04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Reply - Justice Laurie Ackermann 221<br />

be shown to be the natural and legitimate evolution of the cultural<br />

tradition of the particular community.’ Although cultural norms have<br />

complex origins, An-Na’im argues that ‘the religious factor seems to<br />

be a major formative force.’ 9<br />

John Rawls, in A theory of justice, develops a concept of<br />

‘overlapping consensus’ which, although expressed in the context of<br />

civil disobedience, is of general import and relevant to the use of<br />

theological ethics:<br />

In [certain previous] remarks I have assumed that in a nearly just society<br />

there is a public acceptance of the same principles of justice.<br />

Fortunately <strong>this</strong> assumption is stronger than is necessary. There can, in<br />

fact, be considerable difference in citizens’ conception of justice<br />

provided that these conceptions lead to similar political judgments. All<br />

<strong>this</strong> is possible, since different premises can yield the same conclusion.<br />

In <strong>this</strong> case there exists what we may refer to as overlapping rather then<br />

strict consensus. 10<br />

This idea is discussed more fully by Rawls in Political liberalism, 11<br />

where he places the following gloss on the notion of an ‘overlapping<br />

consensus’:<br />

All those who affirm the political conception start from within their own<br />

comprehensive view and draw on the religious, philosophical, and moral<br />

grounds it provides. The fact that people affirm the same political<br />

conception on these grounds does not make their affirming it less<br />

religious, philosophical, or moral, as the case may be, since the grounds<br />

sincerely held determine the nature of their affirmation. 12<br />

9<br />

n 8 above, 9. Lest I unwittingly do an injustice to An-Na’im, I must point out that<br />

the whole thrust of his article, see eg pp. 17-18, is to the effect that:<br />

(1) The status of non-Muslim religious minorities under Shari’ah is not<br />

consistent with current universal human rights. (2) The current state of<br />

affairs cannot be justified under claims of Islamic cultural relativism.<br />

(3) It is not only possible, but also imperative, that the status of non-<br />

Muslims under Shari’ah be reformed from within the fundamental sources<br />

of Islam, namely the Qu’rn and Sunnah. Such reform would be at once<br />

both Islamic and fully consistent with universal human rights standards.<br />

Very broadly stated his argument (9-11) is that the Shari’ah is ‘not the totality of<br />

the word of God.’ According to Muslim belief, ‘the Qu’rn is the literal and final<br />

word of God while Sunnah is the record of what the Prophet is believed to have<br />

said.’ While conceding (17) that not all aspects of Shari’ah are open to<br />

restatement and reinterpretation, he does contend (10) that Shari’ah is no more<br />

than the ‘understanding of the early Muslims of the sources of Islam’ influenced<br />

by their historical context and ‘experience and perception of the world’. It<br />

developed under the conditions and influenced by the problems of an Islamic<br />

state in seventh century Arabia. Since these problems have altered and the<br />

historical answers are no longer valid, An-Na’im argues (11) that ‘new answers<br />

must be developed out of the Qu’rn and Sunnah ... [For] the Islamic Shari’ah for<br />

today.’<br />

10 (1973) 387.<br />

11<br />

(1993) 133-172.<br />

12 n 11 above, 147.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!