04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

346 Chapter 19<br />

the current version of the reasonableness approach runs the risk of<br />

impoverishing the translation of socio-economic rights, first, by<br />

restricting the terms of courtroom dialogue over their content,<br />

secondly, by silencing voices that may meaningfully contribute to the<br />

dialogue and, thirdly, by diverting much of the dialogue to the<br />

political arena. Such restriction, silence and diversion may not only<br />

deflate the possibilities of dialogue over constitutional meaning but<br />

also unnecessarily restrict the judicial contribution to the overarching<br />

dialogue over transformation.<br />

Liebenberg is right to contend that the reasonableness approach<br />

can accommodate a more direct engagement with the content of<br />

socio-economic rights. As I have argued elsewhere, a latent notion of<br />

entitlement may already be lurking within the reasonableness<br />

approach. 56 But it would probably be even more useful if an approach<br />

aimed at ascertaining compliance with socio-economic obligations<br />

were, conceptually, to separate the deliberation over the content of<br />

a right from the question of whether measures that aim to give effect<br />

to the right are reasonable in light of that content. This need not<br />

amount to a minimum core approach or to a similarly dialoguemonopolising<br />

exercise of interpretation. On the contrary, the<br />

context-specific, open and flexible deliberation over the content of<br />

specific entitlements, their limits and the appropriateness of<br />

suggested remedies for their vindication may ultimately enrich<br />

deliberative dialogue over the translation of socio-economic rights.<br />

As a matter of fact, there is no need for courts to adopt a single,<br />

one-size-fits-all approach to socio-economic rights adjudication.<br />

Indeed, the fixation of academic scholarship (including <strong>this</strong> reply) on<br />

the strengths and the shortcomings of the reasonableness approach<br />

should not blind us to the fact that the Constitutional Court has itself<br />

flirted with different approaches in relation to different kinds of<br />

allegations of non-compliance with socio-economic rights. In<br />

Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu Natal, it focused on the<br />

rationality and bona fides of an executive directive which rationed<br />

the availability of certain forms of tertiary medical care. 57 In Khosa v<br />

Minister of Social Development; Mahlaule v Minister of Social<br />

Development, it appeared to combine the reasonableness approach<br />

56 Pieterse (n 20 above) 497-500.<br />

57<br />

1998 1 SA 765 (CC), 1997 12 BCLR 1696 (CC). For a critical discussion, see D<br />

Moellendorf ‘Reasoning about resources: Soobramoney and the future of socioeconomic<br />

rights claims’ (1998) 14 South African Journal on Human Rights 327; M<br />

Pieterse ‘Health care rights, resources and rationing’ (2007) 124 South African<br />

Law Journal 514 527-535.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!