13.07.2015 Views

Political Corruption in America: A Search for Definitions ... - See also

Political Corruption in America: A Search for Definitions ... - See also

Political Corruption in America: A Search for Definitions ... - See also

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong>: A <strong>Search</strong> <strong>for</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>itions and a Theory, or If <strong>Political</strong><strong>Corruption</strong> Is <strong>in</strong> the Ma<strong>in</strong>stream of <strong>America</strong>n Politics Why Is it Not <strong>in</strong> the Ma<strong>in</strong>stream of<strong>America</strong>n Politics Research?Author(s): John G. Peters and Susan WelchSource: The <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review, Vol. 72, No. 3 (Sep., 1978), pp. 974-984Published by: <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1955115 .Accessed: 19/12/2010 19:33Your use of the JSTOR archive <strong>in</strong>dicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/<strong>in</strong>fo/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, <strong>in</strong> part, that unlessyou have obta<strong>in</strong>ed prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and youmay use content <strong>in</strong> the JSTOR archive only <strong>for</strong> your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact the publisher regard<strong>in</strong>g any further use of this work. Publisher contact <strong>in</strong><strong>for</strong>mation may be obta<strong>in</strong>ed at .http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa. .Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must conta<strong>in</strong> the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or pr<strong>in</strong>tedpage of such transmission.JSTOR is a not-<strong>for</strong>-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent <strong>in</strong> a trusted digital archive. We use <strong>in</strong><strong>for</strong>mation technology and tools to <strong>in</strong>crease productivity and facilitate new <strong>for</strong>msof scholarship. For more <strong>in</strong><strong>for</strong>mation about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.<strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Association is collaborat<strong>in</strong>g with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toThe <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review.http://www.jstor.org


<strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong>:A <strong>Search</strong> <strong>for</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>itions and a Theory, orIf <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> Is <strong>in</strong> the Ma<strong>in</strong>stream of <strong>America</strong>n PoliticsWhy Is It Not <strong>in</strong> the Ma<strong>in</strong>stream of <strong>America</strong>n Politics Research?*JOHN G. PETERSSUSAN WELCHUniversity of Nebraska, L<strong>in</strong>colnLack of a clear def<strong>in</strong>ition of political corruption has limited its systematic study by analysts of<strong>America</strong>n politics. This article offers a conceptual framework with which to view corruption. Acorrupt act is categorized by its four components: the donor, the favor, the public official and thepayoff. For each component, propositions about perceived corrupt and noncorrupt elements canbe <strong>for</strong>mulated and tested. The usefulness of this scheme <strong>in</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g attitudes about corruption isdemonstrated with data from state legislators. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the article suggests some future researchpossibilities us<strong>in</strong>g this scheme to compare elites and public or other group<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> the politicalsystem.Though corruption has been an everpresentpart of <strong>America</strong>n political life (cf. Tooqueville,1861), analysts of <strong>America</strong>n politics have notstudied it systematically (<strong>for</strong> exceptions, seeGreenste<strong>in</strong>, 1964; Gard<strong>in</strong>er, 1970; Wolf<strong>in</strong>ger,1972). This paper offers a conceptual schemewhich circumvents def<strong>in</strong>itional problems thathave posed such a roadblock to the systematicstudy of corruption. We <strong>also</strong> provide someattitud<strong>in</strong>al data about corrupt acts gatheredfrom state senators across the U.S. and showhow our scheme contributes to the analysis ofthis data. F<strong>in</strong>ally, some reasonable future researchdirections <strong>for</strong> the study of corruptionare briefly discussed.Def<strong>in</strong>itions of <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong>The attention devoted to a serious exam<strong>in</strong>ationof corruption <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong> occurs largely atthose times when particularly venal acts havebeen exposed. Thus, the post-Watergate periodhas brought with it a renewed <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> thestudy of political corruption, especially amongpolitical scientists (cf. Rundquist et al., 1977;Scoble, 1973; Gard<strong>in</strong>er 1970, Berg et al.,1976). In all of these studies it becomesimmediately apparent that no matter what*The authors would like to thank Barry S. Rundquist,University of Ill<strong>in</strong>ois-Urbana, and Alan Booth,University of Nebraska-L<strong>in</strong>coln <strong>for</strong> their helpful comments.This project was supported by a grant from theUniversity of Nebraska Research Council.974aspect of <strong>America</strong>n politics is exam<strong>in</strong>ed, thesystematic study of corruption is hampered bythe lack of an adequate def<strong>in</strong>ition. What maybe "corrupt" to one citizen, scholar, or publicofficial is "just politics" to another, or "<strong>in</strong>discretion"to a third. Several def<strong>in</strong>itions ofpolitical corruption have been proposed andg<strong>See</strong>rallyf w be tsuiftd accord<strong>in</strong>g to *wreecriteria: def<strong>in</strong>itions based on legality, def<strong>in</strong>itionsbased on the public <strong>in</strong>terest, and def<strong>in</strong>itionsbased on public op<strong>in</strong>ion (Scott, 1972).The def<strong>in</strong>ition of political corruption basedon legalistic criteria assumes that political behavioris corrupt when it violates some <strong>for</strong>malstandard or rule of behavior set down by apolitical system <strong>for</strong> its public officials. Perhapsthe clearest statement of this def<strong>in</strong>ition hasbeen given by J. S. Nye when he stated that apolitical act is corrupt when it "deviates fromthe <strong>for</strong>mal duties of a public role (elective orappo<strong>in</strong>tive) because of private-regard<strong>in</strong>g (personal,close family, private clique) wealth orstatus ga<strong>in</strong>s: or violates rules aga<strong>in</strong>st the exerciseof certa<strong>in</strong> types of private-regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence"(Nye, 1967, p. 416). While such adef<strong>in</strong>ition of corruption is useful to the researcher<strong>in</strong> that it is generally clear-cut and canbe operationalized, when the behavior <strong>in</strong> questionallegedly deviates from a legal norm orstandard which is not tied to a specific statuteor court rul<strong>in</strong>g, this def<strong>in</strong>ition of politicalcorruption becomes less useful as the <strong>for</strong>malduties of office or the appropriate rules of<strong>in</strong>fluence become ambiguous. Moreover, thisdef<strong>in</strong>ition suffers from be<strong>in</strong>g simultaneouslytoo narrow and too broad <strong>in</strong> scope; all illegal


1978 <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong> 975acts are not necessarily corrupt and all corruptacts are not necessarily illegal.1Def<strong>in</strong>itions of political corruption based onnotions of the public or common <strong>in</strong>terestsignificantly broaden the range of behavior onemight <strong>in</strong>vestigate. Consider the def<strong>in</strong>ition proposedby Arnold Rogow and Harold Lasswell:"A corrupt act violates responsibility toward atleast one system of public or civic order and is<strong>in</strong> fact <strong>in</strong>compatible with (destructive of) anysuch system" (Rogow and Lasswell, 1966, pp.132-33). While this def<strong>in</strong>ition focuses ourattention on any act or set of acts whichthreaten to destroy a political system, theresearcher has the responsibility of determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gwhat the public or common <strong>in</strong>terest is be<strong>for</strong>eassess<strong>in</strong>g whether a particular act is corrupt.The possibility exists that a behavior may beproscribed by law as corrupt but be beneficial<strong>for</strong> the common good, such as "fix<strong>in</strong>g" thepapers of an illegal alien who contributed hislabor and skills to a rapidly expand<strong>in</strong>g economy.Furthermore, this def<strong>in</strong>ition enables apolitician to justify almost any act by claim<strong>in</strong>gthat it is <strong>in</strong> the public <strong>in</strong>terest.A third approach to the def<strong>in</strong>itional problemsuggests that a political act is corrupt when theweight of public op<strong>in</strong>ion determ<strong>in</strong>es it so (see,<strong>for</strong> example, Rundquist and Hansen, 1976).This conception of political corruption harborsthe same limitations as the public <strong>in</strong>terestfocus. Studies of public op<strong>in</strong>ion have revealedthat on many issues public sentiments are eitherambiguous (significant portions of the publichold no op<strong>in</strong>ion or hold those of low <strong>in</strong>tensity)or are divided <strong>in</strong> their op<strong>in</strong>ions. Additionally, adef<strong>in</strong>ition of corruption based on public op<strong>in</strong>ionmust consider the differences which mayexist between the public and political elites <strong>in</strong>their assessment of appropriate standards ofpublic conduct.This approach to political corruption isprobably best illustrated <strong>in</strong> the work of ArnoldJ. Heidenheimer (1970). In his view the corruptnessof political acts is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the<strong>in</strong>teraction between the judgment of a particularact by the public and by political elitesor public officials. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to this scheme,behavior is judged particularly he<strong>in</strong>ous or corruptif both public officials and the publicjudge it corrupt and both wish it restricted.This type of behavior is referred to as "black"corruption. An act such as "a public official<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> hero<strong>in</strong> traffick<strong>in</strong>g" would mostlBerg, Hahn, and Schmidhauser (1976, p. 170)discuss sem<strong>in</strong>ars be<strong>in</strong>g conducted <strong>for</strong> large campaigndonors on how to use the loopholes <strong>in</strong> the newcampaign fund laws.likely fit this category <strong>in</strong> that both groups f<strong>in</strong>dthe act reprehensible and would demandpunishment <strong>for</strong> the guilty public official. At theother end of the corruption spectrum might becategorized political acts judged corrupt byboth public officials and the people, but whichneither feel are severe enough to warrantsanction. Quite possibly such acts of "white" orpetty corruption as a city council memberfix<strong>in</strong>g a park<strong>in</strong>g ticket <strong>for</strong> a constituent fall <strong>in</strong>tothis category. Between these two extremes ofcorruption acts lie the <strong>for</strong>ms of behavior whichare the most difficult to def<strong>in</strong>e and detect, andconsequently are potentially most destructiveto a political system organized along democraticpr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Heidenheimer refers to thesepolitical acts as "gray corruption" when eitherpublic officials or the people want to see anaction punished, while the other group doesnot, or it may well be that one group is <strong>in</strong>tenseabout the issue and the other ambivalent orunconcerned.2 Heidenheimer's work <strong>in</strong> thisarea, there<strong>for</strong>e, po<strong>in</strong>ts to the existence of ascale or dimension of corruption that can beused to classify political behaviors accord<strong>in</strong>g totheir degree of corruptness from "black" to"gray" to "white." It does not, however,account very well <strong>for</strong> those acts seen as corruptby only one group, nor does it seek to expla<strong>in</strong>why some groups may see an act as corrupt butother groups see it as less corrupt. Althoughthis conception of political corruption is basedon the criterion of op<strong>in</strong>ion (both public andelite), the assessment of a specific political actmay rest on violation of a legal norm or a threatto the public <strong>in</strong>terest. In other words, def<strong>in</strong>itionsof corruption are not mutually exclusive:elements of the public <strong>in</strong>terest and publicop<strong>in</strong>ion criteria are embedded <strong>in</strong> legal normswhich sanction certa<strong>in</strong> political behaviors ascorrupt.Although the Heidenheimer scheme enablesus to classify politically corrupt acts <strong>in</strong> ageneral way, a more detailed scheme seemsrequired if we are to classify adequately the2Harry Scoble (1973) refers to the situation (graycorruption) where public officials tolerate a corruptact or practice and citizens are unaware or ignorant ofthe act but would condemn it if they knew about it as"systemic corruption." Moreover, this view of politicalcorruption is useful and important <strong>in</strong> that it leads toan emphasis on the basic defects and weaknesses <strong>in</strong> thepolitical system which may be responsible <strong>for</strong> corruption(see Berg, Hahn, and Schmidhauser, 1976).There<strong>for</strong>e, rather than attribut<strong>in</strong>g such phenomena as"Watergate" to the weaknesses and foibles of <strong>in</strong>dividualpolitical actors, the "systemic view" of corruptionwould lead to a search <strong>for</strong> the sources of "Watergate"<strong>in</strong> the defects of the political process itself.


976 The <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review Vol. 72many variations of corrupt acts, and if we areto develop an explanation of why some acts arejudged corrupt and others not. We propose toanalyze potentially corrupt acts accord<strong>in</strong>g tothe component elements apparently <strong>in</strong>volvedwith every political act or exchange. We believethis process can mean<strong>in</strong>gfully be partitioned<strong>in</strong>to the "public official" <strong>in</strong>volved, the actual"favor" provided by the public official, the"payoff" ga<strong>in</strong>ed by the public official, and the"donor" of the payoff and/or "recipient" ofthe "favor" act. Although at this early stage <strong>in</strong>the development of a theory of political corruptionit would be too much to claim to beable to specify the exact nature of each of thesecomponents and its relation to the others, wedo believe that exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g acts of politicalcorruption <strong>in</strong> this manner might hold the keyto a better understand<strong>in</strong>g of why public officialsperceive some acts as corrupt and othersas "just politics," and why public officials andthe public may differ <strong>in</strong> their assessment.When discuss<strong>in</strong>g the subdimensions of eachcomponent of a potentially corrupt act, we willbe stat<strong>in</strong>g some propositions about what actswill be seen as corrupt. Those propositions willbe discussed <strong>in</strong> some detail later. When exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>ga "public official" <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> an alleged actof corruption, we are particularly <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>whether the act was entered <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong> theper<strong>for</strong>mance of the official's political duties.Presumably, an act which is considered malfeasance,misfeasance, or nonfeasance of publicduty is more corrupt than a behavior engaged <strong>in</strong>outside of one's official political role. In otherwords, misus<strong>in</strong>g one's political office <strong>for</strong> privatega<strong>in</strong> is more objectionable than engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>questionable behavior outside of one's officialduties.3A second characteristic of the public officialthat seems to determ<strong>in</strong>e whether behavior is tobe judged corrupt is the political nature of thepublic official's role. If a public official is <strong>in</strong> ajudicial or other nonpolitical post, certa<strong>in</strong> actsare more likely to be seen as corrupt than if thepublic official holds a political post. For example,judges have traditionally been held tohigher standards with regard to conflict-of<strong>in</strong>terestsituations than legislators. With the newcongressional actions to regulate conflict of<strong>in</strong>terest, it is possible that this situation may bechang<strong>in</strong>g at the national level, however.The second component of a politically corruptact is the "donor" of the payoff or"recipient" of the political favor. It is most3The recent example of Congressman Allan Howe's(D-Utah) alleged solicitation of a prostitute might be agood example. He committed an illegal act, but itwould hardly be called the misuse of public office.This is not to say that the voters <strong>in</strong> his district judgedhim any less harshly. The other recent "congressionalsex scandal," that of Congressman Wayne Hayes, whoallegedly put Elizabeth Ray on the payroll onlybecause she was his mistress, more rightly fits <strong>in</strong>to themisuse of public office category, and thus would bejudged more politically corrupt.Table 1. Components of a Potentially Corrupt Act and Some Salient CharacteristicsComponent More Corrupt Less CorruptPublic OfficialType of Position "Nonpolitical," i.e., the official <strong>Political</strong>is a judgeRole when Act Per<strong>for</strong>med Public Role, i.e., act is done as Private Role, i.e., act is per<strong>for</strong>med bypart of official's public duties public official act<strong>in</strong>g as a privatecitizenDonor's Relation to Public Official Nonconstituent pays official Constituent pays officialPublic official pays selfFavor Rendered by Public OfficialType of Benefit Private PublicType of Recipient Nonconstituent ConstituentNature of Act Provid<strong>in</strong>g Nonrout<strong>in</strong>e, i.e., official departs Rout<strong>in</strong>e, i.e., favor is per<strong>for</strong>med asFavor from normal rout<strong>in</strong>e to provide rout<strong>in</strong>e part of jobfavorPayoffSize Large SmallTime when Benefits Accrueto Donor Short-range benefit Long-range benefitSubstance Specific GeneralRelation to Campaign Noncampaign Campaign


1978 <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong> 977important to determ<strong>in</strong>e if the "donor" is aconstituent, broadly def<strong>in</strong>ed, or a nonconstituent.If the donor is a constituent, then a"favor" given is more likely to be perceived asless corrupt than if the favor is rendered to anonconstituent. The reason is obvious: actswhich are per<strong>for</strong>med under the rubric of"constituency service," no matter how questionable,have a certa<strong>in</strong> legitimacy. Of twosimilar, potentially corrupt acts, the odds arethat the constituency-related act will be judgedless corrupt than the service rendered to thenonconstituent. Beard and Horn (1975) offertwo examples support<strong>in</strong>g this proposition. Inone case, members of Congress were askedabout the legitimacy of putt<strong>in</strong>g favorable articlesabout campaign donors <strong>in</strong> the CongressionalRecord, as a "thank you" to donors. Thiswas seen as more legitimate if the donor were aconstituent rather than a firm outside thedistrict. A second example <strong>in</strong>volved accept<strong>in</strong>grides to and from one's congressional district ona national firm's private plane. If the firm hadties to the constituency, accept<strong>in</strong>g such favorswas seen as more legitimate than if the firm hadno such ties. Probably the most corrupt situationis when the donor is the public officialhimself. If the public official can directly enrichhimself by tapp<strong>in</strong>g the public till, he himself isthe donor. Examples of this <strong>in</strong>clude padd<strong>in</strong>gthe expense account, us<strong>in</strong>g public funds <strong>for</strong>personal travel, us<strong>in</strong>g money allocated <strong>for</strong>office expenses <strong>for</strong> personal activities, and soon.Another characteristic to be considered iswhether the "donor" of the payoff (recipientof the "favor") is more than one private<strong>in</strong>dividual or firm. We argue that the s<strong>in</strong>gledonor will be perceived as mak<strong>in</strong>g an actionmore corrupt than if the donor is a large groupof <strong>in</strong>dividuals or firms.A third component to consider is the "favor"provided by the public official. We cansurmise that the corruptness of the favor willvary <strong>in</strong> some ways as does the nature of thedonor. Private favors and nonconstituency favorswill be seen as more corrupt than thosewith large public benefit or those done <strong>for</strong> aconstituent.4 F<strong>in</strong>ally, if the favor is done <strong>in</strong>rout<strong>in</strong>e per<strong>for</strong>mance of duty rather than extraord<strong>in</strong>aryactivity, it is less likely to be seen ascorrupt. For example, a member of Congresswho makes a rout<strong>in</strong>e phone call to a federal4Even though the dimensions of "favor" are similarto those outl<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>for</strong> the "donor," there are somedifferences. For example, it is conceivable that aprivate donor might pay <strong>for</strong> a favor hav<strong>in</strong>g publicbenefit.agency to check on a federal contract of a firmwhose officers supported the Congress member<strong>in</strong> an election campaign is less likely to beviewed as per<strong>for</strong>m<strong>in</strong>g a corrupt act than onewho makes threats or acts <strong>in</strong> a way that thefederal bureaucrat perceives as nonrout<strong>in</strong>e.The fourth component of a potentiallycorrupt act, the "payoff" given to the publicofficial, is possibly the most important determ<strong>in</strong>antof its perceived corruptness. The obviousfact to consider is, of course, the size of thepayoff. It should come as no surprise that thelarger the payoff, the greater the perceiveddegree of corruptness <strong>in</strong> the act, although as weshall see later on, just what is "large" can bedifficult to agree upon. The payoff can <strong>also</strong>vary accord<strong>in</strong>g to the long- versus short-rangenature of the benefit to the public official. Wewould assume that a short-range benefit wouldbe perceived as more corrupt than a payoff thatwill yield benefits at a much later date, becausethe long-range payoff is separated <strong>in</strong> time fromthe favor done. Consider, <strong>for</strong> <strong>in</strong>stance, anofficial of a regulatory agency who takes alucrative position <strong>in</strong> a regulated corporationafter leav<strong>in</strong>g government service. Presumablythe official looked with some benevolence onthe activities of the corporation while <strong>in</strong> publicoffice; if that official had been given animmediate tangible payoff, <strong>for</strong> example a giftof money, we th<strong>in</strong>k most people would chargecorruption. But the later payoff probably isseen by many as legitimate.5In a similar ve<strong>in</strong>, the payoff can be dist<strong>in</strong>guishedas to whether it is specific or general.If a payoff takes specific <strong>for</strong>m, such as moneyor a service rendered, it will likely be perceivedas more corrupt than a general payoff, such asfuture electoral support or good will. Althoughthis is a rather special case of payoff, it is <strong>also</strong>important to determ<strong>in</strong>e if a gift is related to apolitical campaign. Payoffs <strong>in</strong> the <strong>for</strong>m ofcampaign contributions have a legitimacy notrendered to other <strong>for</strong>ms of material payoffs. A$1,000 cash donation to a campaign is perfectlyacceptable, while an equal amount offered as apersonal gift to a public official subjects thedonor and official to possible legal penalties.In Table 1, we have summarized the basiccomponents of a politically corrupt act, and<strong>in</strong>dicated the dimensions <strong>in</strong> each componentwhich can vary accord<strong>in</strong>g to perceived corruptness.In outl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g these components and theirsalient characteristics, we have articulated a5President Carter, however, has extracted pledgesfrom his high-level appo<strong>in</strong>tees that they will not takejobs with firms do<strong>in</strong>g bus<strong>in</strong>ess with or regulated bytheir agency <strong>for</strong> a period of two years.


978 The <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review Vol. 72large number of testable propositions about theconditions under which an act can and will beviewed as corrupt. We have only outl<strong>in</strong>edpropositions at the first level, i.e., deal<strong>in</strong>g witheach subdimension s<strong>in</strong>gly, and have not def<strong>in</strong>edpropositions deal<strong>in</strong>g with more than one subdivisionat a time. Certa<strong>in</strong>ly an act hav<strong>in</strong>g mostor all of the characteristics listed on the leftside is considered more corrupt than one hav<strong>in</strong>gonly characteristics on the right. Which componentsare most important <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g corruptnessis a researchable question not answeredhere. Yet tak<strong>in</strong>g a broader view, ourrudimentary scheme offers a conceptual framework<strong>for</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g and compar<strong>in</strong>g potentiallycorrupt political acts. This framework allows usto circumvent the def<strong>in</strong>itional problems surround<strong>in</strong>gthe mean<strong>in</strong>g of "corruption."The Study DesignOur study was designed specifically to ascerta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong><strong>for</strong>mation on attitudes about corruptionheld by a large group of public officials. Wemailed questionnaires to all 978 state senators<strong>in</strong> 24 states.6 After three mail<strong>in</strong>gs, 441 senatorshad responded with completed questionnaires.7Response rate by state ranged from only 21percent <strong>in</strong> Cali<strong>for</strong>nia to over 78 percent fromNorth Dakota. Generally, response rate wasslightly higher <strong>in</strong> the rural states than <strong>in</strong> the<strong>in</strong>dustrialized ones.86AM1 of our mail<strong>in</strong>gs, sent <strong>in</strong> October, Decemberand January, 1975-76 were sent to the senators'home addresses, <strong>in</strong> order to m<strong>in</strong>imize the possibilitythat the senator would delegate fill<strong>in</strong>g out the questionnaireto a staff member or legislative <strong>in</strong>tern. Thestates surveyed were ALABAMA, Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, Connecticut,Florida, Georgia, Ill<strong>in</strong>ois, IOWA, Kansas,Kentucky, Ma<strong>in</strong>e, Massachusetts, MICHIGAN, M<strong>in</strong>nesota,MISSOURI, Nevada, New Jersey, New York,NORTH DAKOTA, Oregon, PENNSYLVANIA,TEXAS, Utah, West Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, and Wyom<strong>in</strong>g. Thesestates were picked randomly, with a few substitutionsto assure geographic dispersion (after our <strong>in</strong>itialrandom selection, we had eight southern states but nostates from the <strong>in</strong>dustrial Middle West). Only some ofthe nonrespondents, those from the states listed <strong>in</strong>capital letters, were sent a third-wave questionnaire.7For a discussion of the rationale beh<strong>in</strong>d theshorter, third-wave questionnaire, see Welch and Peters(1977a).81n addition to Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, only New York (25percent) had a response rate of less than 30 percent.Three more had response rates less than 40 percent:Massachusetts (30 percent), Ill<strong>in</strong>ois (32 percent), andMassachusetts (32 percent). On the other hand, eightstates had a response rate of more than 50 percent:North Dakota (78 percent), Utah (62 percent), Iowa(62 percent), Alabama (60 percent), Ma<strong>in</strong>e (58 per-The major focus of the questionnaire was aseries of items concern<strong>in</strong>g ten actions by publicofficials that might or might not be consideredcorrupt. As sometimes happens, we have s<strong>in</strong>cefound problems and lack of clarity <strong>in</strong> some ofthe items. These problems will be discussedlater. The items are as follows (<strong>in</strong> the orderlisted on the questionnaire):1. A presidential candidate who promises anambassadorship <strong>in</strong> exchange <strong>for</strong> campaigncontributions (AMBASSADOR);2. A member of Congress us<strong>in</strong>g seniority toobta<strong>in</strong> a weapons contract <strong>for</strong> a firm <strong>in</strong>his or her district (WEAPONS).3. A public official us<strong>in</strong>g public funds <strong>for</strong>personal travel (TRAVEL);4. A secretary of defense who owns$50,000 <strong>in</strong> stock <strong>in</strong> a company withwhich the Defense Department has amillion-dollar contract (DEFENSESTOCK);5. A public official us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence to get afriend or relative admitted to law school(LAW SCHOOL);6. The driveway of the mayor's home be<strong>in</strong>gpaved by the city crew (DRIVEWAY);7. A state assembly member while chairpersonof the public roads committee authoriz<strong>in</strong>gthe purchase of land s/he hadrecently acquired (LAND SALE);8. A judge with $50,000 worth of stock <strong>in</strong> acorporation hear<strong>in</strong>g a case concern<strong>in</strong>gthat firm (JUDGE);9. A legislator accept<strong>in</strong>g a large campaigncontribution <strong>in</strong> return <strong>for</strong> vot<strong>in</strong>g "theright way" on a legislative bill (RIGHTWAY);10. A member of Congress who holds a largeamount of stock (about $50,000 worth)<strong>in</strong> Standard Oil of New Jersey work<strong>in</strong>g toma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> the oil depletion allowance(OIL).We omitted items on which we felt therewould be near total consensus, either becausethey were so serious or because they were sotrivial: at one extreme, <strong>for</strong> example, a publicofficial engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> hero<strong>in</strong> traffic, and at theother, a policeman tak<strong>in</strong>g a free cup of coffeefrom a local cafe. We asked several questionsabout each item, with five degrees of response.In this article we will exam<strong>in</strong>e responses to thecent), Kansas (53 percent), Wyom<strong>in</strong>g (53 percent),and Oregon (53 percent).


1978 <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong> 979question as to whether the act was believed tobe corrupt or not.F<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gsWe do not have enough items to exploresystematically a number of propositions thatcould be generated by our work, but we willuse these data <strong>in</strong> ways that <strong>in</strong>dicate theusefulness of our scheme <strong>in</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g corruption.We first ranked the items accord<strong>in</strong>g to theproportion agree<strong>in</strong>g that the act was corrupt orvery corrupt (Table 3). In Table 2 we havesketched the most salient characteristics of eachact, accord<strong>in</strong>g to our fourfold scheme; we have<strong>also</strong> outl<strong>in</strong>ed the characteristics of a hypotheticalact <strong>in</strong> which a member of Congress <strong>in</strong> adistrict with a large percent of m<strong>in</strong>ority populationsvotes <strong>in</strong> favor of the civil rights act(CIVIL RIGHTS). In return, members of civilrights groups <strong>in</strong> the district support the memberof Congress <strong>in</strong> a reelection bid. We judge thatfew would see anyth<strong>in</strong>g corrupt <strong>in</strong> this sequenceof events.The first conclusion from Table 3 is that theacts considered corrupt by most people havemany characteristics starred (where starredcharacteristics <strong>in</strong>dicate more corrupt features,i.e., features on the left-hand side of Table 1).Clusters of stars are particularly apparent <strong>in</strong> the"payoff" boxes. Acts considered by few to becorrupt have few stars; CIVIL RIGHTS hasonly one. Those acts whose corruptness is mostdisputed have an <strong>in</strong>termediate number of characteristicsstarred. We can <strong>also</strong> immediately seethat any one attribute, <strong>in</strong> isolation, probablydoes not determ<strong>in</strong>e corruptness. For example,an act per<strong>for</strong>med <strong>in</strong> one's public role may leadto corruption, but simply know<strong>in</strong>g that anofficial per<strong>for</strong>med an act as part of a public roletells us noth<strong>in</strong>g by itself. Un<strong>for</strong>tunately notenough <strong>in</strong><strong>for</strong>mation was given to classify fullysome of the acts on our four components.Greater specificity may have changed the publicofficials' responses, and would <strong>also</strong> have madethe pattern of classification clearer.Four acts were perceived as corrupt by over90 percent of our sample: RIGHT WAYDRIVEWAY, TRAVEL, and LAND SALE.While two of these acts <strong>in</strong>volve m<strong>in</strong>or sums ofmoney, all are illegal and all result <strong>in</strong> personalf<strong>in</strong>ancial ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>for</strong> the public official. In terms ofour four components we can say that three ofthe four acts are characterized by the merger ofthe donor and the public official role. That is,<strong>in</strong> the cases of DRIVEWAY, TRAVEL, andLAND SALE, the public official is <strong>in</strong> theposition of personally ensur<strong>in</strong>g direct f<strong>in</strong>ancialga<strong>in</strong>. Of our ten examples, these are the onlythree where such a merger is the case, and arethe <strong>in</strong>stances of highest consensus. The fourthcase perceived as corrupt by over 90 percent isRIGHT WAY. Here the donor is not the publicofficial but an unspecified second party. However,the payoff is very direct and immediate,though <strong>in</strong> the context of a campaign contribution.We assume that if a campaign contributionwere not <strong>in</strong>volved, almost all would have seenthe act as corrupt. RIGHT WAY might becompared with another example, OIL, wherethe payoff from vot<strong>in</strong>g a certa<strong>in</strong> way is muchmore <strong>in</strong>direct and long-range (i.e., the possible<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the value of the legislator's stock),and fewer see this type of payoff as corrupt. Insum, from these four examples, we <strong>in</strong>fer thatthese illegal acts are judged highly corruptbecause of the merger of the donor and publicofficial role <strong>in</strong> three cases, and because of thedirect and monetary ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> exchange <strong>for</strong> a vote<strong>in</strong> the fourth.At the other end of the cont<strong>in</strong>uum, less than40 percent of the sample found LAW SCHOOLand the WEAPONS examples corrupt. Theseacts might be characterized as rather m<strong>in</strong>or<strong>for</strong>ms of <strong>in</strong>fluence peddl<strong>in</strong>g. In both cases, thepayoff is <strong>in</strong>direct and long-range: good will thatperhaps <strong>in</strong>creases the possibility of future campaignsupport. In both cases the donor ispresumably a constituent. The acts themselvesobviously are seen by most as rout<strong>in</strong>e k<strong>in</strong>ds offavors that public officials try to do <strong>for</strong>constituents, and thus only a m<strong>in</strong>ority areWill<strong>in</strong>g to call the acts corrupt.Our fourfold typology <strong>also</strong> sheds some lighton why there is some ambiguity about theseacts. While the payoff is long-range, the donor aconstituent, it is implied that do<strong>in</strong>g the favortakes the legislator outside the narrow per<strong>for</strong>manceof legislative duty. While the questionis un<strong>for</strong>tunately silent about some aspects ofthe transaction, it can be presumed that thelegislator is call<strong>in</strong>g the law school dean ormembers of the admissions committee <strong>in</strong> theone <strong>in</strong>stance, and perhaps putt<strong>in</strong>g undue pressureon a bureaucrat <strong>in</strong> the other. These actswould be considered by some to be overstepp<strong>in</strong>gthe normal scope of a legislator's activity,but by others as rout<strong>in</strong>ely try<strong>in</strong>g to provide aconstituent service. Perhaps a clarification ofthe item would allow a better <strong>in</strong>terpretation.The acts where there is the least consensusare conflict of <strong>in</strong>terest activities: OIL, DE-FENSE STOCK, JUDGE, and AMBASSADOR.In each case, public officials are <strong>in</strong> the positionof further<strong>in</strong>g personal f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>terests whilemak<strong>in</strong>g a decision <strong>in</strong> their public role. In thecase of DEFENSE STOCK, OIL and JUDGE,public officials are <strong>in</strong> the position of per<strong>for</strong>m<strong>in</strong>ga favor (i.e., cast<strong>in</strong>g a favorable vote oraward<strong>in</strong>g a contract) <strong>for</strong> which the payoff is an


980 The <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review Vol. 72<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the value of their own stock. Unlikethe DRIVEWAY, TRAVEL or LANDSALE<strong>in</strong>stances, legislators are not the sole donors,although they are <strong>in</strong> the position of be<strong>in</strong>g pastdonors. Public officials, by their acts, cannotconvert favors directly <strong>in</strong>to payoffs. Otherevents might have an impact on the stock'svalue, regardless of a public official's favor.And, the payoff is much less direct than a cashgrant or immediate service rendered. The governmentcontract, the favorable court rul<strong>in</strong>g,the <strong>in</strong>creased oil depletion allowance may ormay not <strong>in</strong>crease stockholders' dividends. Onthe other hand, the payoff is more tangiblethan the generalized "good will" engendered bythe WEAPONS or LAW SCHOOL acts.Other factors are <strong>also</strong> <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>gconflict-of-<strong>in</strong>terest acts to the others previouslyTable 2. Characteristics of Ten Potentially Corrupt ActsAct Public Official Donor Favor PayoffDRIVEWAY <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Self* Private* Large (?)*Specific*Short-range*Noncampaign*TRAVEL <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Self* Private* Large*Specific*Short-range*Noncampaign*LAND SALE <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Self* Private* Large*Specific*Short-range*Noncampaign*RIGHT WAY <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Unclear ? Unclear ? Large*Specific*Short-range*CampaignJUDGE Nonpolitical,* public Unclear ? (<strong>in</strong> part)* Unclear Indeterm<strong>in</strong>ate sizerole* Self Potential Specific*Private*Long-rangeRout<strong>in</strong>e act NoncampaignAMBASSADOR <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Constituent Private* Large*Constituent Specific*Rout<strong>in</strong>e act Short-range*CampaignDEFENSE STOCK <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Unclear, <strong>in</strong> part self* Unclear Indeterm<strong>in</strong>ate size(?) ~~~~~~~~~~Potential Speciflc*Private * Long-rangeRout<strong>in</strong>eNoncampaign*OIL<strong>Political</strong>, public role* Unclear, <strong>in</strong> part self* Unclear Indeterm<strong>in</strong>ate sizePotentialSpeciflc*Private * Long-rangeRout<strong>in</strong>eNoncampaign*WEAPONS <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Unclear, possibly Unclear, possibly SmallCONTRACT constituent nonrout<strong>in</strong>e* NonspecificLong-rangeNoncampaignLAW SCHOOL <strong>Political</strong>, unclear Unclear, possibly Unclear, possibly Smallconstituent nonrout<strong>in</strong>e* NonspecificLong-rangeNoncampaignCIVIL RIGHTS <strong>Political</strong>, public role* Constituent Rout<strong>in</strong>e SmallConstituent NonspecificPublicLong-rangePossibly campaign*More corrupt.


1978 <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong> 981discussed. The size of the payoff as well as itsimmediacy <strong>in</strong>fluences an official's perception ofcorruption. We cannot demonstrate that withour data, as all <strong>in</strong>volve $50,000 worth of stock.Beard and Horn (1975), however, offer arelevant example. More Congress members believeit more corrupt <strong>for</strong> a legislator to cast avote <strong>for</strong> benefits to the sav<strong>in</strong>gs and loan<strong>in</strong>dustry when the legislator owns $100,000worth of stock rather than only $5000 (1975,p. 22). In our own data, several people <strong>in</strong>dicatedthat if <strong>in</strong>stead of own<strong>in</strong>g $50,000 ofstock, the Secretary of Defense were a "major"stockholder, then the ta<strong>in</strong>t of corruption mightbe greater.F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> these four items we can see thatthe nature of the public office is <strong>also</strong> relevant.The conflict of <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a judge wasbelieved more odious than that <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g eithera bureaucrat or a member of Congress. A judge,<strong>in</strong> a nonpolitical role, is held to higher standardsthan are legislators.The AMBASSADOR items differ from theOIL, DEFENSE and JUDGE acts. The payoff, acampaign donation, is much more immediate.The donor, however, is provid<strong>in</strong>g a campaigncontribution rather than funds to be usedsimply <strong>for</strong> personal enrichment. To us, theAMBASSADOR and RIGHT WAY cases seemparallel. In one case, the favor is a vote, <strong>in</strong>another, an appo<strong>in</strong>tment. Why the <strong>for</strong>mer isseen as more corrupt is undoubtedly becausethe "spoils system" of appo<strong>in</strong>tment has aresidue of legitimacy that the practice of"vot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>for</strong> pay" has not.Our typology of corrupt acts helps expla<strong>in</strong>why these conflict-of-<strong>in</strong>terest behaviors areoften ambiguous. As the payoff becomes moreand more long-range, and the donor and favorsare constituency-oriented, it is easy to arguethat an act is not corrupt. Most public officialshope that all acts have some positive payoff <strong>for</strong>them, pr<strong>in</strong>cipally reelection (Mayhew, 1975),and do<strong>in</strong>g constituency-oriented favors is oneway to <strong>in</strong>crease the probability of reelection.99Jack Anderson commented on this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> arecent "expose" of congressional misbehavior:"Favors are part of a politician's stock <strong>in</strong> trade. He isexpected to produce government jobs, public worksprojects, appo<strong>in</strong>tments to military academies andTable 3. Percent Agree<strong>in</strong>g Act Is CorruptPercent ofPercent ofRespondents Believ<strong>in</strong>g Respondents Believ<strong>in</strong>gPercent of Most Public Officials Most of PublicRespondents View<strong>in</strong>g Would Condemn Would CondemnThis Act as Corrupt This Act This ActDRIVEWAY 95.9 92.2 97.5TRAVEL 95.2 80.4 96.5LAND SALE 95.1 92.1 97.5RIGHT WAY 91.9 82.2 94.3JUDGE 78.8 82.3 91.0AMBASSADOR 71.1 44.5 81.2DEFENSE STOCK 58.3 62.1 84.4OIL 54.9 55.1 81.2WEAPONS CONTRACT 31.6 20.9 34.4LAW SCHOOL 23.7 15.5 35.9Table 4. Correlation Matrix of Perceived <strong>Corruption</strong> ItemsTRVL LDSL RTWY JUDG AMB DFST OIL WPNS LAWSDRIVEWAY .19 .28 -.28 .06 .12 .13 .02 .03 .09TRAVEL - .29 .35 .07 .15 .08 .10 .10 .10LAND SALE - .33 .16 .15 .16 .06 .08 .10RIGHT WAY - .16 .20 .14 .10 .14 .06JUDGE - .16.45 .31 .11 .20AMBASSADOR .19 .23 .15 .22DEFENSE STOCK - .46 .07 .18OIL .12 .12WEAPONS CONTRACT - L2 l


982 The <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review Vol. 72When the "favor" done <strong>for</strong> a constituentco<strong>in</strong>cides with personal enrichment, then thecharge of conflict of <strong>in</strong>terest is relevant. Clearlyour sample is ambivalent and divided about thepropriety of these acts.In sum, the simple rank order<strong>in</strong>g of our tenexamples shows at one end of the cont<strong>in</strong>uum acluster<strong>in</strong>g of acts that are clearly illegal orrepresent a direct f<strong>in</strong>ancial ga<strong>in</strong>, at the other,acts that are m<strong>in</strong>or <strong>in</strong>fluence peddl<strong>in</strong>g, and <strong>in</strong>between a set of acts represent<strong>in</strong>g a variety ofconflict-of-<strong>in</strong>terest situations. A Guttman scal<strong>in</strong>gprocedure revealed that this set of acts wasunidimensional. They scaled <strong>in</strong> the same orderas discussed, and produced a coefficient ofreproducibility of .95, as shown <strong>in</strong> Table 4.1 0Our categorization of the components of acorrupt act aided <strong>in</strong> p<strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g some of thereasons <strong>for</strong> differential perceptions of the corruptnessof various acts. The nature of thefavor, the donor, the public official, and particularlythe payoff were all useful <strong>in</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>gthese perceptions. Acts most perceived as corrupttended to have different characteristicsfrom those few perceived as corrupt. And,where there was near-unanimity about thecorruptness of an act, more components of theact were regarded as corrupt than where therewere divided sentiments. Us<strong>in</strong>g only these tenacts, it could not be determ<strong>in</strong>ed which (if any)components, or comb<strong>in</strong>ations of components,were crucial <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g perceptions. Moreresearch on that po<strong>in</strong>t is necessary. We haveonly explored reasons why some acts areperceived as more corrupt than others; we havenot yet tried to analyze why there are <strong>in</strong>tergroupdifferences <strong>in</strong> perception of corruption,particularly differences between elites and thepublic. I IDiscussion<strong>Political</strong> corruption has not been subjectedto the sort of rigorous analysis received byother phenomena <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong>n politics. In largemeasure, the difficulty of def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g "politicalcorruption" accounts <strong>for</strong> this neglect. Thepresent analysis develops a fourfold classificationscheme composed of what we consider theessential <strong>in</strong>gredients of every act of politicalcorruption. While this scheme is not a "theory,"it does offer a conceptual frameworkhelpful <strong>in</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g and analyz<strong>in</strong>g potentiallycorrupt acts. In do<strong>in</strong>g that it allows us to avoidthe def<strong>in</strong>itional pitfalls which have stalematedthe study of corruption <strong>for</strong> so long. Theseproblems can be avoided because the componentsof our conceptual scheme allow one toanalyze acts classified as corrupt accord<strong>in</strong>g toany of the corruption def<strong>in</strong>itions describedearlier: the public op<strong>in</strong>ion, public <strong>in</strong>terest, andlegalistic def<strong>in</strong>itions.The scheme, <strong>for</strong> <strong>in</strong>stance, renders the "publicop<strong>in</strong>ion" def<strong>in</strong>ition more usable by ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>git <strong>in</strong> such a way as to allow gradients ofcorruptness <strong>in</strong> an act and to assist <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>greasons why public officials and elites holdsimilar or divergent beliefs about a particularcorrupt act. This can be accomplished bysystematically vary<strong>in</strong>g each component of ourscheme over a wide variety of acts. The resultshould enable researchers to p<strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t differencesbetween elites and the mass public,and thus to <strong>in</strong>fer why there are divergentareas-"gray areas of political corruption."Might it be because the two groups view the"payoff" differently: what is seen as small orpetty by public officials may be viewed as largeand serious to citizens? Or, does the divergencelie <strong>in</strong> the perception of what is extraord<strong>in</strong>ary <strong>in</strong>the act provid<strong>in</strong>g the favor? Many similarexplanations could be posited and tested.government contracts can be arranged with<strong>in</strong> theconstra<strong>in</strong>ts of the law and ethics. But some legislatorsare not content to wait until election day to bask <strong>in</strong>the gratitude of the voters."10This correlation matrix of the ten items partiallyconfirms the cluster<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to three groups though thecorrelation between the two <strong>in</strong>fluence-peddl<strong>in</strong>g itemsis very small.I We have no public op<strong>in</strong>ion data to test hypothesesabout elite-mass differences. We do, however,have data on how our respondents th<strong>in</strong>k citizens feelabout these acts. While the rank order<strong>in</strong>g or legislators'perceptions of citizens beliefs of corrupt acts is similarto the respondents' belief that most citizens would seeevery conflict-of-<strong>in</strong>terest act as corrupt (Table 3). Theonly acts the majority of our respondents believecitizens would not condemn are the WEAPONS andLAW SCHOOL acts. Un<strong>for</strong>tunately, these data do nottest our propositions. They are only suggestive. Therespondent's views of citizens reactions to thesepotentially corrupt acts <strong>also</strong> <strong>for</strong>m an acceptableGuttman scale, with a CR of .94 and with no itemshav<strong>in</strong>g more than 10 percent error.One study that surveyed public op<strong>in</strong>ion aboutcorrupt acts was that of John Gard<strong>in</strong>er (1970), whoassessed the attitudes of citizens about politicalcorruption <strong>in</strong> their community. While he exam<strong>in</strong>edtolerance of corruption as it related to several socioeconomicattributes, he did not compare public andelite attitudes. He did f<strong>in</strong>d, however, that moreeducated people were less tolerant of corruption thanthose with less education.


1978 <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong> 983Moreover, the opportunity now exists toexplore possible differences <strong>in</strong> corruption perceptionsbased on social class and other subgroups<strong>in</strong> the population such as race, region,and sex (see Welch and Peters, 1977b). <strong>Corruption</strong>may <strong>also</strong> be related to psychological orattitud<strong>in</strong>al predispositions. For example, "private-"vs. "public-regard<strong>in</strong>g" dist<strong>in</strong>ctions sometimesused to expla<strong>in</strong> corrupt behavior can beencompassed with<strong>in</strong> our scheme. For <strong>in</strong>stance,are citizens and elites whose approach topolitical life is considered "private-regard<strong>in</strong>g"<strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to be less severe <strong>in</strong> their condemnationof certa<strong>in</strong> political acts than those display<strong>in</strong>g a"public-regard<strong>in</strong>g" disposition? In this manner,the study of political corruption can be <strong>in</strong>tegrated<strong>in</strong>to the broader propositions aboutthe social and attitud<strong>in</strong>al bases of politicalbehavior.The scheme can <strong>also</strong> be related to thedef<strong>in</strong>itions of corruption based on "illegal acts"or violations of the "public <strong>in</strong>terest." Are allcorrupt acts viewed similarly which are proscribedby law because they deviate from the<strong>for</strong>mal duties of public office <strong>for</strong> personal ga<strong>in</strong>?If so, the explanation <strong>for</strong> the common beliefmay lie <strong>in</strong> the components of illegal acts such asthe payoff, favor, public official or donor. Onecan view acts considered to be aga<strong>in</strong>st thepublic <strong>in</strong>terest or order <strong>in</strong> a similar way. An actof political corruption may or may not beviewed by all public officials and citizens asviolat<strong>in</strong>g a responsibility to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> civic orderor as destroy<strong>in</strong>g a political system. Given thewide and vary<strong>in</strong>g op<strong>in</strong>ions about the "public<strong>in</strong>terest," one would expect they would not.And the four elements, public official, donor,favor, and payoff, allow us to compare andanalyze a wide variety of political acts, whethertheir potential corruptness is based on illegality,violation of the public <strong>in</strong>terest, or condemnationby public op<strong>in</strong>ion. Our approach is <strong>also</strong>compatible with the "systemic view" of politicalcorruption. If a large part of politicalcorruption <strong>in</strong> the United States can be attributedto <strong>in</strong>herent weaknesses <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong>offices, situations, or processes, then morehonest government will only come about whenthose weaknesses are identified and eradicatedby public officials and concerned citizens. Thusan understand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>dividual attitudes isimportant even when consider<strong>in</strong>g the systemicview of corruption.Inherent weaknesses are difficult to identify.But once exposed they can be analyzed accord<strong>in</strong>gto our conceptual scheme. Patterns mayemerge which would help one predict thoseoffices, <strong>in</strong>stitutions or processes susceptible topolitical corruption. In this manner the sourcesof political corruption can be systematicallyidentified.1 2Our approach to def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g corruption, then,is offered as a way to <strong>in</strong>tegrate research oncorruption with the ma<strong>in</strong>stream of research <strong>in</strong><strong>America</strong>n politics, a way of <strong>in</strong>tegrat<strong>in</strong>g theoriesabout corruption to a well-grounded literature<strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong>n political beliefs and behavior. Thisapproach <strong>also</strong> offers a way to study politicalcorruption from the comparative and <strong>in</strong>ternationalperspective. Aga<strong>in</strong> the four componentsare common to every potentially corruptact. Different hypotheses might be suggested <strong>in</strong>the cross-national or <strong>in</strong>ternational study ofcorruption, but our scheme offers a framework<strong>for</strong> such a study. For example, a hypothesismight specify that one type of political cultureviews a certa<strong>in</strong> type of payoff as a rout<strong>in</strong>e partof a public official's prerequisites, whileanother culture views the payoff quite differently.Thus our understand<strong>in</strong>g of differentialviews toward potentially corrupt acts is en-hanced. The citizens of one country maycondemn a specific political act as corruptbecause it violates the norms of public officehold<strong>in</strong>g, while the citizens of another countrycondone the same act because it does not. Thescheme can help us understand why the leadersof a <strong>for</strong>eign country consider it proper toexpect monetary kickbacks from large U.S.corporations <strong>in</strong> exchange <strong>for</strong> a governmentcontract, or to offer bribes to key members ofthe U.S. Congress <strong>in</strong> exchange <strong>for</strong> favorabletreatment. Moreover, it may well be that stagesof economic development, modernization, social<strong>in</strong>frastructure, and so <strong>for</strong>th, bear systematicrelationship to the components of our conceptualframework. It provides us with anotherway of demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g how political corruptionis related to political development.This approach can <strong>also</strong> be l<strong>in</strong>ked to the moretraditional approach of study<strong>in</strong>g corruptiononly when a significant local or national scandalhas occurred. One can monitor public and eliteattitudes over time <strong>in</strong> an attempt to l<strong>in</strong>k publicattitudes to the situational context.For too long the systematic study of politicalcorruption has been neglected by seriousstudents of <strong>America</strong>n politics. That this shouldbe so is understandable, consider<strong>in</strong>g not onlythe impos<strong>in</strong>g conceptual problems but <strong>also</strong> the121n our own sample, 35.5 percent believed thatthere were no specific offices particularly susceptibleto corruption; rather, it was a few susceptible <strong>in</strong>dividuals(the "rotten apple" view). Of the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g64.5 percent, there was little apparent agreement as towhich offices were more susceptible to corruption.Most frequently mentioned were offices handl<strong>in</strong>g a lotof money, named by 7.3 percent.


984 The <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review Vol. 72lack of <strong>in</strong>tellectual respectability about theconcept itself. But it has become <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>glyevident to citizens, public officials, and scholarsalike that "corruption <strong>in</strong> politics" is just tooprevalent a phenomenon not to be subjected torigorous study. Our article has attempted todemonstrate one approach, but by no meansthe only approach, to the systematic study ofpolitical corruption.ReferencesAnderson, Jack (1976). "A Citizen's Committee isNeeded to Crack Down on Congressmen whoCheat."Parade, 21 November 1976,4-5.Banfield, Edward and James Q. Wilson (1963). CityPolitics. New York: V<strong>in</strong>tage.Beard, Edmund and Stephen Horn (1975). CongressionalEthics: A View from the House. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton:Brook<strong>in</strong>gs.Berg, Larry L., Harlan Hahn, and John R. Schmidhauser(1976). <strong>Corruption</strong> <strong>in</strong> the <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong>System. Morristown, N.J.: General Learn<strong>in</strong>gPress.Cohen, Richard M., and Jules Witcover (1974). AHeartbeat Away. New York: Vildng.Edelman, Murray (1964). The Symbolic Uses ofPolitics. Urbana: University of Ill<strong>in</strong>ois Press.Elazar, Daniel (1966). <strong>America</strong>n Federalism: A Viewfrom the States. New York: Crowell.Gard<strong>in</strong>er, John (1970). The Politics of <strong>Corruption</strong>.New York: Sage.Getz, Robert S. (1966). Congressional Ethics: TheConflict of Interest Issue. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: VanNostrand.Greenste<strong>in</strong>, Fred I. (1964). "The Chang<strong>in</strong>g Pattern ofUrban Party Politics." Annals of the <strong>America</strong>nAcademy of <strong>Political</strong> and Social Science353:1-13.Heidenheimer, A. J., ed. (1970). <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong>:Read<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> Comparative Analysis. New York:Holt.Lippman, Walter (1970; first published 1930). "ATheory about <strong>Corruption</strong>. In Arnold Heidenheimer(ed.), <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong>. New York: Holt, pp.294-97.Nye, J. S. (1967). "<strong>Corruption</strong> and <strong>Political</strong> Development:A Cost-Benefit Analysis." <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong>Science Review 61:417-27.P<strong>in</strong>to-Dusch<strong>in</strong>sky, Michael (1976). "Theories of <strong>Corruption</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong>n Politics," paper presented atthe annual meet<strong>in</strong>g of the <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong>Science Association, Chicago, 1976.Rogow, Arnold A. and Harold Lasswell (1963). Power,<strong>Corruption</strong> and Rectitude. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:Prentice-Hall.Rundquist, Barry S. and Susan Hansen (1976). "OnControll<strong>in</strong>g Official <strong>Corruption</strong>: Elections vs.Laws." Unpublished manuscript.Rundquist, Barry S., Gerald S. Strom and John G.Peters (1977). "Corrupt Politicians and TheirElectoral Support: Some Theoretical and EmpiricalObservations." <strong>America</strong>n <strong>Political</strong> Science Review71:954-63.Scoble, Harry (1973). "Systemic <strong>Corruption</strong>," a paperpresented at the annual meet<strong>in</strong>g of the <strong>America</strong>n<strong>Political</strong> Science Association, New Orleans, September,1973.Scott, James (1972). Comparative <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong>.Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.De Tocqueville, Alexis (1961). Democracy <strong>in</strong> <strong>America</strong>,Vols. 1-2. New York: Schocken.Welch, Susan and John G. Peters (1977a). "SomeProblems of Stimulat<strong>in</strong>g Responses to Mail Questionnaires:Controllable and Non Controllable Aspects."<strong>Political</strong> Methodology 4:139-52.(1977b). "Attitudes of U.S. State LegislatorsToward <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Corruption</strong>." Legislative StudiesQuarterly 2:445-64.Wilson, James Q. (1966). "<strong>Corruption</strong>: The Shame ofthe States." The Public Interest 2:28-38.Wolfmger, R. E. (1972). "Why Mach<strong>in</strong>e Politics HaveNot Withered Away and Other RevisionistThoughts." Journal of Politics 34:365-98.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!