12.07.2015 Views

Normalising-the-Unthinkable-Report

Normalising-the-Unthinkable-Report

Normalising-the-Unthinkable-Report

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>the</strong> moral realm to include obligations to animals. Working in <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian virtue ethics tradition, RosalindHursthouse rejects <strong>the</strong> concept of moral status and argues that a well-developed account of <strong>the</strong> virtues wouldrequire compassion for animals (Hursthouse, 2011).Grounds for extending moral solicitude5.29. In contrast to <strong>the</strong>se dominant tendencies in Western thought, <strong>the</strong> consensus among ethicists has movedtowards embracing three positions.The first is that animals have worth in <strong>the</strong>mselves, what may be termed ‘inherent’ or ‘intrinsic’value. Sentient beings, or sentients, are not just things, objects, machines, or tools; <strong>the</strong>y have<strong>the</strong>ir own interior life that deserves respect. This view extends worth to sentients as individualsnot just as collectivities or as part of a community.The second position is that, given <strong>the</strong> conceding of sentience, <strong>the</strong>re can be no rational groundsfor not taking animals’ sentience into account or for excluding individual animals from <strong>the</strong> samebasic moral consideration that we extend to individual human beings.The third position is that it follows that causing harm to individual sentients (except when it is for<strong>the</strong>ir own good – for example, in a veterinary operation) requires strong moral justification. Somewould argue that such acts of harming innocent (i.e., morally blameless) sentients is wrong initself, and such acts are usually termed ‘intrinsically wrong’ or ‘intrinsically evil’.5.30. There are a number of considerations that provide grounds for granting animals moral solicitude: 3a. Animals cannot give or withhold <strong>the</strong>ir consent.5.31. It is commonly accepted that informed consent is required in advance from an individual when anyonewishes to override <strong>the</strong> legitimate interests of that individual. The absence of this factor requires, at <strong>the</strong> very least,that we exercise extraordinary care and thoughtfulness. The very (obvious) fact that animals cannot agree to <strong>the</strong>purposes to which <strong>the</strong>y are put increases our responsibility.5.32. It may be claimed that although animals cannot talk consensually and non-consensually, <strong>the</strong>ir actions maymanifest consent and <strong>the</strong> lack <strong>the</strong>reof. So, for example, it may be presumed that an animal who fights (and howlsperhaps) to stay out of a kennel is registering her will against being placed in a kennel. So maybe an animal canbehaviourally, and even vocally, manifest his or her lack of consent.5.33. Although we cannot deny <strong>the</strong> importance of <strong>the</strong>se behavioural indications, <strong>the</strong>y obviously fall short ofwhat humans mean when <strong>the</strong>y speak of voluntary, informed consent. Consent makes sense, logically, only ifan individual is presented with alternative possibilities and has both <strong>the</strong> knowledge of what <strong>the</strong>se possibilitiesrepresent and <strong>the</strong> freedom to choose one of <strong>the</strong>m – and to do so without coercion. When an animal cries orhowls or reels in pain, she registers displeasure at her predicament, but registering displeasure (or pleasure)is not voluntary consent. In short, we can sometimes know how animals feel (largely negatively) about <strong>the</strong>irstate (and we do well to be sensitive to such indications). In that sense we do often (rightly or wrongly) presumeconsent, but presumed consent is still a long way from voluntary, verbal consent as we know it between humanbeings.5.34. It is pertinent to look at how <strong>the</strong> issue of consent has evolved historically in relation to <strong>the</strong> ethics of researchinvolving human subjects. The 1931 German Guidelines on Human Experimentation, which preceded <strong>the</strong>Nuremberg Code, were claimed to be <strong>the</strong> first of <strong>the</strong>ir kind in providing protection for human subjects of scientificresearch, even though <strong>the</strong> 1900 Berlin Code briefly preceded <strong>the</strong>m (Ghooi, 2011). Of note are <strong>the</strong> followingparagraphs:3The following rationale is adapted from Linzey (2009b).A <strong>Report</strong> by <strong>the</strong> Working Group of <strong>the</strong> Oxford Centre for Animal Ethics27

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!