12.07.2015 Views

Normalising-the-Unthinkable-Report

Normalising-the-Unthinkable-Report

Normalising-the-Unthinkable-Report

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

5.15. It would be a mistake to minimise <strong>the</strong> influence of this teaching of St Thomas. In relation to animals,Thomistic formulations have held sway for subsequent centuries of Christian thought. His idea that animals haveno mental life and do not act by conscious will, but by ‘nature’ or ‘instinct’, has been persuasive right up to <strong>the</strong>present day.5.16. St Thomas’s negative <strong>the</strong>ology undoubtedly contributed to a dismissive Christian view of animal welfare.Historic Catholic moral textbooks deny that humans have any direct duties to animals. The Dictionary of MoralTheology, written as recently as 1962, explains why:Zoophilists [animal lovers] often lose sight of <strong>the</strong> end for which animals, irrational creatures, werecreated by God, viz., <strong>the</strong> service and use of man. In fact, Catholic moral doctrine teaches thatanimals have no rights on <strong>the</strong> part of man. (Palazzini, 1962, p. 73)5.17. Notice how animals are deemed to have no independent worth o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>ir service to human beings.Their end (telos) is understood entirely in instrumentalist terms. It should not come as a surprise <strong>the</strong>n to discoverthat Pope Pius IX, in <strong>the</strong> nineteenth century, reputedly forbade <strong>the</strong> opening of an animal protection office in Romeon <strong>the</strong> grounds that humans had duties to o<strong>the</strong>r humans but none to animals (Gaffney, 1986, pp. 149, 159–160).5.18. Although <strong>the</strong> Christian tradition is very diverse and comprises many traditions that are favourable to animals,<strong>the</strong> dominant voices in Western Christianity have laid great emphasis upon instrumentalism. But it is not onlywithin <strong>the</strong> Christian tradition that instrumentalist attitudes have persisted. Immanuel Kant, for example, held that‘inasmuch as crops (for example, potatoes) and domestic animals are products of human labour, at least as faras <strong>the</strong>ir quantity is concerned, we can say that <strong>the</strong>y may be used, consumed, or destroyed [killed]’ (Kant, 1965, pp.345–346). Kant divides <strong>the</strong> moral universe into persons and things: persons are rational beings, and things arenon-rational beings. Morality is, on this view, a reciprocal relationship among persons; thus, we have no moralobligations to animals, understood as non-rational beings. Kant’s fundamental moral principle – <strong>the</strong> categoricalimperative – is that persons are to be treated as ends in <strong>the</strong>mselves, not merely as means to an end. Thisprinciple does not apply to our interactions with animals because <strong>the</strong>y are things, or mere means to human ends.5.19. It does not follow, however, that we may not hold some indirect duties to animals insofar as some humaninterest is involved. Aquinas held that cruelty to animals may be wrong if it dehumanises <strong>the</strong> perpetrator (Aquinas,1945, pp. 220–224). Kant judged likewise: ‘Our duties towards animals are merely indirect duties towardshumanity’. He provided an example of how it would not be wrong to kill a dog who could no longer provideservice, but <strong>the</strong> owner must be careful not to stifle humane feelings since ‘he who is cruel to animals becomeshard also in his dealings with men’ (Kant, 1963, pp. 239–241). Some contemporary Kantians, such as ChristineKorsgaard, have attempted to include animals in <strong>the</strong> moral universe by considering what animals would consentto if <strong>the</strong>y could consent (Korsgaard, 2011).5.20. Again, <strong>the</strong> obvious weakness in instrumentalism is its circularity. We know that animals are slaves because<strong>the</strong>y are enslaveable. As such, <strong>the</strong> argument seems to be little more than <strong>the</strong> working out of <strong>the</strong> notion thatmight is right – that power is its own justification. Both anthropocentrism and instrumentalism reject <strong>the</strong> idea thatwe have direct duties to animals and that we should consider <strong>the</strong>ir interests independently of human wants orneeds. Moreover, it is not obvious (as it was for Aristotle and Aquinas) that <strong>the</strong>re exists (or should exist) a rationalhierarchy in <strong>the</strong> world such that <strong>the</strong> rationally ‘inferior’ should exist for or serve <strong>the</strong> ‘superior’. At <strong>the</strong> very least,<strong>the</strong> contrary implication should be enjoined – namely, that <strong>the</strong> species blessed with greater rationality shoulddemonstrate that ‘superiority’ (if such <strong>the</strong>re be) by a particular regard for <strong>the</strong> weak of all species. As AlexanderPope argued, ‘I cannot think it is extravagant to imagine that mankind are no less, in proportion, accountable for<strong>the</strong> ill use of <strong>the</strong>ir dominion over creatures of <strong>the</strong> lower rank of beings, than for <strong>the</strong> exercise of tyranny over <strong>the</strong>irown species’ (Pope, 1950, pp. 159–165).The challenge to dualism5.21. By ‘dualism’ in this context, we mean <strong>the</strong> tendency to distinguish and separate humans from o<strong>the</strong>r animalsin terms of a binary ‘us’ and ‘<strong>the</strong>m’. In dualistic perspectives, animals are invariably judged inferior to humans.A <strong>Report</strong> by <strong>the</strong> Working Group of <strong>the</strong> Oxford Centre for Animal Ethics25

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!