04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

198 Chapter 12<br />

3.1 Dignity 1: Individual as an end-in-herself<br />

Justice Ackermann, the Court’s original exponent of dignity, grounds<br />

the first definition of dignity in two sources that we have already<br />

identified: apartheid and the work of Immanuel Kant:<br />

[I]t is permissible and indeed necessary to look at the ills of the past<br />

which [the Constitution] seeks to rectify and in <strong>this</strong> way try to establish<br />

what equality and dignity mean. ... What lay at the heart of the<br />

apartheid pathology was the extensive and sustained attempt to deny to<br />

the majority of the South African population the right of selfidentification<br />

and self-determination. ... Who you were, where you<br />

could live, what schools and universities you could attend, what you<br />

could do and aspire to, and with whom you could form intimate personal<br />

relationship was determined for you by the state. ... That state did its<br />

best to deny to blacks that which is definitional to being human, namely<br />

the ability to understand or at least define oneself through ones own<br />

powers and to act freely as a moral agent pursuant to such<br />

understanding of self-definition. Blacks were treated as means to an end<br />

and hardly ever as an end in themselves; an almost complete reversal of<br />

the Kantian imperative and concept of priceless inner worth and<br />

dignity. 7<br />

For Kant, as for Ackermann, the recognition of every human being’s<br />

inherent dignity takes the form of a variation on the golden rule, the<br />

categorical imperative: ‘Act in such a way that you always treat<br />

6 explanation. In the first place, legal rules often perform more than a single<br />

function. See JW Harris Legal Philosophies (1980) 105 - 109 (In the accepted<br />

parlance of legal positivism, primary rules are generally understood to impose<br />

duties and obligations, while secondary rules, which are parasitic on the<br />

existence of primary rules, determine how primary rules are to be applied or to<br />

be altered). See also Hart (supra) at 77–96. However, I use ‘first order rule’ and<br />

‘second order rule’ in a technical sense not meant to evoke passionate debate<br />

about the virtues and vices of legal positivism. First order rules resolve disputes;<br />

second order rules assist in the interpretation of—though they do not necessarily<br />

determine— the content of first order rules in a manner that permits resolution of<br />

disputes. See S Woolman ‘Review of Corder and Du Plessis Understanding South<br />

Africa’s Transitional Bill of Rights’ (1996) 112 South African Law Journal 711, 715.<br />

See also T Morawetz ‘Understanding Disagreement, the Root Issue of<br />

Jurisprudence: Applying Wittgenstein to Positivism, Critical Theory and Judging’<br />

(1992) 141 University of Pennsylvania LR 371. Not only do different denotations of<br />

dignity operate as different kinds of rules, the very same definition of ‘dignity’<br />

may operate as both a primary rule and a secondary rule. In the second place,<br />

while the word ‘dignity’ may not be so open-textured as to be the basic unit in a<br />

jurisprudential ‘Lego-land’, its multiple uses confound all attempts to reduce the<br />

courts’ jurisprudence to a finite number of rules. Fourth, two distinct dangers<br />

attach to a purely positivist account of dignity: (a) formally fair rules may mask<br />

substantially unjust arrangements; (b) once a constitutional norm such as dignity<br />

is reduced to rules, obedience to the law tends to supplant considerations of<br />

justice as the primary end of our political community. We need to be regularly<br />

reminded that the legal rules that the right to dignity produces are only as good<br />

as the everyday ethical practices that inform, and regularly transform, those<br />

rules.<br />

7 Ackermann ‘Legal Nature’ (n 1 above) 650.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!