04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

64 Chapter 5<br />

Thank you too for the opportunity to respond to Professor<br />

Michelman, a constitutional lawyer whom I much admire. I thoroughly<br />

enjoyed reading Chapter 11 of Constitutional Law of South Africa,<br />

‘The rule of law, legality and the supremacy of the Constitution’.<br />

There can be no doubt that discussions of the sort facilitated by<br />

<strong>this</strong> conference are of great value in contributing to our<br />

understanding of constitutional democracy. Nevertheless, I must also<br />

say, at the outset, that I found preparation for our discussion difficult<br />

for two inter-related reasons. First, as a sitting judge, there are<br />

important concerns of confidentiality and appropriate judicial<br />

reticence which limit the scope of my comments. It is my view that,<br />

as a matter of jurisprudential philosophy, every effort should be made<br />

in a judgment to articulate the premises and assumptions on which it<br />

is founded. At times, the result of <strong>this</strong> philosophy may have been, and<br />

may still be, to expand the boundaries of the doctrine of judicial<br />

notice beyond the terrain in which it has ordinarily been applied to<br />

enable the description of social, economic and political context in<br />

judicial decision making.<br />

Such a philosophy, while accepting that it has epistemological<br />

limits and recognising that there is always a potential for judicial selfdelusion,<br />

is, in my view, the proper approach to judicial reasoning in<br />

a constitutional democracy that asserts as founding values openness,<br />

responsiveness and accountability. 2 In responding to the text of the<br />

chapter written by Professor Michelman, I rely largely on the<br />

reasoning to be found in the judgments of the Constitutional Court.<br />

The second difficulty lies in the fact that Professor Michelman’s<br />

chapter runs to some 60 pages. I did not have the text of what he was<br />

going to say <strong>this</strong> evening, which differs somewhat from the chapter<br />

and understandably expands on some of its reasoning. So I thought it<br />

might be easiest if I started by identifying the arguments to which I<br />

was responding. Having heard him speak <strong>this</strong> evening, it is clear that<br />

my remarks are directed at aspects of the chapter which he has not<br />

repeated in full. In addition, he has raised some other arguments<br />

tonight which I will not have time to address. In the circumstances, it<br />

will be particularly helpful for me to start by explaining to what I am<br />

responding. I also accept that I may have misunderstood his reasoning<br />

in the chapter, and to the extent I have, I apologise in advance.<br />

The propositions to which I would like to respond are twofold. The<br />

first is that the development of the doctrine of legality by the<br />

Constitutional Court was not based on any constitutional text or<br />

principle; 3 and that the effect of the doctrine of legality is to render<br />

2<br />

See FC sec 1.<br />

3 See Michelman (n 1 above) 11-3.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!