04.06.2014 Views

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

Download this publication - PULP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

340 Chapter 19<br />

Through the years, Liebenberg has engaged critically with<br />

features of both of these approaches. 32 In her current paper, she<br />

evaluates both from a dialogic perspective and concludes that, while<br />

a minimum core approach valuably captures part of the content of<br />

socio-economic rights and ‘imposes a high burden of justification in<br />

contexts where people are deprived of the basic necessities of life’, 33<br />

a reasonableness approach is better suited to a society committed to<br />

translation through dialogue. A reasonableness approach ‘avoids<br />

closure and creates the on-going possibility of challenging various<br />

forms of socio-economic deprivations in the different contexts in<br />

which they arise’. 34<br />

In relation to minimum core, Liebenberg explains how the onceoff<br />

judicial formulation and enforcement of a comprehensive core<br />

standard can frustrate dialogue over the content of socio-economic<br />

rights. She shows, convincingly, that a minimum core approach may<br />

operate to ‘stifle institutional conversation and collaboration<br />

between the three branches of government’, may result in over- or<br />

under-inclusive specification of obligations, may invite undue<br />

reductionism and/or minimalism in need–definition, may ‘exclude or<br />

marginalise the needs of various groups that do not fit the background<br />

norms informing the definition of core obligations’ and may<br />

oversimplify the interaction between and co-dependence of<br />

interconnected socio-economic needs of varying levels of complexity,<br />

urgency, and cost. 35<br />

I agree that the adoption of a minimum core approach may<br />

amount to the once-off, ‘top-down’ imposition of a singular,<br />

contested, point of view that denies and precludes reasonable<br />

disagreement over its conceptual foundations, contextual appropriateness,<br />

feasibility and logic. 36 But, to be fair to minimum core<br />

proponents, it need not engender such outcomes. It should be<br />

possible for courts to engage in a far more gradual, open-ended,<br />

context-specific and contingent process of case-by-case elaboration<br />

of the essential minimum content of rights, in a manner that invites,<br />

rather than forestalls, dialogue. 37<br />

32 See, eg, S Liebenberg ‘South Africa’s evolving jurisprudence on socio-economic<br />

rights: An effective tool in challenging poverty?’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy &<br />

Development 159; S Liebenberg ‘The interpretation of socio-economic rights’ in S<br />

Woolman et al (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd Edition, OS, 2003)<br />

Chapter 33; S Liebenberg ‘The value of human dignity in interpreting socioeconomic<br />

rights’ (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 1.<br />

33 Liebenberg (n 3 above) 324.<br />

34 Liebenberg (n 3 above) 320.<br />

35<br />

Liebenberg (n 3 above) 309-318. See also Dixon (n 2 above) 416-418; Steinberg (n<br />

2 above) 274-276; Wesson (n 31 above) 303-305.<br />

36 See Pieterse (n 20 above) 490-491 and authorities cited there.<br />

37<br />

Pieterse (n 20 above) 491. See further Bilchitz (n 27 above) 160; Woolman &<br />

Botha (n 8 above ) 34-104 — 34-113.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!