04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 173<br />

value that is common to the frequently conflicting imperatives of<br />

equality and freedom.<br />

The purpose of Ackermann’s two intuition pumps is to convince us<br />

that the stronger the dignity interest is on one side of the equality/<br />

freedom divide, the weaker it is likely to be on the other. In the<br />

example of the restrictive condition, the discrimination strikes at the<br />

heart of the dignity interests of a prospective black buyer, while only<br />

marginally disturbing the dignity interests of the property owner. But<br />

these — on Ackermann’s account — are easy cases. One could well<br />

imagine cases in which there are strong dignity/equality interests and<br />

dignity/freedom interests on both sides. Consider, for example, a<br />

clash between the rights of women who wish to participate equally in<br />

traditional or religious communities and the ‘autonomy’ rights of such<br />

religious or cultural communities. 54 In such cases, the discrimination<br />

constitutes a serious impairment of the fundamental human dignity of<br />

women while, at the same time, the religious or cultural practice in<br />

question is so fundamental to the worldview and customs of its<br />

adherents that a ruling of unconstitutionality would strike at the heart<br />

of that community’s sense of dignity. Dignity does not, in such cases,<br />

offer a neutral or a principled way of striking a balance between<br />

equality and freedom.<br />

The second problem with dignity as a neutral, mediating principle<br />

is that it assumes that a dignity-based reading of the limitations<br />

clause adequately captures the various interests served by rights as<br />

varied as equality, privacy and association. A number of<br />

commentators have argued that something is likely to get lost in the<br />

process of translating the right to equality into the language of human<br />

dignity. 55 One of their concerns has been that a dignity-based<br />

approach to equality focuses primarily on individual moral harm,<br />

rather than material disadvantage and structural power. While some<br />

forms of disadvantage can be expressed quite easily in moral terms,<br />

others may not be so readily recognised. This difference may explain<br />

why the transformative vision of the Constitutional Court’s<br />

jurisprudence in the field of sexual orientation has easily outpaced its<br />

jurisprudence on discrimination on the grounds of sex and gender.<br />

While discrimination against gays and lesbians is usually rooted in<br />

moral disapproval and results directly in an affront to their dignity<br />

54 See eg Bhe & Others v Magistrate, Khayelitsha & Others 2005 1 SA 580 (CC), 2005<br />

1 BCLR 449 (CC).<br />

55 C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Facing the challenge of transformation: difficulties in<br />

the development of an indigenous jurisprudence of equality’ (1998) 14 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 248; DM Davis ‘Equality: The majesty of<br />

legoland jurisprudence’ (1999) 116 South African Law Journal 398; H Botha<br />

‘Equality, dignity, and the politics of interpretation’ (2004) 19 South African<br />

Public Law 724. But see S Cowen ‘Can “dignity” guide South Africa’s equality<br />

jurisprudence?’ (2001) 17 South African Journal on Human Rights 34.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!