04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Stu Woolman 201<br />

law does not reflect the ‘naked preferences’ of government; and (2)<br />

a right to equal treatment that guarantees that individuals are not<br />

subject to unfair discrimination on the basis of largely ascriptive<br />

characteristics. 17 Of <strong>this</strong> demand for equal concern and equal<br />

respect, Justice Ackermann writes:<br />

[A]t the heart of the prohibition of unfair discrimination lies the<br />

recognition that the purpose of our new constitutional and democratic<br />

order is the establishment of a society in which all human beings will be<br />

accorded equal dignity and respect regardless of their membership in<br />

particular groups. The achievement of such a society in the context of<br />

our deeply inegalitarian past will not be easy, but that that is the goal of<br />

the Constitution should not be forgotten or overlooked. 18<br />

3.3 Dignity 3: Self-actualisation<br />

Another formulation of the categorical imperative shapes a third<br />

strand of the Court’s dignity jurisprudence. Kant writes: ‘Act only on<br />

the maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should<br />

become a universal law.’ 19 Here, the term that warrants the closest<br />

scrutiny is ‘will’. For Kant, the hallmark of humanity is its ability to<br />

‘will’ or to shape its ends through ‘reason’. But when Kant writes that<br />

our humanity consists, at least in part, in our power to rationally set<br />

and will an end, he is not speaking solely of an individual’s capacity<br />

to adopt an end for purely moral reasons. While Kant certainly<br />

contends that the defining feature of humanity is our capacity to<br />

overcome our instincts and that we are only truly free when we are<br />

moral, he maintains that we define ourselves — and our humanity —<br />

through the rational choice of all of our ends and not just those that<br />

are explicitly moral. This broader capacity to create meaning — to<br />

‘will’ value into the world — gives rise to the modern political and<br />

ethical pre-occupation with ‘self-actualisation’. An individual’s<br />

capacity to create meaning generates an entitlement to respect for<br />

the unique set of ends that the individual pursues. In Ferreira v Levin,<br />

Justice Ackermann writes:<br />

Human dignity cannot be fully valued or respected unless individuals are<br />

able to develop their humanity, their ‘humanness’ to the full extent of<br />

its potential. Each human being is uniquely talented. Part of the dignity<br />

of every human being is the fact and awareness of <strong>this</strong> uniqueness. An<br />

17 See President of the Republic of South Africa v Hugo 1997 4 SA 1 (CC), 1997 6<br />

BCLR 708 (CC) para 41 (‘[T]he purpose of our new constitutional and democratic<br />

order is the establishment of a society in which all human beings will be accorded<br />

equal respect regardless of their membership in particular groups.’ (My<br />

emphasis.))<br />

18 LWH Ackermann ‘Equality under the 1996 South African Constitution’ in Wolfrem<br />

(ed) Gleichheit und Nichtdiskriminierung im Nationalen und Internationalen<br />

Mesenchenrechtssschutz (2003) 547.<br />

19 Kant (n 8 above) 37-38.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!