04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

158 Chapter 10<br />

beings value a vast array of goods. And we value each good in our own<br />

and its own particular way. This first claim about pluralism and the<br />

qualitatively different ways in which we value goods suggests a second<br />

claim. Human goods are often incommensurable. It is fair to say that<br />

the things we value most in life — friends, lovers, work, beauty,<br />

nature, and yes, money — cannot be compared with one another. Put<br />

differently, while we may be able to compare the virtues of friends<br />

with friends, the virtues of lovers with lovers, the virtues of work with<br />

work, the virtues of certain objects of beauty with other objects of<br />

beauty, and certainly the virtues of more money with less money,<br />

there is no single template against which we can measure claims of<br />

friendship, love, work, beauty, nature and money. They may compete<br />

with one another. But they compete in a way not easily assessed.<br />

Indeed, justice may require us to refrain, in so far as it is possible,<br />

from attempts to measure these competing goods by a single<br />

yardstick. Michael Walzer puts our second complex claim thus:<br />

There has never been a universal medium of exchange. ... [T]here has<br />

never been a single criterion, or a single set of interconnected criteria<br />

for all distributions. Desert, qualification, birth and blood, friendship,<br />

need, free exchange, political loyalty, democratic decision: each has<br />

had its place, along with many others, uneasily coexisting, invoked by<br />

competing groups, confused with one another. 16<br />

From these observations, Walzer draws the following conclusions.<br />

First, goods, like people, have shared meanings in a society, because<br />

goods, like people, are a product of social, political, economic,<br />

educational, religious and linguistic practices which generate<br />

meaning. Second, it is the shared meaning of a good which<br />

determines, or should determine, its distribution. Third, and perhaps<br />

most importantly for Walzer, when the meanings of social goods are<br />

distinct, their distributions must be autonomous. That is, for each<br />

good there exists a set of criteria and procedures deemed to be<br />

appropriate for its distribution.<br />

Walzer’s view may need to be qualified. The demands of justice<br />

— even in a world of plural and incommensurable goods — are, in fact,<br />

far more complex than Walzer’s account allows. First, spheres of<br />

human activity do overlap and thereby complicate the criteria for the<br />

distribution of any particular social good. Second, to the extent that<br />

some spheres of activity are inextricably linked, it is inevitable that<br />

the distribution of one good will influence the distribution of another.<br />

Third, given the spontaneous, evolutionary manner in which most<br />

spheres of activity have come into being — meaning they are never the<br />

product of a single agent — the criteria for the distribution of a social<br />

good are rarely going to be clear or conflict-free. The criteria for<br />

16 Spheres of Justice (1985) 4.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!