12.07.2015 Views

safeguarding democracy inside the eu - Transatlantic Academy

safeguarding democracy inside the eu - Transatlantic Academy

safeguarding democracy inside the eu - Transatlantic Academy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

© 2013 <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>. All rights reserved.No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any meanswithout permission in writing from <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>. Please direct inquiries to:<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>1744 R Street, NWWashington, DC 20009T 1 202 745 3886F 1 202 265 1662E Info@transatlanticacademy.orgThis publication can be downloaded for free at www.transatlanticacademy.org.<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong> Paper SeriesThe <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong> Paper Series presents research on a variety of transatlantic topics by staff,fellows, and partners of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>. The views expressed here are those of <strong>the</strong> authorand do not necessarily represent <strong>the</strong> views of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>. Comments from readersare welcome; reply to <strong>the</strong> mailing address above or by e-mail to Info@transatlanticacademy.org.About <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>The <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong> was created in 2007 as a partnership between <strong>the</strong> German MarshallFund of <strong>the</strong> United States (GMF) and <strong>the</strong> ZEIT-Stiftung Ebelin und Gerd Bucerius. The RobertBosch Stiftung and <strong>the</strong> Lynde and Harry Bradley Foundation joined as full partners beginning in2008, and <strong>the</strong> Fritz Thyssen Foundation joined as a full partner in 2011. The Compagnia di SanPaolo joined in providing additional support in May 2009, as did <strong>the</strong> Joachim Herz Stiftung and <strong>the</strong>Volkswagen Stifung in 2011. In addition, <strong>the</strong> <strong>Academy</strong> received startup funding from <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong>Program of <strong>the</strong> Government of <strong>the</strong> Federal Republic of Germany through funds of <strong>the</strong>European Recovery Program (ERP) of <strong>the</strong> Federal Ministry of Economics and Technology.


Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EUBrussels and <strong>the</strong> Future of Liberal Order<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong> Paper SeriesFebruary 2013Jan-Werner Müller 1Executive Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3Supranational Democracy-Protection: The Story So Far . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5Four Concerns . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9Four Criteria . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15Three Strategies — and <strong>the</strong>ir Limits . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17Some Modest Proposals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23Concluding Thoughts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 271Jan-Werner Müller is a professor of politics at Princeton University, where he also directs <strong>the</strong> Project in <strong>the</strong> History ofPolitical Thought. During <strong>the</strong> fall of 2012 he was a non-resident fellow at <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong> in Washington, DC;he is currently at <strong>the</strong> Institute of Advanced Study, Princeton, NJ. His latest book is Contesting Democracy: Political Ideas inTwentieth-Century Europe (Yale, 2011). He is currently writing a book on how Catholic thinkers in 19th and 20th centuryEurope imagined reconciling religion and modern <strong>democracy</strong>.For discussions on <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of EU interventions, <strong>the</strong> author is grateful to Elmar Brok, Giovanni Capoccia, GáborHalmai, Mattias Kumm, Alexander Graf Lambsdorff, Miguel Poiares Maduro, Peter Niesen, Grigore Pop-Eleches, KimLane Scheppele, Wojciech Sadurski, Alexander Somek, Rui Tavares, and Vladimir Tismaneanu. He also wishes to thank hisfellow fellows at <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>, Washington, DC, during fall 2012; <strong>the</strong> audience at <strong>the</strong> Engelsberg seminar on“The Pursuit of Europe,” June 2012; <strong>the</strong> participants in <strong>the</strong> workshop “Saving Democracy in Europe,” Princeton University,October 2012; as well as <strong>the</strong> staff of ARENA, Oslo, for helpful reactions to earlier versions of this essay. Particular thanks to<strong>the</strong> director of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>, Stephen Szabo.


Executive SummaryRecent illiberal turns in Hungary andRomania have prompted <strong>the</strong> question what,if anything, <strong>the</strong> EU could and should do toprotect liberal <strong>democracy</strong> within member states.This paper discusses four principled concerns about<strong>democracy</strong>-saving EU interventions in memberstates: that an institution that is itself largelyundemocratic cannot credibly protect <strong>democracy</strong>;that <strong>the</strong>re are in fact no common Europeanstandards that could be used to determine whe<strong>the</strong>ra member state is departing from a sharedEuropean understanding of <strong>democracy</strong>; thatinterventions are per se illiberal; and, finally, thatonly small states will be subject to intervention, aform of EU hypocrisy that delegitimizes Brusselsboth in <strong>the</strong> states concerned and possibly across<strong>the</strong> EU as a whole. This paper counters all <strong>the</strong>seconcerns and argues that, ultimately, <strong>the</strong> problemwith intervention is not to be found on a <strong>the</strong>oreticalnormative level, but on a practical plane. As ofnow, <strong>the</strong> EU lacks a tool-kit to intervene effectivelyin member states; whatever it has recently usedby way of sticks and carrots can seem arbitrary oropportunistic. This paper concludes by makinga number of modest proposals as to how thissituation might be remedied. In particular, itsuggests <strong>the</strong> creation of an expert body, tentativelycalled <strong>the</strong> “Copenhagen Commission,” whichcontinuously assesses <strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule oflaw within member states. Such an institution oughtto be authorized to conduct its own investigations,to raise <strong>the</strong> alarm about turns to illiberalism —and to impose a very limited range of sanctions.The existing mechanisms should stay in place, butideally would be complemented with <strong>the</strong> possibilityof entirely excluding a state from <strong>the</strong> EU.Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 1


1IntroductionIn <strong>the</strong> nightmare of <strong>the</strong> darkAll <strong>the</strong> dogs of Europe bark,And <strong>the</strong> living nations wait,Each sequestered in its hate;Intellectual disgraceStares from every human face,And <strong>the</strong> seas of pity lieLocked and frozen in each eye.From W. H. Auden, “In Memory of W. B. Yeats”If a people — especially one whose freedom hasnot yet become prescriptive — does not value itsufficiently to fight for it, and maintain it againstany force which can be mustered within <strong>the</strong> country,even by those who have <strong>the</strong> command of <strong>the</strong> publicrevenue, it is only a question in how few years ormonths that people will be enslaved. Ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>government which it has given to itself, or somemilitary leader or knot of conspirators who contriveto subvert <strong>the</strong> government, will speedily put an endto all popular institutions: unless indeed it suits <strong>the</strong>irconvenience better to leave <strong>the</strong>m standing, and becontent with reducing <strong>the</strong>m to mere forms; for, unless<strong>the</strong> spirit of liberty is strong in a people, those whohave <strong>the</strong> executive in <strong>the</strong>ir hands easily work anyinstitutions to <strong>the</strong> purposes of despotism.From J. S. Mill, “A Few Words on Non-Intervention”Are <strong>the</strong>re limits to political change within <strong>the</strong>European Union? Or, put less abstractly,what if a member state appears to be on apath toward a regime that is no longer recognizableas a form of liberal <strong>democracy</strong>? Put even morebluntly, could <strong>the</strong>re be a dictatorship <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong>EU? If such a specter appeared, should Brusselssomehow step in to save or, for that matter, revive<strong>democracy</strong>? Or would this constitute an illegitimateform of meddling in <strong>the</strong> domestic affairs ofcountries that, after all, have delegated specificpowers to Europe — and not empowered Brusselsto be a policeman <strong>safeguarding</strong> liberal <strong>democracy</strong>across <strong>the</strong> European continent, or even just tolecture Europeans from Lapland to Lampedusaon how popular rule is correctly understood? All<strong>the</strong>se are no longer <strong>the</strong>oretical questions: recentdevelopments in Hungary and Romania have putsuch challenges squarely on <strong>the</strong> agenda of Europeanpolitics — even if concerns about a possible slidetoward illiberalism in both countries have beenlargely overshadowed by <strong>the</strong> <strong>eu</strong>ro crisis.I argue that it is legitimate for Brussels to interferein individual member states for <strong>the</strong> purpose ofprotecting liberal <strong>democracy</strong>. Four commonconcerns about such interventions are largelymisplaced.• First, <strong>the</strong> criticism that <strong>the</strong>y are hypocriticalbecause <strong>the</strong> Union is itself not democratic and<strong>the</strong>refore in no position credibly to act as <strong>the</strong>guardian of <strong>democracy</strong> on <strong>the</strong> continent.• Second, <strong>the</strong> worry that <strong>the</strong>re is no single, fullyagreed model of European liberal <strong>democracy</strong>that could be used as a template to decidewhe<strong>the</strong>r countries are departing from shared“European Standard” (<strong>the</strong>re might often betalk of such standards, but effectively, so criticswould claim, <strong>the</strong>y don’t exist).Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 3


• Third, <strong>the</strong> concern that such interventions<strong>the</strong>mselves are in and of <strong>the</strong>mselves paternalisticand, ultimately, illiberal.• Finally, <strong>the</strong> charge that only smaller, relativelypowerless member states would ever be subjectto interference from Brussels (in a sense, <strong>the</strong>n,this criticism also comes down to a suspicion ofhypocrisy).These are not unreasonable concerns. But one cancounter <strong>the</strong>m and, in <strong>the</strong> process, develop a set ofcriteria as to when and how European interventionis justified. In fact, <strong>the</strong> real problem arises not ata relatively abstract <strong>the</strong>oretical level, but when itcomes to policy instruments and concrete politicalstrategies. To say it outright: as of now, <strong>the</strong> EUhas no convincing tool kit to deal with situationsthat probably not many Eurocrats — or, for thatmatter, European elites more broadly — everforesaw. Brussels, as well as national capitals,seemed to have assumed that <strong>the</strong> consolidation ofliberal democracies in <strong>the</strong> run-up to EU accessionwas irreversible. Once <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> club, so <strong>the</strong>ra<strong>the</strong>r complacent reasoning seemed to go, youngdemocracies would count <strong>the</strong>ir blessings and neverlook back (or, for that matter, sideways and forwardto illiberal forms of statecraft).To be sure, <strong>the</strong> repertoire of legal and politicalinstruments <strong>the</strong> EU has at its disposal at <strong>the</strong>moment to exert pressure on member statesmight occasionally work — but it can also appeararbitrary and opportunistic. I propose extendingthis repertoire as well as <strong>the</strong> creation of a new kindof <strong>democracy</strong> watchdog — tentatively called <strong>the</strong>“Copenhagen Commission” — that can raise aEurope-wide alarm about deteriorations in <strong>the</strong> ruleof law and <strong>democracy</strong>. Such a body also ought to beable to trigger a limited set of “smart sanctions.”4<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


2Supranational Democracy-Protection:The Story So FarAcliché of our time holds that “identitycreation”requires an “O<strong>the</strong>r,” that is to say:an enemy, or, at <strong>the</strong> very least, someonewho clearly is “not us.” If that is correct, <strong>the</strong> EUshould have found its identity in early 2000, whenEurope’s O<strong>the</strong>r appeared — not for <strong>the</strong> first timein 20 th century European history — in <strong>the</strong> form ofa charismatic Austrian: Jörg Haider. The inclusionof Haider’s populist right-wing Freedom Party in<strong>the</strong> government prompted <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>n EU members— minus Austria, obviously — to take “sanctions”against Vienna: for instance, <strong>the</strong>y vowed not topromote Austrian candidates for positions ininternational organizations.Yet what came to be known as <strong>the</strong> Haider Affairin some ways deeply traumatized European elites:<strong>the</strong> (for <strong>the</strong> most part symbolic) sanctions lookedsomewhat ridiculous; fear mounted that <strong>the</strong>remight be a nationalist backlash in Austria; mostimportant, in <strong>the</strong> end, a group of three “wise men”chosen by Brussels certified in an official reportthat <strong>the</strong>re was nothing wrong with <strong>the</strong> Austriangovernment (even if <strong>the</strong>re remained concerns about<strong>the</strong> FPÖ). 1 Europe had its fingers burnt, or so manypeople think today.More than a decade later, <strong>the</strong> question of how, if atall, to protect democracies <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU is back on<strong>the</strong> agenda. Two countries in particular have givenrise to concern in Brussels: Hungary and Romania. 21Martti Ahtisaari, Jochen Frowein, and Marcelino Orejta,“Report on <strong>the</strong> Austrian Government’s Commitment to <strong>the</strong>Common European Values, in particular concerning <strong>the</strong> Rightsof Minorities, Refugees and Immigrants, and <strong>the</strong> Evolution of<strong>the</strong> Political Nature of <strong>the</strong> FPÖ (The Wise Men Report),” inInternational Legal Materials, vol. 40 (2001), 102-23.2On Hungary, see <strong>the</strong> special section on Hungary’s illiberal turnin <strong>the</strong> Journal of Democracy, vol. 23, no. 3 (2012), <strong>the</strong> collectionedited by Gábor Attila Tóth, Constitution for a DisunitedNation: On Hungary’s 2011 Fundamental Law (Budapest: CEUPress, 2012), Pierre Verluise, “UE-Hongrie V. Orban: vers larupture?,” diploweb.com, December 2, 2012, available onlineat http://www.diploweb.com/UE-Hongrie-V-Orban-vers-la-To recap very briefly, in Hungary, a right-wingpopulist party, Fidesz, came to power with a twothirdsmajority in parliament in April 2010. TheFidesz government under Viktor Orbán announceda new “system of national cooperation,” passed adraconian media law that was widely criticized —rupture.html [last accessed January 25, 2013], and, for fur<strong>the</strong>rhistorical background, my “Longing for Greater Hungary,”London Review of Books, vol. 34, no. 12 (2012), as well as PaulLendvai, Hungary: Between Democracy and Authoritarianism(New York: Columbia UP, 2012). On Romania, see VladimirTismaneanu, “Democracy on <strong>the</strong> Brink: A Coup AttemptFails in Romania,” in World Aaffirs (January/February 2013),83-7, and, for <strong>the</strong> larger background, Tom Gallagher, Theft ofa Nation: Romania Since Communism (London: Hurst, 2005),but also Daniel Barbu, Die abwesende Republik, trans. LarisaSchippel (Berlin Frank & Timme, 2009). See also <strong>the</strong> EuropeanCommission’s latest report on Romania at http://static.<strong>eu</strong>ractiv.com/sites/all/<strong>eu</strong>ractiv/files/CVM%20Romania%20political.pdf [last accessed January 7, 2013], which highlights a rangeof serious problems that have no equivalent in Hungary. Ingeneral, it needs to be pointed out that Hungary by 2010was widely considered a consolidated <strong>democracy</strong>, whereasRomania continued to suffer from a number of deep problems,from corruption to a tendency to play fast and loose with<strong>the</strong> constitutional framework, and easily escalating conflictsamong <strong>the</strong> political elite (observers have spoken of “triagedemocratization,” where urgent problems are — sometimes —addressed, but where <strong>the</strong>re is little systematic state-building andentrenchment of <strong>the</strong> rule law. See Ronald F. King and Paul E.Sum (eds.), Romania under Basescu: Aspirations, Achievements,and Frustrations during His First Presidential Term (Lanham:Lexington Books, 2011). Moreover, observers have crediblyshown that accession for Romania meant an immediatedeterioration in elite political practices, as well as efforts atstate-building and <strong>the</strong> rule of law — a phenomenon VenelinGanev has termed “post-accession political hooliganism” (seeVenelin I. Ganev, “Post-Accession Hooliganism: DemocraticGovernance in Bulgaria and Romania after 2007,” in EastEuropean Politics and Societies and Cultures, vol. 27 [2013],1-19). Nothing similar occurred in Hungary, although <strong>the</strong>re,at least since 2002, one of <strong>the</strong> major political players denied<strong>the</strong> legitimacy of its main opponents. (After his electionloss in 2002 Orbán declared that <strong>the</strong> nation itself cannot be inopposition.) In that sense, in both countries <strong>the</strong> promise of1989 remains unfulfilled: a liberal-democratic political systemthat allows for civilized conflict within a shared constitutionalframework that all major actors regard as legitimate (and where<strong>the</strong> main political actors regard each o<strong>the</strong>r as legitimate).Sanctions againstAustria are todayoften seen asa failure.Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 5


Fidesz waspursuing astrategy ofsystematicallyoccupying <strong>the</strong>state, so that <strong>the</strong>party might losean election, butnever lose power.by <strong>the</strong> OSCE, among o<strong>the</strong>rs 3 — and, in <strong>the</strong> springof 2011, rammed through a new constitutionthat was deeply nationalist and underminedchecks and balances (and which was also widelycriticized internationally, for instance by <strong>the</strong>Venice Commission). 4 In addition, Fidesz packed<strong>the</strong> constitutional court and, in general, keptappointing loyal followers to what were meant to benon-partisan institutions, often for unusually longterms (sometimes for more than two parliamentarycycles). Observers held that Fidesz was pursuinga strategy of systematically occupying <strong>the</strong> state, sothat <strong>the</strong> party might occasionally lose an election,but never lose power. Critics even began to speak of“Putinization” or “Lukashenko lite.” 5In Romania <strong>the</strong> attack on <strong>the</strong> rule of law happenedmuch more quickly. In <strong>the</strong> summer of 2012, anominally social democratic-liberal coalition(to be sure: <strong>the</strong>se labels have limited meaning3A timeline of <strong>the</strong> development of <strong>the</strong> media law as well as anextensive assessment of <strong>the</strong> Hungarian government’s claims thatall its elements have parallels elsewhere in democracies, canbe found on <strong>the</strong> website of <strong>the</strong> Central European University’sCenter for Media and Communications Studies: http://cmcs.c<strong>eu</strong>.hu/ [last accessed January 7, 2013].4See <strong>the</strong> criticism of <strong>the</strong> new constitution by <strong>the</strong> VeniceCommission: http://www.venice.coe.int/docs/2011/CDL-AD(2011)016-E.pdf [last accessed January 7, 2013].5These ra<strong>the</strong>r under-<strong>the</strong>orized terms (to put it politely)point to a very real difficulty in conceptualizing regimes likePutin’s and Lukashenko’s. “Illiberal <strong>democracy</strong>” appears tooweak, dictatorship too strong. At <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>the</strong> corecharacteristics of <strong>the</strong>se regimes are not really much disputed:virtually complete centralization of power; abuse of <strong>the</strong> ruleof law to weaken opposition forces, and also <strong>the</strong> removal ofall legal checks on centralized power; almost complete controlof <strong>the</strong> media; a tendency to keep speaking <strong>the</strong> language of<strong>democracy</strong> (think of <strong>the</strong> development of <strong>the</strong> concept of“sovereign <strong>democracy</strong>” under Putin). It is debatable whe<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong> price of oil should play a role in characterizations of<strong>the</strong>se regimes — for surely nei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong>m could have beenas relatively stable as <strong>the</strong>y have been without <strong>the</strong> boom in oilprices. See also Ivan Krastev and Stephen Holmes, “An Autopsyof Managed Democracy,” in Journal of Democracy, vol. 23(2012), 33-45in Romanian politics 6 ) sought to impeach <strong>the</strong>nominally conservative-liberal president, TraianBăsescu (who was accused of overstepping <strong>the</strong>constitutional limits to his powers; one attempt toimpeach him, based on similar charges, had alreadyfailed in 2007). To that effect, it disempowered<strong>the</strong> constitutional court in addition to passing anumber of emergency decrees that were clearlyaimed at ensuring only one possible outcome for<strong>the</strong> referendum on <strong>the</strong> president’s impeachment.In particular, <strong>the</strong> threshold of participationfor a referendum to be valid was lowered. Thegovernment led by Victor Ponta also removed <strong>the</strong>heads of <strong>the</strong> two houses of parliament and deposed<strong>the</strong> “Advocate of <strong>the</strong> People” (<strong>the</strong> ombudsman) —<strong>the</strong> former initiative insured that one of Ponta’sallies would become acting president while Băsescuwas suspended; <strong>the</strong> latter helped to get rid of <strong>the</strong>one actor who could have taken <strong>the</strong> emergencydecrees to <strong>the</strong> constitutional court. 7In both Hungary and Romania, <strong>the</strong> EU intervenedin a substantial (and controversial) manner. TheCommission criticized Hungary’s media law,which was eventually changed — although it isdebatable whe<strong>the</strong>r it does not in many ways retainits illiberal character. Hungary was also investigatedfor failing to implement EU law — in particular,<strong>the</strong>re were concerns about <strong>the</strong> independenceof <strong>the</strong> central bank, of <strong>the</strong> judiciary, and of <strong>the</strong>data protection ombudsman — and, in <strong>the</strong> end,<strong>the</strong> European Commission took Hungary to <strong>the</strong>European Court of Justice. Again, <strong>the</strong> results so farhave been somewhat mixed: Budapest compliedwith some of <strong>the</strong> demands to ensure central bank6 Herta Müller spoke of “die sogenannte sozialdemokratischeRegierung in Bukarest.” See “Ich habe die Sprache gegessen,” inDer Spiegel, August 27, 2012.7 For an account (and an opinion of <strong>the</strong> legality of <strong>the</strong>measures), see <strong>the</strong> Venice Commission’s Opinion on Romaniafrom August 18, 2012, available online at http://www.venice.coe.int//docs/2012/CDL-AD%282012%29026-e.pdf [lastaccessed January 7, 2013].6<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


independence (knowing fully that <strong>the</strong> president of<strong>the</strong> bank is set to retire in April 2013 and can <strong>the</strong>nbe replaced by someone more to <strong>the</strong> government’sliking); <strong>the</strong> European Court ruled on at least oneoccasion against Hungary and held that <strong>the</strong> drasticlowering of <strong>the</strong> retirement age for judges to 62violated European law — but <strong>the</strong> judges have yet tobe reinstated.In July 2012, <strong>the</strong> Commission called on Romania— once declared “<strong>the</strong> EU’s true test case” by TonyJudt 8 — to take back some proposed changes to<strong>the</strong> rules for referenda on <strong>the</strong> president, which <strong>the</strong>government did (and which decisively contributedto <strong>the</strong> failure of <strong>the</strong> impeachment process). Eventhough 88.5 percent of voters turned out to be infavor of removing Băsescu, <strong>the</strong> critical thresholdof participation (50 percent plus one vote), whichPonta had tried to lower, was not reached. 9 Aftersome attempts by <strong>the</strong> government to change <strong>the</strong>number of eligible voters retroactively in orderto get <strong>the</strong> desired outcome after all, and somereluctance to accept a ruling by <strong>the</strong> constitutionalcourt that <strong>the</strong> referendum was indeed valid,Băsescu was reinstated. Since his resoundingelection victory in December 2012, Ponta on onehand agreed to a truce with a much weakenedBăsescu (<strong>the</strong>reby seemingly bringing what has oftenbeen called “<strong>the</strong> war of <strong>the</strong> two palaces” — that ofpresident and prime minister — to an end). On <strong>the</strong>8Though only partly because it might prove <strong>the</strong> ultimatechallenge for Europenization in <strong>the</strong> sense of democratizationthrough membership, as some might have thought. Ra<strong>the</strong>r,Judt argued that “Romania is peripheral, and <strong>the</strong> rest of Europestands to gain little from its presence in <strong>the</strong> union. Left outsideit would be an embarrassment, but hardly a threat. But forjust this reason Romania is <strong>the</strong> EU’s true test case.” Tony Judt,Reappraisals: Reflections on <strong>the</strong> Forgotten Twentieth Century(New York: Penguin, 2009), 263.9“Der unermüdlich Kampf der Kleptokraten,” in FrankfurterAllgemeine Zeitung, August 28, 2012, available online athttp://www.faz.net/aktuell/politik/ausland/rumaenien-derunermuedliche-kampf-der-kleptokraten-11870946.html[lastaccessed January 24, 2013]o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>the</strong>re have been reports of Ponta tryingto put toge<strong>the</strong>r a two-thirds majority in parliamentin order to change <strong>the</strong> constitution. If that is indeed<strong>the</strong> plan, Ponta might have learnt from his neighborto <strong>the</strong> west: ra<strong>the</strong>r than relying on ad hoc measures,ra<strong>the</strong>r than being “impatient” (Ponta on Ponta),<strong>the</strong> government should implement long-terminstitutional changes. 10 Even if Ponta belongs to adifferent party-political family — he seems to provea good pupil of Orbán: entrenching highly partisanpreferences legally is far smarter than what observersof <strong>the</strong> Romanian scene sometimes called Ponta’s“parliamentary putsch.” 1110 See “Clear victory, uncertain future,” on The Economist’s“Eastern Approaches” blog, December 10, 2012, available athttp://www.economist.com/blogs/easternapproaches/2012/12/romanian-politics-0 [last accessed January 7, 2013]; Karl-PeterSchwarz, “Doppelzüngig,” in Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung,December 10, 2012, available online at http://www.faz.net/aktuell/politik/ausland/victor-ponta-doppelzuengig-11989098.html [last accessed January 7, 2013]. To be sure, Băsescualso violated democratic principles by hinting initially tha<strong>the</strong> might suggest a prime minister o<strong>the</strong>r than Ponta, despite<strong>the</strong> latter’s clear victory in <strong>the</strong> elections. Of course, a semipresidentialsystem like Romania’s is more likely to generateconflicts of this kind in <strong>the</strong> first place.11 As Müller put it dramatically: “Denen ist das Land scheißegal.Ungarn war ein Lehrstück, die haben sich angesehen, wie mandort die Demokratie aushebelt. Es macht einem Angst, dass esso junge L<strong>eu</strong>te sind. Victor Ponta, der n<strong>eu</strong>e Ministerpräsident,ist 39. Aber auch er ist noch von Ceauşescu sozialisiert.Seine Doktorarbeit ist in weiten Teilen ein Plagiat, zudemhat er sich noch mit einem erfundenen Universitätsabschlussgeschmückt. Betrug gehört zum Selbstverständnis.” (“Theydon’t give a shit about <strong>the</strong> country. Hungary was an instructiveexample, <strong>the</strong>y looked at how <strong>democracy</strong> was disabled <strong>the</strong>re.It’s frightening that it’s such young people. Victor Ponta, <strong>the</strong>new prime minister, is 39 years old. But even he was stillsocialized by Ceauşescu. His doctoral dissertation is in largeparts plagiarized, in addition he has adorned himself withan invented university degree. Fraud belongs to his selfunderstanding.”)See “Ich habe die Sprache gegessen.” Theparallel has been suggested in an interview to Ponta himself.He ei<strong>the</strong>r failed to get <strong>the</strong> point or, more likely, decided not toengage with it:“Question: Il y a un point commun entre vous et votrehomologue hongrois Viktor Orban: une façon de brutaliserles institutions..” — “Answer: Ma malchance est que monprénom est Victor. Avec tout le respect que j’ai pour lui, nosPonta might havelearned fromOrbán: ra<strong>the</strong>rthan relying onad hoc measures,ra<strong>the</strong>r than being“impatient” (Pontaon Ponta), <strong>the</strong>party shouldentrench itspreferences in anew constitution.Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 7


EU intervention in both Hungary and Romaniahas met with fierce criticism — and not just in <strong>the</strong>two countries concerned. In fact, a clear left-rightsplit across Europe emerged among critics of <strong>the</strong>actions of <strong>the</strong> Commission: British Euroscepticsvues sont totalement différentes. Je suis le premier leaderroumain à ne pas avoir de passé dans le communisme. J’espèrereprésenter la fin de la période de transition postcommuniste.Je v<strong>eu</strong>x rendre les institutions au contrôle populaire, et pasles brutaliser.” (“Question: You and your pendant ViktorOrban have something in common: a way of brutalizing <strong>the</strong>institutions. Answer: It is my misfortune that my first nameis Victor. With all <strong>the</strong> respect I have for him, our views arecompletely different. I am <strong>the</strong> first Romanian leader withoutany past under communism. I hope to represent <strong>the</strong> endof <strong>the</strong> postcommunist transition period. I want to put <strong>the</strong>institutions under popular control, not to brutalize <strong>the</strong>m.”) See“L’agressivité de nos luttes politiques a surpris la Commissionet les Européens,” in Le Monde, September 18, 2012, availableonline at http://www.lemonde.fr/<strong>eu</strong>rope/article/2012/09/18/roumanie-l-agressivite-de-nos-luttes-politiques-a-surpris-les<strong>eu</strong>ropeens_1761835_3214.html[last accessed January 7, 2013].no less than German conservatives emphasized<strong>the</strong> importance of nation-state sovereignty (and<strong>the</strong> harm done to national pride by supposedlyheavy-handed EU interventions); on <strong>the</strong> left, <strong>the</strong>rewas less principled opposition to interferencefrom Brussels as such, but a widespread sensethat <strong>the</strong> Commission ultimately cares only abouteconomics, or, put more precisely, <strong>safeguarding</strong>neoliberal understandings of <strong>the</strong> role of centralbanks, <strong>the</strong> interests of multinational companies,and fiscal austerity.Clearly, <strong>the</strong>re is a need for more systematic thoughtabout <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of such interventions. EUlaw provides some guidelines, of course, but it isnoticeable that much of <strong>the</strong> public argument aboutintervention from Brussels has been conducted lessin <strong>the</strong> idiom of jurisprudence than in <strong>the</strong> languageof democratic <strong>the</strong>ory. So what can and what cannotbe justified here in <strong>the</strong> name of <strong>democracy</strong>?8<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


3Four ConcernsThe first standard charge against <strong>the</strong> EUprotecting <strong>democracy</strong> is that <strong>the</strong> Unionitself is not democratic — hence Brussels isfundamentally hypocritical in speaking out for andin <strong>the</strong> name of values to which it does not adhereitself. 12 This charge misses <strong>the</strong> point that <strong>the</strong> Unionderives its legitimacy not from being a continentwide<strong>democracy</strong> (at least at this point in time).Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is legitimate because national parliamentshave freely voted to bind <strong>the</strong>mselves and followEuropean rules. 13 In <strong>the</strong> <strong>eu</strong>ro crisis, this logic ofself-binding is clearly under attack — marketshave not found <strong>the</strong> model of rules and sanctionscredible. But with <strong>the</strong> single market, it has workedwell for decades. Nobody is complaining thatBrussels is taking member state governments tocourt for violating competition rules, for instance. 14One might still object that <strong>the</strong> parallel betweeninterventions to safeguard <strong>the</strong> single market andinterventions to protect <strong>democracy</strong> is misplaced.Are <strong>the</strong> purity of beer and <strong>the</strong> length of cucumbersnot a categorically different matter than <strong>the</strong> shapeand form of national political institutions? IsEuropean integration not predicated on <strong>the</strong> factthat member states remain both “masters of <strong>the</strong>treaties” and, in many clearly demarcated areas,masters of <strong>the</strong>ir own political fate? Or, taking adifferent line of attack: is <strong>the</strong> European Union notmeant to be irreducibly pluralist in character? Is<strong>the</strong> spirit of its laws, so to speak, not something12To be sure, this is not a claim one hears from many EUspecialists — but it is one that is almost immediately airedin public discussions and, for what it’s worth, in onlinecommentary.13For an elaboration of this point see Peter L. Lindseth, Powerand Legitimacy: Reconciling Europe and <strong>the</strong> Nation-State (NewYork: Oxford UP, 2010).14To be sure, self-binding is not <strong>the</strong> only source of legitimacy.This is not <strong>the</strong> moment to enter into a debate about <strong>the</strong>“democratic deficit,” but even <strong>the</strong> most hardened critics of <strong>the</strong>EU would concede that democratically elected governments,national parliaments, and <strong>the</strong> European Parliament all havemeaningful roles in European decision-making.that can best be described as a matter of mutualrecognition and mutual accommodation, whereconflicts are resolved by trying to normativelyrelativize oneself and open oneself to <strong>the</strong> point ofview of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, to find higher common groundand shared terms to address disputes — and neverthrough just bowing to commands from above, soto speak? Less abstractly, does not <strong>the</strong> Lisbon Treaty(which is now simply <strong>the</strong> Treaty on EuropeanUnion) itself enshrine <strong>the</strong> very principle that <strong>the</strong>Union ought to respect <strong>the</strong> national identities of<strong>the</strong> member states? And, on a less legalistic noteagain, did not Europe’s most powerful politicianonce appear in front of <strong>the</strong> European Parliament todeclare that <strong>the</strong> “soul of Europe” was “tolerance”? 15In response, a more specific argument about <strong>the</strong>meanings (and legitimacy) of European integrationas a political project to safeguard <strong>democracy</strong>needs to be advanced. After all, one of <strong>the</strong> explicitgoals of European enlargement to <strong>the</strong> East was toconsolidate liberal democracies (or, in <strong>the</strong> caseof Romania, complete <strong>the</strong> transition to liberal<strong>democracy</strong> in <strong>the</strong> first place). Governments inturn sought to lock <strong>the</strong>mselves into Europe so as toprevent “backsliding” 16 ; it was like Ulysses bindinghimself to <strong>the</strong> mast in order to resist <strong>the</strong> sirensongs of illiberal and antidemocratic demagoguesin <strong>the</strong> future. 17 Hence nei<strong>the</strong>r Hungarian Prime15 http://www.<strong>eu</strong>2007.de/en/News/Speeches_Interviews/January/Rede_Bundeskanzlerin2.html (last accessedSeptember 24, 2007).16 This has become a widespread term, without its usersnecessarily being aware of its origins in religious contexts. Ishall avoid it for <strong>the</strong> remainder of this paper.17 This thought has come under much criticism recently —including by Jon Elster who made it influential in <strong>the</strong> firstplace. While one can indeed question <strong>the</strong> notion of “selfbinding,”<strong>the</strong> case under discussion here is actually a matterof “wanting to be bound by o<strong>the</strong>rs” — and clearly renouncing<strong>the</strong> power to unbind oneself, short of jumping <strong>the</strong> (EU) shipaltoge<strong>the</strong>r. See <strong>the</strong> chapter “Ulysses Unbound: Constitutionsas Constraints,” in Ulysses Unbound: Studies in Rationality,Precommitment, and Constraints (New York: CambridgeThe Union derivesits legitimacynot from beinga continent-wide<strong>democracy</strong>.Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 9


fight for power. It would also cut short what onemight call a “democratic learning process,” <strong>the</strong>rebypreventing <strong>the</strong> proper development of a democraticpolitical culture (though one could of coursereasonably ask whe<strong>the</strong>r Italians should not havefigured out by <strong>the</strong> end of Berlusconi’ second stint inoffice at <strong>the</strong> very latest that <strong>the</strong> Cavaliere’s statecraftwas somewhat deficient). 33in <strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> 19 th century. Ideally peoplesstruggle for freedom and democracies (andpreserve <strong>the</strong>ir democracies) <strong>the</strong>mselves. 34 As Millput it in his A Few Words on Non-Intervention,“<strong>the</strong> only test … of a people’s having become fitfor popular institutions is that <strong>the</strong>y, or a sufficientportion of <strong>the</strong>m to prevail in <strong>the</strong> contest, are willingto brave labor and danger for <strong>the</strong>ir liberation.” 35All this is no more than restating an old point,a point familiar from John Stuart Mill’s writings33See also Peter Niesen, “Anti-Extremism, NegativeRepublicanism, Civic Society: Three Paradigms for BanningPolitical Parties,” in Shlomo Avineri and Zeev Sternhell(eds.), Europe’s Century of Discontent: The Legacies of Fascism,Nazism, and Communism, (Jerusalem: Magnes Press, 2003),249-68.34 Certainly, this argument could be reformulated with referenceto <strong>the</strong> concept of subsidiarity.35 Quoted by Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New YorkBasic Books, 1992), 88.14<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


5Three Strategies — and <strong>the</strong>ir LimitsLegitimacy and having appropriate policyinstruments at hand is not <strong>the</strong> same thing. Inthis section, I would like briefly to inspect <strong>the</strong>EU’s existing tool-kit, when <strong>the</strong> challenge consistsin <strong>safeguarding</strong> <strong>democracy</strong> in member states. I shallconclude that even where <strong>the</strong> tools seem to fit <strong>the</strong>task, so to speak, <strong>the</strong>y are ei<strong>the</strong>r unusable becauseof political reasons (something that, to be sure,could change over time) or have o<strong>the</strong>r drawbacks(mostly to do with <strong>the</strong> time it might take to apply<strong>the</strong>m).The Politics of Article 7As is well known, Article 7 of <strong>the</strong> Treaty on <strong>the</strong>European Union allows for <strong>the</strong> suspension ofmembership rights for states persistently violatingbasic European values. The idea for such anarticle had in fact been pushed by two paragons ofWestern European <strong>democracy</strong>, Italy and Austria,in <strong>the</strong> run-up to enlargement, clearly out of a fearof what those uncouth Eastern Europeans mightdo (<strong>the</strong> irony being that sanctions — thoughnot under Article 7 — were first applied againstAustria in 2000). 37 After <strong>the</strong> Haider Affair, anintermediate step was introduced to allow <strong>the</strong> EUto send a strong signal that <strong>the</strong>re exists a “clearrisk of a serious breach by a member state of <strong>the</strong>values referred to in Article 2” (that is, “respect forhuman dignity, freedom, <strong>democracy</strong>, equality, <strong>the</strong>rule of law, and respect for human rights, including<strong>the</strong> rights of persons belonging to minorities”). Ino<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> Union opted for a strategy thatallowed for step-by-step escalation, instead ofhaving only <strong>the</strong> choice of immediately confrontinga government with <strong>the</strong> charge that it is, in fact, inviolation of shared European values.However, even with this differentiated approach,<strong>the</strong>re is today a sense that Article 7 as a whole37Wojciech Sadurski, “Adding Bite to <strong>the</strong> Bark: The Story ofArticle 7, E.U. Enlargement, and Jörg Haider,” in ColumbiaJournal of European Law, vol. 16 (2009), 385-426.somehow constitutes a “nuclear option,” as <strong>the</strong>president of <strong>the</strong> European Commission recentlyput it. 38 In o<strong>the</strong>r words, it is unusable, 39 and isnothing more than what a British legal scholar hascalled an “empty gesture.” 40 Countries, it seems, aresimply too concerned that sanctions might also beapplied against <strong>the</strong>m one day. And since Article 7is obviously a political, not a judicial, process thatmakes national executives <strong>the</strong> decisive actors, <strong>the</strong>reis no reason to think that <strong>the</strong>ir inherent “sensitivityabout sovereignty” (Mattias Kumm) will not alwaysmake <strong>the</strong>m extremely reluctant to take sanctionsagainst one of <strong>the</strong>ir own. 41 In fact, <strong>the</strong> very idea ofsanctions goes against what might be called a wholeEU ethos of compromise, mutual accommodation,and mutual trust, as well as deference towardnational understandings of political values — <strong>the</strong>kind of EU self-understanding that celebrates38 This sense was echoed by <strong>the</strong> German foreign minister, whocalled Article 7 “die große K<strong>eu</strong>le” [<strong>the</strong> big cudgel]. See GuidoWesterwelle, “Europas Werte verteidigen!,” in FrankfurterAllgemeine Zeitung, September 5, 2012.39 The point was explicitly conceded by <strong>the</strong> president of <strong>the</strong>European Commission in his 2012 State of <strong>the</strong> Union address.As Barroso put it, “in recent months we have seen threatsto <strong>the</strong> legal and democratic fabric in some of our Europeanstates. The European Parliament and <strong>the</strong> Commission were<strong>the</strong> first to raise <strong>the</strong> alarm and played <strong>the</strong> decisive role inseeing <strong>the</strong>se worrying developments brought into check.” Hewent on to claim that “<strong>the</strong>se situations also revealed limits ofour institutional arrangements. We need a better developedset of instruments— not just <strong>the</strong> alternative between <strong>the</strong> ‘softpower’ of political persuasion and <strong>the</strong> ‘nuclear option’ of article7 of <strong>the</strong> Treaty.” At <strong>the</strong> time of writing no “better developedset of instruments” had been presented by <strong>the</strong> EuropeanCommission.40 Andrew Williams, “The indifferent gesture: Article 7 TEU, <strong>the</strong>Fundamental Rights Agency, and <strong>the</strong> U.K.’s invasion of Iraq,” inEuropean Law Review, vol. 31 (2006), 3-27.41 Of course, this problem has been even fur<strong>the</strong>r exacerbatedby <strong>the</strong> rise of what Jürgen Habermas, following Stefan Oeter,has called “executive federalism” in <strong>the</strong> EU — <strong>the</strong> process thathas systematically sidelined <strong>the</strong> European Commission, <strong>the</strong>European Parliament, and <strong>the</strong> national legislatures. See JürgenHabermas, Zur Verfassung Europas (Berlin Suhrkamp, 2011).Article 7 is widelyconsideredunusable.Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 17


Nowadays,attempts toundermine<strong>democracy</strong> and<strong>the</strong> rule of law arenot likely to b<strong>eu</strong>ndertaken withreference to <strong>the</strong>great advantagesof authoritariangovernance,or by invokingprecedents ofauthoritarian, letalone totalitarian,regimes in <strong>the</strong>20 th century.diversity and pluralism and that is summed up indeclarations that <strong>the</strong> soul of Europe is tolerance.True, some of <strong>the</strong> constraints on Article 7 mightbe very contingent. They could change over time,especially if <strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule of law wereattacked both more swiftly and more openlythan <strong>the</strong>y have been in <strong>the</strong> cases of Hungary andRomania (imagine a scenario where Victor Pontahad not — at least officially — backed down soquickly over <strong>the</strong> summer of 2012). Still, a clear-eyedassessment of <strong>the</strong> limits of Article 7 has to reckonwith <strong>the</strong> fact that nowadays attempts to undermine<strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule of law are not likely to b<strong>eu</strong>ndertaken with reference to <strong>the</strong> great advantagesof authoritarian governance, or by invokingprecedents of authoritarian, let alone totalitarian,regimes in <strong>the</strong> 20 th century. This is a problemfamiliar from debates about “militant <strong>democracy</strong>”within democratic states. Just think of <strong>the</strong>controversial (and difficult to prove requirement)for party bans in what is undoubtedly <strong>the</strong> mostfamous example of militant <strong>democracy</strong> in postwarEurope, <strong>the</strong> German wehrhafte or streitbareDemokratie: parties have not only to indicatesome general hostility to <strong>the</strong> liberal democraticorder, <strong>the</strong>y also have to exhibit what <strong>the</strong> GermanConstitutional Court has called an “actively fighting,aggressive attitude.” 42 Member state governments, itseems reasonable to assume, would always seek toclaim that <strong>the</strong>y are engaged in a legitimate politicalstruggle within <strong>the</strong> parameters of liberal <strong>democracy</strong>,and that <strong>the</strong>y are simply pursuing somewhat differentvalues than o<strong>the</strong>r member states (or that <strong>the</strong>y are infact close to some member states in terms of valuesand simply <strong>the</strong> victim of a partisan or ideologicalcampaign of some o<strong>the</strong>r member states). This42For an extended discussion of <strong>the</strong> dilemmas associated withmilitant <strong>democracy</strong>, see my “Militant Democracy,” in MichelRosenfeld and András Sajó (eds.), The Oxford Handbook ofComparative Constitutional Law (New York: Oxford UP, 2012),1253-69.was clearly Orbán’s strategy, when he explainedto a German newspaper in March 2012 that <strong>the</strong>problem consisted simply of <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> WesternEuropean Left did not like his advocacy of nationalpride, Christianity and family values. 43 In o<strong>the</strong>rwords, this was not about institutions and norms,it was a European-wide Kulturkampf, where oneside was pretending to speak in <strong>the</strong> name of Europeand malign <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side as undemocratic. Thereferences to “values” in Article 7 and in Europeandebates more widely can in fact encourage such areading. After all, one ought to be able to ascertainwhe<strong>the</strong>r law has been broken or not and whe<strong>the</strong>rcommon principles are adhered to. Whe<strong>the</strong>r w<strong>eu</strong>ltimately really “share values” seems a much moresubjective matter to verify. 44 It doesn’t help that <strong>the</strong>post-war understanding of <strong>democracy</strong> I discussedfur<strong>the</strong>r above is not in any way legally codified. Itsinvocation could certainly serve to make a case for<strong>the</strong> use of Article 7, but it is not in any clear sensecontained in Article 7 itself — or in Article 2, for that43 “Viktor Orbán im Gespräch: ‘Es gibt ein verborgenes Europa’,”in Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, March 4, 2012, at http://www.faz.net/aktuell/politik/<strong>eu</strong>ropaeische-union/viktor-orbanim-gespraech-es-gibt-ein-verborgenes-<strong>eu</strong>ropa-11671291.html [last accessed October 1, 2012]. A basic insight of <strong>the</strong>democratization literature is that subnational authoritarianismin a <strong>democracy</strong> is threatened by a nationalization of politicalconflict (see Edward L. Gibson, “Boundary Control:Subnational Authoritarianism in Democratic Countries,” inWorld Politics, vil. 58 [2005], 101-32). At <strong>the</strong> same time, weakerparties to a conflict generally have an interest in “socializing”or, in this case, Europeanizing a conflict — an argument goingall <strong>the</strong> way back to Schattschneider. Hence Orbán‘s calculationmight be that going mano-a-mano with <strong>the</strong> Commission inisolation is in fact a losing proposition, whereas igniting aEuropean Kulturkampf — which reframes <strong>the</strong> conflict as oneof moral and cultural, not legal and political, values — is veryrisky, but could turn out to be a winning strategy (Not leastbecause it calls <strong>the</strong> impartiality of official guardians of <strong>the</strong>treaties into question. After all, <strong>the</strong>y might just be strongholdsof radical, secular European left-wingers).44 For critiques along <strong>the</strong>se lines see also Robert Spaemann,“Europa ist kein Werteverbund,” in Cicero (April 2004) andCarl Schmitt, Die Tyrannei der Werte (Berlin Duncker &Humblot 2011).18<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


A governmentdeterminedto undermine<strong>democracy</strong> and<strong>the</strong> rule of lawmight not bemuch impressedby rulings fromLuxembourg.European norms, as expressed in individual rightsfor European citizens. 48As said above, this is a clever thought. Yet <strong>the</strong>thought is too clever by half in <strong>the</strong> eyes of criticswho think that all member state governmentswould be very reluctant to even come close to<strong>the</strong> possibility of <strong>the</strong> Court empowering itselfsystematically to review <strong>the</strong> rule of law withinmember states. After all, <strong>the</strong>re had been extensivediscussions of involving <strong>the</strong> European Court indeciding on sanctions against member states,when <strong>the</strong> idea of Article 7 was debated in <strong>the</strong> late1990s and early 2000s — and such a role was in <strong>the</strong>end clearly rejected by member states (which, notsurprisingly, sought to make <strong>the</strong> Council <strong>the</strong> centralactor). 49There is also a more fundamental question of howmuch political weight EU citizenship can bear.After all, EU citizenship has not been <strong>the</strong> resultof a political process or, put more dramatically,it has not been <strong>the</strong> outcome of a real struggle forcitizenship rights. Citizenship was granted fromabove and extended by <strong>the</strong> European Court inway that could well be labeled “constitutionalpaternalism.” 50 One also has to wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r48Think of <strong>the</strong> Commission taking Hungary to <strong>the</strong> Courtfor age discrimination, after <strong>the</strong> Hungarian governmentdrastically lowered <strong>the</strong> retirement age for judges. Of course,age discrimination is at issue — but here infringementproceedings are at best a very indirect way of getting at <strong>the</strong> realthreat, a systematic undermining of <strong>the</strong> independence of <strong>the</strong>judiciary, since Fidesz can now staff <strong>the</strong> judiciary with its ownappointees.49Sadurski, “Adding Bite to <strong>the</strong> Bark,” 394.50See also <strong>the</strong> comments on <strong>the</strong> “Heidelberg proposal” byAnna Katharina Mangold, “Rescue package for fundamentalrights,” online available at http://www.verfassungsblog.de/en/rescue-package-for-fundamental-rights-comments-by-annakatharina-mangold/#.UKZVllLSzxsand Michaela Hailbronner,“Rescue package for fundamental rights,” available onlineat http://www.verfassungsblog.de/rescue-package-forfundamental-rights-comments-by-michaela-hailbronner/#.UKZeJlLSzxs. I borrow <strong>the</strong> term “constitutional paternalism”concepts like “<strong>the</strong> substance” of EU citizenship canbe sufficiently (and consensually) specified: <strong>the</strong>vagueness of value talk might just be replicated onano<strong>the</strong>r level.Then <strong>the</strong>re is also <strong>the</strong> banal fact that, whe<strong>the</strong>r ona national or European level, judicial proceedingstake a fair amount of time (and <strong>the</strong> related concernthat, like <strong>the</strong> ECHR, <strong>the</strong> Court might soon beoverwhelmed with case load). And realisticallyspeaking, a government determined to undermine<strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule of law might not be muchimpressed by rulings from Luxembourg anyway.Finally, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> worry that a legal response toan essentially political challenge will not do; thatone should not rely on legalism — single citizensenforcing European norms through court cases —instead of invoking a common, public Europeanpurpose; that at issue are whole political systems(and, in Montesqui<strong>eu</strong>’s language, <strong>the</strong>ir “spirit”), notjust isolated individual rights; that we need moreEuropolitics instead of yet more Eurolegalism. 51The Politicization of Europe, <strong>the</strong>Europeanization of PoliticsBut <strong>the</strong>n what would a properly political responselook like? It has often been said that <strong>the</strong> <strong>eu</strong>ro crisishas brought about <strong>the</strong> politicization of Europe,and that it is now time for <strong>the</strong> Europeanization ofpolitics. People across <strong>the</strong> continent have woken upto <strong>the</strong> fact that what happens elsewhere in Europehas a direct impact on <strong>the</strong>ir lives, Brussels is notjust some technocratic machine that producesdecisions best for all. What we need is a Europeanparty system, so that different options for Europe’sfrom Paulina Ochoa Espejo, The Time of <strong>the</strong> PopularSovereignty: Process and <strong>the</strong> Democratic State (University Park,PA: Penn State University Press, 2011)51 R. Daniel Kelemen, Eurolegalism: The Transformation of Lawand Regulation in <strong>the</strong> European Union (Cambridge, Mass.:Harvard UP, 2011)20<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


6Some Modest ProposalsHow could <strong>the</strong> EU deal with challenges toliberal <strong>democracy</strong> more effectively whilealso not overstepping <strong>the</strong> limits of itslegitimacy? Two temptations ought to be resistedin answering this question. On one hand, it willdo no good to let <strong>the</strong> institutional imagination runwild, so to speak; on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, it would alsobe a mistake to think entirely within what one takesto be <strong>the</strong> constraints of political feasibility at anygiven moment in time. A plausible answer here isnei<strong>the</strong>r one that gets highest marks in ingeniousinstitutional engineering nor one that has <strong>the</strong>greatest chance of being acceptable to memberstates. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, we ought to ask again, with a bitmore distance, what <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical and practicalchallenges are precisely. A plausible answer is onethat best addresses <strong>the</strong>se challenges.The <strong>the</strong>oretical challenge, I would submit, is tolocate an agent of credible legal-political judgment.Technical-legal judgment in and of itself (supposingone could successfully isolate such a thing), isinsufficient, for reasons mentioned a number oftimes in this paper. We are dealing with challengesthat will require some understanding of context,some sense of proportion, and, not least, somemeaningful capacity for comparison of whatis actually happening within different politicalsystems (as opposed to <strong>the</strong> claims about what ishappening within <strong>the</strong>se systems by local elites). 55A simple check-list, as so often used in <strong>the</strong> EUaccession process (“Do <strong>the</strong> judiciary’s offices havecomputers? Check.”), will not do. Somebody needsto see and understand <strong>the</strong> whole picture. 56 On <strong>the</strong>55Cf. Ronald Beiner, Political Judgment (New York: Routledge,2010).56See also Kalypso Nicolaïdis and Rachel Kleinfeld, RethinkingEurope’s “Rule of Law” and Enlargement Agenda: TheFundamental Dilemma, Sigma Paper 49/2012, and <strong>the</strong> acerbic,but entirely justified comment by Alina Mungiu-Pippidi on<strong>the</strong> Commission’s elaborate monitoring procedures dependingupon an “overall ‘prescription mechanism’ according towhich countries are evaluated by <strong>the</strong> number of measuresadopted from detailed Commission ‘roadmaps’ ra<strong>the</strong>r thano<strong>the</strong>r hand, judgments cannot be — and certainlycannot be seen as — partisan.On a practical level, a clear challenge has beenthat authority in <strong>the</strong> EU remains highly diffuseand fragmented; <strong>the</strong>re is not much by way of aconsciousness of common European political space(let alone a shared public sphere where substantivearguments could be debated seriously acrossborders); it can be hard to get and direct somethinglike common political attention. More particularly,<strong>the</strong>re is as of now no clear legal or political actorcharged with pushing a red button first, so tospeak, in order to alarm o<strong>the</strong>rs about a potentialdeterioration in <strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule of law<strong>inside</strong> a member state.What follows, <strong>the</strong>n, from framing <strong>the</strong> problemthis way? First of all, it seems to me that Article7 ought to be left in place, but it also ought tobe extended. There might arise situations where<strong>democracy</strong> is not just slowly undermined orpartially dismantled, but where <strong>the</strong> entire edificeof democratic institutions is blown up or comescrashing down, so to speak (think of a militarycoup). However, in such an extreme case, <strong>the</strong> Unionought actually to have <strong>the</strong> option of expelling amember state completely. As is well known, under<strong>the</strong> Treaty on European Union as it exists now,states may decide to leave voluntarily — but <strong>the</strong>reis no legal mechanism for actually removing acountry from <strong>the</strong> Union (and even voluntary exitwould in all likelihood be a very drawn-out affair).True, <strong>the</strong>se all might seem remote scenarios. Butespecially those who insist on <strong>the</strong> symbolic valueby indicators measuring real changes on <strong>the</strong> ground. This isas if a doctor evaluated a patient by <strong>the</strong> number of prescribedmedicines taken, ra<strong>the</strong>r than by measuring <strong>the</strong> patient’s feverto check on <strong>the</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> medicines. Both <strong>the</strong> adequacy and<strong>the</strong> impact of such measures in each country were presumedra<strong>the</strong>r than demonstrated.” See Alina Mungiu-Pippidi, “EUAccession is no ‘End of History’,” in Journal of Democracy, vol.18 (2007), 8-16; here 15.A simple checklist,as so oftenused in <strong>the</strong> EUaccession process,will not do.Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 23


The Commissionmight begin tomonitor <strong>the</strong> stateof <strong>the</strong> rule of lawin all memberstates consistentlyand continuously.of something like Article 7 — by which <strong>the</strong>y mightactually mean something not just symbolic at all,namely its importance as a form of deterrence —ought to be sympa<strong>the</strong>tic to including <strong>the</strong> option ofcomplete removal. 57A difficulty with <strong>the</strong> existing harsher sanctionsenvisaged in Article 7 is, of course, that it requiresagreement among all member states (and even <strong>the</strong>preventive option still requires four-fifths of <strong>the</strong>members of <strong>the</strong> Council). So short of extremelydramatic deteriorations in <strong>the</strong> rule of law and<strong>democracy</strong>, <strong>the</strong> EU ought to have tools availablethat exert pressure on member states, but whoseemployment does not require a lengthy process offinding agreement among all or a large majorityof member states. One suggestion would be that<strong>the</strong> Commission begins to monitor <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong>rule of law (essentially, <strong>the</strong> quality of <strong>the</strong> systemsof justice) in all member states consistently andcontinuously. 58 It is important that such monitoringbe done uniformly in all countries. While <strong>the</strong>reare of course precedents in singling out individualcountries for surveillance (Romania, Bulgaria),it simply sends <strong>the</strong> wrong signal to target onlysome countries, if <strong>the</strong>re is no evidence for singling<strong>the</strong>m out. Such a “universalist” surveillance, aninstitutionalized blanket suspicion, if you wish, alsoeffectively counters <strong>the</strong> rhetoric — amply used bymember of <strong>the</strong> current Hungarian governing party— that some Europeans are treated as “second-class57It is not that <strong>the</strong> possibility of complete exclusion has neverbeen discussed in <strong>the</strong> preparation of various treaty revisions.But <strong>the</strong> option of exclusion has been rejected because, as<strong>the</strong> report of a Reflection Group appointed by <strong>the</strong> EuropeanCouncil put it, “this would call into question <strong>the</strong> irreversibilityof membership [in] <strong>the</strong> Union.” See Sadurski, “Adding Bite to<strong>the</strong> Bark,” 390.58A suggestion that has in fact been made by CommissionerViviane Reding recently. See “EU keen to rank justice inmember states, in EU Observer, September 13, 2012, at http://<strong>eu</strong>observer.com/justice/117535 [last accessed September 27,2012]. O<strong>the</strong>rs have launched <strong>the</strong> idea of an annual democraticaudit of <strong>the</strong> member states (and perhaps of <strong>the</strong> EU as a whole).citizens,” or that <strong>the</strong>re is a two-tier Europe, wheresome are trusted and some are not.However, one might question whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>Commission can really be what I called above acredible agent of legal-political judgment. To besure, <strong>the</strong> Commission is acquiring new powers insupervising and potentially changing <strong>the</strong> budgetsof <strong>eu</strong>rozone member states. But many — possiblyall — proposals to increase <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of <strong>the</strong>Commission (seen as a necessary complementto such newly acquired authority) contain <strong>the</strong>suggestion essentially to politicize <strong>the</strong> Commission:ideas to elect <strong>the</strong> president directly or to make<strong>the</strong> Commissioners into a kind of politicallyuniform cabinet government all would render <strong>the</strong>body more partisan — on purpose. 59 And suchpartisanship makes <strong>the</strong> Commission much lesscredible as an agent of legal-political judgment. 60An alternative to <strong>the</strong> Commission undertakingsuch a task itself would be to delegate it to ano<strong>the</strong>rinstitution, such as <strong>the</strong> Fundamental RightsAgency, 61 or perhaps an entirely new institution59 Not that <strong>the</strong> Commission today is truly “apolitical” — but<strong>the</strong> fiction that Commissioners upon taking office lose <strong>the</strong>irparty-political identities does have some disciplining effect,I would submit. In <strong>the</strong> scenario envisaged by proponents of<strong>the</strong> Commission as de facto (and possibly even in name) aEuropean government, <strong>the</strong> whole point is that <strong>the</strong> body wouldbe — and ought to be — visibly partisan.60 There is also <strong>the</strong> less obvious point that every harsh criticismof a newer member state can be seen to fall back on <strong>the</strong>Commission itself — did <strong>the</strong>y not do <strong>the</strong> proper work beforerecommending admission? See in this context also TomGallagher, Romania and <strong>the</strong> European Union: How <strong>the</strong> WeakVanquished <strong>the</strong> Strong (Manchester: Manchester UP, 2009).61 As suggested by <strong>the</strong> liberal MEP Alexander Graf Lambsdorffin his piece “Zwei Premiers führen die EU an der Nase herum,”available online at http://www.cicero.de/weltbuehne/ungarnrumaenien-ponta-orban-zwei-premiers-fuehren-die-<strong>eu</strong>-dernase-herum/52076.As Lambsdorff rightly points out, <strong>the</strong>mandate of <strong>the</strong> FRA would have to be significantly amended— as, one might add, would have to be its culture. At least for<strong>the</strong> moment it has gained a reputation of being over-sensitiveto member state executives.24<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


that could credibly act as a guardian of whatone might call Europe’s acquis normatif. 62 Onecould think of something like a “CopenhagenCommission” (as a reminder of <strong>the</strong> “Copenhagencriteria” 63 ), analogous to <strong>the</strong> Venice Commission,though with an even stronger emphasis on<strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> overall quality of a politicalsystem — an agency, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, with amandate to offer comprehensive and consistentpolitical judgments. 64 The hope is also that suchan agency can become sufficiently visible so as toeffectively raise an alarm across whatever <strong>the</strong>re isby way of a common European political space.However, <strong>the</strong> real question is of course: and <strong>the</strong>nwhat? What if a country seems systematically toundermine <strong>the</strong> rule of law and restrict <strong>democracy</strong>?My suggestion is that an agency ought to beempowered to investigate <strong>the</strong> situation and <strong>the</strong>ntrigger a mechanism that sends a clear signal(not just words), but far short of <strong>the</strong> measuresenvisaged in Article 7. Following <strong>the</strong> advice of<strong>the</strong> Copenhagen Commission, <strong>the</strong> EuropeanCommission should be required to cut funds forstate capital expenditure, for instance, or imposesignificant fines. 65 Especially <strong>the</strong> former might62One might be tempted to think of decentralizing such anagency: having ombudsmen or something analogous todiscrimination agencies in each country — <strong>the</strong> obviouscounter-argument being that such actors and agencies wouldlikely be subject to national capture.63The Copenhagen criteria can be found here: http://<strong>eu</strong>ropa.<strong>eu</strong>/legislation_summaries/glossary/accession_criteria_copenhague_de.htm64I am indebted to Rui Tavares for discussions on this point.65A major problem here is of course that such measures tendto punish populations, and not governments. The presentHungarian government has already made it clear that fineswill be passed on to all citizens, clearly hoping that such“<strong>democracy</strong> taxes” will increase resentment vis-à-vis Brussels.This danger is also acute if one thinks of cutting EU cohesionfunds — such cuts would clearly hurt those who are alreadypoor. Less obviously, countries suffering from deficiencies in<strong>the</strong> rule of law already cannot absorb much of such funds — sothis kind of sanction might not hurt as much as one mightprove to be effective, if <strong>the</strong> EU budget as suchwere to be significantly increased in future years(a measure also included in many proposals totackle <strong>the</strong> <strong>eu</strong>ro crisis). 66 Moreover, cuts of EUspecificfunds would also reinforce <strong>the</strong> messagethat a country undermining <strong>the</strong> rule of law is doingsomething that concerns <strong>the</strong> Union as a whole— and that <strong>the</strong> response is a genuinely Europeanone. Surely, <strong>the</strong> Haider Affair taught <strong>the</strong> lessonthat sanctions should not give <strong>the</strong> impression thatindividual nation-states are lining up against —or, put more drastically, ganging up on — an EUmember state. Action of this kind — whe<strong>the</strong>r by<strong>the</strong> European Commission or <strong>the</strong> CopenhagenCommission as envisaged here — would makeit impossible for a country to try to divide o<strong>the</strong>rmember states, or play <strong>the</strong>m off against eacho<strong>the</strong>r, or peel off more powerful countries from acoalition of <strong>the</strong> sanctioning, so to speak.At <strong>the</strong> same time, all <strong>the</strong> existing tools remain at<strong>the</strong> disposal of <strong>the</strong> relevant actors. Member statescould vote on Article 7; <strong>the</strong> Commission could takea member state to <strong>the</strong> European Court of Justice;<strong>the</strong> Court can try to protect <strong>the</strong> substance of EUcitizenship; and politicians can have a serious wordwith one of <strong>the</strong>ir peers in ano<strong>the</strong>r member state,if <strong>the</strong>y feel that <strong>the</strong> State in question is leaving <strong>the</strong>broad European road of liberal <strong>democracy</strong>.think by just looking at <strong>the</strong> gross numbers. I am particularlyindebted to Kim Scheppele for discussions on this point.66 The recent final report of <strong>the</strong> “Future of Europe Group” alsodemanded a “new, lighter mechanism” for <strong>the</strong> Commission,but did not propose to empower <strong>the</strong> Commission itself toimpose sanctions. It claimed, “The possibilities to ensurerespect for <strong>the</strong> fundamental values under Article 2 of <strong>the</strong> TEUshould be streng<strong>the</strong>ned. To this end, a new, light mechanismshould be introduced enabling <strong>the</strong> Commission to drawup a report in <strong>the</strong> case of concrete evidence of violationsof <strong>the</strong> values under Article 2 of <strong>the</strong> TEU and to makerecommendations or refer <strong>the</strong> matter to <strong>the</strong> Council. It shouldonly be triggered by an apparent breach in a member state offundamental values or principles, like <strong>the</strong> rule of law.”The hope is thatsuch a <strong>democracy</strong><strong>safeguarding</strong>agency canbecomesufficiently visibleso as effectivelyto raise an alarmacross whatever<strong>the</strong>re is by wayof a commonEuropeanpolitical space.Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 25


Now, none of <strong>the</strong> above means that some of <strong>the</strong>pluralist principles and practices in <strong>the</strong> EU havebecome irrelevant (or were a fiction all along). All<strong>the</strong> relevant actors can also retain something likea margin of appreciation to account for nationalidiosyncrasies. They can in <strong>the</strong> first instancesuggest to an offending government to takeseriously <strong>the</strong> idea of informal peer review and tryto negotiate disputes away, etc. However, what <strong>the</strong>above also suggests is that it cannot be pluralismall <strong>the</strong> way down. As one political community, <strong>the</strong>EU has outer and inner boundaries. Where liberal<strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule of law cease to function,<strong>the</strong>re Europe ends.26<strong>Transatlantic</strong> <strong>Academy</strong>


6Concluding ThoughtsAs Wojciech Sadurski has pointed out,sanctions against member states and,ultimately, <strong>the</strong> possibility of excludinga member state from <strong>the</strong> Union touch on <strong>the</strong>question of <strong>the</strong> finality of <strong>the</strong> EU and <strong>the</strong> questionwhe<strong>the</strong>r it is in fact a complete and coherentlegal order. 67 They also — yet again — force us toconfront <strong>the</strong> issue of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is such a thingas final authority at all in <strong>the</strong> Union, and, in an evenmore Schmittian vein, <strong>the</strong> question of whe<strong>the</strong>r anongoing “project” whose institutions translate allconflicts into matters of economics or ethics canultimately even be called “political.” 6867Sadurski, “Adding Bite to <strong>the</strong> Bark.”68Questions that are not exclusive to <strong>the</strong> EU, of course:see Daniel Halberstam, “Constitutional Heterarchy: TheCentrality of Conflict in <strong>the</strong> European Union and <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates,” in Jeffrey L. Dunoff and Joel P. Trachtman (eds.),Ruling <strong>the</strong> World? Constitutionalism, International Law, andGlobal Governance (New York: Cambridge UP, 2009), 326-55.Schmitt’s thought on liberalism translating all conflicts intoquestions of ethics (which can reasonably be discussed andadjudicated by courts) or questions of economics (which canbe subject to bargaining and negotiations among organizedinterests) can be found in Carl Schmitt, The Concept of <strong>the</strong>This essay has not even begun to engage with <strong>the</strong>selarger questions. It has, however, made <strong>the</strong> casefor <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of EU sanctions from <strong>the</strong> pointof view of democratic <strong>the</strong>ory. It has also arguedthat — as of now — <strong>the</strong> EU has no coherent set oflegal and policy instruments to address challengesto <strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule of law within memberstates. Given how much member states haveresisted <strong>the</strong> idea of empowering <strong>the</strong> Commissionor <strong>the</strong> Court to form comprehensive judgmentson <strong>the</strong> quality of <strong>democracy</strong> and <strong>the</strong> rule of lawwithin member states, it is of course by no meansclear whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> proposals suggested in this essayhave any chance of being adopted. But arguably, in<strong>the</strong> wake of Brussels’ conflicts with Budapest andBucharest, <strong>the</strong>re is now at least a consciousness ofwhat <strong>the</strong>se challenges might mean, in <strong>the</strong> way that<strong>the</strong>re wasn’t during <strong>the</strong> times when everybody — orso it seemed — was fond of telling a fairy tale thatended with accession, and political happiness everafter.Political, trans. George Schwab (Chicago: The University ofChicago Press, 2007).Safeguarding Democracy <strong>inside</strong> <strong>the</strong> EU 27


1744 R Street NWWashington, DC 20009T: 1 202 745 3886F: 1 202 265 1662E: Info@transatlanticacademy.orgwww.transatlanticacademy.org

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!