04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

284 Chapter 17<br />

deprivations). Roux worries that the doctrine will suppress forever<br />

from South African constitutional law the question of developing a<br />

doctrinal method for differentiating (in debatable cases) those stateauthored<br />

property-value impairments that count as ‘expropriations’<br />

from those that do not. From a US observer’s standpoint, the effect is<br />

to deprive South Africa forever of the possible development of a body<br />

of law paralleling that which in the US is known as the doctrine of<br />

‘regulatory taking’ (and elsewhere is sometimes called ‘constructive<br />

expropriation’). From among state actions that in form do no more<br />

than regulate the use and enjoyment of an asset, such a doctrine<br />

selects some for subjection to a compensation requirement that, by<br />

the express terms of the constitutional text, applies only when the<br />

state takes away property from an owner.<br />

I agree with Roux that the doctrine according to FNB has the<br />

effects I have just described. My view is that these effects supply no<br />

ground, none at all, for reservation or worry. To the contrary, I<br />

believe they leave South Africa with a reading of FC section 25 that is<br />

normatively superior to any alternative one might envision, while<br />

being no less textually justified. At the bottom line, my claim is that<br />

a regulatory-taking doctrine would be a bad choice for South Africa<br />

(not to say for any country, but that is beyond the scope of my<br />

undertaking here). In my view, a reading of FC section 25 that<br />

forecloses that possibility is to be preferred over one that doesn’t, all<br />

else being equal. I postpone the justification for that normative claim<br />

to late in my discussion. Everything else I shall have to say along the<br />

way will be on an analytical-descriptive, not a normative-substantive<br />

level. I thus aim to confirm and to drive home, in a somewhat<br />

different way, much of what Roux has said, while perhaps questioning<br />

one aspect of it. I confess to uncertainty about how far, if at all, Roux<br />

will disagree with anything I shall have to say on <strong>this</strong> point. I do think<br />

I am putting a somewhat different spin on the matters discussed than<br />

is conveyed by the rhetoric, at least, of Roux’s Conversations-piece.<br />

The second question I wish to examine is that of the relation<br />

between FC section 25(1)’s ‘internal’ limitation clause and the<br />

general limitation clause contained in FC section 36(1). Read strictly<br />

according to its terms, FC section 25 grants only what has been called<br />

a ‘truncated’ property right: 3 A right against deprivation not<br />

authorised by a non-arbitrary law and expropriation not for a public<br />

purpose or in the public interest, or not attended by just and<br />

equitable compensation, with justification of violations of that<br />

truncated right still a possibility in terms of FC section 36(1). In an<br />

3 See AJ van der Walt Constitutional property law (2005) 62-65.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!