16.12.2012 Views

PROSPECT THEORY AND POLITICAL SCIENCE Jonathan Mercer

PROSPECT THEORY AND POLITICAL SCIENCE Jonathan Mercer

PROSPECT THEORY AND POLITICAL SCIENCE Jonathan Mercer

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

14 MERCER<br />

variance in outcome. Even access to primary sources might not resolve the debate<br />

over the riskiness of an actor’s policy. For example, was President Eisenhower<br />

pursuing a risk-averse strategy in the 1956 Suez crisis (McDermott 1998) or merely<br />

a rational strategy (Richardson 1993)? This problem, like many, is as serious as one<br />

wishes to make it. Observers, like actors, will sometimes differ in their assessment<br />

of risk, and this makes prospect theory difficult to test.<br />

LOSS-AVERSION EFFECT OR RATIONAL DECISION? Loss aversion can be rational. A<br />

wild gamble to avoid a loss can be rational if one has nothing left to lose, or if<br />

one holds certain beliefs and desires that make that gamble rational. Goemans<br />

illustrates the first type of rational gamble: when one has nothing left to lose (see<br />

also Downs & Rocke 1995, pp. 56–75). Goemans (2000) suggests that states persist<br />

in losing war efforts in an attempt to escape domestic political punishment for<br />

failure. Semirepressive, moderately exclusionary regimes will gamble that through<br />

luck or a new strategy they can win a war. For example, the German leadership in<br />

1917 felt their prospects for victory in World War I were grim and for this reason<br />

they embraced unrestricted submarine warfare. “The German leadership was now<br />

willing to try a very risky strategy because they estimated that was the only way to<br />

achieve the terms of settlement necessary to stave off punishment...” (Goemans<br />

2000, p. 97). Although the risky bet on naval warfare did not maximize the expected<br />

utility of the German people, German leaders knew that any defeat would (at a<br />

minimum) end their careers and usher in a new social order. (Of course, if leaders<br />

know that they cannot survive even small losses, then these leaders should not start<br />

wars that they know they might lose.) Goemans’s careful analysis demonstrates<br />

that actors in semirepressive and moderately exclusionary regimes can be both<br />

rational and risk acceptant in the domain of loss.<br />

Distinguishing rational from irrational gambles demands testing alternative explanations<br />

against empirical cases. Policy makers confronting important decisions<br />

should approximate rational decision making. Often they do not. For example, in<br />

a study with a contemporary echo, Richardson (1993) examined British decision<br />

making during the Suez crisis to test prospect theory and rational choice models<br />

of decision making (pp. 176, 183–185, 187):<br />

[T]he process bore little or no relation to rational norms. There was no systematic<br />

evaluation of options or calculation of their costs and consequences.<br />

Having resolved to fight, British leaders, for their part, simply discounted all<br />

risks attendant on that decision.... They made no effort to marshal international<br />

support for their action.... No serious effort was made to establish the<br />

financial costs of anticipated military operations.... Moreover, the initial estimates<br />

that were made were extraordinarily optimistic.... Although Treasury<br />

officials warned of the dangers of “going it alone,” the chancellor and the<br />

Egypt Committee remained undeterred.... [T]here appears to have been very<br />

little planning for future developments once Nasser was toppled; only a casual<br />

assumption that he would be replaced by a more compliant leader.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!