01.12.2012 Views

csp-frege-revolu

csp-frege-revolu

csp-frege-revolu

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? 7<br />

work was not just a continuation of the work of Boole, Peirce, and Schröder Peano (see [Anellis 2004-2005; 2011]),<br />

for example, such of regarded Russell’s work as “On Cardinal Numbers” [Whitehead 1902], §III of which was actually<br />

written solely by Russell) and “Sur la logique des relations des applications à la théorie des séries” [Russell 1901a]<br />

as “filling a gap” between his own work and that of Boole, Peirce, and Schröder (see [Kennedy 1975, 206]). 7 Through<br />

the fin de siècle, logicians for the most part understood Russell to be transcribing into Peanesque notation Cantorian<br />

set theory and the logic of relations of Peirce and Schröder.<br />

Bertrand Russell, in addition to the strong and well-known influence which Giuseppe Peano had on him, was a<br />

staunch advocate, and indeed one of the earliest promoters, of the conception of a “Fregean <strong>revolu</strong>tion” in logic, although<br />

he himself never explicitly employed the term itself. Nevertheless, we have such pronouncements, for example<br />

in his manuscript on “Recent Italian Work on the Foundations of Mathematics” of 1901 in which he contrasts the conception<br />

of the algebraic logicians with that of Hugh MacColl (1837–1909) and Gottlob Frege, by writing that (see<br />

[Russell 1993, 353]):<br />

Formal Logic is concerned in the main and primarily with the relation of implication between propositions.<br />

What this relation is, it is impossible to define: in all accounts of Peano’s logic it appears as one of his<br />

indefinables. It has been one of the bad effects of the analogy with ordinary Algebra that most formal logicians<br />

(with the exception of Frege and Mr. MacColl) have shown more interest in logical equations than in implication.<br />

This view was echoed by van Heijenoort, whose chief complaint [van Heijenoort 1967a, vi] regarding the algebraic<br />

logicians was that they “tried to copy mathematics too closely, and often artifically”.<br />

§2. The characteristics of modern mathematical logic as defined and delimited by the “Fregean <strong>revolu</strong>tion”. In<br />

elaborating the distinguishing characteristics of mathematical logic and, equivalently, enumerating the innovations<br />

which Frege—allegedly—wrought to create mathematical logic, van Heijenoort (in “Logic as Calculus and Logic as<br />

Language” [van Heijenoort 1976b, 324]) listed:<br />

1. a propositional calculus with a truth-functional definition of connectives, especially the conditional;<br />

2. decomposition of propositions into function and argument instead of into subject and predicate;<br />

3. a quantification theory, based on a system of axioms and inference rules; and<br />

4. definitions of infinite sequence and natural number in terms of logical notions (i.e. the logicization of mathematics).<br />

In addition, Frege, according to van Heijenoort and adherents of the historiographical conception of a “Fregean <strong>revolu</strong>tion”:<br />

5. presented and clarified the concept of formal system; and<br />

6. made possible, and gave, a use of logic for philosophical investigations (especially for philosophy of language).<br />

Moreover, in the undated, unpublished manuscript notes “On the Frege-Russell Definition of Number”, 8 van<br />

Heijenoort claimed that Bertrand Russell was the first to introduce a means for<br />

7. separating singular propositions, such as “Socrates is mortal” from universal propositions such as “All<br />

Greeks are mortal.”<br />

among the “Fregeans”.<br />

In the “Historical Note” to the fourth edition of his Methods of Logic [Quine 1982, 89] Willard Van Orman<br />

Quine (1908–2000) asserts that “Frege, in 1879, was the first to axiomatize the logic of truth functions and to state<br />

formal rules of inference.” Similar remarks are scattered throughout his textbook. He does, however, give Pierce credit<br />

[Quine 1982, 39]—albeit along with Frege and Schröder—for the “pattern of reasoning that the truth table tabulates.”<br />

Defenders of the concept of a Fregean <strong>revolu</strong>tion” count Peirce and Schröder among the “Booleans” rather than<br />

among the “Fregeans”. Yet, judging the “Fregean <strong>revolu</strong>tion” by the (seven) supposedly defining characteristics of<br />

modern mathematical logic, we should include Peirce as one of its foremost participants, if not one of its initiators and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!