04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Reply - Justice Albie Sachs 39<br />

but had even succeeded in getting the Universities, which they<br />

treated as subalterns, to extol its timeless virtues.<br />

Then much later when I myself had been ‘elevated’ from being<br />

professor to the Bench, I came across an address in which US Supreme<br />

Court Justice William Brennan provided further illumination.<br />

Criticising what he saw as the deadening role of the desiccated,<br />

precedent-based legal text-book, he explained, in an address entitled<br />

Reason, passion and ‘The progress of the law’, that the judicial<br />

branch in his country had been born not on the lofty peaks of pure<br />

reason, but in the trenches of partisan politics. 1 In response, two<br />

important checks on judicial discretion had been institutionalised —<br />

the recording of precedent, and the requirement of a public and<br />

reasoned explanation of the judicial result. The outcome was an<br />

endless string of cites of precedent that began to dominate judicial<br />

opinions.<br />

The effect of <strong>this</strong> practice was to distance the judge from the<br />

outcome of the case: It appeared that precedent alone determined<br />

each outcome. Brennan observed that the rise of the legal treatise,<br />

with its strangely disembodied character, intensified <strong>this</strong> distancing<br />

process:<br />

The goal of the treatise — to classify reported cases into objective and<br />

determinative categories of legal principle — appealed to the positivist<br />

minds of the late-nineteenth century. As one historian had put it:<br />

The legal treatise was regarded by its admirers as above all<br />

demonstrating the ‘scientific’ nature of the law. Through classification<br />

of subjects, it sought to show that law proceeds not from will but from<br />

reason. Through its ‘black letter’ presentation of supposed ‘general<br />

principles’ of law it sought to suppress all controversy over policy while<br />

promoting the comforting ideal of a logical, symmetrical and, most<br />

importantly, inexorable system of law.<br />

Conspicuously absent from the treatises was any narrative voice. The<br />

earliest treatises contain no commentary whatsoever, and even in later<br />

editions authors eschewed personal commentary on the cases and<br />

principles. The absence of commentary was consistent with, and no<br />

doubt helped to reinforce, the nineteenth-century conception of law as<br />

something that judges discovered but did not help define. 2<br />

Brennan added that we could now begin to understand why <strong>this</strong><br />

conception of judge-as-oracle arose, and why the legal community<br />

clung so tenaciously to it.<br />

1<br />

(1988) 10 Cardozo Law Review 3.<br />

2 As above.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!