04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Reply - Danie Brand 101<br />

It must not only ‘lay the foundations for a democratic ... society’ 22 by<br />

creating the different institutions necessary for that purpose, but<br />

must also build, foster and encourage the culture of democracy — and<br />

by culture I mean the discursive practice and political organisation<br />

required for democracy to operate inside and outside of those vessels.<br />

Now, Theunis explicitly disavows a purely institutional understanding<br />

of democracy in his chapter in Constitutional conversations<br />

and in CLoSA. 23 If asked, I am also sure that he would not disagree<br />

that the Final Constitution’s affirmative nature applies to the<br />

constitutional principle of democracy. Finally, although not explicit<br />

about it, Theunis’ articulation of the constitutional principle of<br />

democracy in its use of active and substantive terms leaves room for<br />

a non-institutional, affirmative reading of the constitutional duties<br />

arising from it. Nevertheless, in his analysis of the cases, Theunis does<br />

not engage the question of the nature and scope of democracyrelated<br />

constitutional duty and the Constitutional Court’s limited<br />

understanding thereof. Why he doesn’t do so I can only guess. He<br />

might respond that he was asked to write only one chapter and not a<br />

whole book on the Constitution and democracy! But I do think that it<br />

is, perhaps, an important opportunity missed.<br />

The absence of recognition of the Final Constitution’s affirmative<br />

nature that we see in the democracy cases that Theunis analyses is<br />

but one example of the Constitutional Court’s failure, outside of its<br />

jurisprudence on socio-economic rights, to come to grips with <strong>this</strong><br />

question — to develop, that is, a cogent theory of positive<br />

constitutional duty that applies, as it should, across the board to all<br />

constitutional rights, standards, principles and values. In <strong>this</strong> light,<br />

the added critical engagement with the cases that an affirmative,<br />

non-institutional gloss to Theunis’ principle of democracy would have<br />

necessitated would have been most welcome. South African legal<br />

academics in general have, along with the Court, so far failed<br />

adequately to engage <strong>this</strong> issue. 24<br />

2.2 The tension between rights and democracy<br />

The second thing Theunis does not say about democracy in our<br />

constitutional law has to do with the inevitable tension that exists<br />

between democracy on the one hand and the work of courts enforcing<br />

a constitution on the other that haunts any constitutional standard of<br />

democracy.<br />

22<br />

Preamble to the Final Constitution.<br />

23 Roux (n 1 above) and Roux (n 14 above).<br />

24 For one relatively recent exception, see DM Davis ‘Adjudicating the socioeconomic<br />

rights in the South African constitution: Towards “deference lite”’<br />

(2006) 22 South African Journal on Human Rights 301.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!