equitable balance between<br />

the public interest and the interests of those affected, having regard<br />

to all relevant circumstances’. 10<br />

Finally, since the general limitations clause notionally applies to<br />

the limitation of all rights in the Bill of Rights, competing public and<br />

private interests in property could also conceivably be resolved by<br />

leaving some work for FC section 36. On <strong>this</strong> approach, the rights<br />

8 In its regulatory takings jurisprudence, the US Supreme Court has adopted both a<br />

categorical approach, in terms of which an exercise of the state’s police power<br />

that results in the permanent physical occupation of property is regarded as being<br />

per se unconstitutional, and an ad hoc balancing approach, which applies in other<br />

cases. The locus classicus for the permanent physical occupation rule is Loretto v<br />

Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp 458 US 419 (1982). The ad hoc balancing test<br />

was first announced in Penn Central (n 5 above).<br />

9<br />

FC sec 25(3).<br />

10 As above.


Theunis Roux 269<br />

guaranteed in FC section 25 (assuming the existence of law of general<br />

application, which is in any case a precondition for the application of<br />

FC section 36) would be rights against the arbitrary deprivation of<br />

property and the uncompensated expropriation of property.<br />

Alternatively, the expropriation of property for an impermissible<br />

purpose, which rights could be limited if a sufficiently compelling<br />

justification could be found under FC section 36.<br />

These, then, were the six possible ways, before FNB, in which<br />

competing public and private interests in property might have been<br />

resolved. Note that the first and second stages of the inquiry allow<br />

only a crude, all-or-nothing decision to be taken about whether or not<br />

to protect the individual interest at stake, or to subject the state<br />

action at issue to the discipline of the constitutional property clause.<br />

The fourth stage, the court’s determination whether the impugned<br />

law provides for expropriation, could either be approached<br />

conceptually, in a manner similar to the first and second stages of the<br />

inquiry, or it could be turned into a multi-factor balancing test by<br />

listing a range of criteria that together determined the legal effect of<br />

the law in question, and hence the state’s constitutional obligations.<br />

The fifth and sixth stages are both in their nature, or by reason of the<br />

constitutional text, multi-factor balancing tests in which the court<br />

must eschew conceptual distinctions in favour of an overarching<br />

assessment of the weight to be attributed to a range of criteria.<br />

Before FNB, the academic commentaries on the South African<br />

property clause took a broadly similar view of the way the<br />

Constitutional Court should approach these various stages. 11 The<br />

exception was the comprehensive commentary by AJ van der Walt,<br />

which contained an ingenious argument about how the test for<br />

arbitrary deprivation in FC section 25(1) and the general limitations<br />

test in FC section 36 might be combined. 12 The first striking thing<br />

about FNB is that it expressly rejects Van der Walt’s approach whilst<br />

seeming in fact to endorse some of its components. 13 The other<br />

striking thing is that the decision divides the constitutional property<br />

clause inquiry into seven formally distinct stages, 14 corresponding —<br />

11 See the list of academic authorities cited in FNB (n 1 above) para 57 n 79.<br />

12 AJ van der Walt The constitutional property clause: A comparative analysis of<br />

section 25 of the South African Constitution of 1996 (1997) 92-100.<br />

13 The express rejection occurs in FNB (n 1 above) para 70. As we shall see,<br />

however, in prescribing its test for arbitrary deprivation, the Court renders the<br />

general limitations inquiry largely redundant. In addition, the test it applies for<br />

arbitrary deprivation and the (superfluous) test it later applies under FC sec 36<br />

are remarkably similar. The only real difference between the two approaches,<br />

therefore, is that the Court prefers a sliding-scale standard of review at the first<br />

stage of the constitutional inquiry, whereas Van der Walt’s approach would have<br />

seen proportionality review applied cumulatively with the test for arbitrary<br />

deprivation.<br />

14 FNB (n 1 above) para 46.


270 Chapter 16<br />

with one minor difference — to the six stages just discussed. 15 As it<br />

turns out, however, the focus of the court’s inquiry falls on the third<br />

stage, the test for arbitrary deprivation. Not only that, but the test it<br />

articulates is so all-encompassing as to make the other stages, and the<br />

foreign law that might have assisted in explicating them, redundant.<br />

I shall leave it to AJ van der Walt to point out how the FNB Court’s<br />

approach to the interpretation of FC section 25 might be said to<br />

approximate his own. My concern in <strong>this</strong> presentation is with the<br />

second issue — the way in which the court’s test for arbitrary<br />

deprivation swallows up the other stages of the constitutional<br />

property clause inquiry.<br />

3 FNB<br />

FNB involved a constitutional challenge to section 114 of the Customs<br />

and Excise Act. 16 As it was then worded, section 114 authorised the<br />

Commissioner of the South African Revenue Service, in order to defray<br />

a customs debt, to detain and eventually sell property ‘in the<br />

possession or under the control of’ the customs debtor, even where<br />

such property belonged to a third party. FNB impugned section 114<br />

under FC section 25(2), alleging that it provided for the<br />

uncompensated expropriation of property. On the authority of a<br />

passage in the chapter on property in the first edition of CLoSA, 17 the<br />

FNB Court held that expropriations are a form of deprivation, and<br />

consequently that the impugned provision should first be tested<br />

against FC section 25(1). 18 Dispensing quickly with an argument that<br />

the legal form of a property right was less important than the rightholder’s<br />

‘commercial interest’ in it, 19 the FNB Court restricted itself<br />

to two narrow holdings in respect of the first two stages of the<br />

inquiry: (1) that ownership of a corporeal movable, such as the motor<br />

vehicles at issue in <strong>this</strong> case, constituted property for purposes of FC<br />

section 25; 20 and (2) that ‘dispossessing an owner of all rights, use and<br />

benefit to and of corporeal movable goods, is a prime example of<br />

deprivation in both its grammatical and contextual sense’. 21<br />

These two holdings set the stage for the primary focus of FNB: the<br />

elaboration of the test for arbitrary deprivation. The judgment<br />

15<br />

The FNB Court’s analytic framework consists of an extra stage because the<br />

general limitations stage is mentioned twice, first in respect of deprivations of<br />

property inconsistent with FC sec 25(1), and then in respect of expropriations of<br />

property inconsistent with FC sec 25(2) and (3).<br />

16 Act 91 of 1964.<br />

17 ‘Property’ in M Chaskalson et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (1st<br />

Edition, OS, 1996) Chapter 31.<br />

18 FNB (n 1 above) para 57.<br />

19 FNB (n 1 above) para 55.<br />

20<br />

FNB (n 1 above) para 51.<br />

21 FNB (n 1 above) para 61.


Theunis Roux 271<br />

proceeds in three steps at <strong>this</strong> point. First, the Court discusses — only<br />

to dismiss as unpersuasive — the academic commentaries on the<br />

meaning of the term ‘arbitrary’ in FC section 25(1). 22 Second, the<br />

Court engages in an expansive comparative-law survey, ostensibly<br />

aimed at elucidating the test for arbitrary deprivation, but<br />

encompassing other issues as well. 23 Third, the court summarises the<br />

principles emerging from its comparative-law survey as a prelude to<br />

stating its test for arbitrary deprivation, which is contained in a<br />

single, long paragraph, para 100. At first blush para 100 appears to be<br />

a kind of bluffer’s guide to constitutional property law, encapsulating<br />

the whole of the FNB Court’s test for arbitrary deprivation and<br />

therefore, if the reading suggested here is correct, all that one really<br />

needs to know about FC section 25. On closer inspection, however,<br />

para 100 turns out to be a chimera, promising more than it delivers,<br />

and ultimately reserving to the Court a great deal of discretion to<br />

decide future cases as it deems fit.<br />

Broken up into its constituent parts, <strong>this</strong> is what para 100 says:<br />

Deprivation of property is ‘arbitrary’ as meant by s 25 when the ‘law’<br />

referred to in s 25(1) does not provide sufficient reason for the<br />

particular deprivation in question or is procedurally unfair. Sufficient<br />

reason is to be established as follows.<br />

There follow eight sub-paragraphs, each of which articulates a<br />

different consideration to be factored into the court’s assessment of<br />

the constitutionality of the impugned law. The first sub-paragraph<br />

reads:<br />

(a) It [ie sufficient reason] is to be determined by evaluating the<br />

relationship between means employed, namely the deprivation in<br />

question, and ends sought to be achieved, namely the purpose of the<br />

law in question.<br />

This sub-paragraph typifies the test for arbitrary deprivation as a<br />

means-end relationship test, in terms of which the public interest that<br />

the state claims to be pursuing must be assessed in relation to the<br />

legislative scheme adopted. But more than the relationship between<br />

legislative means and legislative ends is at issue. What is truly at stake<br />

appears in the next three sub-paragraphs:<br />

(b) A complexity of relationships has to be considered.<br />

(c) In evaluating the deprivation in question, regard must be had to the<br />

relationship between the purpose of the deprivation and the person<br />

whose property is affected.<br />

22<br />

FNB (n 1 above) paras 67-70.<br />

23 FNB (n 1 above) paras 71-98.


272 Chapter 16<br />

(d) In addition, regard must be had to the relationship between the<br />

purpose of the deprivation and the nature of the property as well as the<br />

extent of the deprivation in respect of such property.<br />

These sub-paragraphs purport to expand on the sorts of relationships<br />

to which a court must have regard. There is a semantic slippage here,<br />

however, because the relationships mentioned in sub-paras (c) and<br />

(d) are not all means-end relationships as suggested by the crossreference<br />

in sub-para (b) to the word ‘relationship’ in sub-para (a).<br />

Thus, ‘the person whose property is affected’ and ‘the nature of the<br />

property’ affected by the legislative scheme may be entirely<br />

incidental to the means employed in that scheme. Along with ‘the<br />

extent of the deprivation in respect of such property’ these factors<br />

are better described as pertaining to the impact of the legislative<br />

scheme, rather than the means used to implement it. That the impact<br />

of the legislative scheme is the primary determinant of the standard<br />

of review to be applied appears clearly from the next sub-paragraph:<br />

(e) Generally speaking, when the property in question is ownership of<br />

land or a corporeal movable, a more compelling purpose will have to be<br />

established in order for the depriving law to constitute sufficient reason<br />

for the deprivation than in the case when the property is something<br />

different and the property right something less extensive.<br />

Sub-paragraph (e) broaches the question of the nature of the property<br />

right affected by the scheme, and proposes different levels of review<br />

according to the answer to that question. This is a novel approach to<br />

the analysis of constitutional property cases. The closest equivalent<br />

in foreign law can be found in the German Federal Constitutional<br />

Court’s differentiated protection of property interests according to<br />

their social function. 24 In the Commonwealth, the nature of the<br />

property right affected by the legislative scheme is relevant only to<br />

the threshold question of whether the claimant’s interest amounts to<br />

constitutional property. 25 Once <strong>this</strong> has been determined, a uniform<br />

standard of review is generally applied. 26 According to sub-para (e),<br />

by contrast, the nature of the property right remains relevant at the<br />

third stage of the constitutional inquiry, and influences the level of<br />

review.<br />

Lest there was any doubt about <strong>this</strong>, sub-para (f) indicates that<br />

the term ‘property right’ includes the traditional incidents of<br />

ownership recognised at common law:<br />

24 See Alexander (n 6 above) 103.<br />

25<br />

See T Allen ‘Commonwealth constitutions and the right not to be deprived of<br />

property’ (1993) 42 International Comparative Law Quarterly 523.<br />

26 In American regulatory takings jurisprudence, the right to exclude is privileged<br />

through the per se permanent physical occupation rule laid down in Loretto (n 8<br />

above), but property rights are not otherwise hierarchically ordered.


Theunis Roux 273<br />

(f) Generally speaking, when the deprivation in question embraces all<br />

the incidents of ownership, the purpose for the deprivation will have to<br />

be more compelling than when the deprivation embraces only some<br />

incidents of ownership and those incidents only partially.<br />

In addition to specifying that the term ‘property right’ in sub-para (e)<br />

includes the traditional incidents of ownership, sub-para (f) makes it<br />

clear that the level of review will vary according to the number of<br />

‘incidents of ownership’ affected, and that the total deprivation of<br />

one or more of those incidents is not a precondition for the<br />

application of the property clause. My reaction on first reading <strong>this</strong><br />

passage was Archimedean. I didn’t quite shout out ‘Eureka!’ but I<br />

think I might well have sat up a little straighter in my chair. In the<br />

Commonwealth jurisprudence on constitutional property, 27 the number<br />

of incidents of ownership affected by a regulation is, like the<br />

nature of the property right at issue, a consideration that goes to the<br />

threshold question of whether a constitutional property interest is at<br />

stake. By declaring <strong>this</strong> interest to be an issue relevant to the test for<br />

arbitrary deprivation at the third stage of the inquiry, the FNB Court<br />

strongly implies that conceptual considerations of <strong>this</strong> sort will not be<br />

used to bar constitutional property claims at the threshold stage.<br />

Rather, the FNB Court’s declared intention is to countenance all such<br />

claims as constitutional property claims, and deal with the number of<br />

incidents of ownership affected by the deprivation and the impact of<br />

the deprivation as factors bearing on the level of review to be<br />

applied. There could be no clearer signal than <strong>this</strong> that the Court<br />

intends to make a clean break, both with the conceptualist approach<br />

that has caused so many problems in other jurisdictions, and with the<br />

pre-1994 approach of the South African courts to the Expropriation<br />

Act. 28 Rather than hinging on single, case-deciding categorisations of<br />

the property interest at issue or the character of the deprivation, para<br />

100 indicates that future constitutional property cases will be decided<br />

according to an all-things-considered assessment of the seriousness of<br />

the deprivation and its impact on the claimant. The more drastic the<br />

deprivation and the more extensive its impact, the greater will be the<br />

state’s justificatory burden. As the FNB Court states in the final two<br />

sub-paragraphs:<br />

(g) Depending on such interplay between variable means and ends, the<br />

nature of the property in question and the extent of its deprivation,<br />

there may be circumstances when sufficient reason is established by, in<br />

27<br />

See Allen (n 25 above).<br />

28 Act 63 of 1975. See, eg, Tongaat Group v Minister of Agriculture 1977 2 961 (A)<br />

972D. The Constitutional Court endorsed a conceptual approach to the definition<br />

of expropriation in Harksen v Lane NO & Others 1998 1 SA 300 (CC), 1997 11 BCLR<br />

1489 (CC) paras 31-37, a case heard under the Interim Constitution. Although not<br />

expressly over-ruling Harksen, the FNB Court’s test for arbitrary deprivation is<br />

likely to make the categorical distinction drawn in that case between<br />

expropriation and deprivation less important in future cases.


274 Chapter 16<br />

effect, no more than a mere rational relationship between means and<br />

ends; in others <strong>this</strong> might only be established by a proportionality<br />

evaluation closer to that required by section 36(1) of the Constitution.<br />

(h) Whether there is sufficient reason to warrant the deprivation is a<br />

matter to be decided on all the relevant facts of each particular case,<br />

always bearing in mind that the enquiry is concerned with ‘arbitrary’ in<br />

relation to the deprivation of property under section 25.<br />

In essence, therefore, the test for arbitrary deprivation is a meansend<br />

test, with the state’s justificatory burden varying between<br />

rationality and proportionality depending on the considerations<br />

mentioned in sub-paras (b)-(f). The advantage of <strong>this</strong> approach is the<br />

discretionary power it confers on the court to adjust the level of<br />

review to fit the circumstances of the case. This power will enable<br />

South African courts to show the necessary deference when reviewing<br />

the impact on property rights of important social reform programmes,<br />

such as land reform or black economic empowerment. In other cases,<br />

where the state overzealously regulates property in pursuit of<br />

questionable goals, the courts will be able to ratchet up the level of<br />

review in order to provide adequate protection.<br />

4 The vortex<br />

The problem with a flexible test like the one devised in FNB, however,<br />

is that the grounds for the application of one or the other level of<br />

review should be ascertainable in advance. It must be clear to the<br />

state when devising a regulatory scheme, and to persons affected by<br />

that scheme when deciding whether or not to challenge it, what level<br />

of review the court is likely to apply. The FNB test fails to provide <strong>this</strong><br />

degree of certainty. Unlike the German Federal Constitutional Court<br />

in the Groundwater Case, 29 the Court in FNB does not tell us why<br />

certain types of property are more constitutionally valued than<br />

others. Indeed, there is a contradiction between the Court’s<br />

recognition of land reform as a particularly valued purpose, which<br />

suggests a low level of review, and the ownership of land as a<br />

particularly valued property right, which suggests a higher level. The<br />

FNB Court also does not tell us which incidents of ownership are more<br />

constitutionally valued, or how to analyse cases so as to distinguish<br />

the total deprivation of a conceptually severed stick in the bundle<br />

from the partial deprivation of a stick not so severed. All that we<br />

know for certain is that, after consideration of the factors in para 100,<br />

a level of review must be chosen somewhere between mere<br />

29 n 4 above.


Theunis Roux 275<br />

rationality and full proportionality, and that the choice of <strong>this</strong> level<br />

will largely determine the outcome of the case. 30<br />

Fact-specific tests like these are good for courts but bad for rulesetting.<br />

Cases decided under the FNB test for arbitrary deprivation<br />

will necessarily be tied to their own circumstances, and hence have<br />

virtually no precedential value. This outcome is bad enough. It is<br />

made even worse by the fact that it renders all of the other stages of<br />

the constitutional property clause inquiry largely redundant, thus<br />

undermining the capacity of these stages to perform a rule-setting<br />

function as well. This is a serious charge. The rest of <strong>this</strong> presentation<br />

is devoted to substantiating it.<br />

The Concise Oxford Dictionary (1982) defines the word ‘vortex’ as<br />

‘a system, occupation, pursuit, etc, viewed as swallowing up or<br />

engrossing those who approach it.’ The reading of FNB offered here<br />

is that the test for arbitrary deprivation in para 100 is a vortex in <strong>this</strong><br />

sense, swallowing up the other stages of the constitutional property<br />

clause inquiry. I have already hinted at the way in which the first<br />

stage is swallowed up. By making the nature of the property right and<br />

the number of sticks in the property rights bundle affected by the<br />

deprivation an issue for consideration in the test for arbitrariness,<br />

that test requires the court to de-emphasise the importance of these<br />

considerations at the first stage of the constitutional inquiry. What<br />

sense would it make, in light of sub-paras (e) and (f), for the court to<br />

reject a challenge at the first stage of the inquiry, either because the<br />

property interest at stake were not constitutionally protected, or<br />

because insufficient incidents of ownership were affected? A<br />

constitutional claimant litigating after FNB would rightly feel<br />

aggrieved by such a decision, since the promise held out by para 100<br />

is that these issues will not be used to exclude claims at the first and<br />

second stages, but rather factored into the court’s overarching test<br />

30<br />

This point is well-illustrated by the first case to be decided under the FNB test,<br />

Mkontwana (n 7 above). In <strong>this</strong> case — a challenge to a regulation requiring<br />

landowners to pay outstanding municipal debts, including debts incurred by third<br />

parties, as a precondition for formal property transfer — the two lower courts<br />

reached opposing outcomes by choosing different levels of review. As AJ van der<br />

Walt has pointed out, even the Constitutional Court’s reasons for adopting a low<br />

level of review in <strong>this</strong> case are not terribly convincing. See AJ van der Walt<br />

‘Retreating from the FNB arbitrariness test already? Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela<br />

Metropolitan Municipality; Bissett v Buffalo City Municipality; Transfer Rights<br />

Action Campaign v MEC for Local Government and Housing, Gauteng (CC) (2005)<br />

122 South African Law Journal 75.


276 Chapter 16<br />

for arbitrary deprivation. 31<br />

The second stage of the property clause inquiry is swallowed up<br />

both by the test for arbitrary deprivation and also by the extremely<br />

broad definition of deprivation given in para 57 of the judgment. In<br />

<strong>this</strong> paragraph, the FNB Court states: ‘In a certain sense any<br />

interference with the use, enjoyment or exploitation of private<br />

property involves some deprivation in respect of the person having<br />

title or right to or in the property concerned’. This dictum is strictly<br />

speaking obiter, and the Court’s actual holding on the meaning of<br />

deprivation is, as we have seen, restricted to the facts of FNB. 32<br />

Nevertheless, there are indications in para 100 that the Court will<br />

allow almost any claim against a regulation affecting property past<br />

the second stage of the inquiry, and deal with the severity of the<br />

regulation’s impact on the claimant’s rights in its test for arbitrary<br />

deprivation. This impression follows particularly from the reference<br />

to ‘the extent of the deprivation’ in para 100(d) and the notion in para<br />

100(f) that a deprivation that ‘embraces only some incidents of<br />

ownership and those incidents only partially’ should be subject to a<br />

lower standard of review. These phrases strongly suggest that the<br />

second stage of the constitutional property clause inquiry will not be<br />

used as a conceptual barrier to exclude claims involving less extensive<br />

deprivations. Rather, as with claims where only one or two incidents<br />

of ownership are affected, the Court’s inclination is to allow these<br />

claims past the first two stages, and balance competing public and<br />

private interests in property through its more flexible test for<br />

arbitrary deprivation.<br />

The fourth stage of the constitutional property clause inquiry,<br />

which concerns the distinction between deprivations and<br />

expropriations, is rendered largely redundant by the FNB Court’s<br />

decision to treat expropriations as a ‘subset of deprivations’. 33 What<br />

<strong>this</strong> means, as illustrated by FNB itself, is that claims which appear to<br />

involve uncompensated expropriations, or expropriations for an<br />

improper purpose, will be tested first against the standard set by FC<br />

section 25(1) for the arbitrary deprivation of property. Contrary to<br />

what some commentators have said, 34 <strong>this</strong> analytic framework is<br />

likely to make American-style regulatory takings jurisprudence, and<br />

all the difficulties attendant on distinguishing deprivations from<br />

expropriations, irrelevant in South Africa. The reason for <strong>this</strong> is that<br />

31<br />

That <strong>this</strong> is the correct reading of para 100 is once again borne out by Mkontwana<br />

(n 7 above). In <strong>this</strong> case, the only incident of ownership affected by the provision<br />

was the owner’s right to sell, and yet <strong>this</strong> did not prevent the Court from applying<br />

its test for arbitrary deprivation.<br />

32 FNB (n 1 above) para 61.<br />

33 FNB (n 1 above) para 57, quoting Chaskalson & Lewis (n 17 above) 31-14.<br />

34<br />

See K Hopkins & K Hofmeyr ‘New perspectives on property’ (2003) 120 South<br />

African Law Journal 48 57-58.


Theunis Roux 277<br />

the sorts of governmental regulation that are typically the subject of<br />

such inquiries in the United States — exercises of the police power<br />

that go ‘too far’ 35 — will in South Africa be subject first to the test for<br />

arbitrary deprivation. A regulation that goes ‘too far’ in the American<br />

sense (because it interferes with ‘distinct investment-backed<br />

expectations’ or destroys all economically viable use of the property,<br />

for example) will in South Africa likely be struck down under FC<br />

section 25(1) as providing for the arbitrary deprivation of property.<br />

The question whether the regulation, whilst purporting to constitute<br />

an exercise of the state’s police power, in fact provides for the<br />

expropriation of property, will never arise. Even an uncompensated<br />

expropriation, which was effectively what was at issue in the FNB<br />

case, will be treated as an arbitrary deprivation, the arbitrariness of<br />

which will lie precisely in the legislative scheme’s failure to provide<br />

for compensation. 36<br />

As Du Toit, 37 handed down after FNB, illustrates, there will still<br />

be a role for the fifth stage of the constitutional property clause<br />

inquiry in cases where the expropriatory purpose of the law is not in<br />

dispute and where compensation is offered. In such cases, the court<br />

will skip directly to the fifth stage and determine whether just and<br />

equitable compensation has been paid. Where no compensation is<br />

provided for in the legislative scheme, however, and the stated<br />

intention of the legislature is merely regulatory, the state will<br />

presumably seek to defend the claim on the basis that the law merely<br />

deprives the claimant of property. Such a defence would require the<br />

court to apply its test for arbitrary deprivation, with all the<br />

consequences just illustrated.<br />

The problem with <strong>this</strong> aspect of the FNB analytic framework is<br />

that, if the court strikes down a law that fails to provide for<br />

compensation under FC section 25(1), the claimant will not be able to<br />

demand compensation under FC section 25(2). As AJ van der Walt has<br />

pointed out, however, there may be instances where it would be<br />

desirable for the court not to invalidate the law, but to order the<br />

payment of compensation. 38 There are two possible ways out of <strong>this</strong><br />

dilemma. The first would be to allow the claimant to go on to argue<br />

that the law, in addition to providing for the arbitrary deprivation of<br />

35<br />

This phrase was first used in Pennsylvania Coal Co v Mahon 260 US 393 (1922).<br />

The decision is generally agreed to have introduced the idea of regulatory takings<br />

into American takings law.<br />

36<br />

The claimant in FNB would not have challenged section 114 of the Customs and<br />

Excise Act had it provided that the state, from the proceeds of the sale in<br />

execution of the confiscated property and other state funds if necessary, should<br />

pay any third party with a right over that property an amount equivalent to the<br />

market value of its right, in <strong>this</strong> case the amount owing under the motor vehicle<br />

financing agreement.<br />

37<br />

Du Toit v Minister of Transport 2006 1 SA 297 (CC), 2005 11 BCLR 1053 (CC).<br />

38 A van der Walt Constitutional property law (2005) 235-37.


278 Chapter 16<br />

property, also provided for the expropriation of property without<br />

payment of just and equitable compensation. Although the<br />

Constitutional Court’s usual practice is to terminate the<br />

constitutional inquiry as soon as a ground for constitutional invalidity<br />

has been established, it would be in the interests of justice, and also<br />

within the Court’s FC section 38 power to grant appropriate relief, for<br />

the Court to allow the claimant to proceed to the expropriation stage.<br />

The other possibility is that the Court might develop a remedial<br />

jurisprudence for the payment of constitutional damages in respect of<br />

violations of FC section 25(1). The door to such a remedy in<br />

constitutional cases was left open in Fose, 39 and eventually confirmed<br />

in Modderklip, 40 though not, at least in the Constitutional Court’s<br />

decision, for a violation of FC section 25(1). 41 An order for the<br />

payment of constitutional damages under FC section 25(1) would not<br />

be equivalent to an order for the payment of just and equitable<br />

compensation under FC section 25(3). Rather, the point of such an<br />

order would be to make good any loss in excess of the loss the<br />

claimant might reasonably be expected to bear under the test for<br />

arbitrary deprivation. In <strong>this</strong> way, the payment of constitutional<br />

damages under FC section 25(1) would approximate the equalisation<br />

payments made for disproportional regulation in German law. 42 Since<br />

the making of such an order would follow from a finding of violation<br />

under FC section 25(1), the development of such a remedial<br />

jurisprudence would not be tantamount to the acceptance of<br />

regulatory takings. 43 A constitutional claimant who sought just and<br />

equitable compensation would still need to meet whatever criteria<br />

were established for a finding of expropriation under FC section 25(2).<br />

Given the ‘algorithmic’ 44 structure of the property clause inquiry,<br />

it is extremely unlikely that the final, general limitations, stage will<br />

ever be reached. If reached, it is even less likely that <strong>this</strong> stage will<br />

determine the outcome of a case. As we have seen, both laws that<br />

provide for the deprivation of property and those that provide for the<br />

39 Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 3 SA 786 (CC), 1997 7 BCLR 851 (CC).<br />

40 President of the Republic of South Africa & Another v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty)<br />

Ltd (Agri SA & Others, Amici Curiae 2005 5 SA 3 (CC), 2005 8 BCLR 786 (CC).<br />

41 Cf the Supreme Court of Appeal’s decision, which is based on a violation of FC<br />

section 25: Modderfontein Squatters, Greater Benoni City Council v Modderklip<br />

Boerdery (Pty) Ltd (Agri SA and Legal Resources Centre, Amici Curiae); President<br />

of the Republic of South Africa & Others v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd (Agri SA<br />

and Legal Resources Centre, Amici Curiae) 2004 6 SA 40 (SCA), 2004 8 BCLR 821<br />

(SCA).<br />

42 See the discussion in Van der Walt (n 38 above) 221-23 and Alexander (n 6 above)<br />

120-21.<br />

43<br />

Cf Alexander (n 6 above) 121 (arguing that equalisation does not mean ‘that there<br />

is something like inverse condemnation in German law’).<br />

44 The use of the term ‘algorithm’ in <strong>this</strong> context is drawn from Iain Currie’s chapter<br />

on the property clause in I Currie & J de Waal The Bill of Rights handbook 5 ed<br />

(2005) 536.


Theunis Roux 279<br />

expropriation of property will first be tested against FC section 25(1).<br />

Should the court find that FC section 25(1) has been infringed, either<br />

because the deprivation did not take place ‘in terms of law of general<br />

application’, or because the law authorising the deprivation was<br />

arbitrary, the state could theoretically seek to justify such<br />

infringement under FC section 36. On closer analysis, however, the<br />

application of FC section 36 to infringements of FC section 25(1) is<br />

beset by conceptual difficulties. 45 Deprivations that limit FC section<br />

25(1) because they do not occur ‘in terms of law of general<br />

application’ cannot be saved by FC section 36 because the<br />

precondition for the application of <strong>this</strong> section is that the limitation<br />

should have occurred ‘in terms of law of general application’. And a<br />

law of general application that permits the arbitrary deprivation of<br />

property, either because it is procedurally unfair or because it<br />

provides insufficient reason for the deprivation, is hardly likely to be<br />

‘reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society’, as<br />

required by FC section 36(1).<br />

In dealing with the question of justification in FNB, the Court<br />

acknowledged these difficulties, but assumed in favour of the state,<br />

without deciding, that FC section 36 was applicable to infringements<br />

of FC section 25(1). 46 The Court then proceeded to apply a pared<br />

down version of its FC section 36(1) limitation test to the facts, as<br />

follows:<br />

FNB’s ownership in the vehicles concerned is ultimately completely<br />

extinguished by the operation of section 114 of the Act. As against <strong>this</strong><br />

the Commissioner gains an execution object for someone else’s debt.<br />

But, as already indicated, there is no connection between FNB or its<br />

vehicles and the customs debt in question. Under these circumstances<br />

the object achieved by section 114 is grossly disproportional to the<br />

infringement of FNB’s property rights. 47<br />

This passage tends to confirm that FC section 36 has ‘no meaningful<br />

application’ 48 to infringements of FC section 25(1). The issues<br />

addressed by the Court are precisely the same as those addressed in<br />

its test for arbitrary deprivation. 49 The fact that FNB’s ownership of<br />

the vehicles was ‘completely extinguished’ is addressed in sub-paras<br />

(d) and (f) of that test, which require the Court to examine ‘the<br />

extent of the deprivation’ and whether it ‘embraces all the incidents<br />

of ownership’. And the absence of a ‘connection between FNB or its<br />

45<br />

Currie & de Waal (n 44 above) 561-63.<br />

46 FNB (n 1 above) para 110.<br />

47 FNB (n 1 above) para 111.<br />

48<br />

Currie & De Waal (n 44 above) 562.<br />

49 S Woolman & H Botha ‘Limitations’ in Woolman et al (n 1 above) Chapter 34.


280 Chapter 16<br />

vehicles and the customs debt’ was central to the Court’s earlier<br />

finding that ‘no sufficient reason’ existed for the deprivation. 50<br />

In cases where the test for arbitrary deprivation approximates<br />

rational basis review the case for the non-application of FC section 36<br />

is incontrovertible: A law that infringes FC section 25(1) for lack of<br />

means-end rationality will never be capable of justification under the<br />

general limitations clause. At the other end of the scale, where the<br />

test for arbitrary deprivation approaches the FC section 36 test for<br />

proportionality, the application of FC section 36 can at best confirm<br />

a conclusion already reached under FC section 25(1). FNB clearly<br />

illustrates <strong>this</strong> result. 51<br />

FC section 36 also applies in theory to a law of general application<br />

that authorises the expropriation of property other than for a public<br />

purpose or in the public interest, or which fails to provide for the<br />

payment of just and equitable compensation. No such law is ever<br />

likely to survive constitutional scrutiny until the final stage, and if it<br />

does, it is unlikely to be justifiable under FC section 36. For the<br />

reasons given earlier, a law providing for the expropriation of<br />

property that is not aimed at achieving a public purpose or is not<br />

otherwise in the public interest will in all likelihood fail the test for<br />

arbitrary deprivation. In the unlikely event that it survives<br />

constitutional scrutiny to the fifth stage, it will be struck down for<br />

violating FC section 25(2)(a). Thereafter, the state would be faced<br />

with the conceptually impossible task of having to justify, as being<br />

reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society, a law<br />

that ex hypothesi was enacted in pursuit of a private purpose.<br />

Similarly, an expropriatory law that was struck down for failing to<br />

provide for just and equitable compensation could hardly be found to<br />

be reasonable and justifiable under FC section 36 unless the impact<br />

of the law was so inconsequential as not to require compensation, in<br />

which case the better finding would be that the payment of nil<br />

compensation was just and equitable under FC section 25(2) and (3). 52<br />

For all these reasons the test for arbitrary deprivation will have<br />

the effect of minimising the importance of the other stages of the<br />

50 FNB (n 1 above) para 109.<br />

51<br />

See also Janse van Rensburg NO v Minister van Handel en Nywerheid 1999 (2)<br />

BCLR 204 (T) 222E. The contrary finding, in Director of Public Prosecutions: Cape<br />

of Good Hope v Bathgate 2000 (2) SA 535 (C), that an infringement of FC sec 25(1)<br />

was justified under FC sec 36, is explicable on the basis that the limitations<br />

clause was applied to justify the infringement of other rights as well, meaning<br />

that the finding in <strong>this</strong> case that the law was justified was not specific to the<br />

finding that the law infringed FC sec 25(1). In addition, the Bathgate decision<br />

predates that in FNB (n 1 above), and accordingly did not apply the arbitrary<br />

deprivation test as laid down in that case.<br />

52<br />

Cf Currie & De Waal (n 44 above) 563 (discussing Nhlabathi & Others v Fick [2003]<br />

2 All SA 323 (LCC), 2003 7 BCLR 806 (LCC)).


Theunis Roux 281<br />

property clause inquiry. No doubt, the courts will still go through the<br />

motions of considering the other stages, and it is not inconceivable<br />

that a claim may be rejected because the interest at stake is<br />

considered not to amount to constitutional property, 53 or because the<br />

regulation at issue is considered to be too inconsequential as to<br />

amount to deprivation. 54 But the focus of attention in all future cases,<br />

with the exception of disputes purely about the quantum of<br />

compensation, is likely to fall on the third stage. The implication of<br />

<strong>this</strong> prediction in turn is that foreign law will have little relevance to<br />

the resolution of future constitutional property cases. Multi-factor<br />

balancing tests like those prescribed in para 100 of FNB are impervious<br />

to foreign-law influence because their very purpose is to focus the<br />

court’s attention on the facts of the particular case, rather than<br />

principles or rules laid down in other decisions. Indeed, as argued<br />

earlier, even South African decisions applying the test for arbitrary<br />

deprivation will have little precedential effect, unless and until the<br />

Constitutional Court begins to give thicker, substantive reasons for<br />

the weight it chooses to give the various considerations in para 100. 55<br />

53<br />

Cf Van der Walt (n 38 above) 72.<br />

54 See Mkontwana (n 7 above) para 32 (The Constitutional Court flirts with the<br />

dangerous idea that ‘normal restrictions on property use or enjoyment found in<br />

an open and democratic society’ might not amount to deprivation of property, but<br />

in the end declares <strong>this</strong> part of the judgment to be obiter.) See also the discussion<br />

in Van der Walt (n 38 above) 127.<br />

55<br />

Cf Van der Walt (n 38 above) 40-42 (giving a more positive account of the FNB<br />

decision in <strong>this</strong> respect). As Van der Walt notes, Sachs J’s judgment in Port<br />

Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 1 SA 217 (CC), 2004 12 BCLR 1268<br />

(CC) paras 15-23 does begin to supply these thicker, substantive reasons in<br />

explaining the relationship between FC sec 25 and FC sec 26(3) (protection<br />

against arbitrary eviction). But the Court’s remarks in <strong>this</strong> decision are obiter<br />

dicta as far as the property clause inquiry is concerned. Mkontwana (n 7 above)<br />

was disappointingly silent on the purposes informing constitutional property<br />

rights protection in South Africa, whilst the Constitutional Court’s decision in<br />

Modderklip (n 40 above) bypassed the property rights aspect of that case,<br />

choosing to decide the question under the right of access to courts (FC sec 34).


17 Reply<br />

Against regulatory taking: In defense of the two-stage inquiry<br />

A reply to Theunis Roux<br />

Frank Michelman<br />

1 Introduction<br />

Informed and prompted by Theunis Roux’s crisp, clear, incisive, and<br />

largely persuasive analysis — both in his Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa chapter on Property 1 and in his follow-up Conversations-piece 2<br />

— I want to take up for further examination two structural-level<br />

questions that seem still to vex debates over how best to construe FC<br />

section 25.<br />

My first question concerns the vortex effect that Roux so<br />

luminously describes as having been set in motion by the<br />

Constitutional Court’s exegesis of sections 25(1), (2), (3) and their<br />

interrelations, in what I shall call ‘the doctrine according to FNB’. I<br />

have, in general, no quarrel with Roux’s overall characterisation and<br />

appraisal of <strong>this</strong> doctrine’s evolution to date, all of which I find<br />

entirely persuasive and illuminating. I focus on a single dimension of<br />

Roux’s appraisal of what he describes. He appears to be feeling some<br />

qualm about the doctrine according to FNB, insofar as he expects it to<br />

lead in all cases to by-passing direct application of the conditions laid<br />

down by section 25(2) specifically for expropriations (but not for all<br />

1 T Roux ‘Property’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa<br />

(2nd Edition, OS, 2003) Chapter 46, available at www.westlaw.com.<br />

2<br />

T Roux ‘The “arbitrary deprivation” vortex: Constitutional property law after<br />

FNB’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional conversations (2008).<br />

283


284 Chapter 17<br />

deprivations). Roux worries that the doctrine will suppress forever<br />

from South African constitutional law the question of developing a<br />

doctrinal method for differentiating (in debatable cases) those stateauthored<br />

property-value impairments that count as ‘expropriations’<br />

from those that do not. From a US observer’s standpoint, the effect is<br />

to deprive South Africa forever of the possible development of a body<br />

of law paralleling that which in the US is known as the doctrine of<br />

‘regulatory taking’ (and elsewhere is sometimes called ‘constructive<br />

expropriation’). From among state actions that in form do no more<br />

than regulate the use and enjoyment of an asset, such a doctrine<br />

selects some for subjection to a compensation requirement that, by<br />

the express terms of the constitutional text, applies only when the<br />

state takes away property from an owner.<br />

I agree with Roux that the doctrine according to FNB has the<br />

effects I have just described. My view is that these effects supply no<br />

ground, none at all, for reservation or worry. To the contrary, I<br />

believe they leave South Africa with a reading of FC section 25 that is<br />

normatively superior to any alternative one might envision, while<br />

being no less textually justified. At the bottom line, my claim is that<br />

a regulatory-taking doctrine would be a bad choice for South Africa<br />

(not to say for any country, but that is beyond the scope of my<br />

undertaking here). In my view, a reading of FC section 25 that<br />

forecloses that possibility is to be preferred over one that doesn’t, all<br />

else being equal. I postpone the justification for that normative claim<br />

to late in my discussion. Everything else I shall have to say along the<br />

way will be on an analytical-descriptive, not a normative-substantive<br />

level. I thus aim to confirm and to drive home, in a somewhat<br />

different way, much of what Roux has said, while perhaps questioning<br />

one aspect of it. I confess to uncertainty about how far, if at all, Roux<br />

will disagree with anything I shall have to say on <strong>this</strong> point. I do think<br />

I am putting a somewhat different spin on the matters discussed than<br />

is conveyed by the rhetoric, at least, of Roux’s Conversations-piece.<br />

The second question I wish to examine is that of the relation<br />

between FC section 25(1)’s ‘internal’ limitation clause and the<br />

general limitation clause contained in FC section 36(1). Read strictly<br />

according to its terms, FC section 25 grants only what has been called<br />

a ‘truncated’ property right: 3 A right against deprivation not<br />

authorised by a non-arbitrary law and expropriation not for a public<br />

purpose or in the public interest, or not attended by just and<br />

equitable compensation, with justification of violations of that<br />

truncated right still a possibility in terms of FC section 36(1). In an<br />

3 See AJ van der Walt Constitutional property law (2005) 62-65.


Reply - Frank Michelman 285<br />

alternative reading proposed some years ago by AJ van der Walt, 4 FC<br />

section 25 implicitly requires section 36(1) justification for any<br />

limitation of a very broadly defined right to ‘acquire and hold rights<br />

in property’ (to borrow language from IC section 28(1)), in addition to<br />

the requirements laid down by the internal limitations contained in FC<br />

sections 25(1) and (2). FNB has now settled the question in favor of<br />

the truncated-property-right reading, 5 while also imbuing the nonarbitrary-law<br />

requirement of FC section 25(1) with a sweep that<br />

apparently diminishes the practical stakes of choice between the two<br />

readings to near-zero. 6 A genuine puzzle remains about how to relate<br />

the justificatory demands of FC sections 25(1) and 36(1). I shall<br />

discuss <strong>this</strong> relationship in the second part of <strong>this</strong> comment.<br />

2 The FNB vortex: A cause for concern?<br />

I turn now to my first question. Roux claims — correctly, so far as I can<br />

see — that the doctrine according to FNB will tend to suppress forever<br />

from South African constitutional law the question of developing a<br />

doctrinal method for differentiating (in debatable cases) those stateauthored<br />

property-value impairments that count as ‘expropriations’<br />

from those that do not. I read Roux further to suggest that there is<br />

here some cause for concern or regret. It is a ‘problem’, he feels, in<br />

the law according to FNB, that ‘if a court strikes down a law that fails<br />

to provide for compensation under FC section 25(1), the claimant will<br />

not be able to demand compensation under FC section 25(2).’ The<br />

effect, Roux writes, is to make ‘redundant’ any inquiry about whether<br />

the challenged action of the state does or does not qualify as an<br />

‘expropriation’ in terms of FC section 25(2) — or, as he also puts the<br />

matter, the effect is to ‘swallow up’ that seemingly textually<br />

mandated stage of the ‘constitutional property clause inquiry’. 7<br />

‘Problem’, ‘make redundant’, and ‘swallow up’ do not strike my ear<br />

as flattery of the doctrine according to FNB.<br />

As I have said, I do not doubt at all that the doctrine according to<br />

FNB has the effects that Roux describes by those mildly opprobrious<br />

terms. I only cannot see any cause at all for regretting these effects<br />

of the doctrine — or indeed, as I eventually shall suggest, for failing<br />

4<br />

See AJ van der Walt The constitutional property clause: A comparative analysis<br />

of section 25 of the South African Constitution of 1996 (1997) 21-28.<br />

5 First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner, South African<br />

Revenue Service & Another; First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Minister<br />

of Finance 2002 4 SA 768 (CC), 2002 7 BCLR 702 (CC) para 70.<br />

6 As nicely explained both by Roux (n 2 above) and by AJ van der Walt (n 3 above)<br />

62-65.<br />

7 Roux writes: ‘Since two different standards are [respectively] prescribed [by<br />

sections 25(1) and 25(2)], the text requires the interpreter to distinguish between<br />

the deprivation and the expropriation of property.’ Roux (n 2 above) 267. I shall<br />

be, in effect, raising a doubt about whether that is so.


286 Chapter 17<br />

to applaud them. Where I am going to find ground for applause, Roux<br />

apparently can and does find cause for concern and second thought.<br />

For the first step in presenting my view, we shall need to look<br />

closely at exactly how, in Roux’s contemplation, the doctrine<br />

according to FNB works out to the redundancy-producing result upon<br />

which we are agreed. Roux chalks it up to ‘the FNB Court’s decision<br />

(in para 57) to treat expropriations as “a subset of deprivations”’, and<br />

to the Court’s further prescription 8 that all challenges to property<br />

deprivations in terms of FC section 25 are to be channeled first<br />

through inspection under FC section 25(1), with only the survivors<br />

ever possibly to be sorted into those that are and are not<br />

‘expropriations’ to be submitted to further inspection, under FC<br />

section 25(2). As Roux explains:<br />

What <strong>this</strong> means ... is that claims which appear to involve<br />

uncompensated expropriations ... will be tested first against the<br />

standard set by FC section 25(1) for the arbitrary deprivation of<br />

property. [T]he sorts of governmental regulation that are typically the<br />

subject of [constructive expropriation] inquiries in the United States –<br />

exercises of the [regulatory] power that go ‘too far‘ – will in South Africa<br />

be subject first to the test for arbitrary deprivation. A regulation that<br />

[the Americans might treat as a constructive, uncompensated<br />

expropriation] will in South Africa likely be struck down under FC section<br />

25(1) as providing for the arbitrary deprivation of property. The<br />

[constructive expropriation] question ... will never arise ... [A]n<br />

uncompensated expropriation ... will be treated as an arbitrary<br />

deprivation, the arbitrariness of which will lie precisely in the<br />

legislative scheme’s failure to provide for compensation. 9<br />

Just so. I think Roux moves too quickly, though, when he blames the<br />

effect that worries him — the redundancy or swallowing-up effect —<br />

on either the Court’s decision ‘to treat expropriations as “a subset of<br />

deprivations”’, or its direction that FC section 25(1) inspection is<br />

always to precede any possible FC section 25(2) inspection,<br />

apparently regardless of how the claimant may choose to frame its<br />

complaint. As to the first point, I think the FNB Court really had no<br />

choice. As to the second, I think it is not the direction to channel all<br />

cases first through FC section 25(1) that directly leads to the<br />

circumvention of FC section 25(2) inspection that worries Roux, but<br />

rather the idea that failure to provide compensation may be the (sole)<br />

vice in a law that causes it to fail FC section 25(1) inspection.<br />

To construe FC section 25(1) ‘deprivation’ and FC section 25(2)<br />

‘expropriation’ as naming two mutually exclusive categories would be<br />

unnatural to an extreme. Roux himself suggests, as one appropriate<br />

8<br />

FNB (n 5 above) para 46.<br />

9 Roux (n 2 above) 276-77 (my emphasis).


Reply - Frank Michelman 287<br />

way to draw the line between property-impairing acts that are and<br />

are not ‘expropriations’ governed by the requirements of FC section<br />

25(2), that a court can ask whether ‘the impact on the [right holder<br />

is] so severe as to require payment of just compensation.’ But then<br />

how can a subset of impositions that are so specially severe as to<br />

merit subjection to the special requirements of FC section 25(2) be<br />

treated as exempt from a requirement (the one set forth in FC section<br />

25(1)) to which all less severe limitations (‘deprivations’) are<br />

subjected? ‘This imposition is so severe that the requirement of<br />

authorisation by a nonarbitrary law, which is applicable to all less<br />

severe impositions, should be deemed inapplicable to it’? Who would<br />

credit a court that said that, when a way lies textually open to avoid<br />

saying it?<br />

Treating expropriations as a subset of deprivations is thus, in my<br />

view, unavoidable. Granted, the result may be duplication of the FC<br />

section 25(2) requirements by the FC section 25(1) requirement. If so,<br />

then that is a kind of mild misfortune. But the misfortune is owing to<br />

the drafters, not to the Constitutional Court, and I agree with the<br />

apparent judgment of the Court that the duplication is a lesser<br />

misfortune here than would be the anomaly of an exemption for the<br />

most severe impositions on property from a non-arbitrariness<br />

requirement that applies to those that are less severe. 10<br />

The next point to see is that it is not, actually, the subsumption<br />

of expropriations under the broader heading of deprivations, or the<br />

direction (which seems plausible enough) to submit all deprivations to<br />

FC section 25(1) inspection, that causes the effects that worry Roux.<br />

It is rather the expectation created by the Court that (quoting again<br />

from Roux) ‘an uncompensated expropriation ... will be treated as an<br />

arbitrary deprivation, the arbitrariness of which will lie precisely in<br />

the legislative scheme’s failure to provide for compensation.’ Roux, I<br />

think justifiably, treats <strong>this</strong> as a clear implication from the doctrine<br />

according to FNB, and does so approvingly. 11 I am happy to follow<br />

suit. Of course, we can imagine the Court holding oppositely. The FNB<br />

Court could have held that FC section 25(1) inspection always comes<br />

first. It could have also stated that ‘arbitrary’ in FC section 25(1)<br />

refers only to the justifiability of the state’s end and the tightness of<br />

fit (rationality, necessity) of its means, so that a deprivationauthorising<br />

law is not ‘arbitrary’ in terms of FC section 25(1) if its only<br />

alleged vice or deficiency is the distributional injustice of failing to<br />

10 Of course there is no anomaly (but also no consequence that matters), if the<br />

‘public purpose or public interest’ requirement in sec 25(2)(a) has a scope of<br />

application that is known from the start to rule out all the laws that would be<br />

ruled out by the non-arbitrary requirement of sec 25(1). As long as it is<br />

conceivable that the latter may rule out one single law that the former does not,<br />

the anomaly is there.<br />

11 See Roux (n 1 above) 19-20.


288 Chapter 17<br />

make provision for due compensation to owners for their losses. Had<br />

the FNB Court so held, or were it in future to do so, the redundancy<br />

and the circumvention effects that bother Roux would disappear<br />

(although some other untoward consequences might then arise). 12<br />

The necessity for the Court to propound some way of drawing the line<br />

between those deprivations that are and are not also expropriations<br />

would then be back on the table. A dénouement devoutly to be<br />

wished? I say no; decidedly no. And my chief reason is that such a<br />

construction of FC section 25 opens the door to the rise in South<br />

African constitutional jurisprudence of a doctrine of ‘constructive<br />

expropriation’ or ‘regulatory taking’ that it is better off without.<br />

But that is jumping too far ahead in my story. Let us back up, and<br />

proceed more slowly.<br />

Roux observes that a line separating the state’s acts of<br />

‘deprivation’ from its acts of ‘expropriation’ (or separating those<br />

deprivations that are also expropriations from those that are not) can<br />

be placed so that a greater or lesser fraction of the cases will be<br />

classed as expropriations. The line can also, as Roux further notes, be<br />

drawn either categorically or contextually. Thus, Roux lists as one<br />

plausible line-drawing test that of whether ‘the impact on the [right<br />

holder is] so severe as to require payment of just compensation’. That<br />

would be a maximally contextual test. It also is a test that could end<br />

up treating far fewer cases as expropriations than some categorical<br />

tests would do: say, an ‘American’ test treating every instance of<br />

physical invasion by force of the state, no matter how paltry, as an<br />

expropriation for which compensation is constitutionally required. 13<br />

The choice of a line-drawing method or test thus would seem to<br />

be an important question. Why so? Because, Roux explains, ‘the<br />

obligations attaching to the expropriation [compare US ‘taking’] of<br />

property are more onerous from the state’s perspective than those<br />

attaching to the deprivation [compare US ‘mere regulation’] of<br />

property.’ The choice of a line-drawing method thus will ‘affect the<br />

balance struck between the public interest and individual property<br />

rights.’ A line-drawing method that is comparatively expansionary on<br />

the expropriation side ‘put[s] a thumb on the individual side of the<br />

scales, and vice versa.’ 14<br />

At first look, <strong>this</strong> thinking seems obviously correct. We start with<br />

the set of all possible courses of action by the state that are<br />

authorised by non-arbitrary laws. Any course of action in <strong>this</strong> set may<br />

or may not be classed as a deprivation of property and/or as an<br />

12 As above.<br />

13<br />

See Loretto v Teleprompter Manhattan Cable TV Corp 458 US 419 (1982).<br />

14 Roux (n 2 above) 267-68.


Reply - Frank Michelman 289<br />

expropriation of property. If a course of action in the set is classed<br />

(only) as a deprivation of property, but not as an expropriation, the<br />

course is one that the state is free to pursue without any further<br />

obligation. If the course is classed (also) as an expropriation, the state<br />

may proceed only on the further condition of payment of<br />

compensation. A payment condition is obviously more onerous to the<br />

state than no condition. The converse holds if we look at the situation<br />

from the standpoint of property owners. What owner in her right mind<br />

would not wish a larger, as opposed to a smaller, fraction of the cases<br />

to be classed as expropriations? If it’s an expropriation, I collect a just<br />

and equitable compensation by force of FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3); if<br />

it’s not, I don’t.<br />

But of course all of <strong>this</strong> reasoning presupposes that it won’t be<br />

held — as, according to Roux, it has been or will be held — that all<br />

deprivations, if unaccompanied by compensation sufficient to qualify<br />

as just and equitable in the circumstances (noting that <strong>this</strong> amount<br />

may often be R0), are, for just that cause, unconstitutional by the<br />

non-arbitrary-law test of FC section 25(1). If that truly is to be the<br />

shape of the doctrine, then, as Roux has observed, 15 owners can have<br />

no reason to care about whether any instance of a deprivation is<br />

further classed as an expropriation — unless (which I assume we all<br />

hope and suppose will never be the case, and which FC section 25 as<br />

written seems to oppose) owners also can hope that an<br />

‘expropriation’ finding will somehow garner for them a compensation<br />

that is greater than justice and equity require.<br />

That is how the matters will look to owners. How will they look to<br />

the state? Roux says that ‘the [constitutionally imposed] obligations<br />

attaching to the expropriation of property are more onerous from the<br />

state’s perspective than those attaching to the deprivation of<br />

property.’ But again the doctrinal question arises whether a<br />

deprivation-authorising law that fails to provide for compensation<br />

sufficient to qualify as circumstantially just and equitable is to be<br />

deemed ipso facto arbitrary in terms of FC section 25(1). If so, then<br />

the state’s obligation attaching to deprivation is not less onerous than<br />

that attaching to expropriation; rather, the two obligations are the<br />

same: Pay or desist. 16 But <strong>this</strong> is exactly the result that Roux contends<br />

(and I cheerfully agree) is foretold by the vortex-inducing doctrine<br />

announced by the Constitutional Court in FNB.<br />

15<br />

See Roux (n 1 above) 46-20 and 46-29 — 46-30.<br />

16 To spell it out: The obligation attaching to all deprivations is to make sure there is<br />

authorising law, which provides for some amount of compensation not less than<br />

what justice and equity require in the circumstances. That is identical in practice<br />

to the obligation attaching to expropriations.


290 Chapter 17<br />

Can <strong>this</strong> effect possibly be avoided by envisioning a highly<br />

formalistic, categorical test for differentiating those deprivations<br />

that are and are not expropriations? Suppose South Africa were to<br />

follow the US in holding that any state-authored physical intrusion on<br />

privately held property, no matter how practically paltry or harmless,<br />

triggers an obligation to compensate. 17 That might give owners reason<br />

to cheer, but the cheering would not — on Roux’s reading of the<br />

doctrine according to FNB — be directed to the form or location of any<br />

line differentiating expropriations from mere deprivations. Take for<br />

example the US case of Loretto. 18 With state authorisation, a cable<br />

TV carrier strings a wire across the rooftop of Loretto’s multi-storey<br />

apartment building in Manhattan, also attaching a few clamps to the<br />

rooftop, the whole shebang occupying space for which no one has any<br />

conceivable use, interfering with no conceivable activity by anyone,<br />

and very possibly enhancing the value of the building by providing it<br />

with access to cable TV. South Africa, we are now imagining, will<br />

follow the US and treat <strong>this</strong> as a case of an imposition on property<br />

triggering a duty to pay just and equitable compensation in terms of<br />

FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3). How much might that be? Suppose it is any<br />

positive sum, no matter how small. On Roux’s understanding of the<br />

implications of the FNB opinion, the state’s failure to offer <strong>this</strong> sum<br />

through its authorising law will render that law arbitrary in terms of<br />

FC section 25(1), so the resulting invasion of privately owned space<br />

becomes an unconstitutional deprivation of property. The case is<br />

decided without ever reaching any question about how, if at all, to<br />

differentiate between deprivations that are and are not expropriations.<br />

Indeed, the FNB doctrine’s effect of suppressing that<br />

inquiry is seemingly a cause of concern on the part of Roux.<br />

The sum of what we have said so far is <strong>this</strong>: If the constitutional<br />

law of South Africa is in fact as reported and projected by Roux, then<br />

(a) neither an owner nor the state has reason to care about how or<br />

where any line differentiating mere deprivations from expropriations<br />

might be drawn (which is just what Roux says), and, in consequence,<br />

(b) Roux’s statements about how the choice among line-drawing<br />

methods affects the onerousness of the state’s obligations and the<br />

public-interest/private-interest balance are incorrect for South<br />

Africa. Those statements can possibly be correct — can possibly bite<br />

— only insofar as the vortex effect foreseen by Roux will not, in fact,<br />

be so all-embracing as Roux anticipates. It seems Roux must choose<br />

between withdrawing the statements and revising in some way his<br />

characterisation and projection of the doctrine according FNB.<br />

17<br />

See Loretto (n 13 above).<br />

18 As above.


Reply - Frank Michelman 291<br />

I suggest that Roux should choose withdrawal of the statements.<br />

Of course, what I really am driving at is that Roux should forbear from<br />

any intimation that the doctrine according to FNB is in any degree<br />

problematic or regrettable, in the specific respect that the doctrine<br />

idles for all time in South Africa the question of how and where to<br />

differentiate between (mere) deprivations and expropriations, and<br />

thus (as one might be tempted to add) deprives South Africa of for all<br />

time of the possibility of developing a regulatory-taking doctrine.<br />

I wish to be clear. There can be no doubting the importance of the<br />

issue of when, if ever, the state will be required to compensate<br />

owners for property-value impairment occasioned by regulatory, as<br />

opposed to acquisitive, activity. Any responsible jurisprudence of<br />

constitutional property must in due course address and resolve that<br />

issue. The question before us, though, is whether resolution<br />

necessarily must take the shape — or whether anything is lost if it does<br />

not take the shape — of a doctrine based on differentiation between<br />

categories of state-authored impositions on property, along the lines<br />

of ‘deprivation’/‘expropriation’ or ‘regulation’/‘taking’; the alternative<br />

being, as we have seen, to subject all impairments of property<br />

value, including all of those occasioned by regulation, to a<br />

requirement or provision for compensation in an amount sufficient to<br />

satisfy justice and equity, allowing that in many (or let us say most)<br />

cases of regulation that amount will be nil.<br />

We need to consider more closely what might be at stake, and for<br />

whom, in the choice about whether or not to introduce the idea of a<br />

constructive expropriation — of an expropriation by regulation or<br />

regulatory taking — into the constitutional jurisprudence of South<br />

Africa. We have seen already that rejection of such an idea need not<br />

— and in post-FNB South Africa it evidently will not (given the doctrine<br />

according to FNB according to Roux) — leave owners exposed to what<br />

courts may find to be unjust distributions of the real costs of socially<br />

desired or beneficial government operations, or strip the courts of an<br />

important means of ‘balanc[ing]’ the ‘individual’s interests in the use<br />

and enjoyment of property’ with ‘the state’s interest in acquiring<br />

it.’ 19 Or rather, to speak with utmost care, we could say <strong>this</strong> depends<br />

on exactly how we are going to define the idea of a regulatory-taking<br />

doctrine. Suppose the law in South Africa to be as follows: By force of<br />

FC section 25(1), any law authorising any sort of deprivation of<br />

property by the state, including but not limited to regulatory<br />

deprivations, must provide for due compensation to the deprived<br />

owner. I want to stress once more that the doctrine may allow that<br />

for ‘small’ regulatory deprivations — defined, say, as those not<br />

exceeding the magnitude of what owners must reasonably expect to<br />

19 Roux (n 1 above) 46-19.


292 Chapter 17<br />

bear without compensation in a market/regulatory society such as<br />

South Africa — the amount of just and equitable compensation will be<br />

nil.<br />

This body of law does not provide any occasion for a judge or other<br />

official ever to be called upon to differentiate deprivations that are<br />

also expropriations from those that are not (unless, to repeat, we<br />

have some wish to compensate owners in ‘expropriation’ cases in<br />

excess of what justice requires). However, it also does not leave<br />

owners exposed to unjust distribution of regulatory burdens owing to<br />

failure to compensate. In recognition of <strong>this</strong> latter effect of<br />

protecting property owners against excessive, uncompensated<br />

regulation, we might choose to call <strong>this</strong> body of law a ‘regulatory<br />

taking’ doctrine. Shall we, or shall we not? You choose, Reader.<br />

Should you choose ‘we shall’, then it will follow, at least for you, that<br />

South Africa has already chosen in favor of a regulatory-taking<br />

doctrine (it is not still an open question), because the body of law I<br />

have just described is precisely the one Roux says, and I agree, is<br />

prefigured by the opinion of the Constitutional Court in FNB.<br />

Will you, then, choose ‘no, that body of law is not a regulatorytaking<br />

doctrine’? What body of law would deserve that name, then? It<br />

must be a body that deviates from the doctrine according to FNB.<br />

There would seem to be two possibilities to consider. Here is the first,<br />

presented in the form of a scenario of propositions:<br />

(a) If some course of action by the state is classed as an ‘expropriation’<br />

in terms of FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3), it is thereby excluded from the<br />

class of ‘deprivations’ in terms of FC section 25(1). In other words,<br />

‘expropriation’ and ‘deprivation’ are mutually exclusive categories in<br />

terms of section 25.<br />

(b) Regarding deprivations, a deprivation-authorising law is ‘arbitrary’<br />

in terms of FC section 25(1), hence the deprivation is unconstitutional, if<br />

the law fails to make provision for due compensation to owners for their<br />

losses.<br />

(c) Regarding expropriations, they are, by force of FC sections 25(2)(b)/<br />

(3), unconstitutional unless accompanied by just and equitable<br />

compensation.<br />

(d) The measure of due compensation for a deprivation, in terms of the<br />

non-arbitrary requirement in FC section 25(1), differs from the measure<br />

of just and equitable compensation for an expropriation, in terms of the<br />

compensation requirement in FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3).<br />

(e) For typical impairments-by-regulation of property rights or values,<br />

the measure of due compensation in terms of FC section 25(1) is more<br />

suitable than the different measure of just and equitable compensation<br />

in terms of FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3). But for a subset of exceptionally<br />

severe (or whatever) impairments-by-regulation, the opposite is true.<br />

(f) But it follows from (a), (b), and (c) that an impairment-byregulation<br />

can trigger the constitutional requirement of a just and


Reply - Frank Michelman 293<br />

equitable compensation in terms of FC section 25(b)(2)/(3) only if<br />

classed as an expropriation, and thus — given (a) — not a deprivation.<br />

(g) Therefore, some method or test will be required for sorting out the<br />

full set of cases of impairment-by-regulation into those that fall<br />

respectively into the ‘deprivation’ and ‘expropriation’ subsets. That test<br />

or method is what we mean by speaking of a regulatory-taking doctrine.<br />

Do we draw from <strong>this</strong> propositional scenario any normatively<br />

compelling or urgent sense of need for a regulatory-taking doctrine? I<br />

cannot see how. In the first place, <strong>this</strong> scenario starts out from a<br />

premise — ‘(a)’ — that I have already contended is not sustainable.<br />

But the further point I now wish to make is that the whole thing pivots<br />

also on premise (d). If (d) is rejected, then (e) is false — since the two<br />

tests then are identical, neither can be more or less suitable than the<br />

other for a given context — and (g), therefore, is also false. But it<br />

would appear to be impossible to come up with a reason why (d)<br />

should be accepted, because to accept (d) would be to say that due<br />

compensation for a deprivation will at least sometimes be something<br />

other than a just and equitable compensation for that deprivation,<br />

which would be to make hash of our language. I conclude that it is not<br />

a serious objection against the doctrine according to FNB that it fails<br />

to sustain any need for a regulatory-taking doctrine by the foregoing<br />

propositional scenario.<br />

So now consider another:<br />

(p) A deprivation-authorising law is not ‘arbitrary’ in terms of FC<br />

section 25(1), if its only alleged vice or deficiency is failure to make<br />

provision for due compensation to owners for their losses.<br />

(q) Still, some impairments-by-regulation of property rights or values —<br />

by no means all of them — are so severe (or whatever) that the<br />

Constitution must be read to obligate the state to pay just and equitable<br />

compensation in these cases.<br />

(r) Given (p), the only clauses in FC section 25 that will have the<br />

desired effect are sections 25(2)(b)/(3).<br />

(s) But by the terms of FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3), those clauses come<br />

into play only where an ‘expropriation’ occurs.<br />

(t) It follows from the combination of (q), (r), and (s) that the<br />

Constitution must be read to classify as ‘expropriations’ some subset of<br />

the full set of impairments-by-regulation of property rights or values.<br />

(u) Some method or test, therefore, will be required for picking out the<br />

cases of impairment-by-regulation that fall into the ‘expropriation’<br />

subset. That test or method is what we mean by speaking of a<br />

regulatory-taking doctrine.<br />

We have already seen, following Roux, that the law according to FNB<br />

negates premise (p), thus enabling constitutional-legal protection of<br />

owners against unjust distribution of regulatory burdens without any<br />

need to differentiate a subset of ‘expropriations’ out of the full set of<br />

‘deprivations’. South African constitutional law thus fails to occasion


294 Chapter 17<br />

or sustain a regulatory-taking doctrine under our second propositional<br />

scenario. Is <strong>this</strong> in any degree a regrettable result? We cannot call it<br />

so, except insofar as we stand ready to pronounce the negation of (p)<br />

in some degree regrettable. But what might be regrettable about that<br />

negation?<br />

There doesn’t seem to be anything normatively wrong with it.<br />

Rejection of (p) allows the use of the non-arbitrary-law requirement<br />

in FC section 25(1) to protect owners against unjust distribution of the<br />

burdens cast by regulatory schemes that presumably are designed to<br />

benefit society as a whole. That cannot be thought objectionable. But<br />

how about a more formalistic objection: By reading FC section 25(1)<br />

in that manner you render idle, or a dead letter, the express and<br />

somewhat elaborate provisions for compensation contained in FC<br />

sections 25(2)(b)/(3) — in a word, a ‘vortex’ objection. Without<br />

doubting that an objection of <strong>this</strong> kind may sometimes carry weight,<br />

let us ask whether it can possibly be weighty in <strong>this</strong> instance.<br />

I do not see how it can. There are times, after all — and they are<br />

not rarities — when nothing less will satisfy the state or its need than<br />

a complete, overt removal from the erstwhile owner of the total<br />

Hohfeldian package of ownership entitlements, so that Mr or Ms<br />

Erstwhile or Erstwhile Ltd ends up with literally nothing: no right to<br />

exclude, no privilege of entry or use, no power to reallocate<br />

entitlements, no immunity against reallocations by others. You do not<br />

need any sort of ‘constructive’ expropriation doctrine in order to<br />

fasten the compensation duty spelled out by FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3)<br />

onto these cases of (so to speak) undisguised real expropriation. And<br />

of course the set of undisguised real expropriation cases I have just<br />

described is of major potential importance in South Africa, for it<br />

includes (but surely is not limited to) possible instances in which the<br />

successful prosecution of land restitution and land redistribution<br />

would require total divestiture by the state of extant titles to land,<br />

on terms of compensation set not by the owner but, ultimately, by a<br />

judicial umpire applying standards in keeping with those laid down by<br />

FC section 25(3). FC sections 25(2)(b)/(3) have very important work<br />

to do, even in the absence from South African constitutional<br />

jurisprudence of any notion of taking-by-regulation. By no means can<br />

FNB, on any reading, be said to have put those sections out of<br />

business.<br />

But consider, then, <strong>this</strong> further objection. Rather than applying<br />

FC section 25(1) to decide contextually, case by case, whether (to use<br />

Roux’s formulation) ‘the impact on the [right holder is] so severe as<br />

to require payment of just compensation’, it would be better — you<br />

the reader might think — to have some more categorical rule in play<br />

for sorting the full set of regulatory cases into those in which<br />

compensation is or is not to be an issue; better, that is, from the


Reply - Frank Michelman 295<br />

standpoint of adjudicative economy, or of enabling foresight by state<br />

and other parties of the probably legal consequences of their actions,<br />

or of sustaining confidence in the like treatment of like cases. You<br />

might prefer a categorical-rule sort of doctrine here because, in <strong>this</strong><br />

context, anyway, you like rules better than standards. That is fine by<br />

me. But it will not provide you with a potent line of objection to the<br />

doctrine according to FNB. The FNB doctrine leaves all the room in the<br />

world for the development, over time, of categorical sub-rules for<br />

sorting cases into types for which a failure to provide for<br />

compensation will or will not be counted arbitrary in terms of section<br />

25(1).<br />

The decision in FNB itself shows how. Henceforward, any total and<br />

permanent dispossession of a corporeal asset from a nominal owner,<br />

even if only of a security title and not a beneficial interest, is highly<br />

constitutionally suspect if the seizure is occasioned by a default for<br />

which the owner is not culpable. That is already a categorical subrule,<br />

and quite a few more budding categorical sub-rules can easily be<br />

extracted from it. Roux correctly points out that the emergence of a<br />

fully useful stock of more-or-less ‘formulaic applications’ of the nonarbitrary<br />

test must necessarily await decision of ‘many’ more cases. 20<br />

He thus states what is generally and inescapably true of judicial<br />

applications of any clause in a constitutional bill of rights. The clause<br />

on which the US regulatory-taking doctrine is founded provides a<br />

highly pertinent example. 21 So far as one can see from here, the subrule<br />

developing process under FC section 25(1) will be no different in<br />

general character from that by which courts in the US have sought<br />

(pretty much vainly, I must add) 22 to develop robust, quasicategorical<br />

sub-rules for sorting out those regulatory impacts that are<br />

and are not ‘takings’, under a constitutional clause that in terms<br />

prohibits uncompensated takings of property.<br />

It remains to discuss one further respect in which the presence or<br />

absence of the notion of a regulatory taking may matter to the state<br />

and other parties. Insofar as excessively onerous regulation, under an<br />

authorising law that fails to provide for due compensation, is<br />

unconstitutional in South Africa in terms of the non-arbitrary-law<br />

requirement of FC section 25(1), the obvious consequence, for the<br />

future, of a judicial finding of violation is nullification of the<br />

offending regulation. 23 But insofar as excessively onerous regulation<br />

is classified as an ‘expropriation’ covered by FC section 25(2), the<br />

20 Roux (n 1 above) 46-24.<br />

21 See US Constitution 5th amendment: ‘... nor shall private property be taken for<br />

public use, without just compensation’.<br />

22 See FI Michelman ‘Takings, 1987’ (1988) 88 Columbia Law Review 1600 1625-1629.<br />

23 The state may or may not also be held liable for constitutional damages to cover<br />

past losses imposed by the unconstitutional regulation, but here I focus strictly on<br />

the future.


296 Chapter 17<br />

expropriation may seem to be executed at the first instant of<br />

implementation of the offending regulation, thus bringing into play at<br />

that instant an irrevocable obligation of the state to compensate for<br />

the full value of a permanent encumbrance on the owner’s use and<br />

enjoyment. (Compare ‘you broke it, you bought it’, uttered by an<br />

antique shop proprietor to a clumsy shopper.) 24 If that is the view we<br />

would take, then the presence of a regulatory-taking doctrine in<br />

South African law would make a real difference in outcome in some<br />

cases. 25 Would <strong>this</strong> be a normatively desirable consequence?<br />

The consequence is surely troublesome from the standpoint of the<br />

state. The state then finds itself exposed to the risk of very<br />

substantial, unexpected monetary liabilities for purchases that it<br />

never meant to make nor would deliberately have chosen to make,<br />

had it known that its action would be treated by the law as a<br />

purchase, as opposed to a lawful exercise of a general power to<br />

regulate. There is, from a social-transformative standpoint, no<br />

possible advantage to the state or to the public interest in such an<br />

exposure. 26 A likely and, in the US, an oft-reported consequence of<br />

24 As Roux writes (Roux (n 1 above) 46-29), under the law according to FNB:<br />

The only situation in which a claimant might have an interest in<br />

persuading the court that the law being challenged provides for the<br />

expropriation of property rather than the arbitrary deprivation of<br />

property is where it wishes the court to uphold the law and to read in a<br />

requirement that the state pay [just and equitable] compensation. ...<br />

Where ... the purpose of the challenge is to have the law struck down, a<br />

24 finding that the law provides for the arbitrary deprivation of property is as<br />

As Roux<br />

good<br />

writes<br />

as (from<br />

(Roux<br />

the<br />

(n<br />

claimant’s<br />

1 above) 46-29),<br />

perspective)<br />

under the<br />

a finding<br />

law according<br />

that the<br />

to<br />

law<br />

FNB:<br />

provides<br />

for The expropriation only situation and in fails which to meet a claimant the two additional might have requirements an interest set by in<br />

s persuading 25(2). the court that the law being challenged provides for the<br />

See also<br />

expropriation<br />

Roux (n 1 above)<br />

of property<br />

46-20.<br />

rather than the arbitrary deprivation of<br />

25 Relevant<br />

property<br />

US doctrine<br />

is where<br />

shows<br />

it wishes<br />

that<br />

the<br />

numerous<br />

court to<br />

complications<br />

uphold the law<br />

lie<br />

and<br />

down<br />

to read<br />

<strong>this</strong> path<br />

in a<br />

of<br />

reasoning.<br />

requirement<br />

Suppose,<br />

that<br />

for<br />

the<br />

example,<br />

state pay<br />

that<br />

[just<br />

the<br />

and<br />

state<br />

equitable]<br />

imposes a<br />

compensation.<br />

temporary but<br />

...<br />

total<br />

moratorium<br />

Where ...<br />

on<br />

the<br />

development<br />

purpose of<br />

of<br />

the<br />

land<br />

challenge<br />

in an<br />

is<br />

ecologically<br />

to have the<br />

sensitive<br />

law struck<br />

zone,<br />

down,<br />

pending<br />

a<br />

completion<br />

finding<br />

of<br />

that<br />

a less<br />

the<br />

restrictive<br />

law provides<br />

set of<br />

for<br />

permanent<br />

the arbitrary<br />

regulations.<br />

deprivation<br />

Is the<br />

of property<br />

result (a)<br />

is<br />

zero<br />

liability<br />

as good<br />

to compensate,<br />

as (from the<br />

or (b)<br />

claimant’s<br />

liability to<br />

perspective)<br />

compensate<br />

a<br />

but<br />

finding<br />

only for<br />

that<br />

the<br />

the<br />

temporary<br />

law<br />

loss of<br />

provides<br />

use, or<br />

for<br />

(c) liability<br />

expropriation<br />

to compensate<br />

and fails<br />

for<br />

to<br />

permanent<br />

meet the<br />

loss<br />

two<br />

of use?<br />

additional<br />

See First<br />

English<br />

requirements<br />

Church v<br />

set<br />

County<br />

by s 25(2).<br />

of Los Angeles 482 US 304 (1987); Tahoe-Sierra<br />

See Preservation also Roux Council, (n 1 above) Inc. 46-20. v Tahoe Regional Planning Agency 535 US 302 (2002).<br />

26 25 Relevant AJ der US Walt, doctrine whom shows Roux that cites numerous on <strong>this</strong> point, complications adduces lie instances down <strong>this</strong> in which path of a<br />

reasoning. land-reform Suppose, program for cast example, in non-acquisitive, that the state regulatory imposes form a temporary (say, a somewhat but total<br />

moratorium drastically pro-tenant on development revision of of land the law in an of ecologically eviction) can sensitive be saved zone, from pending judicial<br />

completion nullification of under a less sec restrictive 25 if, but set only of permanent if, the court regulations. has the power Is the to result treat the (a) zero case<br />

liability as one for to which compensate, it can order (b) some liability amount to compensate of compensation. but only See for AJ the van temporary der Walt<br />

loss (n 3 of above) use, 235-36. or (c) liability From the to point compensate of view for of the permanent state and loss the of transformationminded,<br />

Church such a regime v County seems of clearly Los Angeles less to be 482 preferred US 304 than (1987); one Tahoe-Sierra<br />

in which the<br />

use? See First<br />

English<br />

Preservation court is powerless Council, to Inc. order v Tahoe compensation, Regional Planning but simply Agency nullifies 535 US the 302 regulatory (2002).<br />

26 program in the absence of constitutionally requisite compensation. Or perhaps a<br />

court might also indicate in its judgment the form and amount of compensation<br />

that could save the program if provided, along the lines of the German idea of<br />

‘equalisation payments’ — see Van der Walt (n 3 above) 222-23 — leaving the<br />

government to choose between its options (ie, to desist or to pay). Or a court<br />

might even see fit to suspend its order of nullification for a time, while<br />

government ponders its alternatives. The key requirement, in my view, is that


Reply - Frank Michelman 297<br />

creating it is timidity on the part of regulatory officials in approaching<br />

the outer bounds — never fully certain, with or without quasicategorical<br />

sub-rules in the picture, given the human composition of<br />

the judiciary — of constitutionally permitted regulation-withoutcompensation.<br />

Officials of regulatory agencies make <strong>this</strong> perhaps<br />

their chief complaint against regulatory-taking doctrine as it exists in<br />

the US, and many US observers suspect it is <strong>this</strong> expected in terrorem,<br />

state-activity-suppressing effect of a regulatory-taking doctrine — as<br />

opposed to a concern about individualised injustice to wiped-out<br />

landowners — that motivates the relentless push of libertarianminded,<br />

US economic conservatives in favor such a doctrine.<br />

These are worries that I should think progressive-minded South<br />

Africans would take to heart. They might accordingly congratulate the<br />

doctrine according to FNB for finding a textually respectable way to<br />

ensure justice to owners without steering into <strong>this</strong> sort of trouble —<br />

and also, so far as I can see, without any cost at all to the pursuit of<br />

constitutional justice in South Africa, for property owners and for all.<br />

3 Making sense of FC section 25(1)’s internal and external<br />

limitations<br />

I now wish to introduce a further reason for endorsing the feature in<br />

the doctrine according to FNB that I have so far sought to vindicate<br />

against certain possible worries that I have associated with Roux’s<br />

texts. That feature is the deployment of the non-arbitrary-law<br />

requirement in FC section 25(1) in such a way as to have it sweep in<br />

(or, if you like, anticipate or preempt) the just-and-equitablecompensation<br />

requirement imposed by FC section 25(2) on that subset<br />

of property limitations that qualify as expropriations.<br />

My further thought is prompted by Roux’s observation, in his<br />

CLoSA chapter, that an effect of the FNB doctrine’s sweeping<br />

construction of the FC section 25(1) requirement is to foreclose, for<br />

property clause cases, the second stage in the established,<br />

‘traditional two-stage inquiry’ for testing the constitutionality of laws<br />

vis-à-vis the protections in the Bill of Rights. 27 I think <strong>this</strong> is slightly<br />

off the mark, and fortunately so for South African constitutional law.<br />

I proceed to explain.<br />

government always gets to choose whether or not to desist, once a court has said<br />

the program cannot go forward without compensation. A ‘constructive<br />

expropriation’ or ‘regulatory taking’ doctrine on the US model jeopardises that<br />

assurance, and so is to be avoided.<br />

27<br />

Roux (n 1 above) 46-3. See also Van der Walt (n 3 above) 36-37.


298 Chapter 17<br />

According to a reading of FC section 25 once proposed by AJ van<br />

der Walt but rejected by the Constitutional Court in FNB, 28 any law<br />

limiting a property interest, or authorising such a limitation, would<br />

have to pass (at least) a double inspection. First, the law would have<br />

to meet FC section 25(1)’s ‘internal’ requirement of being nonarbitrary.<br />

29 Second, it would have to meet FC section 36(1)’s<br />

‘external’ requirement of being reasonable and justifiable (etc). Had<br />

Van der Walt’s proposal been accepted, it would have raised the<br />

following puzzle.<br />

‘Not arbitrary’ in FC section 25(1) and ‘reasonable’ in FC section<br />

36(1) appear to name stronger and weaker versions of the same sort<br />

of test. 30 To say it a little differently, the two terms seem to name<br />

different points on the same scale or axis of appraisal of a law, the<br />

one by which we measure the acceptability of a burdensome means<br />

by assessing its utility, as compared with less burdensome or<br />

otherwise less noxious alternatives, in terms of the ends (and their<br />

weights) for which the means is said to be required. Let us call <strong>this</strong><br />

the axis of ‘mean/ends inspection’. Let the zero point lie at the origin<br />

of the axis, and let it represent a judgment that the law in question<br />

is as wildly arbitrary or unreasonable, in means/ends-inspection<br />

terms, as any law can be imagined to be: If the apparent objective<br />

(‘end’) is within the state’s legitimate pursuit at all, there are a<br />

thousand obviously more effective, less costly or noxious ways to get<br />

at it.<br />

A point near the origin represents a judgment that the law, if<br />

arguably rational by a hair, is still quite plainly not what you would<br />

expect of a reasonably well-informed and considerate lawmaker. A<br />

point quite distant from the origin represents a judgment that the law<br />

stands up well against a robust proportionality test.<br />

Now, as between ‘not arbitrary’ (FC section 25(1)) and ‘reasonable’<br />

(FC section 36(1)), either those two terms name the same point<br />

on the means/ends-inspection axis, or one of them names a point that<br />

is more distant, while the other names a point that is less distant,<br />

from the origin. Any way you cut it, the prospects for double<br />

inspection appear to collapse. If the two terms name the same point,<br />

double inspection is redundant. If the FC section 25(1) test is weaker<br />

— nearer the origin — than the FC section 36(1) test, one need never<br />

trouble to apply the FC section 25(1) test, because the only question<br />

that finally matters is whether the law can pass the more demanding,<br />

28 See n 4 above and text accompanying; FNB (n 5 above) para 70.<br />

29<br />

I am here setting aside cases involving facial expropriations, where the internal<br />

requirements of sec 25(2) would also come into play.<br />

30 Inclusion in <strong>this</strong> analysis of FC sec 36(1)’s additional demand for justifiability in an<br />

open and democratic society (etc.) would only complicate the exposition without<br />

altering the analysis.


Reply - Frank Michelman 299<br />

FC section 36(1) inspection, with the onus on the party supporting<br />

constitutionality (the state). If the section 25(1) test is stronger —<br />

further from the axis — then any law that passes muster under FC<br />

section 25(1) is a fortiori cleared under FC section 36(1). 31 There is<br />

no possible case in which a meaningful double inspection can occur.<br />

The FNB court’s rejection of Van der Walt’s proposal reconfigures<br />

our puzzle, but does not do away with it. We now have a ‘truncated’<br />

property right. 32 FC section 25(1) gives you a right not to be deprived<br />

of property in the absence of a non-arbitrary, authorising law, and<br />

that’s all. 33 And even that truncated right — like all rights under the<br />

Bill of Rights — is subject to limitation by law that meets the test of<br />

FC section 36(1). 34 A law authorising deprivations of property, found<br />

arbitrary in terms of FC section 25(1), may nevertheless be upheld as<br />

constitutional if found reasonable in terms of FC section 36(1). 35 But<br />

<strong>this</strong>, as Roux observes, appears to make no sense, or to posit what<br />

seems a virtual impossibility: To wit, that a law can be simultaneously<br />

arbitrary and reasonable. The prospect of a two-stage inquiry thus<br />

appears to collapse for property clause cases.<br />

Notice, however, that <strong>this</strong> holds true only on the assumption I<br />

introduced above, that ‘(non)arbitrary’ and ‘reasonable’ both name<br />

points somewhere along the same axis of appraisal of laws — the one<br />

I have been calling the axis of means/ends inspection. If<br />

‘(non)arbitrary’ were construed to refer to some quality in a law quite<br />

plainly distinct from its location along that axis, then no collapse<br />

would occur. A law that is arbitrary in that sense might nevertheless<br />

sometimes be upheld as reasonable in terms of FC section 36(1); we<br />

would have to look and see in each case. (To make my point here<br />

crystal-clear, suppose for a moment that when we look up ‘arbitrary’<br />

in the legal dictionary, we unexpectedly find that <strong>this</strong> word means<br />

‘enacted prior to 27 April, 1994’. It would not, then, be nonsense to<br />

offer the state the opportunity to rescue earlier-enacted (‘arbitrary’)<br />

31 But (you may ask) what about the possible effect of onus placement? Under the<br />

rules generally governing the two-stage inquiry, the claimant bears the onus on<br />

the sec 25(1) test, while the state bears the onus on the sec 36(1) test. It thus<br />

seems theoretically possible that the claimant could fail to carry the onus of<br />

showing that the law is arbitrary in terms of sec 25(1), while the state might also<br />

fail to carry the onus of showing that the law is reasonable in terms of sec 36(1),<br />

even if sec 36(1)’s demand for a reasonable law is considered weaker — closer to<br />

the origin of the mean/ends-inspection axis — than sec 25(1)’s demand for a<br />

nonarbitrary law. (Maybe, for example, the state wholly fails to lead evidence or<br />

offer argument on the point.) What would you say is the practical likelihood of<br />

such a combination of judicial findings?<br />

32<br />

See n 3 above and accompanying text.<br />

33 I continue to ignore cases of expropriation, for the sake of expository simplicity.<br />

34 See FNB (n 5 above) paras 46, 59 and 110.<br />

35<br />

Again I set aside sec 36(1)’s additional requirement of justifiability etc., as<br />

needlessly complicating the exposition.


300 Chapter 17<br />

laws from constitutional perdition, by showing that they are<br />

nevertheless reasonable and justifiable etc.)<br />

Now let us consider the following laws:<br />

- A law imposes unpaid-tax liability on a person who owns a security<br />

title in goods in respect of which the tax is owed, but who is in no way<br />

culpable for the tax-generating transaction or for the non-payment of<br />

the tax. 36<br />

- A law imposes penalties on landowners for utility-rate arrears, where<br />

the services were furnished to and at the behest of unlawful occupiers,<br />

whose occupancy and whose consumption of services the owner has<br />

neither invited nor condoned. 37<br />

Those two examples will ring a bell with South African constitutional<br />

lawyers. Here is a third from the USA:<br />

- A law requires landlords to lease at sharply curtailed, below-market<br />

rents to tenants in conditions of special economic hardship. 38<br />

None of these laws is notably short on means-ends rationality, or<br />

appears close to arbitrary in that sense. Each of the laws directly and<br />

effectively serves an obviously permissible, respectable, and weighty<br />

goal. The first two produce revenues for a public fisc that is never in<br />

these days large enough to permit the state to carry out adequately<br />

all of its basic functions and commitments. The third helps ensure<br />

that everyone is decently sheltered, including those who currently<br />

lack the means to pay market price for even the cheapest available<br />

housing. Yet all three laws also share, at least arguably, a certain sort<br />

of vice.<br />

This arguable vice lies not in any overall disproportion between<br />

the magnitude or quality of private burdens imposed and the worth of<br />

public benefits secured (where ‘quality’ of burden would refer to<br />

something like ‘invades inner-core privacy’ or ‘limits free exercise of<br />

religion’). The arguable vice in these laws lies rather in a seemingly<br />

unequal and unfair distribution of burdens among the members of<br />

society. All of these laws pursue undoubtedly worthy and legitimate<br />

goals, by means that are instrumentally well attuned to those goals<br />

and would be unobjectionable, did they not leave burdens distributed<br />

in ways that prima facie look wrong by any fair measure of justice in<br />

the distribution of burdens. (Why should it be the bank who makes<br />

good the importer’s tax default in FNB, or the victim of illegal<br />

36 See FNB (n 5 above).<br />

37<br />

See Mkontwana v Nelson Mandela Metropolitan Municipality; Bissett & Others v<br />

Buffalo City Municipality; Transfer Rights Action Campaign & Others v Member of<br />

the Executive Council for Local Government and Housing, Gauteng & Others 2005<br />

1 SA 530 (CC), 2005 2 BCLR 150 (CC).<br />

38 Pennell v City of San Jose 485 US 1 (1988).


Reply - Frank Michelman 301<br />

occupiers who is penalised for nonpayment for services she never<br />

ordered or consumed in Mkontwana, or the class — in Pennell — of<br />

rental-housing suppliers (as opposed to doctors, pharmacists, food<br />

and clothing purveyors, and the taxpayers at large) that is required to<br />

pay specially for fulfillment of the basic need of the destitute?) 39<br />

I don’t thus mean to be anticipating a final decision of<br />

unconstitutionality for any of the laws in question. To the contrary,<br />

my suggestion is that the prima facie, normatively dubious<br />

distribution of burdens that is apparent on the face of all these laws<br />

might be a feature that renders them all ‘arbitrary’ in terms of FC<br />

section 25(1) — thus ‘limitations’ of the truncated property right for<br />

purposes of the first stage of the traditional two-stage inquiry — while<br />

saving the possibility of rescuing any or all of them from<br />

unconstitutionality by showing them, at the second stage, to be<br />

nevertheless reasonable and justifiable in terms of section 36(1). To<br />

illustrate: The FC 36(1) inquiry might (or might not) save our second<br />

law though reasoning along lines such as those suggested by Justice<br />

O’Regan in Mkontwana 40 — perhaps assisted by argument that the law<br />

as written gives landowners socially beneficial incentives to work<br />

harder at watching out for illegal occupation and notifying public<br />

authorities promptly when such occupation occurs.<br />

The suggestion, in sum, would be that a deprivation-authorising<br />

law should be held ‘arbitrary’ in terms of FC section 25(1) if — and<br />

only if — the law casts its burdens according to an apparently arbitrary<br />

or unfair pattern, judging generously from the standpoint of the<br />

complainant (as always in the two-stage inquiry), prior to any focused<br />

justificational inquiry. Let us now consider what would be gained and<br />

what would be lost by adopting that suggestion, in place of the<br />

exegesis of ‘arbitrary’ now found in the law according to FNB.<br />

39 See Scalia J’s dissent in Pennell (n 37 above) 21-22<br />

40<br />

n 36 above para 115:<br />

[I]t is important to bear in mind that it would be difficult to narrow the<br />

scope of section 118(1). Section 118(1) is a simple procedure which<br />

requires that in all cases a registrar of deeds may not effect the transfer<br />

of immovable property without a certificate from the municipality<br />

confirming that all consumption charges and rates incurred in respect of<br />

that property in the preceding two years have been paid. It is accordingly<br />

the municipality that issues the certificate. It will not always be clear to<br />

a municipality, from its records, who has actually consumed the services<br />

on that property for the previous two years, nor will it be clear whether<br />

that person is the owner or a tenant or an unlawful occupier. Limiting the<br />

terms of the certificate to consumption charges incurred by only<br />

particular classes of occupier may create substantial difficulties for the<br />

efficient conveyancing of the property, as the municipality may not be in<br />

a position to determine the class of occupier that in fact incurred the<br />

consumption charges. This practical difficulty needs to be borne in mind<br />

in determining the sufficiency of the reason for [the failure to except<br />

illegal-occupier cases from the coverage if s 118(1)].


302 Chapter 17<br />

The most obvious gain would be in putting the two-stage inquiry<br />

unquestionably back on track in property clause cases. That counts as<br />

a gain, other things remaining equal, if only because it redeems the<br />

symmetry — or call it legibility — of the constitutional corpus juris of<br />

South Africa. But of course that is not all. The doctrine of the twostage<br />

inquiry presumably has something going for it normatively (or<br />

else why have we got it?). Commitment to the two-stage inquiry is a<br />

loud and clear token of the shift from a culture of authority to a<br />

culture of justification. Protections set forth in the Bill of Rights are<br />

to be given a generous initial scope, with the state then permitted —<br />

but also required! — to explain persuasively to a court what good<br />

reasons (if any) it has for limiting the rights thus generously defined.<br />

Something of value is lost if the Constitutional Court finds itself forced<br />

to yield on <strong>this</strong> simple precept for any clause in the Bill of Rights.<br />

But surely, you will protest, the possible cure I have suggested for<br />

<strong>this</strong> symbolic loss (for is it really anything more?) would be like<br />

throwing out the baby with the bath water. ‘Remember’, you will say:<br />

‘We are dealing here with a truncated property right. If FC section<br />

25(1) does not mandate means/ends inspection for deprivationauthorising<br />

laws, nothing does, because FC section 36(1) never<br />

fastens its teeth on a law passing muster under FC section 25.’ And<br />

that, you say, makes confinement of ‘arbitrary’ to cases of prima<br />

facie maldistribution of burdens unacceptable.<br />

Right you are. Such confinement would open up the very pitfall<br />

that Van der Walt’s rejected double-inspection proposal wisely<br />

foresaw and was meant to avoid. Once the Constitutional Court has<br />

opted in favor the truncated-right construal of FC section 25, it<br />

cannot also so confine the meaning of ‘arbitrary’ in FC section 25(1)<br />

as to forgo entirely a means/ends inspection of deprivationauthorising<br />

laws. 41 That, however, does not totally defeat my point.<br />

As long as some laws that pass muster on the axis of means/ends<br />

inspection will still be found to fail FC section 25(1) inspection, on the<br />

sole ground of maldistribution of burdens (consider again my three<br />

illustrative laws, above), the two-stage inquiry is still in business<br />

under the Property Clause. As I read the law according to FNB, it is<br />

receptive to <strong>this</strong> very understanding. And that, I say again, is a good<br />

thing.<br />

41<br />

This assumes the Court would not wish to saddle the drafters with the design of<br />

entirely precluding means/ends inspection for laws impinging on property but on<br />

no other constitutionally protected interest. Van der Walt’s initial proposal<br />

proceeded from a well-considered reluctance to impute such a design to the<br />

drafters. Van der Walt (n 3 above).


18<br />

SOCIO-ECONOMIC<br />

RIGHTS: REVISITING<br />

THE REASONABLENESS<br />

REVIEW/MINIMUM<br />

CORE DEBATE<br />

Sandra Liebenberg*<br />

1 Introduction<br />

In its landmark decisions in Soobramoney, 1 Grootboom, 2 Treatment<br />

Action Campaign, 3 and Khosa, 4 the Constitutional Court adopted a<br />

model of reasonableness review for assessing whether the state has<br />

complied with the positive duties imposed by the socio-economic<br />

rights in FC sections 26 and 27. In doing so, it has rejected the<br />

argument urged by the amici curiae in Grootboom and TAC that FC<br />

sections 26 and 27 impose a minimum core obligation on the state to<br />

ensure that everyone has access to essential basic levels of the<br />

* I acknowledge, with appreciation, the comments on a draft version of <strong>this</strong> chapter<br />

received from Katharine Young and Inga Winkler. This chapter is based on material<br />

in my forthcoming book Adjudicating socio-economic rights under a<br />

transformative constitution (2008) which is supported by a grant from the<br />

National Research Foundation (NRF). Any opinion, findings and conclusions or<br />

recommendations expressed in <strong>this</strong> material are those of the author and therefore<br />

the NRF does not accept any liability in regard thereto.<br />

1 Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1998 1 SA 765 (CC), 1997 12<br />

BCLR 1696 (CC).<br />

2<br />

Government of the RSA v Grootboom 2001 1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC).<br />

3 Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 5 SA 721 (CC), 2002 10<br />

BCLR 1033 (CC).<br />

4<br />

Khosa v Minister of Social Development, Mahlaule v Minister of Social<br />

Development 2004 6 SA 505 (CC), 2004 6 BCLR 569 (CC).<br />

303


304 Chapter 18<br />

relevant rights. 5 The furthest the Court was prepared to go was to<br />

hold that, where the evidence in a particular case revealed that it was<br />

appropriate, regard could be had to the content of a minimum core<br />

obligation in evaluating the reasonableness of the state’s measures. 6<br />

Thus a litigant could not rely directly on the non-fulfilment of a<br />

minimum core obligation imposed by the rights in FC sections 26 and<br />

27 to secure immediate relief. She could, at most, rely on such an<br />

obligation to support her arguments that the measures adopted by the<br />

state were unreasonable in the circumstances. A finding of unreasonableness<br />

could, in general, not be used to elicit benefits for an<br />

individual or a class of individuals.<br />

The Court’s objections to direct reliance on a concept of minimum<br />

core obligations were basically threefold: the difficulty of defining<br />

the content of minimum core obligations; a concern that any<br />

definition would not reflect the diversity of needs of differently<br />

placed groups; and an incompatibility with the institutional roles and<br />

competencies of the courts. 7<br />

In <strong>this</strong> essay, I evaluate the model of reasonableness review for<br />

positive socio-economic rights claims and compare it to an approach<br />

based on the concept of minimum core obligations. The focus will be<br />

on cases in which people claim access to the services and resources<br />

referred to in FC sections 26 and 27.<br />

Any such evaluation must take into account the critical role of<br />

socio-economic rights in advancing the transformative commitments<br />

and values of the Constitution. Klare describes transformative<br />

constitutionalism as ‘a long term project of constitutional enactment,<br />

interpretation, and enforcement committed (not in isolation, of<br />

course, but in a historical context of conducive political<br />

developments) to transforming a country’s political and social<br />

institutions and power relationships in a democratic, participatory,<br />

5 This concept is endorsed by the UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural<br />

Rights (UNCESCR) which supervises states parties’ obligations under the<br />

International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966). See, for<br />

example, ‘General Comment 3: The nature of states parties obligations (art 2(1)<br />

of the Covenant)’ UN doc E/1991/23 (1990) para 10; ‘General Comment 14: The<br />

right to the highest attainable standard of health (art 12 of the Covenant)’ UN<br />

doc E/C.12/2000/4 (2000) para 43; ‘General Comment 15: The right to water<br />

(arts 11 & 12 of the Covenant)’ UN doc E/C. 12/2002/11 (2002) para 37.<br />

6 See Grootboom (n 2 above) para 33; Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above) para<br />

34.<br />

7<br />

See Grootboom (n 2 above) paras 27-33; Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above)<br />

paras 26-39.


Sandra Liebenberg 305<br />

and egalitarian direction.’ 8 The preamble of the Final Constitution<br />

affirms that it was adopted so as to establish, amongst other goals, a<br />

society based on social justice and an improvement in the quality of<br />

life of all. When interpreting socio-economic rights, the courts are<br />

obliged to ‘promote the values that underlie an open and democratic<br />

society based on human dignity, equality and freedom.’ 9 The<br />

realisation of socio-economic rights is integral to <strong>this</strong> vision of a<br />

transformed society.<br />

2 What does ‘reasonableness review’ mean in the context<br />

of socio-economic rights claims?<br />

In reviewing positive socio-economic rights claims, the central<br />

question that the Court asks is whether the means chosen are<br />

reasonably capable of facilitating the realisation of the socioeconomic<br />

rights in question. 10 The Court’s approach is designed to<br />

allow government a margin of discretion relating to the specific policy<br />

choices adopted to give effect to socio-economic rights:<br />

A Court considering reasonableness will not enquire whether other more<br />

desirable or favourable measures could have been adopted, or whether<br />

public money could have been better spent. The question would be<br />

whether the measures that have been adopted are reasonable. It is<br />

necessary to recognise that a wide range of possible measures could be<br />

adopted by the state to meet its obligations. Many of these would meet<br />

the requirement of reasonableness. Once it is shown that the measures<br />

do so, <strong>this</strong> requirement is met. 11<br />

8 K Klare ‘Legal culture and transformative constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 146; C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Facing the<br />

challenges of transformation: Difficulties in the development of an indigenous<br />

jurisprudence of equality’ (1998) 14 South African Journal on Human Rights 248;<br />

M Pieterse ‘What do we mean when we talk about transformative<br />

constitutionalism?’ (2005) 20 South African Publiekreg/Public Law 155; S<br />

8 Liebenberg ‘Needs, rights and transformation: Adjudicating social rights’ (2005) 1<br />

Stellenbosch<br />

K Klare ‘Legal<br />

Law<br />

culture<br />

Review<br />

and<br />

1; P<br />

transformative<br />

Langa ‘Transformative<br />

constitutionalism’<br />

constitutionalism’<br />

(1998) 14<br />

(2006)<br />

South<br />

3<br />

Stellenbosch<br />

African Journal<br />

Law<br />

on<br />

Review<br />

Human<br />

351.<br />

Rights<br />

See further<br />

146; C<br />

the<br />

Albertyn<br />

cases of<br />

&<br />

S<br />

B<br />

v Makwanyane<br />

Goldblatt ‘Facing<br />

1995 3<br />

the<br />

SA<br />

391<br />

challenges<br />

(CC), 1995<br />

of transformation:<br />

6 BCLR 665 (CC)<br />

Difficulties<br />

para 262; Bato<br />

in the<br />

Star<br />

development<br />

Fishing (Pty)<br />

of<br />

Ltd<br />

an<br />

v Minister<br />

indigenous<br />

of<br />

Environmental<br />

jurisprudence of<br />

Affairs<br />

equality’<br />

and<br />

(1998)<br />

Tourism<br />

14<br />

2004<br />

South<br />

4<br />

African<br />

SA 490<br />

Journal<br />

(CC), 2004<br />

on Human<br />

7 BCLR<br />

Rights<br />

687<br />

248;<br />

(CC)<br />

paras<br />

M Pieterse<br />

73-74; Minister<br />

‘What<br />

of<br />

do<br />

Finance<br />

we mean<br />

v Van Heerden<br />

when we<br />

2004<br />

talk<br />

6 SA 121<br />

about<br />

(CC),<br />

transformative<br />

2004 11 BCLR<br />

1125<br />

constitutionalism?’<br />

(CC) para 142;<br />

(2005)<br />

Rates Action<br />

20 South<br />

Group<br />

African<br />

v City of<br />

Publiekreg/Public<br />

Cape Town 2004 12<br />

Law<br />

BCLR<br />

155;<br />

1328<br />

S<br />

(C)<br />

Liebenberg<br />

para 100.<br />

‘Needs, rights and transformation: Adjudicating social rights’ (2005) 1<br />

9 Sec<br />

Stellenbosch<br />

39(1)(a). See<br />

Law<br />

also<br />

Review<br />

Soobramoney<br />

1; P Langa<br />

(n<br />

‘Transformative<br />

1 above) para 8.<br />

constitutionalism’ (2006) 3<br />

10 Grootboom<br />

Stellenbosch<br />

(n<br />

Law<br />

2 above)<br />

Review<br />

para<br />

351.<br />

41.<br />

See further the cases of S v Makwanyane 1995 3 SA<br />

11 As<br />

391<br />

above.<br />

(CC), 1995<br />

O’Regan<br />

6 BCLR<br />

J describes<br />

665 (CC) para<br />

the<br />

262;<br />

purpose<br />

Bato<br />

of<br />

Star<br />

the<br />

Fishing<br />

reasonableness<br />

(Pty) Ltd v<br />

standard<br />

Minister of<br />

as<br />

follows<br />

Environmental<br />

in Rail Commuters<br />

Affairs and<br />

Action<br />

Tourism<br />

Group<br />

2004<br />

v<br />

4<br />

Transnet<br />

SA 490 (CC),<br />

Ltd t/a<br />

2004<br />

Metrorail<br />

7 BCLR<br />

2005<br />

687 (CC)<br />

2 SA<br />

359<br />

paras<br />

(CC),<br />

73-74;<br />

2005<br />

Minister<br />

4 BCLR<br />

of<br />

301<br />

Finance<br />

(CC) para<br />

v Van<br />

87:<br />

Heerden 2004 6 SA 121 (CC), 2004 11 BCLR<br />

1125 (CC) para 142; Rates Action Group v City of Cape Town 2004 12 BCLR 1328<br />

(C) para In adopting 100. <strong>this</strong> standard the Court requires the bearer of constitutional<br />

9<br />

Sec 39(1)(a). obligations See to also perform Soobramoney them (n in 1 a above) manner para which 8. is reasonable. This<br />

10 Grootboom standard (n strikes 2 above) an para appropriate 41. balance between the need to ensure that


306 Chapter 18<br />

However, in practically all the socio-economic rights cases<br />

decided by the Constitutional Court, the effect of its decisions has<br />

been to require government to alter its preferred policy choices and<br />

to allocate additional resource to particular programmes. 12 This<br />

statement can therefore be understood to signal a two-fold<br />

awareness: (1) that the courts’ role will be to decide, in the context<br />

of concrete cases, the appropriate margin of discretion to allow the<br />

state to make policy and budgetary choices; and (2) the courts will<br />

still scrutinise these choices for their compliance with the purposes<br />

and values protected by the socio-economic rights in the Constitution.<br />

The implication is that there is no brightline boundary between law<br />

and policy, and that substantive evaluative choices will have to be<br />

made regarding when and how the courts should intervene in policy<br />

choices which impact on people’s socio-economic welfare. 13 The<br />

challenge facing the Court in <strong>this</strong> context is the formulation of<br />

transparent criteria to guide the making of these evaluative<br />

choices. 14 The jurisprudence shows that the Court has gone a<br />

substantial distance in articulating its approach to evaluating the<br />

reasonableness of the state’s acts or omissions in the context of socioeconomic<br />

rights claims.<br />

Thus the Court has indicated that it will assess the reasonableness<br />

of the state’s conduct in the light of the social, economic and<br />

historical context, and consideration will be given to the capacity of<br />

11 constitutional obligations are met, on the one hand, and recognition for<br />

the fact that the bearers of those obligations should be given appropriate<br />

leeway to determine the best way to meet the obligations in all the<br />

circumstances.<br />

Reasonableness review has synergies with the description of ‘obligations of<br />

conduct’ imposed by economic, social and cultural rights according to The<br />

Maastricht Guidelines on Violations of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights. Thus<br />

an obligation of conduct ‘requires action reasonably calculated to realise the<br />

enjoyment of a particular right.’ ‘The Maastricht guidelines on violations of<br />

economic, social and cultural rights’ (1998) 20 Human Rights Quarterly 691 para<br />

7. The Maastricht Guidelines were adopted by a group of eminent international<br />

law experts to elaborate on the obligations imposed by the International<br />

Covenant on Economic Social and Cultural Rights.<br />

12 The Court acknowledges that its decisions have budgetary implications, but<br />

understands it as a by-product of the enforcement of constitutional rights as<br />

opposed to any direct attempt to ‘rearrange budgets’. See Treatment Action<br />

Campaign (n 3 above) para 38. For an insightful analysis of the Court’s approach<br />

to decisions with implications for resource allocation, see: T Roux ‘Legitimating<br />

transformation: Political resource allocation in the South African Constitutional<br />

Court’ 10 (4) Democratization (2003) 92-111.<br />

13 On the importance of substantive legal reasoning in the context of socioeconomic<br />

rights, see S Liebenberg ‘Towards a transformative adjudication of<br />

socio-economic rights’ 21 Speculum Juris (2007) 41. See also J Froneman ‘Legal<br />

reasoning and legal culture: Our “vision” of law’ (2005) 1 Stellenbosch Law<br />

Review 3.<br />

14 As Karl Klare suggests, one of the values of substantive legal reasoning which<br />

openly engages with the evaluative choices involved in interpretive work, is that<br />

it improves the transparency of the legal process thereby contributing to<br />

‘deepening democratic culture.’ Klare (n 8 above) 171.


Sandra Liebenberg 307<br />

institutions responsible for implementing the programme. 15 While<br />

Soobramoney raised the spectre of the Court adopting a thin standard<br />

of rationality scrutiny for socio-economic rights claims, the Court in<br />

Grootboom and TAC proceeded to develop a more substantive set of<br />

criteria for assessing the reasonableness of the state’s acts or<br />

omissions. 16 Thus the Court held that a reasonable government<br />

programme must have the following features: 17<br />

• It must be comprehensive, coherent and coordinated; 18<br />

• Appropriate financial and human resources must be made available<br />

for the programme; 19<br />

• It must be balanced and flexible 20 and make appropriate provision for<br />

short, medium and long-term needs; 21<br />

• It must be reasonably conceived and implemented; 22 and<br />

• It must be transparent, and its contents must be made known<br />

effectively to the public. 23<br />

The element of the reasonableness test that comes closest to a<br />

threshold requirement is that a reasonable government programme<br />

must cater for those in urgent need:<br />

To be reasonable, measures cannot leave out of account, the degree and<br />

extent of the denial of the right they endeavour to realise. Those whose<br />

needs are most urgent and whose ability to enjoy all rights is therefore<br />

most in peril, must not be ignored by the measures aimed at achieving<br />

realisation of the right. It may not be sufficient to meet the test of<br />

reasonableness to show that the measures are capable of achieving a<br />

statistical advance in the realisation of the right. Furthermore, the<br />

Constitution requires that everyone be treated with care and concern. If<br />

the measures, though statistically successful, fail to respond to the<br />

needs of those most desperate, they may not pass the test. 24<br />

This requirement of the reasonableness test is justified in terms of the<br />

value of human dignity. Thus in Grootboom the Court held:<br />

15 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 43.<br />

16<br />

See Bel Porto School Governing Body & Others v Premier, Western Cape &<br />

Another 2002 3 SA 265 (CC), 2002 9 BCLR 891 (CC) para 46; Khosa (n 4 above) para<br />

67.<br />

17<br />

The Court noted in Khosa that the factors identified in the assessment of<br />

reasonableness were not a closed list and that ‘all relevant factors have to be<br />

taken into account’. The Court went on to observe that ‘[w]hat is relevant may<br />

vary from case to case depending on the particular facts and circumstances.’<br />

Khosa (n 4 above) para 44<br />

18 Grootboom (n 2 above) paras 39 and 40.<br />

19<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) para 39.<br />

20 Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above) paras 68, 78, 95.<br />

21 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 43.<br />

22<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) para 40–43.<br />

23 Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above) para 123.<br />

24 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 44. See A van der Walt ‘A South African reading of<br />

Frank Michelman’s theory of social justice’ in H Botha et al (eds) Rights and<br />

democracy in a transformative constitution (2004) 163 207.


308 Chapter 18<br />

It is fundamental to an evaluation of the reasonableness of state action<br />

that account be taken of the inherent dignity of human beings. ...<br />

Section 26, read in the context of the Bill of Rights as a whole, must<br />

mean that the respondents have a right to reasonable action by the state<br />

in all circumstances and with particular regard to human dignity. In<br />

short, I emphasise that human beings are required to be treated as<br />

human beings. 25<br />

The assessment of the reasonableness of government programmes is<br />

influenced by two further factors derived from sections 26(2) and<br />

27(2). The first is the concept of ‘progressive realisation’ which was<br />

interpreted as follows in Grootboom:<br />

The term ‘progressive realisation’ shows that it was contemplated that<br />

the right could not be realised immediately. But the goal of the<br />

Constitution is that the basic needs of all in our society be effectively<br />

met and the requirement of progressive realisation means that the state<br />

must take steps to achieve <strong>this</strong> goal. It means that accessibility should<br />

be progressively facilitated: legal, administrative, operational and<br />

financial hurdles should be examined and, where possible, lowered over<br />

time. Housing must be made more accessible not only to a larger number<br />

of people but to a wider range of people as time progresses. 26<br />

In <strong>this</strong> context, the Court also specifically endorsed the views of the<br />

UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights that<br />

any deliberately retrogressive measures ... would require the most<br />

careful consideration and would need to be fully justified by reference<br />

to the totality of the rights provided for in the Covenant and in the<br />

context of the full use of the maximum available resources. 27<br />

The second factor (which is linked to the first one) is the availability<br />

of resources. In <strong>this</strong> regard, the Court held that<br />

both the content of the obligation in relation to the rate at which it is<br />

achieved as well as the reasonableness of the measures employed to<br />

achieve the result are governed by the availability of resources. 28<br />

25<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) para 83. See also A Sachs ‘The judicial enforcement of<br />

socio-economic rights’ (2003) 56 Current Legal Problems 579 594–596; S<br />

Liebenberg, ‘The value of human dignity in interpreting socio-economic rights’<br />

(2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 1.<br />

26 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 45.<br />

27 As above, citing UNCESCR General Comment 3 (n 5 above) para 9. The concept of<br />

‘retrogressive measures’ has not yet received further elaboration from the<br />

Constitutional Court. The major interpretative difficulty is whether retrogression<br />

should be assessed in relation to particular individuals or groups, or in respect of<br />

the entire population.<br />

28 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 46.


Sandra Liebenberg 309<br />

This last consequence flows from the Court’s understanding that<br />

the positive duties imposed by the socio-economic rights provisions<br />

are limited by the second subsections of both FC sections 26 and 27. 29<br />

The model of reasonableness review is confined to the positive<br />

duties imposed by socio-economic rights. In respect of the negative<br />

duties, the Court has adopted a different model of review. Thus<br />

where legislation or conduct deprives people of the existing access<br />

which they enjoy to the relevant rights, <strong>this</strong> deprivation constitutes a<br />

breach of the first subsection of FC sections 26 and 27. This breach is<br />

only justifiable in terms of the stringent requirements of the general<br />

limitations clause (FC section 36). Thus the limitation must be in<br />

terms of a law of general application and is tested against the purpose<br />

and proportionality requirements inherent in section 36. Negative<br />

violations are thus subject to a much more stringent form of scrutiny<br />

than positive violations of socio-economic rights. The principled<br />

sustainability of the distinction between negative rights and positive<br />

rights is somewhat dubious. And it can likewise lead to a number of<br />

practical difficulties in characterising various kinds of claims. 30<br />

However, as the focus of the essay is on cases involving positive claims<br />

by people to the various services and resources referred to in sections<br />

26 and 27, <strong>this</strong> issue will not be pursued further.<br />

3 An alternative model of review based on ‘minimum<br />

core’ obligations<br />

The Court’s jurisprudence, particularly its rejection of minimum core<br />

obligations, has attracted quite a bit of criticism. 31 Several authors<br />

have questioned whether the Court’s jurisprudence sufficiently<br />

defines the content of the relevant socio-economic rights, and<br />

protects those who are experiencing a severe deprivation of minimum<br />

29 Soobramoney (n 1 above) paras 11 and 28; Grootboom (n 2 above) para 38;<br />

Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above) para 39.<br />

30<br />

For a critique of the negative and positive duties distinction in the context of<br />

socio-economic rights, see M Craven ‘Assessment of the progress on adjudication<br />

of economic, social and cultural rights’ in J Squires, M Langford & B Thiele (eds)<br />

The road to a remedy: Current issues in the litigation of economic, social and<br />

cultural rights (2005) 27 34-36.<br />

31 A sustained critique of the failure of the Court to adopt the notion of a minimum<br />

core obligation has been mounted by David Bilchitz. See D Bilchitz: ‘Giving socioeconomic<br />

rights teeth: The minimum core and its importance’ (2002) 118 South<br />

African Law Journal 484; ‘Towards a reasonable approach to the minimum core:<br />

Laying the foundations for future socio-economic rights jurisprudence’ (2003) 19<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 1; Poverty and fundamental rights: The<br />

justification and enforcement of socio-economic rights (2007). See also: C Scott<br />

& P Alston ‘Adjudicating constitutional priorities in a transnational context: A<br />

comment on Soobramoney’s legacy and Grootboom’s promise’ (2000) 16 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 206 244-45, 250, 252; S Liebenberg ‘South<br />

Africa’s evolving jurisprudence on socio-economic rights: An effective tool in<br />

challenging poverty’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy & Development 159.


310 Chapter 18<br />

essential levels of basic socio-economic goods and services. 32 Other<br />

authors have pointed out that the failure to provide for people’s<br />

urgent socio-economic need imperils their health, lives and future<br />

socio-economic well-being, and represents a failure to respect their<br />

inherent human dignity. 33<br />

The major theoretical rival to the reasonableness model of review<br />

adopted by the courts is a model which incorporates the notion of<br />

minimum core obligations. David Bilchitz, a leading proponent of <strong>this</strong><br />

view, argues that the minimum core obligation protects people’s<br />

urgent threshold interests in survival ‘as the inability to survive wipes<br />

out all possibility for realising the sources of value in the life of a<br />

being.’ 34 On <strong>this</strong> conception, the minimum core places an obligation<br />

on the state to ensure that individuals ‘are not exposed to the general<br />

conditions that threaten their survival’. 35 Individuals also have a more<br />

maximal interest ‘in the general conditions that are necessary for the<br />

fulfilment of a wide range of purposes’. 36 This more maximal interest<br />

would require a standard of socio-economic provisioning which allows<br />

them to flourish and achieve their goals. However, the meeting of<br />

minimum core obligations should enjoy prioritised consideration in<br />

social policy making and in the judicial enforcement of these rights<br />

due to the urgency of the interests they protect. In other words,<br />

without the meeting of minimum essential needs to survival, the<br />

obligation to progressively achieve the full realisation of the rights to<br />

a satisfactory standard of adequacy becomes meaningless. The<br />

implications for adjudication are that a court must require<br />

particularly weighty reasons by way of justification from the state for<br />

a failure to fulfil core obligations. 37<br />

A number of academic commentators have contested the view<br />

that a model of review incorporating the notion of minimum core<br />

obligations is better suited to the judicial review of positive socioeconomic<br />

rights claims. 38 In many respects, these interventions<br />

32<br />

See, eg, M Pieterse ‘Coming to terms with judicial enforcement of socioeconomic<br />

rights’ (2004) 20 South African Journal on Human Rights 383 410–411.<br />

33 For an argument that human dignity requires taking account of the relative<br />

urgency of the needs of different individuals and groups and a corresponding<br />

urgent response, see Liebenberg (n 25 above) 15-18 and 22-23.<br />

34 Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 187.<br />

35<br />

Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 188.<br />

36 As above.<br />

37 See Bilchitz’s endorsement of the notion of ‘weighted priority’ as opposed to<br />

‘lexical priority’ in relation to assessing compliance with minimum core<br />

obligations: Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 208–213.<br />

38 Sachs (n 25 above); M Wesson ‘Grootboom and beyond: Reassessing the socioeconomic<br />

rights jurisprudence of the South African Constitutional Court’ (2004)<br />

20 South African Journal on Human Rights 284; B Porter ‘The crisis of ESC Rights<br />

and strategies for addressing it’ in Squires, Langford & Thiele (n 30 above) 43 48–<br />

55; MS Kende ‘The South African Constitutional Court’s embrace of socioeconomic<br />

rights: A comparative perspective’ (2003) 6 Chapman Law Review 137.


Sandra Liebenberg 311<br />

represent elaborations of the concerns articulated by the Court in<br />

relation to the minimum core concept. 39<br />

The first set of objections relates broadly to the impact of the<br />

minimum core concept on democratic institutional functioning and<br />

culture in South Africa. The concept of minimum core obligations<br />

ostensibly compels the courts to transgress the boundaries of their<br />

institutional legitimacy and competence, thus undermining the<br />

separation of powers doctrine. The process of defining and enforcing<br />

minimum core obligations results in the courts usurping government’s<br />

policy-making functions. One response to <strong>this</strong> line of argument is that<br />

the notion of bounded ‘separate spheres’ does not accord with the<br />

relational, dialogic character of the relationship between the<br />

different spheres of government under the South African<br />

Constitution. 40<br />

Of greater concern to a vision of transformative constitutionalism<br />

that promotes institutional and social dialogue in the process of<br />

realising socio-economic rights is the argument that the endorsement<br />

of minimum core obligations by the judiciary will undermine<br />

deliberative democracy. Thus Carol Steinberg argues that the<br />

minimum core represents an ‘intrusive rule-based’ approach which is<br />

likely to stifle institutional conversation and collaboration between<br />

the three branches of government. 41 In contrast, she argues,<br />

the abstract and open-ended nature of the reasonableness inquiry should<br />

be understood as a ‘democracy-promoting’ form of minimalism in which<br />

the court settles the case before it on narrow grounds, avoiding the<br />

laying down of clear rules and final resolutions that will inhibit the<br />

effective functioning of the other branches of government. 42<br />

The kind of case-by-case evolution of standards on socio-economic<br />

rights promoted by reasonableness review is more likely to promote<br />

‘the kind of argumentative give-and-take, evolution, learning and<br />

compromise’ which will produce wiser and more sustainable decisions<br />

on socio-economic rights. 43 Her analysis is based on the understanding<br />

that there is a legitimate diversity of views regarding the nature and<br />

role of socio-economic rights, how different socio-economic needs<br />

39<br />

n 7 above and accompanying text.<br />

40 In terms of FC sec 1(d), the South African state is founded on the values of,<br />

amongst others, ‘accountability, responsiveness and openness.’ Chapter 3 of the<br />

Constitution endorses ‘co-operative government’. See generally H Botha<br />

‘Freedom and constraint in constitutional adjudication’ (2004) 20 South African<br />

Journal on Human Rights 249 277–278.<br />

41<br />

C Steinberg ‘Can reasonableness protect the poor? A review of South Africa’s<br />

socio-economic rights jurisprudence’ (2006) 123 South African Law Journal 264<br />

274.<br />

42<br />

Steinberg (n 41 above) 276.<br />

43 Steinberg (n 41 above) 272.


312 Chapter 18<br />

should be prioritised and ranked, and the measures through which<br />

these rights should be realised. 44 Given their limited institutional<br />

competence, judges may get it wrong in defining the minimum<br />

content of the rights. 45<br />

While an institutional dialogue between the branches of<br />

government is to be encouraged, the institutional advantages of the<br />

legislature as an institution should not be overstated. However sound<br />

the theoretical justifications for preferring legislative measures for<br />

giving effect to socio-economic rights, it is premised on a certain<br />

understanding of the ideal role and functioning of legislatures which<br />

does not reflect the current realities both in South Africa and other<br />

jurisdictions. Most modern legislatures are subject to the constraints<br />

of time and resource pressures, are at a relative disadvantage to the<br />

executive in relation to technical expertise and resources, and are,<br />

finally subject to capture by powerful business and interest groups in<br />

society. 46 This results in imperfect legislation which may disregard or<br />

neglect the rights of particular groups, most frequently those who are<br />

politically, economically and socially marginalised. 47 In addition,<br />

many of the decisions made in relation to socio-economic rights are<br />

policy and administrative decisions which do not enjoy the same<br />

democratic legitimacy as legislative decisions. In making policy<br />

decisions relating to the implementation of socio-economic rights,<br />

the purposes and values which these rights seek to protect and to<br />

promote may be overlooked or discounted. 48<br />

44<br />

Steinberg (n 41 above) 275. For a similar argument in favour of the kind of weakform<br />

judicial review of socio-economic rights represented by the Court’s<br />

reasonableness model, see R Dixon ‘Creating dialogue about socio-economic<br />

rights: Strong-form versus weak-form judicial review revisited’ (2007) 5<br />

International Journal of Constitutional Law 391 401-402. Dixon highlights the<br />

various theoretical groundings which have been provided for the minimum core<br />

concept in constitutional scholarship, and the different practical consequences<br />

which these approaches have for the interpretation of socio-economic rights<br />

claims (400–401). On ‘weak form’ judicial review, see generally: M Tushnet ‘New<br />

forms of judicial review and the persistence of rights- and democracy-based<br />

worries’ (2003) 38 Wake Forest Law Review 813.<br />

45 Steinberg (n 41 above) 268.<br />

46<br />

For an excellent discussion of the institutional advantages and disadvantages of<br />

the courts and legislatures in relation to socio-economic rights, see Pieterse (n 32<br />

above) 389-399.<br />

47<br />

For a discussion of the ‘blind spots’ and ‘burdens of inertia’ in legislative<br />

processes, see Dixon (n 44 above) 402-406.<br />

48 See, eg, the High Court’s analysis of the administrative nature of the decisions of<br />

the City of Johannesburg in relation to the introduction of pre-payment meters<br />

and the limitation of the free basic water supply to the residents of the Phiri<br />

Township to 25 litres per person per day (or 6 kilolitres per household per month)<br />

in Mazibuko & Others v The City of Johannesburg & Others [2008] ZAGPHC 128<br />

(30 April 2008) paras 63, 70, 104, 163 – 164, 181.


Sandra Liebenberg 313<br />

A related concern from the perspective of establishing a culture<br />

of participatory democracy 49 in South Africa is that if the courts were<br />

to provide complete normative definition of the minimum core of<br />

socio-economic rights it would foreclose legitimate dialogue within<br />

the broader civil society about the conceptual and value-based<br />

underpinnings of socio-economic rights and the best modes of<br />

realising them in the variety of contexts in which they arise. 50 The<br />

minimum core concept seeks to establish a normative essence for<br />

socio-economic rights which is beyond contestation and debate. 51<br />

This may tend to promote closure in broader deliberative and<br />

discursive processes relating to the implementation of socioeconomic<br />

rights.<br />

The second critique of the minimum core concept concerns its<br />

linkage to the standard of survival needs. Contrary to what is claimed,<br />

the survival standard does not guarantee clarity and certainty in<br />

defining priority claims in the context of socio-economic rights<br />

adjudication. 52 Given the fact that threats to life can be relatively<br />

short-term, medium-term or long-term, the survival-standard does<br />

not provide clear guidance as to which socio-economic interventions<br />

should be adopted or enjoy prioritised consideration in policy-making<br />

and adjudication. Health education measures concerning the dangers<br />

of smoking and the need for safe sex may not seem to be an urgent<br />

priority, but may nevertheless have a significant impact in terms of<br />

saving lives in the longer term. It is not, as some proponents of the<br />

minimum core would seem to claim, easy to disentangle short,<br />

medium and long-term needs.<br />

A third critique of grounding the minimum core concept in<br />

biological survival is that the standard is unduly reductionist in the<br />

context of a transformative constitution which seeks to promote the<br />

achievement of social justice. Depending on the context, it results in<br />

either over- or under-inclusivity in the specification of core<br />

obligations. On the one hand, people can survive on very little which<br />

49 Danie Brand has argued that there is an overemphasis in the Court’s socioeconomic<br />

rights jurisprudence on the institutional relations between the<br />

different branches of government, and insufficient attention to promoting<br />

broader discursive engagement in defining and implementing socio-economic<br />

rights. See D Brand ‘The “politics of need interpretation” and the adjudication of<br />

socio-economic rights claims in South Africa’ in AJ van der Walt (ed) Theories of<br />

social and economic justice (2005) 17.<br />

50 Dixon (n 44 above) 416–417. Dixon points out that while it may be possible ‘as an<br />

abstract and theoretical matter’ to formulate the morally and constitutionally<br />

correct grounding for these core obligations, it is also likely and reasonable that<br />

South Africans, with a variety of different life experiences and perspectives, will<br />

differ on these questions.’<br />

51 See K Young ‘The minimum core of economic and social rights: A concept in<br />

search of content’ (2008) 33 The Yale Journal of International Law 112 138-140.<br />

52<br />

See Bilchitz’s critique of the lack of clear standards and benchmarks provided by<br />

reasonableness review: Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 161-162.


314 Chapter 18<br />

can support a kind of minimalism in socio-economic provisioning that<br />

is inappropriate in contexts where the state has the resources to<br />

provide more than the bare necessities for survival. For example,<br />

Amartya Sen points out that people ‘have been known to survive with<br />

incredibly little nutrition’ and that so-called ‘“minimum nutrition<br />

requirements” have an inherent arbitrariness that goes well beyond<br />

variations between groups and regions.’ 53<br />

On the other hand, in the context of health care rights, a survivalbased<br />

standard supports the provision of expensive, tertiary health<br />

care interventions. Such interventions will, under conditions of<br />

scarcity, occur at the expense of less expensive preventative and<br />

primary health care interventions. 54<br />

Young argues that ‘the emphasis on minimalism behind the core<br />

becomes suggestive, when attached to life, of a more scientific,<br />

needs-based assessment of the commodities necessary for biological<br />

survival.’ 55 This approach does not reflect the socially and<br />

communally determined processes and values through which social<br />

needs are identified and validated. 56 As Justice O’Regan observes in<br />

S v Makwanyane:<br />

It is not life as mere organic matter that the Constitution cherishes but<br />

the right to human life: the right to live as a human being, to be part of<br />

a broader community, to share in the experience of humanity. ... The<br />

right to life is more than existence, it is a right to be treated as a human<br />

being with dignity. 57<br />

In finding that the City of Johannesburg’s decision to limit the<br />

residents of Phiri Township’s free basic water supply to 25 litres of<br />

water per person per day (or 6 kilolitres per household per month)<br />

infringed FC section 27, Tsoka J held that <strong>this</strong> supply was inadequate<br />

to secure the right to health and the right to lead a dignified life. 58<br />

The court held that it was uncontested that the City of Johannesburg<br />

had the resources to provide a free basic water supply of 50 litres per<br />

53 A Sen Poverty and Famines (1981) 12 as discussed by Young (n 51 above) 131.<br />

54 The ethical and practical problems associated with the survival-based standard<br />

for determining minimum core obligations in the context of health rights, impels<br />

Bilchitz to develop the notion of ‘the pragmatic minimum threshold’ in relation to<br />

health rights. The pragmatic minimum core represents a conglomeration of the<br />

principled survival-based standard together with a range of other theoretical and<br />

practical considerations such as the resources and capacity available in a<br />

particular society. Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 220–225.<br />

55<br />

Young (n 51 above) 131.<br />

56 Nancy Fraser describes the way in which social needs are politically and<br />

discursively determined. N Fraser Unruly practices: Power, discourse and gender<br />

in contemporary social theory (1989) 144–160, 163–183. For discussions of Fraser’s<br />

theoretical perspectives on the struggle over needs in contemporary capitalist<br />

societies, see Brand (n 49 above) 17; Liebenberg (n 8 above) 5.<br />

57<br />

Makwanyane (n 8 above) paras 326–327.<br />

58 Mazibuko (n 48 above) paras 124 and 179.


Sandra Liebenberg 315<br />

person per day which the World Health Organisation and an<br />

international expert recommended as being required for a healthy<br />

and dignified lifestyle. 59 This judgment suggests that the application<br />

of a heightened review standard should not only be confined to one<br />

core value or interest such as biological survival. Moreover, in respect<br />

of other socio-economic rights, such as the right to education, the<br />

focus on mere biological survival simply does not accord with the<br />

broader purposes and interests which such a right protects. In striving<br />

to establish clear, fixed and judicially manageable standards for the<br />

adjudication of socio-economic rights claims, the minimum core<br />

approach is in danger of encouraging minimalism in social provisioning<br />

when the context may in fact render such minimalism unnecessary<br />

and inappropriate. 60<br />

A fourth difficulty with the minimum core concept is related to<br />

the Constitutional Court’s observations concerning the difficulty of<br />

defining minimum core obligations given the diversity of needs and<br />

circumstances in which different groups find themselves. 61 The<br />

underlying concern is that the minimum core approach is unduly rigid,<br />

and its application may operate to exclude or marginalise the needs<br />

of various groups that do not fit the background norms informing the<br />

definition of core obligations. Bilchitz responds to <strong>this</strong> concern by<br />

arguing that the minimum core should aim to define a general<br />

standard informed by people’s urgent survival needs. This standard,<br />

for example, still allows for a measure of latitude and flexibility<br />

regarding what precisely is needed to meet people’s needs in<br />

different contexts. 62 However, he argues that the minimum core does<br />

require ‘a rigid stance in one respect: it requires us to recognise that<br />

it is simply unacceptable for human beings to have to live without<br />

sufficient resources to be free from threats to their survival.’ 63 He<br />

thus argues for a form of heightened scrutiny to be applied to claims<br />

59 Mazibuko (n 48 above) paras 179 – 181.<br />

60 See the similar concern expressed by Porter (n 38 above) 55.<br />

61<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) paras 32–33.<br />

62 Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 198. See also his response<br />

(200-202) to Danie Brand’s argument that the minimum core may be suitable for<br />

the international enforcement of socio-economic rights, but is not useful for the<br />

domestic context where we must be ‘far more specific, concrete, contextsensitive<br />

and flexible in our thinking about basic standards, core entitlements and<br />

minimum obligations.’ D Brand ‘The minimum content of the right to food in<br />

context: A response to Rolf Künnemann’ in D Brand & S Russell (eds) Exploring the<br />

core content of socio-economic rights: South African and international<br />

perspectives (2002) 99 101.<br />

63 Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 208.


316 Chapter 18<br />

which implicate minimum core obligations. 64 This two-tier approach<br />

requires distinguishing between core needs (those that implicate<br />

survival) and non-core needs (those that relate to fulfilling a range of<br />

purposes and flourishing as a human being) in relation to both socioeconomic<br />

policy-making and in adjudicating cases.<br />

However, the difficulty, as I have previously suggested, is that<br />

social needs are in fact interconnected and that no clear-cut<br />

distinction exists between core and non-core needs. Nancy Fraser<br />

describes needs these claims as ‘nested’ in that they are ‘connected<br />

to one another in ramified chains of “in order to” relations’. 65 It is<br />

generally possible to reach consensus on what Fraser terms, ‘thin<br />

needs’ such as the need of people in non-tropical climates for shelter<br />

in order to survive. However, as soon as one inquires into the detail<br />

of what precisely is required in order to provide shelter which can be<br />

sustained and fulfil its purposes, one encounters a diversity of views.<br />

In relation to housing, for example, the issue of the location of<br />

housing close to employment and livelihood opportunities is generally<br />

not defined as part of the minimum core obligations of the state. 66<br />

However, the location of housing is usually a crucial factor in people’s<br />

abilities to pursue sustainable livelihood strategies which secure the<br />

socio-economic well-being of themselves and their dependants. 67<br />

64 Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 210-213 characterises <strong>this</strong><br />

heightened scrutiny as a form of ‘weighted priority’. It refers ‘to a reason which<br />

has great importance to us and which can only be overridden by considerations<br />

that are of equivalent weight’ (211). Bilchitz identifies four such weighty reasons<br />

which can justify overriding core obligations: (1) scarcity of resources; (2)<br />

situations where the minimal interests of some individuals can only be met by<br />

dedicating a disproportionately vast amount of resources to them; (3) the need to<br />

preserve some space for individuals to pursue interests beyond the minimal<br />

interest in survival, such as ‘opportunities to realise their goals and achieve<br />

positive experiences’; and (4) situations when the realisation of the minimum<br />

core of a particular right would prevent the realisation of the minimum core of<br />

64<br />

other Bilchitz rights Poverty and liberties and fundamental (212). rights (n 31 above) 210-213 characterises <strong>this</strong><br />

65 Fraser heightened (n 56 scrutiny above) 163. as a form of ‘weighted priority’. It refers ‘to a reason which<br />

66 For has great example, importance Bilchitz to argues us and that which the can general only be standard overridden that by constitutes considerations the<br />

minimum that are of core equivalent obligation weight’ of the (211). state Bilchitz in relation identifies to four housing such weighty would be reasons that<br />

everyone which can should justify have overriding ‘access core to obligations: accommodation (1) scarcity that involves, of resources; at least, (2)<br />

protection situations where from the the elements minimal in interests sanitary of conditions some individuals with access can to only basic be services, met by<br />

such dedicating as toilets a disproportionately and running water.’ vast Bilchitz amount Poverty of resources and fundamental to them; (3) rights the need (n 31 to<br />

above) preserve 198. some space for individuals to pursue interests beyond the minimal<br />

67 See interest City in of survival, Johannesburg such v as Rand ‘opportunities Properties to (Pty) realise Ltd & their Others goals 2007 and 6 achieve SA 417<br />

(SCA). positive The experiences’; Supreme Court and of (4) Appeal situations ordered when the the City realisation of Johannesburg of the to minimum provide<br />

temporary core of a particular accommodation right would to occupiers prevent who the face realisation eviction of in the terms minimum of the National core of<br />

Building other rights Regulations and liberties and (212). Building Standards Act 103 of 1977. The Court ordered<br />

65<br />

that Fraser <strong>this</strong> ‘Unruly ‘temporary Practices’ accommodation (n 56 above) 163. is to consist of at least the following<br />

66<br />

elements: For example, a place Bilchitz where argues they may that live the secure general against standard eviction; that a structure constitutes that the is<br />

waterproof minimum core and secure obligation against of the elements; state in relation and with to access housing to basic would sanitation, be that<br />

water everyone and should refuse services.’ have ‘access In order to accommodation to implement the that foregoing, involves, the at City least, was<br />

ordered protection to from determine the elements the location in sanitary of conditions the alternative with access accommodation to basic services, ‘after<br />

consultation’ such as toilets if and requested running by water.’ any occupier Bilchitz (para Poverty 78, and Orders fundamental (c), 2.1 and rights 2.3). (n This 31<br />

represents above) 198. an implicit acknowledgment of the significance of the location of


Sandra Liebenberg 317<br />

Taking location into account in fulfilling core obligations will usually<br />

require the state to purchase more expensive land closer to<br />

employment opportunities thus increasing substantially the resource<br />

implications of providing basic shelter. However, <strong>this</strong> detracts from<br />

the clarity of definition and relatively low-cost implications which is<br />

an argument in favour of the minimum core as a manageable judicial<br />

standard for the enforcement of basic subsistence needs. On the<br />

other hand, excluding location from the ambit of core obligations in<br />

the sphere of housing will have the effect of deepening the<br />

marginalisation of those for whom proximity to employment<br />

opportunities is crucial to the sustainability of their livelihood<br />

strategies and long term development. 68<br />

While Bilchitz’s approach does permit a diversity of specification<br />

by defining the minimum core as a general standard, the problem lies<br />

precisely in <strong>this</strong> attempt to ground core/priority obligations in a single<br />

metric. This approach does not reflect the fact that people may have<br />

other important needs which do not meet the threshold of survival,<br />

but which warrant prior consideration in a constitutional order<br />

founded on the values of human dignity, equality and freedom. 69 For<br />

example, the provision of child care facilities may not be crucial to<br />

survival, but, given the gendered burden of care 70 and the conditions<br />

of socio-economic deprivation in which many women live, the<br />

provision of such facilities is crucial to their ability to participate in<br />

67 accommodation to the fundamental interests of occupiers. In its judgment on<br />

appeal, the Constitutional Court focused on the obligation of ‘meaningful<br />

engagement’ between the parties in relation to the consequences of a threatened<br />

eviction. See Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road, Berea Township and 197 Main Street,<br />

Johannesburg v The City of Johannesburg & Others 2008 3 SA 208 (CC) paras 9 –<br />

36. The UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights defines the<br />

‘location’ of housing to be one of the elements which must be taken into account<br />

in assessing the ‘adequacy’ of housing in terms of article 11 of the International<br />

Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights. Thus adequate housing ‘must<br />

be in a location which allows access to employment options, health care services,<br />

schools, child-care centres and other social facilities. ... Similarly housing should<br />

not be built on polluted sites nor in immediate proximity to pollution sources that<br />

threaten the right to health of the inhabitants.’ ‘General Comment 4: The right<br />

to adequate housing (art.11(1) of the Covenant)’ UN doc E/1992/23 (1991) para<br />

8(f).<br />

68 The Indian Supreme Court held in Olga Tellis v Bombay Municipal Corp (1985) 3<br />

SCC 545 that the right to a livelihood was implicated in the eviction of pavement<br />

dwellers in the city.<br />

69 See, eg, Rosalind Dixon’s argument that it is equally plausible to base a notion of<br />

minimum core obligations on the rights and values of human dignity and equality<br />

Dixon (n 44 above) 399–401. For an argument that a heightened review standard<br />

should be applied to basic need claims informed by a dignity-based standard, see<br />

Liebenberg (n 25 above).<br />

70<br />

See President of the Republic of South Africa v Hugo 1997 4 SA 1 (CC), 1997 6<br />

BCLR 708 (CC) para 37.


318 Chapter 18<br />

development programmes, employment and society more generally. 71<br />

By excluding such facilities from the ambit of ‘heightened priority’<br />

obligations, the gendered character of social provisioning is rendered<br />

invisible. The exclusion of such gender-specific priorities simultaneously<br />

reinforces the marginalisation of both women’s needs and,<br />

more generally, the needs of those men and women who undertake<br />

the burden of reproductive work in our society. Similarly the provision<br />

of various forms of specially adapted housing and social services to<br />

people with disabilities may not be necessary for their survival, but is<br />

nonetheless crucial for their ability to participate as equals in<br />

society. 72 The case for judicial intervention becomes even more<br />

compelling if the context reveals that the state (or a private<br />

institution) has sufficient resources to provide such facilities.<br />

Finally, it has been argued that a two-tiered approach 73 which<br />

requires prioritisation of core needs is also likely to be<br />

counterproductive in a developmental state. Murray Wesson argues<br />

that it will encourage the diversion of state resources to temporary,<br />

emergency-type measures from long-term, and often more efficient,<br />

investments. 74 Because the state is faced with ‘a spectrum of<br />

needs’, 75 Wesson contends that a more nuanced approach is<br />

advisable: Such an approach does not prioritise one set of needs to the<br />

absolute exclusion of others, and allows for a balance between shortterm<br />

and long-term aims. 76 That said, such balancing risks<br />

downplaying the undisputed importance of ensuring that immediate<br />

socio-economic needs are met in favour of economic initiatives which<br />

promise an improvement in overall well-being in the medium- to<br />

longer term. As the Court noted in Grootboom, a general statistical<br />

improvement in access to socio-economic rights may reflect an<br />

insufficient commitment to the Final Constitution’s demand that<br />

everyone is treated with care and concern. 77 Moreover, empirical<br />

71<br />

See B Goldblatt ‘Citizenship and the right to child care’ in A Gouws (ed)<br />

(Un)thinking citizenship: Feminist debates in contemporary South Africa (2005)<br />

117. Goldblatt argues that childcare rights can be derived from the right of<br />

everyone to social security (sec 27(1)(c)), the right of children to social services<br />

(sec 28(1)(c)), and the right to fair labour practices (sec 23(1)).<br />

72 See S Liebenberg & B Goldblatt ‘The interrelationship between equality and<br />

socio-economic rights under South Africa’s transformative constitution’ (2007) 23<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 335.<br />

73 Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 202 argues that the ‘twotier<br />

structure’ that he proposes ‘has the benefit of offering a clear, structured<br />

way in which to approach the application of socio-economic rights to particular<br />

situations.’<br />

74<br />

Wesson (n 38 above) 304.<br />

75 Wesson (n 38 above) 303.<br />

76 Wesson (n 38 above) 304. See also the similar argument by Dixon (n 44 above)<br />

411.<br />

77 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 44.


Sandra Liebenberg 319<br />

evidence suggests that the direct provision of social assistance to<br />

individuals promotes social and economic development. 78<br />

4 Re-evaluating reasonableness review<br />

On the other hand, ‘reasonableness review’ has been criticised for<br />

amounting to little more than an administrative law model that does<br />

not engage in a sufficiently substantive analysis of the content of<br />

socio-economic rights and the obligations they impose. 79 The<br />

vagueness and openness of the reasonableness inquiry allows courts<br />

to avoid giving clear normative content to socio-economic rights. 80<br />

Minimum core arguments are, most often, a direct outgrowth of <strong>this</strong><br />

critique of reasonableness review. 81<br />

For other scholars, <strong>this</strong> ‘openness’ represents the major<br />

advantage of reasonableness review. For such openness or flexibility<br />

enables courts to attain a skilful balance between ‘displacing<br />

democratic judgments about how to set priorities’ and abdicating any<br />

meaningful role in the judicial enforcement of socio-economic<br />

rights. 82 Reasonableness review allows the courts to set general<br />

norms while simultaneously placing the burden of justification on<br />

government to explain its priority-setting. 83<br />

In many respects, reasonableness review provides the courts with<br />

a flexible and context-sensitive basis for evaluating socio-economic<br />

rights claims. It allows government the space to design and formulate<br />

appropriate policies to meet its socio-economic rights obligations. At<br />

the same time, it subjects government’s choices to the requirements<br />

of reasonableness, inclusiveness and particularly the threshold<br />

78<br />

See, eg, Committee of Inquiry into a Comprehensive System of Social Security for<br />

South Africa Transforming the present, protecting the future (2002) available at<br />

www.welfare.gov.za/Documents/2002/2002.htm (accessed on 26 May 2008);<br />

Economic Policy Research Institute The social and economic impact of South<br />

Africa’s social security system (2004) available at www.sarpn.org.za/documents/<br />

d0001041/Full_Report.pdf (accessed on 26 May 2008). Children’s development<br />

and life prospects are particularly affected by a failure to ensure that their basic<br />

socio-economic needs are met. See, eg, D Budlender & I Woolard ‘The Impact of<br />

the South African child support and old age grants on children’s schooling and<br />

work’ International Labour Organisation (ILO) (2006).<br />

79 D Brand ‘The proceduralisation of South African socio-economic rights<br />

jurisprudence, or “what are socio-economic rights for?”’ in Botha et al (n 24<br />

above) 33.<br />

80 Pieterse (n 32 above) 410–411. Dennis Davis points out that reasonableness review<br />

can easily degenerate into a highly deferential standard of review. See DM Davis<br />

‘Socio-economic rights in South Africa: The record of the Constitutional Court<br />

after ten years’ (2004) 5 Economic and Social Rights Review 3 5; and<br />

‘Adjudicating the socio-economic rights in the South African Constitution:<br />

Towards “deference lite”?’ (2006) 22 South African Journal on Human Rights 301.<br />

81 Bilchitz ‘Towards a reasonable approach’ (n 31 above) 9–10.<br />

82 CR Sunstein ‘Social and economic rights? Lessons from South Africa’ (2001) 11(4)<br />

Constitutional Forum 123 131.<br />

83 As above.


320 Chapter 18<br />

requirement that all programmes must provide short-term measures<br />

of relief for those whose circumstances are urgent and intolerable. 84<br />

Reasonableness review enables courts to adjust the stringency of its<br />

review standard informed by factors such as the position of the<br />

claimant group in society, the nature of the resource or service<br />

claimed, 85 and the impact of the denial of access to the service or<br />

resource in question on the claimant group. 86 The Court’s<br />

jurisprudence suggests that the government’s justifications will be<br />

subject to more stringent scrutiny when a disadvantaged sector of<br />

society is deprived of access to essential services and resources. In<br />

<strong>this</strong> regard, the Court has acknowledged the poor as a vulnerable<br />

group in society, whose needs require special attention. 87<br />

Thus the reasonableness inquiry takes into account a number of<br />

considerations relevant to the claimant group, the nature of the<br />

service or resource in question as well as the historical, economic and<br />

social context 88 in which the claim arises. In <strong>this</strong> sense,<br />

‘reasonableness review’ avoids closure and creates the on-going<br />

possibility of challenging various forms of socio-economic<br />

deprivations in the different contexts in which they arise. Such review<br />

could facilitate the participation and the dialogical interaction<br />

between the state and civil society in the defining of and realisation<br />

of socio-economic rights. The Treatment Action Campaign (TAC) has<br />

been able to use reasonableness review to win a major victory in the<br />

provision of appropriate medical treatment to reduce the risk of the<br />

transmission of HIV from mother to child. 89 The TAC and other civil<br />

society organisations have been able to use <strong>this</strong> victory and the<br />

criteria for a reasonable programme established in Grootboom as part<br />

84 Steinberg (n 41 above) 277 argues that ‘the intense scrutiny’ of government<br />

conduct combined with the heavy weighting of the values of human dignity and<br />

equality in the proportionality assessment, gives the reasonableness inquiry in<br />

socio-economic rights cases a discrete character.<br />

85 In Soobramoney (n 1 above), a more tertiary and expensive form of medical<br />

treatment was claimed and the Court applied a deferential standard of review<br />

based on rationality. In contrast, in Grootboom (n 2 above), Treatment Action<br />

Campaign (n 3 above) and Khosa (n 4 above) the review standard was stricter and<br />

involved a more searching scrutiny of government’s justifications for denying the<br />

applicants access to a basic level of service provision.<br />

86 In Grootboom, Treatment Action Campaign and Khosa, the Court emphasised the<br />

severe impact on the claimants of the deprivation in question. See, for example,<br />

the historical context and current socio-economic circumstances of the claimants<br />

sketched by the Court in its judgments at Grootboom (n 2 above) paras 2-11;<br />

Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above) 78-79; Khosa (n 4 above) paras 71, 76-77,<br />

80-81.<br />

87 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 36; Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above) para 79.<br />

88<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) paras 43–44 and 92.<br />

89 See M Heywood ‘Preventing mother-to-child HIV transmission in South Africa:<br />

Background, strategies and outcomes of the Treatment Action Campaign Case<br />

against the Minister of Health’ (2003) 19 South African Journal on Human Rights<br />

278.


Sandra Liebenberg 321<br />

of broad-based strategy for achieving a general anti-retroviral roll-out<br />

programme. 90<br />

However, a significant disadvantage of reasonableness review is<br />

that it does not incorporate the traditional two stage approach to<br />

constitutional analysis. 91 Put differently, it does not begin with an<br />

initial principled focus on the content and scope of the right and<br />

situation of the claimants, and thereafter a consideration of possible<br />

justifications for the infringement. 92 As a result, the Court engages<br />

only very superficially with the content and underlying purposes and<br />

values of the relevant rights.<br />

5 Towards substantive reasonableness<br />

The Court is clearly committed to the model of reasonableness<br />

review. However, it has not excluded a role for the notion of minimum<br />

core obligations as a factor in its evaluation of the reasonableness of<br />

government measures. 93<br />

This part considers how reasonableness review can be<br />

strengthened so as to ensure that courts engage adequately with the<br />

content of the rights and their underlying values. Such an approach<br />

would preserve the openness and context-sensitivity of<br />

reasonableness review that facilitates greater participation and<br />

deliberation in interpreting the normative commitments underlying<br />

socio-economic rights. At the same time, such an approach can assist<br />

in ensuring that a heightened standard of review is applied in cases<br />

involving basic needs without encountering the disadvantages<br />

associated with the survival-based standard of minimum core<br />

obligations. 94<br />

90 This programme was announced by government in August 2003. See also the civil<br />

society submission on the operational plan for the rollout of an anti-retroviral<br />

programme entitled, ‘A people-centred ARV programme’ available at<br />

www.tac.org.za/Documents/TreatmentPlan/FullFinalSubmissiontoARVTaskTeam.<br />

doc (accessed 30 January 2008). See further M Heywood ‘Shaping, making and<br />

breaking the law in the campaign for a national HIV/AIDS treatment plan’ in P<br />

Jones & K Stokke (eds) Democratising development: The politics of socioeconomic<br />

rights in South Africa (2005) 181.<br />

91 For more on the relationship between internal limitations of socio-economic<br />

rights and the general limitations clause found in FC sec 36, see S Woolman & H<br />

Botha ‘Limitations’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa<br />

(2nd Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 34.<br />

92 See also Pieterse (n 32 above) 406–407.<br />

93<br />

n 6 above and accompanying text. In Mazibuko (n 48 above) Tsoka J interprets the<br />

Constitutional Court judgments in Grootboom (n 2 above) and Treatment Action<br />

Campaign (n 3 above) not as an outright rejection of the minimum core concept<br />

as part of our law (para 131).<br />

94 See the discussion in part 4 above.


322 Chapter 18<br />

In Grootboom, the Court held that the comprehensive, coordinated<br />

programme which the state is obliged to adopt to give<br />

effect to socio-economic rights ‘must be capable of facilitating the<br />

realisation of the right.’ 95 However, until some understanding is<br />

developed (even if it is provisional) of the content of the right, the<br />

assessment of whether the measures adopted by the state are<br />

reasonably capable of facilitating its realisation takes place in a<br />

normative vacuum. Reasonableness review should thus be developed<br />

in a way which incorporates a principled and substantive<br />

interpretation of the content of socio-economic rights. Such an<br />

interpretation should seek to elucidate the purposes and interests<br />

which these rights protect and should promote ‘the values that<br />

underlie an open and democratic society based on human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom’ as required by FC section 39(1)(a).<br />

As I observed above, the Court has not spent much interpretive<br />

energy in developing the substantive content of the various socioeconomic<br />

rights in FC sections 26 and 27. Grootboom offered a<br />

promising start. The Court held that ‘access to adequate housing’<br />

implies a recognition ‘that housing entails more than bricks and<br />

mortar’:<br />

It requires available land, appropriate services such as the provision of<br />

water and the removal of sewerage and the financing of all of these,<br />

including the building of the house itself. For a person to have access to<br />

adequate housing all of these conditions need to be met: there must be<br />

land, there must be services, there must be a dwelling. 96<br />

However, in arriving at <strong>this</strong> definition the Court proffers little<br />

engagement with the very purposes that the right to housing is meant<br />

to protect. The Court’s main engagement with the constitutional<br />

values, particularly human dignity, is in the context of justifying the<br />

element of the reasonableness test which requires that short-term<br />

measures of relief must be provided for those in desperate need. 97<br />

These values do not play any significant role in developing the<br />

substantive content of the rights protected in FC sections 26 and 27.<br />

In Treatment Action Campaign, the Court provides even less<br />

insight into the scope and content of the right of access to health care<br />

services. 98 The Court’s primary aim is to demonstrate that<br />

government’s inflexible stance regarding the confining of Nevirapine<br />

to the nine research sites could not be justified in the light of the<br />

policy, capacity and resource arguments raised by the state itself.<br />

The Court does not explain why the provision of essential drugs and<br />

95 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 41<br />

96 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 35.<br />

97<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) para 44.<br />

98 Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above).


Sandra Liebenberg 323<br />

attendant services to reduce the risk of HIV-transmission should form<br />

an integral part of health care services in the South African context. 99<br />

For example, access by women to Nevirapine in the public health<br />

sector to reduce the risk of mother-to-child transmission of HIV could<br />

be regarded as an integral component of the right to reproductive<br />

health care. Such treatment advances the constitutional values of<br />

human dignity and equality — particularly in the context of the<br />

gendered burden of child care. In the South African context, the<br />

burden of caring for an HIV-positive baby will fall disproportionately<br />

on poor, black women.<br />

Similarly in Khosa, while the Court emphasises the significance of<br />

the values of human dignity and equality in evaluating the<br />

reasonableness of the exclusion of permanent residents from the<br />

impugned social assistance legislation, it does not engage with the<br />

content or scope of the social security and assistance rights in FC<br />

section 27(1)(c). 100 Until some understanding is developed (even if it<br />

is provisional) of the content of the right, it is impossible to assess<br />

whether the measures adopted by the state are reasonably capable of<br />

facilitating its realisation. 101<br />

Neither does the Court engage in any detail with how the rights<br />

have been interpreted in relevant international human rights law or<br />

in other jurisdictions as required in section 39(1)(b) and (c) of the<br />

Constitution. There is an increasing volume of international and<br />

comparative jurisprudence that the courts can consider in developing<br />

the interpretation of socio-economic rights. For example, the<br />

European Committee on Social Rights, which supervises the<br />

obligations of state parties to the European Social Charter, 102 has<br />

developed a sophisticated understanding of the housing rights in the<br />

99 It is noteworthy in <strong>this</strong> regard that the UN Committee on Economic, Social and<br />

Cultural Rights regards the provision of ‘essential drugs, as from time to time<br />

defined under the WHO Action Programme on Essential Drugs’ as part of the core<br />

obligations imposed by the right to the highest attainable standard of health in<br />

article 12 of the ICESCR. General Comment 14 (n 5 above) para 43(d). As the<br />

Court noted in Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above), Nevirapine was<br />

recommended ‘without qualification’ for the purpose of the reduction of motherto-child<br />

transmission of HIV (para 60). The Committee also regards the taking of<br />

measures ‘to prevent, treat and control epidemic and endemic diseases’ to be an<br />

obligation of ‘comparable priority’ (para 44(c)). On the right to health in<br />

international law, see generally BCA Toebes The right to health as a human rights<br />

in international law (1999).<br />

100 The Court deals briefly with the ambit of the right of access to social security in<br />

terms of section 27(1)(c) in Khosa (n 4 above) at paras 46-47.<br />

101<br />

As noted by the Court in Grootboom (n 2 above) para 41, the programme which<br />

the state is obliged to adopt to give effect to socio-economic rights ‘must be<br />

capable of facilitating the realisation of the right.’ On <strong>this</strong> point, see K McLean<br />

‘Housing’ in Woolman et al (n 92 above) Chapter 55.<br />

102 Housing rights are protected in article 16 of the European Social Charter, 1961<br />

and articles 16 and 31 of the European Social Charter (Revised), 1996. A system of<br />

collective complaints was instituted through the Additional Protocol to the<br />

European Social Charter Providing for a System of Collective Complaints, 1995.


324 Chapter 18<br />

Charter. Thus in the complaint of European Roma Rights Centre v<br />

Greece, the Committee held:<br />

The right to housing permits the exercise of many other rights — both<br />

civil and political as well as economic, social and cultural. It is also of<br />

central importance to the family. The Committee recalls its previous<br />

case law to the effect that in order to satisfy Article 16 states must<br />

promote the provision of an adequate supply of housing for families,<br />

take the needs of families into account in housing policies and ensure<br />

that existing housing be of an adequate standard and include essential<br />

services (such as heating and electricity). The Committee has stated<br />

that adequate housing refers not only to a dwelling which must not be<br />

sub-standard and must have essential amenities, but also to a dwelling<br />

of suitable size considering the composition of the family in residence.<br />

Furthermore the obligation to promote and provide housing extends to<br />

security from unlawful eviction. 103<br />

The purpose of considering international and comparative law sources<br />

is not so that they can be slavishly followed, but rather because they<br />

broaden the range of options available to courts in developing the<br />

interpretation of socio-economic rights. They also ensure that the<br />

Court is aware of applicable international law standards, and the<br />

practices of other open and democratic societies. As Kent Roach<br />

observes: 104<br />

A globalised world is one where people, including judges, engage in<br />

multiple and ongoing conversations that cross borders. It is hopefully a<br />

world characterised by a sense of openness, modesty and willingness to<br />

learn from others.<br />

Ultimately, the South African courts remain under a duty to consider<br />

which interpretations best advance the values and transformative<br />

commitments of the Constitution in the current political, economic<br />

and social context of South Africa. However, a reflective<br />

consideration of the interpretation of socio-economic rights in other<br />

international and comparative jurisdictions should generate new<br />

options and possibilities in considering our own jurisprudence. This<br />

openness to on-going self-examination and renewal is essential if<br />

socio-economic rights are to fulfil their transformative potential<br />

under the Constitution.<br />

Reasonableness review should thus include a more principled and<br />

systematic interpretation of the content of the various socioeconomic<br />

rights, the values at stake in particular cases and the impact<br />

103<br />

104<br />

European Roma Rights Centre v Greece Complaint No. 15/2003 para 24. See also<br />

European Roma Rights Centre v Italy Complaint No. 27/2004; European Roma<br />

Rights Centre v Bulgaria Complaint No. 31/2005.<br />

K Roach ‘Constitutional, remedial, and international dialogue about rights: The<br />

Canadian experience’ (2004–2005) 40 Texas International Law Journal 537 538.


Sandra Liebenberg 325<br />

of the denial of access to these rights on the complainant group. A<br />

consideration of impact would require close attention to the<br />

historical, social, economic and political context in which groups<br />

experience a denial of access to socio-economic rights. The courts<br />

should first engage with the content of the rights and the context and<br />

implications of the alleged violation, and avoid moving too quickly to<br />

a consideration of the state’s justificatory arguments. This approach<br />

will help guard against reasonableness degenerating into an<br />

unprincipled and unduly deferential standard of review.<br />

A further dimension of reasonableness review which requires<br />

development is the standard of justification which should be applied<br />

in various types of socio-economic rights cases. One of the advantages<br />

of the minimum core approach is that it imposes a high burden of<br />

justification in contexts where people are deprived of the basic<br />

necessities of life. This helps promote social and economic policies<br />

which are orientated toward ensuring that people’s basic needs are<br />

met. 105 When people’s basic needs go unmet, they live in conditions<br />

which are inconsistent with human dignity and freedom, and are<br />

unable to participate as equals in society. Thus in Grootboom, the<br />

Court observed:<br />

The right of access to adequate housing is entrenched because we value<br />

human beings and want to ensure that they are afforded their basic<br />

human needs. A society must seek to ensure that the basic necessities of<br />

life are provided to all if it is to be a society based on human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom. 106<br />

This advantage of the minimum core approach can be incorporated<br />

within the framework of reasonableness review by placing a heavy<br />

burden of justification on the state in circumstances where a person<br />

or group lacks access to a basic socio-economic service or resource<br />

105<br />

The Constitution prescribes that one of the basic values and principles governing<br />

public administration in South Africa is that ‘[p]eople’s needs must be responded<br />

to, and the public must be encouraged to participate in policy-making.’ (FC sec<br />

195(1)(e)).<br />

106 Grootboom (n 2 above) para 44. See also Khosa (n 4 above) para 52. In Khosa,<br />

Mokgoro J further noted that ‘decisions about the allocation of public benefits<br />

represent the extent to which poor people are treated as equal members of<br />

society.’ Khosa (n 4 above) para 74 (footnotes omitted).


326 Chapter 18<br />

corresponding to the rights in FC sections 26 and 27. 107 The Court<br />

itself has acknowledged that there ‘may be cases where it may be<br />

possible and appropriate to have regard to the content of a minimum<br />

core obligation to determine whether the measures taken by the state<br />

are reasonable.’ 108<br />

In determining what constitutes a basic social need or the<br />

necessities of life, the courts need not be guided by a single<br />

overarching standard such as biological survival. Instead, it is of<br />

critical importance that they engage in a context-sensitive<br />

assessment of the impact of the deprivation on the particular group.<br />

In assessing the severity of the impact, the courts should consider the<br />

implications of the lack of access to the resource or service in<br />

question for other intersecting rights and values such as the rights to<br />

life, freedom and security of the person, equality and human<br />

dignity. 109 Courts should also be alert to the ways in which the denial<br />

of access to the particular right creates or reinforces patterns of<br />

inequality and marginalisation in our society. 110 A failure to ensure<br />

such basic social provisioning should only be justifiable when<br />

resources are demonstrably inadequate, 111 or other compelling<br />

justifications exist. The latter may include, for example, competing<br />

urgent priorities which are justifiable in an open and democratic<br />

society based on human dignity, equality and freedom. 112<br />

107<br />

In Rail Commuters (n 11 above) para 88 the Constitutional Court held that the<br />

assessment of reasonableness should include, amongst others factors, ‘the extent<br />

of any threat to fundamental rights should the duty not be met as well as the<br />

intensity of any harm that may result. The more grave is the threat to<br />

fundamental rights, the greater is the responsibility on the duty-bearer.’ This was<br />

in the context of the duty of public companies in charge of rail transport to take<br />

reasonable measures to ensure the safety and security of commuters. These<br />

positive obligations were derived from reading the South African Transport<br />

Services Act 9 of 1989 in the light of the Constitution, particularly sections 10<br />

(human dignity), 11 (right to life) and 12 (the right to freedom and security of the<br />

person). This illustrates how these rights, traditionally regarded as falling within<br />

the civil and political rights camp, also impose positive duties on the state and<br />

that the courts are prepared to adopt a similar standard of reasonableness for<br />

assessing their compliance with these duties.<br />

108<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) para 33; Treatment Action Campaign (n 3 above) para 34.<br />

109 In Khosa (n 4 above) Mokgoro J was at pains to emphasise the implications of<br />

socio-economic deprivation for other rights and values in the Bill of Rights. See,<br />

eg, paras 40–45 and 49.<br />

110 On the interrelationship between socio-economic rights, and the right and value<br />

of equality, see Liebenberg & Goldblatt (n 72 above).<br />

111<br />

The UNCESCR has held that: ‘In order for a state party to be able to attribute its<br />

failure to meet at least its minimum core obligations to a lack of available<br />

resources it must demonstrate that every effort has been made to use all<br />

resources that are at its disposition in an effort to satisfy, as a matter of priority,<br />

those minimum obligations.’ General Comment 3 (n 5 above) para 10.<br />

112 See, for example, David Bilchitz’s suggestions regarding possible grounds of<br />

justification for the non-fulfillment of minimum core obligations. Bilchitz Poverty<br />

and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 212–213.


Sandra Liebenberg 327<br />

The seriousness of the impact of the deprivation in question may<br />

warrant a strict proportionality requirement approximating the<br />

section 36 test. Proportionality should, in the context of positive<br />

socio-economic rights claims, also require the state to consider lesser<br />

forms of provisioning where it is not possible to meet everyone’s basic<br />

needs within current resource constraints. 113 A strict standard of<br />

scrutiny was illustrated in the Khosa judgment where the fact that a<br />

vulnerable group of complainants (non-nationals) was denied access<br />

to a social grant with the effect that they were forced into relations<br />

of dependence on their community triggered ‘a hard look’ review of<br />

the state’s policy and budgetary justifications. 114<br />

It is currently unclear whether the Court will confine its scrutiny<br />

to the resources allocated in the budget to particular programmes or<br />

Departments or whether it will be prepared to examine the resources<br />

available to the state as a whole. Both a textual and purposive reading<br />

of sections 26(2) and 27(2) suggests that a broad concept of the<br />

state’s ‘available resources’ should be adopted. Allowing the state to<br />

rely simply on its own budgetary allocations would defeat the purpose<br />

of socio-economic rights by allowing the state to determine the<br />

extent of its own obligations. Thus courts should examine the<br />

resources available in the national budget as a whole as opposed to<br />

focusing exclusively on existing allocations. 115 To enable the courts to<br />

conduct <strong>this</strong> assessment, it is imperative that the state be required to<br />

place the necessary budgetary and policy information before the<br />

court in support of its justificatory arguments.<br />

This approach to the review of positive socio-economic rights<br />

claims is not premised on a dichotomous two-tier distinction between<br />

core and non-core interests. Compliance with socio-economic rights<br />

obligations is assessed in terms of the single evaluative criterion of<br />

reasonableness. However, reasonableness review must incorporate<br />

substantive factors such as the interpretation of the relevant socio-<br />

113<br />

On the need to ensure that reasonableness review imposes a strong burden of<br />

justification on the state and incorporates a proportionality analysis in cases<br />

where litigants seek access to basic needs, see Liebenberg (n 25 above) 21–29;<br />

and (n 8 above) 31–33. The UNCESCR has emphasised that, even in times of severe<br />

resource constraints, states are obliged to put in place ‘relatively low-cost<br />

programmes’ to protect vulnerable members of society. General Comment 3 (n 5<br />

above) para 12.<br />

114 Khosa (n 4 above) paras 53–67.<br />

115 For an argument that litigants have generally been too timid in urging judicial<br />

review of government’s resource allocation priorities, see K Lehmann ‘In defense<br />

of the Constitutional Court: Litigating socio-economic rights and the myth of the<br />

minimum core’ (2006) 22 American University International Law Review 163. For<br />

arguments in favour of a broad interpretation of the state’s ‘available resources’<br />

to incorporate the national budget as a whole, see D Moellendorf ‘Reasoning<br />

about resources: Soobramoney and the future of socio-economic rights claims’<br />

(1998) 14 South African Journal on Human Rights 327; Bilchitz Poverty and<br />

Fundamental Rights (n 31 above) 227-230.


328 Chapter 18<br />

economic right, and a detailed, contextual assessment of the impact<br />

of the denial of the right on the complainant group. This<br />

interpretation and assessment should entail a consideration of both<br />

relevant international and comparative law, as well as the<br />

implications of the denial of access to basic socio-economic needs for<br />

the enjoyment of other intersecting rights and constitutional values.<br />

In cases where individuals or groups lack access to a resource or<br />

service which has a severe impact on them, a higher standard of<br />

justification should be imposed upon the state. Where the service in<br />

question is of a more tertiary nature, and the evidence suggests that<br />

ordering its provision will prejudice other basic service and<br />

redistributive programmes, a greater margin of discretion can be<br />

afforded to the state in its priority setting. 116 However, such<br />

relaxation does not absolve the courts from their duty to undertake a<br />

serious assessment of whether available resources do not in fact<br />

warrant the provision of the more extensive socio-economic resource<br />

or service. It should be borne in mind that the purpose of the rights in<br />

FC sections 26 and 27 is to ensure the full realisation of the relevant<br />

rights. Although the state is afforded a reasonable measure of latitude<br />

to achieve <strong>this</strong> ‘progressively’, it cannot defer its obligation to ensure<br />

the full realisation of the rights when the requisite resources exist.<br />

6 Conclusion<br />

The approach developed above is intended to facilitate a relational<br />

and dialogic approach to the interpretation of socio-economic rights<br />

whilst preserving the features of the minimum core approach that<br />

requires heightened scrutiny of acts and omissions which result in a<br />

denial of basic needs. As such, it resonates with an approach to rightsbased<br />

transformation in South Africa which values participatory<br />

democracy and public deliberation. Chief Justice Pius Langa reminds<br />

us of the tradition of critical scholarship 117 in South Africa which<br />

emphasises the ‘permanent ideal’ of transformation embraced by our<br />

Constitution:<br />

On that view, transformation is not a temporary phenomenon that ends<br />

when we all have equal access to resources and basic services and when<br />

lawyers and judges embrace a culture of justification. Transformation is<br />

a permanent ideal, a way of looking at the world that creates a space in<br />

which dialogue and contestation are truly possible, in which new ways of<br />

116 See Soobramoney (n 1 above).<br />

117 See, eg, H Botha ‘Metaphoric reasoning and transformative constitutionalism<br />

(Part I)’ (2002) Tydskrif vir die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg 612; ‘Metaphoric reasoning<br />

and transformative constitutionalism (Part II)’ (2003) Tydskrif vir die Suid-<br />

Afrikaanse Reg 20; A van der Walt ‘Dancing with codes — protecting, developing<br />

and deconstructing property rights in a constitutional state’ (2001) 118 South<br />

African Law Journal 258.


Sandra Liebenberg 329<br />

being are constantly explored and created, accepted and rejected and<br />

in which change is unpredictable but the idea of change is constant. 118<br />

The approach I have advocated has the further advantage of<br />

narrowing the distinction between the way in which the courts review<br />

the positive and negative duties imposed by socio-economic rights.<br />

This distinction is based on the false premise that the current patterns<br />

of those who have and of those who lack access to resources and<br />

services are perpetuated by the state through existing rules of public<br />

or private law.<br />

Law and legal processes alone cannot bridge the chasm between<br />

the realities of poverty and inequality that pervade our society and<br />

the constitutional ideal of a new society founded on human dignity,<br />

equality and freedom. However, when cases concerning socioeconomic<br />

rights do come before the courts, it is important that the<br />

jurisprudence applied to these claims facilitates the transformation<br />

of unjust social and economic relations entrenched by current laws. A<br />

more robust model of reasonableness review which engages seriously<br />

with the purposes and values underlying socio-economic rights — and<br />

the devastating impact of poverty on any individual’s life chances —<br />

will help these rights fulfill their transformative potential.<br />

118 Langa (n 8 above) 354.


19 Reply<br />

On ‘dialogue’, ‘translation’ and ‘voice’:<br />

A reply to Sandra Liebenberg<br />

Marius Pieterse*<br />

1 Introduction<br />

A substantive jurisprudence on social rights ... can serve to enhance the<br />

participatory capabilities of those living in poverty and inequality. At its<br />

best it should constantly remind us of our constitutional commitment to<br />

establishing a society based on social justice, and facilitate the inclusion<br />

of marginalised voices in the debate on what is required to achieve such<br />

a society. 1<br />

Sandra Liebenberg used these words to conclude a recent article on<br />

the transformative potential of socio-economic rights adjudication. In<br />

‘Socio-economic rights: Revisiting the reasonableness review/<br />

minimum core debate’, Liebenberg essentially builds on <strong>this</strong><br />

conclusion. She evaluates the manner and extent to which the two<br />

most often-discussed approaches to socio-economic rights<br />

adjudication in South Africa (the ‘reasonableness approach’ followed<br />

by the Constitutional Court and the ‘minimum core approach’ often<br />

contended for by is critics) facilitate and contribute to discussions<br />

over the meaning of socio-economic rights. Given that these<br />

discussions, in turn, contribute to overarching deliberations over what<br />

is required to achieve a society based on social justice, Liebenberg’s<br />

* I am grateful to Michael Bishop and Sandra Liebenberg for their critical<br />

engagement with a previous draft of <strong>this</strong> reply.<br />

1<br />

S Liebenberg ‘Needs, rights and transformation: Adjudicating social rights’ (2006)<br />

17 Stellenbosch Law Review 5 36.<br />

331


332 Chapter 19<br />

evaluation doubles as an assessment of the transformative potential<br />

of the two approaches.<br />

In conducting the evaluation, Liebenberg joins other scholars in<br />

endorsing a ‘relational and dialogic approach’ to socio-economic<br />

rights-interpretation and, ultimately, to transformation. 2 This approach<br />

views neither rights nor transformation as concepts that are<br />

fixed in content or capable of universal or lasting definition. Instead,<br />

it embraces the reality of reasonable disagreement over the<br />

(continuously shifting) aims of a socially just society and over the<br />

means through which these aims are to be achieved. It attempts to<br />

broaden the democratic base of institutional processes (such as<br />

judicial review) through which rights are given meaning, by<br />

simultaneously conceiving of such processes as invitations and<br />

contributions to ongoing dialogues over such meaning, which are, in<br />

turn, viewed as constitutive strands in an overarching deliberation on<br />

the meaning of social justice, transformation and the common good. 3<br />

Whereas theories on constitutional dialogue extend beyond<br />

questions of judicial review and rights-interpretation, my focus in <strong>this</strong><br />

reply to Liebenberg is limited to the manner in which transformation<br />

is conceived and advanced by a dialogic approach to the<br />

interpretation of socio-economic rights. In particular, I am interested<br />

in the manner in which a dialogic approach facilitates the ‘translation’<br />

of socio-economic rights from conceptually abstract principles into<br />

more concrete, claimable entitlements. 4 I regard such ‘translation’ as<br />

being necessary to offset the potentially counter-transformative use<br />

of human rights to deflate and ultimately defeat claims by individuals<br />

and social movements for egalitarian redistribution, basic service<br />

provision or the satisfaction of individual needs. 5 I therefore view the<br />

calls by Liebenberg and others for a dialogic approach to socio-<br />

2 See, in particular, R Dixon ‘Creating dialogue about socio-economic rights: Strongform<br />

v weak-form judicial review revisited’ (2007) 5 International Journal of<br />

Constitutional Law 391; C Steinberg ‘Can reasonableness protect the poor? A<br />

review of South Africa’s socio-economic rights jurisprudence’ (2006) 123 South<br />

African Law Journal 264 272-73.<br />

3<br />

S Liebenberg ‘Socio-economic rights: Revisiting the reasonableness review/<br />

minimum core debate’ in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds) Constitutional<br />

conversations (2008) text accompanying n 37-44, 50, 99-101. See also Dixon (n 2<br />

above) text accompanying n 53-55. For a cogent exposition and evaluation of the<br />

various strands of ‘dialogic theory’ and associated approaches to constitutional<br />

interpretation, see C Bateup ‘The dialogic promise: Assessing the normative<br />

potential of theories of constitutional dialogue’ (2006) 71 Brooklyn Law Review<br />

1109.<br />

4 On the notion of ‘translation’ in <strong>this</strong> context, see D Brand ‘Introduction to socioeconomic<br />

rights in the South African Constitution’ in D Brand & CH Heyns (eds)<br />

Socio-economic rights in South Africa 1 ed (2005) 1 12-18.<br />

5 See M Pieterse ‘Eating socio-economic rights: The usefulness of rights talk in<br />

alleviating social hardship revisited’ (2007) 29 Human Rights Quarterly 796 820-<br />

821.


Reply - Marius Pieterse 333<br />

economic rights interpretation as indicating a preference for multiactor<br />

dialogue as the means of such translation.<br />

This reply proceeds to consider, as Liebenberg has done, the<br />

manner in which the ‘minimum core’ and ‘reasonableness’<br />

approaches to the interpretation of socio-economic rights<br />

respectively structure and contribute to societal dialogue over the<br />

meaning of these rights. As will become apparent, I agree with<br />

Liebenberg on the appropriateness of dialogue as the means of<br />

translation, the shortcomings of a minimum core approach from a<br />

dialogic perspective and the need for the reasonableness approach to<br />

be grounded more firmly in an understanding of the content of the<br />

rights it seeks to vindicate. However, I am somewhat more<br />

sentimental over the loss of the language of entitlement that was<br />

inherent in minimum core arguments rejected by the Constitutional<br />

Court and less optimistic over the potential of the reasonableness<br />

approach to foster the kind of open and responsive dialogue over the<br />

meaning of socio-economic rights that both Liebenberg and myself<br />

would like to see. In particular, I express concern over the manner in<br />

which the current formulation of the reasonableness approach<br />

appears to divert the bulk of the dialogue over the meaning of socioeconomic<br />

rights to the political process, to silence the voices of<br />

certain vital participants to the dialogue and to restrict the judicial<br />

role in the overarching societal discussion over the means and ends of<br />

transformation.<br />

I hope that <strong>this</strong> expression of my concerns serves to strengthen<br />

Liebenberg’s call for a more substantive judicial approach to<br />

reasonableness, that builds on, or at least incorporates, a ‘more<br />

principled and systematic interpretation of the content of the various<br />

socio-economic rights, the values at stake in particular cases and the<br />

impact of the denial of access to these rights on the complainant<br />

group’. 6 I also hope to emphasise the need for such an approach to be<br />

open and responsive to claims of individual entitlement.<br />

2 Translation through dialogue: Mapping the field and the<br />

players 7<br />

In order for a dialogic approach to constitutional interpretation both<br />

to ease separation of powers tensions inherent in judicial review and<br />

to enhance participatory democracy, it is important to conceive<br />

broadly of both the entities that are permitted to contribute to<br />

dialogue over constitutional meaning and the venues where such<br />

6 Liebenberg (n 3 above) 324.<br />

7<br />

In <strong>this</strong> section I reiterate and elaborate on points raised in Pieterse (n 5 above)<br />

819-822.


334 Chapter 19<br />

dialogue is allowed to occur. It has therefore been argued that<br />

dialogue over constitutional meaning should be conceived as taking<br />

place simultaneously between the judiciary and the democratic<br />

branches of state as partners in the endeavour of constitutional<br />

interpretation, between these entities and the broader constitutional<br />

community (including other governmental agencies and civil society)<br />

as well as between these entities and the citizenry at large. 8 Such<br />

dialogue should further be understood to occur simultaneously in<br />

various arenas — at the polling booth, during legislative and law<br />

reform processes, in the pages of newspapers and law reviews, on the<br />

streets and, importantly, in the courtroom.<br />

There are unique strengths and weaknesses to the institutional or<br />

societal positions of each of the potential contributors to the dialogue<br />

over constitutional meaning that obviously affect their suitability as<br />

translators of socio-economic rights from abstraction into reality. In<br />

<strong>this</strong> section, I briefly highlight some of these strengths and<br />

weaknesses in relation to certain of the participants in the South<br />

African dialogue over the content of socio-economic rights.<br />

Prime among these are the legislature and executive policymakers,<br />

which possess the democratic mandate, the expertise and<br />

the resources to define the scope of socio-economic entitlements and<br />

to establish and operate structural mechanisms for their<br />

enforcement. 9 The legislature, in particular, is well-suited to dialogic<br />

translation, due to the deliberative nature of the legislative process<br />

and to the fact that it is generally open to arguments advanced by<br />

social movements. However, a drawback of legislative translation is<br />

that it tends to cast entitlements in stone, hence limiting their scope<br />

to the (often under-inclusive) parameters of the enactment and<br />

foreclosing (albeit not entirely) further dialogue over their content. 10<br />

As Rosalind Dixon shows, translation through the legislative process<br />

may further be compromised by ‘legislative blind spots’ (arising, for<br />

instance, where the legislature ‘fail[s] to recognise that a law could<br />

be applied in a way that infringes rights’; ‘fail[s] to anticipate the<br />

impact of laws on rights because they do not appreciate, adequately,<br />

the perspective of rights claimants with very different life<br />

experiences and viewpoints’ or fails to ‘perceive ways in which a<br />

rights-based claim may be more fully accommodated, without undue<br />

8 See Bateup (n 3 above) 1157-1159, 1168-1169 and 1174-1176. See also S Woolman<br />

& H Botha ‘Limitations’ in S Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South<br />

Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 34.<br />

9 On the necessity of such structural backing for effective translation, see LA<br />

Williams ‘Issues and challenges in addressing poverty and legal rights: A<br />

comparative United States/South African analysis’ (2005) 21 South African<br />

Journal on Human Rights 436 439. On legislative and executive translation of<br />

socio-economic rights in South Africa generally, see Brand (n 4 above) 12-16.<br />

10 Williams (n 9 above) 455.


Reply - Marius Pieterse 335<br />

cost to the relevant legislative objective’) as well as by legislative<br />

‘burdens of inertia’ (relating, for instance, to the time-consuming<br />

nature of the legislative process, lack of capacity and the partypolitical<br />

driving forces behind legislative agendas). 11<br />

Civil society and non-governmental institutions may contribute to<br />

constitutional dialogue. At their best, they will engage directly<br />

legislatures and policy makers and facilitate and structure further<br />

debate between these institutions, social movements and the<br />

individual beneficiaries of rights. In South Africa, particular mention<br />

should be made of the role of the South African Human Rights<br />

Commission (SAHRC). The SAHRC is a constitutionally created, independent<br />

institution tasked with monitoring government compliance<br />

with socio-economic rights as well as with conducting research,<br />

raising awareness, initiating and contributing to judicial proceedings<br />

and with other functions relating to the elaboration of the content of<br />

human rights. 12<br />

Beyond institutional players, social movements, rights-activists<br />

and individual litigants all have a crucial role in translating socioeconomic<br />

rights from ‘the bottom up’. In particular, individual<br />

beneficiaries of socio-economic rights are best-placed to articulate<br />

the needs that the rights should aim to satisfy. 13 By voicing their<br />

needs in the form of rights-claims, beneficiaries direct the subjectmatter<br />

of the constitutional dialogue to issues directly pertaining to<br />

the satisfaction of these needs. However, the very poverty and<br />

material deprivation that shape these needs often contribute to<br />

rendering their expression inaudible to political and judicial<br />

processes. For instance, the voices of individual victims of socioeconomic<br />

rights violations are often muted by the victims’ inability to<br />

11<br />

Dixon (2 above) text accompanying n 60-62.<br />

12 See FC sec 184 read with the Human Rights Commission Act 54 of 1994. On the<br />

role of the SAHRC in the translation of socio-economic rights see CH Heyns ‘Taking<br />

socio-economic rights seriously: The “domestic reporting procedure” and the role<br />

of the South African Human Rights Commission’ (1999) 32 De Jure 195; J Klaaren<br />

‘A second look at the South African Human Rights Commission, access to<br />

information, and the promotion of socioeconomic rights’ (2005) 27 Human Rights<br />

Quarterly 539; S Liebenberg ‘Violations of socio-economic rights: The role of the<br />

South African Human Rights Commission’ in P Andrews & S Ellmann (eds) The<br />

Post-Apartheid Constitutions: Perspectives on South Africa’s Basic Law (2001)<br />

405; DG Newman ‘Institutional monitoring of social and economic rights: A South<br />

African case study and a new research agenda’ (2003) 19 South African Journal on<br />

Human Rights 189.<br />

13 See, eg, MJ Matsuda ‘Looking to the bottom: Critical legal studies and<br />

reparations’ (1987) 22 Harvard Civil Liberties Civil Rights Law Review 323; PJ<br />

Williams ‘Alchemical notes: Reconstructing ideals from deconstructed rights’<br />

(1987) 22 Harvard Civil Liberties Civil Rights Law Review 401 410-414.


336 Chapter 19<br />

access the justice system, their lack of rights-awareness, and their<br />

scepticism over or distrust of judicial or political processes. 14<br />

Accordingly, the voices of the most vulnerable beneficiaries of<br />

socio-economic rights often become audible only if expressed through<br />

social movements. By placing pressure on political institutions and by<br />

strategic use of the justice system, such movements can at once<br />

implore and enable the accommodation of beneficiaries’ needs and<br />

experiences in ‘top-down’ articulations of rights. 15 However, given<br />

that social movements are primarily agenda-driven, and are unequally<br />

distributed across issues and interest groups, their unmediated<br />

prominence in processes of dialogic translation runs the risk of<br />

distorting the terms of the dialogue, by placing undue emphasis on<br />

particular agendas. 16<br />

Academic scholars, in turn, contribute to the dialogue over<br />

constitutional meaning by making researched and thoroughlytheorised<br />

interpretations of socio-economic rights accessible to both<br />

‘top-down’ translators such as legislatures and courts and ‘bottomup’<br />

translation efforts by individual rights-bearers or social<br />

movements. 17 However, scholars are as equally prone to distorted<br />

perspectives as social movements. They are often far removed from<br />

the ‘real’ experiences of material deprivation and institutional<br />

translation that form the crux of the dialogue. 18<br />

Finally and, for purposes of <strong>this</strong> reply, most importantly, is the<br />

dual role of courts as translators of and translation venues for socioeconomic<br />

rights. Provided that courts are accessible, the adjudication<br />

process provides virtually the only space within which all, or most of,<br />

the other contributory voices to the dialogue over the meaning of<br />

socio-economic rights can simultaneously be present and heard.<br />

Indeed, a prime advantage of the courtroom as venue for dialogic<br />

deliberation over the meaning of socio-economic rights is that the<br />

14 See S Gloppen ‘Social rights litigation as transformation: South African<br />

perspectives’ in P Jones & K Stokke (eds) Democratising development: The<br />

politics of socio-economic rights in South Africa (2005) 153 158-159.<br />

15 See T Madlingozi ‘Post-apartheid social movements and the quest for the elusive<br />

“new” South Africa’ (2007) 34 Journal of Law & Society 77 81, 89 and 91. On the<br />

articulation of needs by social movements on behalf of socially vulnerable<br />

plaintiffs in South Africa, see M Heywood ‘Preventing mother-to-child HIV<br />

transmission in South Africa: Background, strategies and outcomes of the<br />

Treatment Action Campaign case against the Minister of Health’ (2003) 19 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 278 147.<br />

16<br />

Madlingozi (n 15 above) 92 and 94-95. For a related concern, see A Sachs ‘The<br />

judicial enforcement of socio-economic rights: The Grootboom case’ in Jones &<br />

Stokke (n 14 above) 131 149-150.<br />

17<br />

See S Liebenberg ‘Socio-economic rights under a transformative constitution: The<br />

role of the academic community and NGOs’ (2007) 8(1) Economic and Social<br />

Rights Review 3 7-8.<br />

18<br />

See generally T Madlingozi ‘Legal academics and progressive politics in South<br />

Africa: Moving beyond the ivory tower’ (Nov 2006) 2 Pulp Fictions 5.


Reply - Marius Pieterse 337<br />

individual beneficiaries of socio-economic rights are empowered to<br />

participate on a more-or-less equal footing with more powerful<br />

institutional players. 19<br />

Provided that they are sufficiently legally or constitutionally<br />

empowered to do so, judges may contribute invaluably to the<br />

translation of socio-economic rights through their interpretation and<br />

vindication of these rights in the concrete contexts of particular<br />

cases. Given that socio-economic rights are fully justiciable under the<br />

Final Constitution, that it grants courts significant interpretative<br />

leeway and remedial flexibility and that it requires of them to take<br />

rights’ international law meaning into account when considering their<br />

content, there can be little doubt that South African courts are<br />

empowered to engage in generous, purposive and thoroughly<br />

theorised interpretation of socio-economic rights. 20 Moreover, judges<br />

are generally regarded as being reasonably well-equipped translators.<br />

Judges are independent and impartial, as well as trained,<br />

experienced and skilled in the interpretation of legal provisions and<br />

their application in concrete cases. 21 Courts are further well-placed<br />

to correct for problems occasioned by legislative ‘blind spots’ or<br />

‘burdens of inertia’, 22 not least because they ‘handle real cases and<br />

thus can test more effectively the particular implications of abstract<br />

principles and discover problems the legislature could not forecast’. 23<br />

But there are also important reasons not to award judges a<br />

monopoly over the translation of socio-economic rights. Most<br />

obviously, judges lack the direct democratic legitimacy associated<br />

with the legislative and political branches of government. They are<br />

also generally drawn from privileged sectors of society: as a result,<br />

they are often unfamiliar with, or insensitive to, the needs and the<br />

experiences of society’s materially deprived sectors. Furthermore,<br />

South African judges have been trained in a formalist and liberalindividualist<br />

legal culture that is not favourably disposed towards the<br />

notion of enforceable socio-economic rights. 24<br />

19 See D Davis ‘Socio-economic rights in South Africa: The record of the<br />

Constitutional Court after ten years’ (2004) 5(5) Economic and Social Rights<br />

Review 3 7.<br />

20 See, eg, FC secs 36, 38 and 39(1). For discussion of these and other ‘enabling’<br />

provisions, see M Pieterse ‘Resuscitating socio-economic rights: Constitutional<br />

entitlements to health care services’ (2006) 22 South African Journal on Human<br />

Rights 473 478-479.<br />

21 See also M Pieterse ‘Coming to terms with judicial enforcement of socio-economic<br />

rights’ (2004) 20 South African Journal on Human Rights 383 395.<br />

22 Dixon (n 2 above) text accompanying n 79.<br />

23 H Spector ‘Judicial review, rights and democracy’ (2003) 22 Law & Philosophy 285<br />

319.<br />

24 For a discussion of these and related problems, see Pieterse (n 21 above) 390-399.


338 Chapter 19<br />

Since court judgments carry significant authority and imply a<br />

measure of finality, judicial interpretations of socio-economic rights<br />

may sometimes foreclose or unduly limit dialogue over constitutional<br />

meaning. This result is particularly unwelcome in socio-economic<br />

rights matters: A significant number of differently situated persons<br />

may possess diverse needs implicated by a single right. It may also be<br />

pernicious where such finality is implied in relation to an overbroad<br />

or unduly restrictive interpretation of a right. 25 Because of the<br />

substantial costs associated with access to justice, it is further<br />

possible that courts may continuously be seized by socio-economic<br />

rights claims representing the interests of relatively privileged sectors<br />

of society and that their translation of the rights in such cases may<br />

reflect such interests at the expense of the concerns of the most<br />

vulnerable.<br />

Nevertheless, we may expect courts to remain vital venues for<br />

dialogue over constitutional meaning, not least since the Constitution<br />

itself foresees such a role for them. 26 Because judges are in charge of<br />

court proceedings and of transcribing the outcome of such<br />

proceedings in the form of judgments, their role is not only to<br />

contribute to courtroom dialogue over constitutional meaning, but<br />

also to direct its terms and to determine the manner in which all<br />

participants conduct themselves. Given that their judgments have an<br />

impact on the contours of future dialogue, even in contexts beyond<br />

those in which they were conceived, the manner in which courts<br />

conduct themselves in <strong>this</strong> respect is of particular significance.<br />

It is therefore important that any judicial ‘approach’ to socioeconomic<br />

rights adjudication neither monopolises the process of<br />

translation through dialogue, nor foregoes participation therein. Any<br />

such approach must further be open to dialogic contributions by as<br />

many of the entities discussed above as possible. It should aim to<br />

maximise the progressive potential of each individual contribution<br />

without unduly favouring any one of them, lest it be tainted by the<br />

shortcomings associated with exclusive translation by the favoured<br />

entity. Finally, the approach should simultaneously remain true to the<br />

aim of translation (turning conceptually empty background norms into<br />

vehicles for the effective confrontation of denial of need) and enable<br />

all parties to the dialogue to participate freely in the overarching<br />

societal discourse on transformation.<br />

25<br />

See Liebenberg (n 17 above) 7.<br />

26 See FC secs 39, 165 and 172(1).


Reply - Marius Pieterse 339<br />

3 Minimum core, reasonableness and translation through<br />

dialogue<br />

As Liebenberg explains, South African scholarly debates over the<br />

‘proper’ method of dealing with socio-economic rights claims have<br />

predominantly boiled down to the expression of a preference for one<br />

of two, seemingly opposed, approaches to the adjudication of the<br />

positive duties implied by sections 26 and 27 of the Final Constitution.<br />

On the one hand, much support has been expressed for a ‘minimum<br />

core approach’. This approach turns on the identification and the<br />

immediate enforcement of basic entitlements (corresponding with<br />

human survival interests) inherent in socio-economic rights. 27<br />

Arguments consistent with <strong>this</strong> approach (which has foundations in<br />

international law) were raised by the amici curiae in the two most<br />

high-profile socio-economic rights matters thus far heard by the<br />

Constitutional Court: Government of the Republic of South Africa v<br />

Grootboom (Grootboom) 28 and Minister of Health v Treatment Action<br />

Campaign (TAC). 29 In both cases, the Constitutional Court rejected<br />

these arguments. Instead it adopted a different approach, that of<br />

‘reasonableness’. The ‘reasonableness approach’ is based on the<br />

constitutional requirement that measures adopted in pursuit of the<br />

progressive realisation of socio-economic rights must be reasonable<br />

and involves the scrutiny of laws and polices aimed at giving effect to<br />

the rights, for adherence to a number of requirements associated with<br />

good governance. The ‘reasonableness approach’, which tends to be<br />

criticised by proponents of a ‘minimum core approach’, 30 has also<br />

attracted its fair share of supporters, most of whom justify their<br />

preference for ‘reasonableness’ by referring to the shortcomings of<br />

the ‘minimum core approach’. 31<br />

27 For the most thorough theoretical defense of <strong>this</strong> approach in the South African<br />

context, see D Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights: The justification and<br />

enforcement of socio-economic rights (2007) 178-235.<br />

28 2001 1 SA 46 (CC), 2000 11 BCLR 1169 (CC).<br />

29<br />

2002 5 SA 721 (CC), 2002 10 BCLR 1033 (CC).<br />

30 See, eg, D Bilchitz ‘Towards a reasonable approach to the minimum core: Laying<br />

the foundations for future socio-economic rights jurisprudence’ (2003) 19 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 1. See also D Bilchitz ‘Health’ in S Woolman et<br />

al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2006) Chapter 56A.<br />

31 See, eg, Steinberg (n 2 above); M Wesson ‘Grootboom and beyond: Reassessing<br />

the socio-economic jurisprudence of the South African Constitutional Court’<br />

(2004) 20 South African Journal on Human Rights 284.


340 Chapter 19<br />

Through the years, Liebenberg has engaged critically with<br />

features of both of these approaches. 32 In her current paper, she<br />

evaluates both from a dialogic perspective and concludes that, while<br />

a minimum core approach valuably captures part of the content of<br />

socio-economic rights and ‘imposes a high burden of justification in<br />

contexts where people are deprived of the basic necessities of life’, 33<br />

a reasonableness approach is better suited to a society committed to<br />

translation through dialogue. A reasonableness approach ‘avoids<br />

closure and creates the on-going possibility of challenging various<br />

forms of socio-economic deprivations in the different contexts in<br />

which they arise’. 34<br />

In relation to minimum core, Liebenberg explains how the onceoff<br />

judicial formulation and enforcement of a comprehensive core<br />

standard can frustrate dialogue over the content of socio-economic<br />

rights. She shows, convincingly, that a minimum core approach may<br />

operate to ‘stifle institutional conversation and collaboration<br />

between the three branches of government’, may result in over- or<br />

under-inclusive specification of obligations, may invite undue<br />

reductionism and/or minimalism in need–definition, may ‘exclude or<br />

marginalise the needs of various groups that do not fit the background<br />

norms informing the definition of core obligations’ and may<br />

oversimplify the interaction between and co-dependence of<br />

interconnected socio-economic needs of varying levels of complexity,<br />

urgency, and cost. 35<br />

I agree that the adoption of a minimum core approach may<br />

amount to the once-off, ‘top-down’ imposition of a singular,<br />

contested, point of view that denies and precludes reasonable<br />

disagreement over its conceptual foundations, contextual appropriateness,<br />

feasibility and logic. 36 But, to be fair to minimum core<br />

proponents, it need not engender such outcomes. It should be<br />

possible for courts to engage in a far more gradual, open-ended,<br />

context-specific and contingent process of case-by-case elaboration<br />

of the essential minimum content of rights, in a manner that invites,<br />

rather than forestalls, dialogue. 37<br />

32 See, eg, S Liebenberg ‘South Africa’s evolving jurisprudence on socio-economic<br />

rights: An effective tool in challenging poverty?’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy &<br />

Development 159; S Liebenberg ‘The interpretation of socio-economic rights’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2003)<br />

Chapter 33; S Liebenberg ‘The value of human dignity in interpreting socioeconomic<br />

rights’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 1.<br />

33 Liebenberg (n 3 above) 324.<br />

34 Liebenberg (n 3 above) 320.<br />

35<br />

Liebenberg (n 3 above) 309-318. See also Dixon (n 2 above) 416-418; Steinberg (n<br />

2 above) 274-276; Wesson (n 31 above) 303-305.<br />

36 See Pieterse (n 20 above) 490-491 and authorities cited there.<br />

37<br />

Pieterse (n 20 above) 491. See further Bilchitz (n 27 above) 160; Woolman &<br />

Botha (n 8 above ) 34-104 — 34-113.


Reply - Marius Pieterse 341<br />

In any event, the Constitutional Court’s rejection of minimum<br />

core arguments in Grootboom and, especially, TAC, seemed to be<br />

motivated by more than concern about the dialogic disadvantages<br />

that are arguably inherent to the approach. Consider, for instance,<br />

the following statements in TAC:<br />

It is impossible to give everyone access even to a ‘core’ service<br />

immediately. All that is possible, and all that can be expected of the<br />

state, is that it act reasonably to provide access to the socio-economic<br />

rights identified in sections 26 and 27 on a progressive basis. 38<br />

Section 27(1) of the Constitution does not give rise to a self-standing and<br />

independent positive right enforceable irrespective of the considerations<br />

mentioned in section 27(2). Sections 27(1) and 27(2) must be<br />

read together as defining the scope of the positive rights that everyone<br />

has and the corresponding obligations on the state to ‘respect, protect,<br />

promote and fulfill’ such right. The rights conferred by sections 26(1)<br />

and 27(1) are to have ‘access’ to the services that the state is obliged to<br />

provide in terms of sections 26(2) and 27(2). 39<br />

These passages suggest that the Court’s rejection of the minimum<br />

core approach was at least partly motivated by an aversion to the<br />

notion of individual entitlement. 40<br />

This aversion was, in turn, also the driving force behind the<br />

Court’s opting for the reasonableness approach. This conclusion<br />

seems to be borne out by the fact that the approach appears to entail<br />

little or no enforceable entitlement for the beneficiaries of socioeconomic<br />

rights. 41 Indeed, both Liebenberg and minimum core<br />

proponents’ main criticism of the ‘reasonableness approach’ is that it<br />

fails to engage meaningfully with the content of the rights. 42<br />

This ‘conceptual emptiness’ of socio-economic rights conceived in<br />

terms of ‘reasonableness’ seems to indicate a potentially significant<br />

drawback of the approach from a dialogic perspective. Indeed, it<br />

38<br />

TAC (n 29 above) para 35.<br />

39 TAC (n 29 above) para 39. See also paras 31-32, 34 (‘the socio-economic rights of<br />

the Constitution should not be construed as entitling everyone to demand that<br />

the minimum core be provided to them’); 125 (‘[w]e have held that [the] policy<br />

fails to meet constitutional standards. ... That does not mean that everyone can<br />

immediately claim access to such treatment’). See further Grootboom (n 28<br />

above) para 95 (‘neither section 26 nor section 28 entitles the respondents to<br />

claim housing or shelter immediately upon demand’).<br />

40 See also D Brand ‘The proceduralisation of South African socio-economic rights<br />

jurisprudence, or “what are socio-economic rights for?”’ in H Botha et al (eds)<br />

Rights and democracy in a transformative constitution (2003) 33 46; P de Vos ‘So<br />

much to do, so little done: The right of access to anti-retroviral drugs post-<br />

Grootboom’ (2003) 7 Law, Democracy & Development 83 89.<br />

41 See I Currie ‘Bill of Rights jurisprudence’ (2002) Annual Survey of South African<br />

Law 36 72; Pieterse (n 20 above) 487 and authorities cited there.<br />

42<br />

Liebenberg (n 3 above) 318-320. See also, eg, Bilchitz (n 30 above) 5-10; Pieterse<br />

(n 21 above) 410-411 and authorities cited there.


342 Chapter 19<br />

appears altogether to prevent translation through dialogue from<br />

taking place. But <strong>this</strong> negative gloss on ‘reasonableness’ is not<br />

entirely fair. The outcome of the TAC case — that pregnant, HIVpositive<br />

women who could previously not access Nevirapine in the<br />

public sector could now do so — indicates that some translation of the<br />

right to have access to health care services has occurred. But where,<br />

and by whom?<br />

The answer, I think, lies in the textual positioning of the<br />

reasonableness standard in FC sections 26(2) and 27(2). It is the<br />

content of legislative and other measures aimed at achieving the<br />

progressive realisation of socio-economic rights that is assessed<br />

through an analysis of reasonableness, not the content of the rights<br />

themselves. 43 Nor, for the most part, does the Constitutional Court<br />

pretend to be considering anything other than the content of such<br />

measures, in either Grootboom or TAC. What the reasonableness test<br />

does do is to change the topic of the dialogue being held in the<br />

courtroom. Instead of a discussion about the translation of rights, the<br />

courtroom dialogue mainly considers the desirability of the content<br />

and the implementation of particular measures (in both cases,<br />

executive policies).<br />

But that does not mean that rights-translation is not occurring.<br />

The effect of the reasonableness approach is simply to reduce the<br />

extent to which such translation occurs in the courtroom and instead<br />

to relegate much of the actual translation exercise to the architects<br />

of the measures in question. In the TAC hearing, for instance, much<br />

was made of the fact that Nevirapine was the government’s ‘drug of<br />

choice’ in preventing mother-to-child-transmission of HIV, in<br />

accordance with its decision to provide a ‘comprehensive package of<br />

care’ for such prevention. 44 In other words, it was the Department of<br />

Health, and not the Constitutional Court, which decided whether the<br />

right to have access to reproductive health care services should<br />

include access to Nevirapine in the public sector. While a minimum<br />

core approach would have required of the Court to express an opinion<br />

on <strong>this</strong> question (or, at least, on the question of whether the right<br />

required the existence of a plan aimed at preventing mother-to-childtransmission),<br />

in terms of the reasonableness approach it could simply<br />

focus on whether seemingly arbitrary restrictions on enjoyment of<br />

access to the right, as defined elsewhere by the executive, was<br />

permissible. Similarly, the Grootboom Court could have merely<br />

insisted on the inclusion of vulnerable sectors of society within the<br />

ambit of an already formulated executive plan, without itself having<br />

43<br />

See Bilchitz (n 27 above) 143.<br />

44 Heywood (n 15 above) 285-90. See also TAC (n 29 above) paras 42, 45 and 65.


Reply - Marius Pieterse 343<br />

to indicate whether the Constitution required the state to provide<br />

housing for the poor. 45<br />

Under the current formulation of the reasonableness approach,<br />

the Constitutional Court is consciously limiting its involvement in the<br />

translation of socio-economic rights. For the most part, the Court<br />

seems content with endorsing translations by the democratic<br />

branches while ensuring that citizens derive meaningful and equal<br />

benefit from entitlements transpiring from such translation. While<br />

the Court arguably remains capable of testing democratic translations<br />

of socio-economic rights for constitutional compliance, its reluctance<br />

to make a more substantive, independent contribution to the dialogue<br />

over the meaning of the rights is (as Liebenberg agrees) lamentable.<br />

The significant margin of discretion awarded by the reasonableness<br />

approach to the democratic branches pertains not only to the form<br />

and content of their policies but also to the extent of the immediately<br />

enforceable entitlements inherent in socio-economic rights. Again<br />

<strong>this</strong> approach runs many of the risks associated with the exclusive<br />

translation of socio-economic rights by the coordinate branches.<br />

As the highest court in constitutional matters in a legal system<br />

that values precedent and legal certainty, the Constitutional Court’s<br />

reluctance to engage the content of socio-economic rights more<br />

robustly has the effect of discouraging more substantive dialogic<br />

contributions by all other, subordinate judicial fora. In <strong>this</strong> respect,<br />

the most progressive socio-economic rights judgments to come from<br />

the High Courts have been in matters that have not subsequently<br />

reached the Constitutional Court. They have either dealt with socioeconomic<br />

rights that have not yet been considered by the<br />

Constitutional Court or with the few spaces for entitlementorientated<br />

jurisprudence implicitly created by its judgments. 46<br />

More troubling, perhaps, is that while the reasonableness<br />

approach shows some sensitivity to vulnerability and need, the<br />

Court’s denial of enforceable entitlements inherent to socioeconomic<br />

rights in its current application of the approach significantly<br />

45<br />

For a related argument, see T Roux ‘Understanding Grootboom — A response to<br />

Cass R Sunstein’ (2002) 12(2) Constitutional Forum 41 47 and 49.<br />

46 Consider, for instance, the manner in which the High Courts have exploited the<br />

space for entitlement-orientated jurisprudence created by the implied finding in<br />

Grootboom (n 28 above) para 77 that orphans or abandoned children may have<br />

direct subsistence claims against the state in terms of FC sec 28(1)(c). See Centre<br />

for Child Law v Minister of Home Affairs 2005 6 SA 50 (T) Centre for Child Law v<br />

MEC for Education, Gauteng 2008 1 SA 223 (T). Consider also the progressive<br />

remedial framework emerging from High Court judgments giving effect to diverse<br />

elements of the right to dignified conditions of detention in terms of FC sec<br />

35(2)(e). I have elaborated on <strong>this</strong> framework in M Pieterse ‘The potential of<br />

socio-economic rights litigation for the achievement of social justice: Considering<br />

the example of access to care in South African prisons’ (2006) 50 Journal of<br />

African Law 118.


344 Chapter 19<br />

restricts individuals in articulating their demands for needsatisfaction<br />

as rights-claims. As a result, the beneficiaries’ voices are<br />

dampened specifically in relation to that aspect of the socioeconomic<br />

rights dialogue (the identification and elaboration of need)<br />

to which they can most valuably contribute. 47 By instead shifting the<br />

focus of the courtroom dialogue to the content of an intricate array<br />

of policy choices in a particular sector, the Court further compounds<br />

the evidentiary burden on prospective individual claimants. Given<br />

that such claimants are moreover unlikely, in terms of the current<br />

entitlement-free application of the reasonableness approach, to be<br />

awarded immediate and tangible relief if a claim of unreasonableness<br />

was to succeed, it will seldom be worth their while to raise their<br />

voices in the courtroom. 48<br />

The current formulation of the reasonableness approach may thus<br />

be accused of largely un-inviting socio-economic rights’ individual<br />

beneficiaries from the courtroom dialogue over the meaning of their<br />

rights. Instead, it appears to relegate them to the political process<br />

where, absent a powerful, well-resourced or well-connected social<br />

movement that shares their concerns, they are likely to remain<br />

silenced. Given that one of the prime advantages of the litigation<br />

process as a dialogic forum is that it allows for the amplification of<br />

voices which would ordinarily be muted in political processes, <strong>this</strong> is<br />

unfortunate.<br />

Liebenberg’s optimism over its openness, flexibility and<br />

sensitivity to context notwithstanding, the reasonableness approach,<br />

as applied in Grootboom and TAC, runs the risk of unnecessarily<br />

stifling dialogue over the meaning of socio-economic rights in the<br />

courtroom. Such silence may ultimately impoverish the broader<br />

translation of socio-economic rights in South Africa.<br />

Since institutions are themselves ‘affected and shaped’ by their<br />

contributions to dialogues over constitutional meaning, 49 their<br />

conduct in the course of such dialogues also reveals and/or predicts<br />

the extent of their participation in the overarching societal dialogue<br />

over the means and the ends of transformation. The Constitutional<br />

Court’s deflection of dialogue — through the reasonableness approach<br />

— restricts its role to legitimating and endorsing the transformation<br />

efforts of the political branches: even as it holds them accountable<br />

47<br />

On the sidelining of need in terms of the reasonableness approach, see Bilchitz (n<br />

27 above) 160; Brand (n 40 above) 36-37, 49 and 55.<br />

48 See J Dugard & T Roux ‘The record of the South African Constitutional Court in<br />

providing an institutional voice for the poor: 1995-2004’ in R Gargarella et al<br />

(eds) Courts and social transformation in new democracies (2006) 107 113 and<br />

118-119; Gloppen (n 14 above) 169; Liebenberg ‘Dignity’ (n 32 above) 22; Pieterse<br />

(n 20 above) 490.<br />

49 Bateup (n 3 above) 1159.


Reply - Marius Pieterse 345<br />

for upholding their constitutional commitments in the course of these<br />

efforts. 50 In particular, it appears reluctant to proclaim its own vision<br />

of the transformative project despite the fact that it has been tasked<br />

to uphold the Constitution ‘without fear, favour or prejudice’. 51 It<br />

largely defers instead to an executive-driven economic policy<br />

environment that may depart, in important respects, from such a<br />

vision. 52<br />

This is, perhaps, understandable. However, the record also<br />

indicates that the Court views its accountability-enhancing function in<br />

a very ‘business as usual’ manner. While the Court has insisted on<br />

robust justification for non-compliance with the negative obligations<br />

implied by socio-economic rights (which correspond largely to<br />

‘classical’ civil rights violations), the evaluative and remedial<br />

paradigms presented by the reasonableness approach for the<br />

adjudication of positive socio-economic rights claims do not suggest<br />

any meaningful departure from conceptions of the judicial role under<br />

pre-constitutional administrative law. 53 The unfortunate result is that<br />

the judicial contribution to the debate over transformation is no<br />

different than it would have been in a constitutional setting where<br />

socio-economic rights had either not been entrenched at all or had<br />

functioned only as directive principles of state policy.<br />

4 Conclusion: Towards openness, responsiveness and<br />

substantive participation?<br />

A Constitutional Court is like a parachute, it has to be open to work. If<br />

the Court turns inward, to whom do those seeking justice reach out? 54<br />

This reply has attempted to strengthen Liebenberg’s call for the<br />

modification of the reasonableness approach. This modification<br />

should embrace substantive engagement with the content of socioeconomic<br />

rights as well as more rigorous scrutiny of justifications for<br />

laws and policies that cause, exacerbate or fail to address<br />

deprivations of basic socio-economic resources. 55 I have argued that<br />

50<br />

See T Roux ‘Legitimating transformation: Political resource allocation in the<br />

South African Constitutional Court’ (2003) 10 Democratisation 92; DM Davis<br />

‘Adjudicating the socio-economic rights in the South African Constitution:<br />

Towards ‘deference lite’?’ (2006) 22 South African Journal on Human Rights 301<br />

318.<br />

51 FC sec 165(1).<br />

52<br />

See Davis (n 50 above) 315-316.<br />

53 See D Bilchitz ‘Giving socio-economic rights teeth: The minimum core and its<br />

importance’ (2002) 119 South African Law Journal 484 495; Currie (n 41 above)<br />

72; CR Sunstein ‘Social and economic rights? Lessons from South Africa’ (2001) 12<br />

Constitutional Forum 123.<br />

54 G van Bueren ‘Alleviating poverty through the Constitutional Court’ (1999) 15<br />

South African Journal on Human Rights 52 73.<br />

55 Liebenberg (n 3 above) 321-327.


346 Chapter 19<br />

the current version of the reasonableness approach runs the risk of<br />

impoverishing the translation of socio-economic rights, first, by<br />

restricting the terms of courtroom dialogue over their content,<br />

secondly, by silencing voices that may meaningfully contribute to the<br />

dialogue and, thirdly, by diverting much of the dialogue to the<br />

political arena. Such restriction, silence and diversion may not only<br />

deflate the possibilities of dialogue over constitutional meaning but<br />

also unnecessarily restrict the judicial contribution to the overarching<br />

dialogue over transformation.<br />

Liebenberg is right to contend that the reasonableness approach<br />

can accommodate a more direct engagement with the content of<br />

socio-economic rights. As I have argued elsewhere, a latent notion of<br />

entitlement may already be lurking within the reasonableness<br />

approach. 56 But it would probably be even more useful if an approach<br />

aimed at ascertaining compliance with socio-economic obligations<br />

were, conceptually, to separate the deliberation over the content of<br />

a right from the question of whether measures that aim to give effect<br />

to the right are reasonable in light of that content. This need not<br />

amount to a minimum core approach or to a similarly dialoguemonopolising<br />

exercise of interpretation. On the contrary, the<br />

context-specific, open and flexible deliberation over the content of<br />

specific entitlements, their limits and the appropriateness of<br />

suggested remedies for their vindication may ultimately enrich<br />

deliberative dialogue over the translation of socio-economic rights.<br />

As a matter of fact, there is no need for courts to adopt a single,<br />

one-size-fits-all approach to socio-economic rights adjudication.<br />

Indeed, the fixation of academic scholarship (including <strong>this</strong> reply) on<br />

the strengths and the shortcomings of the reasonableness approach<br />

should not blind us to the fact that the Constitutional Court has itself<br />

flirted with different approaches in relation to different kinds of<br />

allegations of non-compliance with socio-economic rights. In<br />

Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu Natal, it focused on the<br />

rationality and bona fides of an executive directive which rationed<br />

the availability of certain forms of tertiary medical care. 57 In Khosa v<br />

Minister of Social Development; Mahlaule v Minister of Social<br />

Development, it appeared to combine the reasonableness approach<br />

56 Pieterse (n 20 above) 497-500.<br />

57<br />

1998 1 SA 765 (CC), 1997 12 BCLR 1696 (CC). For a critical discussion, see D<br />

Moellendorf ‘Reasoning about resources: Soobramoney and the future of socioeconomic<br />

rights claims’ (1998) 14 South African Journal on Human Rights 327; M<br />

Pieterse ‘Health care rights, resources and rationing’ (2007) 124 South African<br />

Law Journal 514 527-535.


Reply - Marius Pieterse 347<br />

with an equality-analysis, where an alleged infringement of a socioeconomic<br />

right coincided with an allegation of unfair<br />

discrimination. 58 In Jaftha v Schoeman; Van Rooyen v Stoltz, it<br />

adopted a more ‘traditional’ two-stage approach, including a FC<br />

section 36 limitations analysis, in relation to the negative duties<br />

implied by socio-economic rights. 59 Whereas the dialogic contribution<br />

of each of these approaches is, perhaps, debatable, the institutional<br />

flexibility implied by <strong>this</strong> experimentation is to be welcomed.<br />

As Liebenberg has reminded us elsewhere, courts must ‘remain<br />

open to new and innovative interpretations of socio-economic rights<br />

that better protect the interests and values underpinning these rights’<br />

even though ‘[t]his may entail a measure of sacrifice of the ideals of<br />

stability and certainty’. 60 This new approach could involve the<br />

substantive expansion of the reasonableness approach, its variation<br />

according to the demands of different contexts or its substitution in<br />

appropriate circumstances. Whatever approach is adopted in the<br />

circumstances of a particular case, it should aim to translate socioeconomic<br />

rights in a manner that responds to the needs of their<br />

beneficiaries and in a way that maximises the transformative<br />

potential of the courtroom as a venue for dialogue.<br />

58 2004 6 SA 505 (CC), 2004 6 BCLR 569 (CC). For critical analysis, see Bilchitz (n 27<br />

59<br />

above) 166-173.<br />

2005 2 SA 140 (CC), 2005 1 BCLR 78 (CC). See the concluding section of<br />

Liebenberg (n 3 above) for a critical view of the continued distinction between<br />

60<br />

the negative and positive obligations imposed by socio-economic rights.<br />

Liebenberg (n 17 above) 6.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!