04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Stu Woolman & Henk Botha 161<br />

3.4 Incrementalism and conservatism<br />

Balancing is also sometimes associated with a conservative bench. In<br />

the United States, balancing got a bad reputation during the McCarthy<br />

era, when courts used the language of balancing to validate serious<br />

infringements of freedom of expression. Such an account seems to<br />

oversimplify the historical record. Balancing has, at various times in<br />

history, also been associated with liberal and progressive causes and<br />

the extension of constitutional rights and freedoms. But even if<br />

balancing does not necessarily translate into a readiness to sacrifice<br />

individual rights and freedoms in the name of collective interests,<br />

there may still be something conservative about it. Balancing is, we<br />

think, legitimately associated with a cautious, incrementalist<br />

approach to constitutionality inspired judicial law-making. The<br />

balancer is inclined to restrict her finding to the case at hand, as the<br />

next case may, ostensibly, require that a different balance be struck.<br />

While there may be advantages to such a judicious approach, which<br />

was indeed a hallmark of the Chaskalson Court, there is a growing<br />

concern within the academy that the case-by-case approach to<br />

constitutional analysis, in general, and limitations analysis, in<br />

particular, blunts the transformative potential of the Final<br />

Constitution. 21<br />

3.5 Science and silence<br />

Balancing, some critics suggest, encourages judges to resort to<br />

‘scientific’ language — ie, cost-benefit analysis. The fear here is that<br />

such talk invites a new type of formalism which, like all formalist<br />

doctrines, tends to eschew dialogue about important moral and<br />

political issues. As Aleinikoff puts it:<br />

Scientifically styled opinions, written to answer charges of subjectivity,<br />

make us spectators as the Court places the various interests on the<br />

scales. The weighing mechanism remains a mystery, and the result is<br />

simply read off the machine. Scientific balancing decisions are neither<br />

opinions nor arguments that can engage us; they are demonstrations. 22<br />

A related critique is that balancing rests upon the assumption that the<br />

primary aim of constitutional law is to mediate pre-existing interests.<br />

21 For a critique of the incrementalist approach to the development of the common<br />

law, see generally R Nagel ‘Liberals and balancing’ (1992) 63 University of<br />

Colorado Law Review 319. See also A van der Walt ‘Tradition on trial: A critical<br />

analysis of the civil-law tradition in South African property law’ (1995) 11 South<br />

African Journal on Human Rights 169; A van der Walt ‘Dancing with codes —<br />

Protecting, developing and deconstructing property rights in a constitutional<br />

state’ (2000) 18 South African Law Journal 258; S Woolman ‘The amazing,<br />

vanishing Bill of Rights’ (2007) 124 South African Law Journal 762.<br />

22 Aleinikoff (n 15 above) 993.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!