14.10.2015 Views

ARCHITECTURE

The_Art_of_Inequality

The_Art_of_Inequality

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

so as not to include ‘peculiar advantages of skill, shrewdness, and experience, regarding<br />

which . . . no one has a right to call upon us to abandon. Here, justice permits us to use<br />

our superiority freely.’ ‘All know what a wide difference exists among men in these points,<br />

and whatever advantage may result from that inequality, is silently conceded in the<br />

very fact of making a bargain. It is a superiority on one side – an inferiority on the other,<br />

perhaps very great, but they are allowed. This must be so; the business of life could not<br />

go on were it otherwise.’ Thus, while he refused in theory to separate law and morality,<br />

Verplanck confined fraud to a range sufficiently narrow to permit the contract system to<br />

reinforce existing social and economic inequalities.” Gulian C. Verplanck, An Essay on the<br />

Doctrine of Contracts: Being an Inquiry How Contracts Are Affected in Laws and Morals,<br />

By Concealment, Error, or Inadequate Price (New York: G. & C. Carvill, 1825), cited and<br />

discussed in Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 182–183.<br />

17. “[I]n a society in which value came to be regarded as entirely subjective and in which<br />

the only basis for assigning value was the concurrence of arbitrary individual desire,<br />

principles of substantive justice were inevitably seen as entailing an “arbitrary and<br />

uncertain” standard of value. Substantive justice, according to the earlier view, existed<br />

in order to prevent men from using the legal system in order to exploit each other.<br />

But where things have no “intrinsic value,” there can be no substantive measure of exploitation<br />

and the parties are, by definition, equal. Modern contract law was thus<br />

born staunchly proclaiming that all men are equal because all measures of inequality<br />

are illusory.” Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 161.<br />

18. This is not to say that speculations over the future value of investments were not a<br />

feature of pre-eighteenth century markets (in fact, market speculation has been traced<br />

to, at least, the thirteenth century, such as with the development of Genovese contracts<br />

of “comanda” for long-distance trade), but rather that contracts were not an essential<br />

legal-bureaucratic vehicle for the establishment of regional, national, and international<br />

market economies until the late eighteenth century. Until then, merchants had relied<br />

on a variety of customs, documents, and instruments to stabilize, hedge, or attempt to<br />

fix the risks associated with bad investments and the potential of a party’s failure to perform<br />

as agreed. These ( juridically) non-enforceable instruments and practices included<br />

private forms of mercantile arbitration, the use of bills of exchange, bonds, and sealed<br />

agreements to govern business dealings—instruments that were rarely considered worthy<br />

evidence in cases of contractual breach by pre-eighteenth century courts, but which were<br />

able to exert pressure in the realms of banking and the market. See Ibid., 172.<br />

19. “[T]he moment at which courts focus on expectation damages rather than restitution<br />

or specific performance to give a remedy for nondelivery is precisely the time at which<br />

contract law begins to separate itself from property. It is at this point that contract begins<br />

to be understood not as transferring the title of particular property, but as creating an<br />

expected return. Contract then becomes an instrument for protecting against changes<br />

in supply and price in a market economy. The first recognition of expectation damages<br />

appeared after 1790 in both England and America in cases involving speculation in stock.<br />

. . . Between 1799 and 1810 a number of English cases applied the rule of expectation<br />

damages for failure to deliver stock on a rising market. In America the transformation<br />

occurred a decade earlier, in response to an active “futures” market for speculation in<br />

state securities which rapidly developed after the Revolutionary War in anticipation of<br />

the assumption of state debts by the new national government. The earliest cases allowing<br />

expectation damages on contracts of stock speculation appeared in South Carolina,<br />

Virginia, and Pennsylvania.” Ibid., 174.<br />

20. “The underlying logic of the attack on a substantive doctrine of consideration came to<br />

fruition in America with the great New York case of Seymour v. Delancey (1824), in<br />

which a sharply divided High Court of Errors reversed a decision of Chancellor Kent,<br />

who had refused to specifically enforce a land contract on the ground of gross inadequacy<br />

of consideration between the parties. ‘Every member of this Court,’ the majority opinion<br />

noted, ‘must be well aware how much property is held by contract; that purchases are<br />

constantly made upon speculation; that the value of real estate is fluctuating.’ The result<br />

was that there ‘exists an honest difference of opinion in regard to any bargain, as to its being<br />

a beneficial one, or not.’ The court held that only where the inadequacy of price was itself<br />

evidence of fraud would it interfere with the execution of private contracts.” Ibid., 179–180.<br />

21. On the history of corporate “personhood”, see Joshua Barkan, Corporate Sovereignty: Law<br />

and Governance under Capitalism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2013),<br />

Chapter 3, “Personhood.”<br />

22. “[C]ontractarian ideology above all expressed a market conception of legal relations.<br />

Wages were the carefully calibrated instrument by which supposedly equal parties<br />

would bargain to arrive at the proper “mix” of risk and wages. In such a world the old<br />

ideal of legal relations shaped by a normative standard of substantive justice could<br />

scarcely coexist. Since the only measure of justice was the parties’ own agreement, all<br />

preexisting legal duties were inevitably subordinated to the contract relation.” Horwitz,<br />

The Transformation of American Law, 209.<br />

23. “The doctrine of “assumption of risk” in workmen’s injury cases expressed the triumph<br />

of the contractarian ideology more completely than any other nineteenth century legal<br />

creation. It arose in an economywhich already had all but eradicated traces of an earlier<br />

model of normative relations between master and servants. And without the practice<br />

of enforcing preexisting moral duties, judges and jurists could no longer ascribe any<br />

purpose to legal obligations that were superior to the expressed “will” of the parties.<br />

As contract ideology thus emasculated all prior conceptions of substantive justice, equal<br />

bargaining power inevitably became established as the inarticulate major premise of all<br />

legal and economic analysis. The circle was completed; the law had come simply to ratify<br />

those forms of inequality that the market system produced.” Ibid., 210.<br />

24. “Since the authority of commercial custom could not easily be absorbed into the traditional<br />

category of ancient usage, Mansfield instead emphasized its universal character<br />

and its correspondence with the dictates of natural reason. It was, Mansfield frequently<br />

reiterated, not the law of any one country but of the entire civilized world. Proof of particular<br />

commercial customs, therefore, served only as evidence of universal mercantile<br />

custom that already had ripened into a rule of law.” Ibid., 189–90. “Once the subjective<br />

theory of contract had performed the function of enabling judges and jurists to destroy<br />

the connection between contract law and a conception of objective value, they felt free<br />

once again to revive an objective theory of contract and to reintroduce its intellectual<br />

companion, a conception of general mercantile custom.” Ibid., 196.<br />

25. “Courts, in essence, were developing a series of new doctrines designed to apply to<br />

large impersonal business dealings between commercially sophisticated insiders which,<br />

we have seen, were rapidly replacing the face-to-face transaction as the dominant mode<br />

of trade.” Ibid., 200.<br />

26. “Once contractual obligation was founded entirely on an arbitrary ‘meeting of minds,’<br />

it endowed the parties with a complete power to remake law. To the extent that it<br />

was seriously followed it made every contract a unique event depending only on the<br />

momentary intention of the parties. National markets, however, required uniformity and<br />

standardization, which inevitably entailed a sacrifice, at least in theory, of the individual’s<br />

power to contract. The emergence of the objective theory, then, is another measure of the<br />

influence of commercial interests in the shaping of American law. No longer finding it<br />

necessary to enter into battle against eighteenth century just price doctrines, they could<br />

devote their energies to establishing in the second half of the nineteenth century a system<br />

of objective rules necessary to assure legal certainty and predictability. And having<br />

destroyed most substantive grounds for evaluating the justice of exchange, they could<br />

elaborate a legal ideology of formalism, of which Williston was a leading exemplar, that<br />

could not only disguise gross disparities of bargaining power under a facade of neutral<br />

and formal rules of contract law but could also enforce commercial customs under the<br />

comforting technical rubric of ‘contract interpretation’.” Ibid., 200–201.<br />

27. Thorstein Bunde Veblen, Absentee Ownership. Business Enterprise in Recent Times:<br />

The Case of America 3rd ed. (New Brunswick: Transaction Publications, 2009 [1926]).<br />

See also: Adolf A. Berle, and Gardiner C. Means, The Modern Corporation & Private<br />

Property (New York: Macmillan, 1932).<br />

28. “[F]rom about the beginning of the twentieth century the preponderant nature of<br />

property has been changing again, and property is again beginning to be seen as a right<br />

to something; now, more often than not, a right to a revenue rather than a right to a<br />

specific material thing. . . . [T]he rise of the corporation as the dominant form of business<br />

enterprise has meant that the dominant form of property is the expectation of revenue.<br />

The market value of a modern corporation consists not of its plant and stocks of materials<br />

but of its presumed ability to produce a revenue for itself and its shareholders by its organization<br />

of skills and its manipulation of the market. Its value as a property is its ability to<br />

produce a revenue. The property its shareholders have is the right to a revenue from that<br />

ability.” Macpherson, Property, 8.<br />

146 147

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!