04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Sandra Liebenberg 315<br />

person per day which the World Health Organisation and an<br />

international expert recommended as being required for a healthy<br />

and dignified lifestyle. 59 This judgment suggests that the application<br />

of a heightened review standard should not only be confined to one<br />

core value or interest such as biological survival. Moreover, in respect<br />

of other socio-economic rights, such as the right to education, the<br />

focus on mere biological survival simply does not accord with the<br />

broader purposes and interests which such a right protects. In striving<br />

to establish clear, fixed and judicially manageable standards for the<br />

adjudication of socio-economic rights claims, the minimum core<br />

approach is in danger of encouraging minimalism in social provisioning<br />

when the context may in fact render such minimalism unnecessary<br />

and inappropriate. 60<br />

A fourth difficulty with the minimum core concept is related to<br />

the Constitutional Court’s observations concerning the difficulty of<br />

defining minimum core obligations given the diversity of needs and<br />

circumstances in which different groups find themselves. 61 The<br />

underlying concern is that the minimum core approach is unduly rigid,<br />

and its application may operate to exclude or marginalise the needs<br />

of various groups that do not fit the background norms informing the<br />

definition of core obligations. Bilchitz responds to <strong>this</strong> concern by<br />

arguing that the minimum core should aim to define a general<br />

standard informed by people’s urgent survival needs. This standard,<br />

for example, still allows for a measure of latitude and flexibility<br />

regarding what precisely is needed to meet people’s needs in<br />

different contexts. 62 However, he argues that the minimum core does<br />

require ‘a rigid stance in one respect: it requires us to recognise that<br />

it is simply unacceptable for human beings to have to live without<br />

sufficient resources to be free from threats to their survival.’ 63 He<br />

thus argues for a form of heightened scrutiny to be applied to claims<br />

59 Mazibuko (n 48 above) paras 179 – 181.<br />

60 See the similar concern expressed by Porter (n 38 above) 55.<br />

61<br />

Grootboom (n 2 above) paras 32–33.<br />

62 Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 198. See also his response<br />

(200-202) to Danie Brand’s argument that the minimum core may be suitable for<br />

the international enforcement of socio-economic rights, but is not useful for the<br />

domestic context where we must be ‘far more specific, concrete, contextsensitive<br />

and flexible in our thinking about basic standards, core entitlements and<br />

minimum obligations.’ D Brand ‘The minimum content of the right to food in<br />

context: A response to Rolf Künnemann’ in D Brand & S Russell (eds) Exploring the<br />

core content of socio-economic rights: South African and international<br />

perspectives (2002) 99 101.<br />

63 Bilchitz Poverty and fundamental rights (n 31 above) 208.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!