04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

54 Chapter 4<br />

detection of a need to revamp the common law of defamation was<br />

impelled by anything other than the long entrenched, deep-lying<br />

principles of the common law itself.)<br />

The Constitutional Court’s view, as expressed in Carmichele and<br />

as confirmed by that Court’s actions in quite a number of other cases,<br />

is that the choice among such possibilities — where any of several<br />

would satisfy the Constitution’s requirements, so the unity (in that<br />

sense) of the entire law of South Africa is not at stake — ought to be<br />

shaped by considerations having to do with preserving, insofar as<br />

possible, the internal integrity (or might one say the unity?) of the<br />

common law viewed as an identifiable, bounded component of South<br />

African law. That would be a main reason why deciding among such<br />

constitutionally acceptable choices is normally and properly business<br />

in which the Supreme Court of Appeal, not the Constitutional Court,<br />

should take the lead. In these cases, the Constitution, as some might<br />

say, runs out before all the available legal-doctrinal options are<br />

resolved. And that would seem to be a main reason why judges whose<br />

decisional writ cannot outrun the Constitution consider themselves<br />

well advised to leave the labouring oar in such cases to others to<br />

whom the Constitution has ostensibly assigned a broader<br />

jurisdictional competence.<br />

It is interesting to ponder how <strong>this</strong> picture might look to partisans<br />

in the well-known debate between HLA Hart and Ronald Dworkin.<br />

Jurisprudes will recall Hart’s view that the normative fabric of the law<br />

inevitably leaves open spaces, wherein judges necessarily exercise a<br />

discretionary choice as if they were legislators, choosing as they<br />

suppose legislators would or ought to do. And then they also will recall<br />

Dworkin’s counter-insistence that for any case at law brought before<br />

a judge of the law, there can be only a single legally correct answer,<br />

and the judge’s job in every case is to find that answer out as best she<br />

can.<br />

In relation to that debate, the Constitutional Court’s view as<br />

expounded in Carmichele might be described as a straddle. From the<br />

standpoint of the Constitution, there are indeed those bounded<br />

spaces of discretion envisioned by Hart. They are the spaces where<br />

the Constitution runs out before the case is fully solved, in which<br />

some further exercise of judgment (‘discretion’) necessarily is<br />

required to reach a doctrinally complete solution to the case. But<br />

from the standpoint of the common law, choosing within the bounds<br />

imposed by the Constitution, there is no such open space; rather,<br />

there is a unique right answer — that which will best comport with the<br />

general fabric of common-law doctrine and principle while<br />

comporting also with the Constitution’s demands — the ascertainment<br />

of which is properly the business of judges steeped in the knowledge

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!