16.12.2012 Views

PROSPECT THEORY AND POLITICAL SCIENCE Jonathan Mercer

PROSPECT THEORY AND POLITICAL SCIENCE Jonathan Mercer

PROSPECT THEORY AND POLITICAL SCIENCE Jonathan Mercer

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

10 MERCER<br />

Emotion<br />

Although Kahneman & Tversky emphasized cognition, emotion is central to<br />

prospect theory. Actors do not consult utility; they experience it (Kahneman<br />

1994, Kahneman & Tversky 1984). As one decision theorist noted, “The effects<br />

of changes from reference points are feelings, or changes in hedonic states”<br />

(Read 2002, p. 471). “Experienced utility” captures the finding that we care more<br />

about recent changes in our welfare than we do about our total value position.<br />

We are not indifferent to our net assets, but what influences us most is the direction<br />

of change, whether it is a gain or a loss relative to some reference point.<br />

Emotion’s influence on decision making is thus fundamental to prospect theory<br />

and to political science more generally (Bueno de Mesquita & McDermott 2004,<br />

McDermott 2005). My subjective feelings of gain or loss influence my choices.<br />

Although greed is important and provides the inspiration in most rationalist treatments<br />

of self-interest (Hirschman 1977), other emotions, such as fear, anger, regret<br />

(Jervis 1992, McDermott 2004), panic, desperation (Welch 1993a), pride (Gries<br />

2004), desire for justice (Rabin 2002, Welch 1993b), or trust (<strong>Mercer</strong> 2005) may<br />

be equally important.<br />

Emotion is not merely a consequence of a frame but can be a source of framing.<br />

Farnham (1997) demonstrates that our feelings can cause us to reframe our<br />

choices which, in turn, can cause us to reverse our preferences. For example, President<br />

Franklin D. Roosevelt viewed war in Europe as undesirable but as having no<br />

direct impact on the United States, and thus he opposed U.S. intervention. As the<br />

1938 Munich crisis unfolded, Roosevelt’s view remained constant. He expected<br />

war and he expected the Allies to win. The crisis provided no new information<br />

about German intentions, the dangers for Europe, or the risks for the United States.<br />

In the midst of the crisis, Roosevelt realized that war was no longer highly probable<br />

but certain and he began to feel emotionally engaged in the crisis: “as the president<br />

became increasingly affected by the emotional impact of the news from Europe, he<br />

began to experience the prospect of war as a loss” (Farnham 1992, p. 229). Bombarded<br />

by frantic and emotionally charged messages about impending war in Europe,<br />

Roosevelt reframed the war as a loss to the United States. Farnham confirms<br />

the general psychological insight that often preferences are not prior to a choice but<br />

are constructed during a choice (Shafir & LeBoeuf 2002). We figure out our preferences<br />

as we go along, which means they are neither stable nor hierarchical. It is<br />

not abstract ideas, dry information, or heuristics that explain President Roosevelt’s<br />

domain, but feelings, mood, and the affect-laden reports of imminent war.<br />

Welch (1993b) finds additional evidence that feelings influence how we frame<br />

our prospects. Although Welch is not a prospect theorist—in this work injustice,<br />

not loss aversion, drives risky behavior 2 —he notes that his approach provides clues<br />

for how actors will frame their choices. Welch argues that feelings of injustice,<br />

defined as a perceived discrepancy between entitlements and benefits, explains<br />

2 A new book (Welch 2005) uses insights from prospect theory but arrived too late for review.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!