04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

22 Chapter 1<br />

immediately enforce. Liebenberg’s and Pieterse’s colloquy breathes<br />

new life into <strong>this</strong> debate.<br />

Professor Liebenberg contends that the major problem with a<br />

minimum core approach is that it stifles dialogue: It relies on a single<br />

top-down decision of what a socio-economic right requires. It<br />

therefore closes down further debate — in government and in civil<br />

society — about the content of the socio-economic rights found in FC<br />

sections 25, 26, 27, 28, 29 and 35. Liebenberg further argues that the<br />

alleged clarity of a minimum-core approach is illusory. It is illusory<br />

because it traps us in programs focused solely on survival — from<br />

which we may never escape — and eschews equally hard decisions<br />

about how to transform South African society in a number of equally<br />

important non-survival settings. Liebenberg thus concludes that ‘the<br />

minimum core approach is in danger of encouraging minimalism in<br />

social provisioning when the context may in fact render such<br />

minimalism unnecessary and inappropriate.’<br />

On the other hand, reasonableness review allows a contextsensitive<br />

test that is responsive to democratic dialogue. The major<br />

drawback of <strong>this</strong> approach, as Liebenberg notes, is that it collapses<br />

the traditional two-stage rights analysis and does not properly engage<br />

‘with the content, scope and underlying values of the relevant rights’.<br />

Liebenberg suggests argues that a reasonableness approach might<br />

overcome <strong>this</strong> deficiency if courts were to conduct more substantive<br />

evaluations of the content of socio-economic rights. Moreover, the<br />

reasonableness approach already possesses some of the strengths of<br />

the minimum-core argument by requiring a higher level of scrutiny<br />

where the very lives of the complainants are on the line. 38<br />

Professor Marius Pieterse’s response focuses on Liebenberg’s<br />

belief that both extant reasonableness review and minimum core<br />

doctrines stifle dialogue about the content and the contours of<br />

existing socio-economic rights doctrine and discourse. Pieterse<br />

stresses the importance of <strong>this</strong> dialogue in ‘translating’ socioeconomic<br />

rights from ‘conceptually empty, abstract principles into<br />

more concrete, claimable entitlements.’ This dialogue must occur not<br />

only between the judiciary and the other branches of government,<br />

but between other players in the ‘constitutional community’ —<br />

NGO’s, social movements, and, ultimately, the citizenry at large.<br />

Each of these players has different strengths and different roles to<br />

play. Social movements, for example, provide a voice for the people<br />

who are most in need of socio-economic rights. Academics offer<br />

38 See further S Liebenberg ‘The interpretation of socio-economic rights’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2007)<br />

Chapter 33 (CD track 10); S Liebenberg Adjudicating fundamental rights under a<br />

transformative constitution (2008).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!