02.02.2021 Views

The 1451 Review (Volume 1) 2021

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

This being said, the DIVUM does not only take the nature of objects as a

justification for their ownership, but also answers the concerns raised by their

provenance. Stating that they ‘were acquired under conditions that are not comparable

with current ones’, (ICOM et al. 2004) the signatories ignore the question of colonial

lootings and coerced sales. ‘The past is the past’, as declared by Montebello (2009: 69)

and under the colonial domination, these acquisitions, not matter how violent, were

legal (Savoy & Sarr 2018: 123). However, this seems profoundly unsatisfactory. ‘To

justify the plunder of the past based on a time period, and to claim that it differs from

the current or recent plunder, is seen … as an insult bordering on historical mischief’

(Abungu 2008: 37). We are not questioning the legal ownership of these objects, but

the ethical basis for their possession. Hence this argument is irrelevant to the

discussion and cannot legitimise European museums’ holding of, for example, Ataï’s

skull or the Benin Bronzes. Neither the DIVUM signatories’ claim of ownership based

on the objects’ universal nature nor on their legal provenance is satisfactory. This

questions the idea that we could really base ownership claims solely on either the

meaning of an object or its provenance. To answer this, I will explore two other

examples.

Firstly, we should wonder whether the nature and significance of an object alone

can challenge a museum’s ownership. Objects have a plurality of meanings and

identities - which one matters the most when it comes to deciding who is the righteous

owner? The University of Aberdeen museum came with a very interesting answer to

this issue. Confronted with multiple repatriation requests, they created a procedure to

help a panel decide whether or not an object should be repatriated (Curtis 2006: 46).

Its goal is to evaluate both ‘the signification of the item to the claimant and to the

University [and] the consequences of return to the claimant or retention by the

University’ (Curtis 2006: 46). Although this procedure does mention the provenance

of the object elsewhere, it is not the basis on which the panel will judge the request.

Instead, it is the significance of the object, its meaning, both in the past and in the

future that is most important. Repatriation of culturally-sensitive items often

stimulates a revival and renewal of cultural identities that were disappearing, as was

the case with the repatriation to the Haida of 466 of their ancestors remains. For the

Haida, this return led to the transfer and rebirth of carving skills, the creation of new

burial rituals, an increase in research around the items as well as new intergenerational

connexions (Simpson 2008: 71-74). As illustrated here, repatriation of

significant items can bring extraordinarily positive outcomes to communities. The

ownership change sometimes leads to such revival of identities and histories that had

been suppressed by colonisation and the systematic collecting of material culture.

Comparing the present and future meanings of an object to both the source community

and the museum then sometimes provides a great basis to judge who should own it and

whether or not we should operate a transfer of ownership.

Savoy and Sarr’s repatriation guidelines, on the opposite, focus on the history of

the object. This can be explained by the fact that their work is centred more around

questions of justice for historical wounds linked to lootings than on the pragmatic

outcomes of a repatriation. They conclude their research by declaring that any object

acquired during military or scientific missions, where there is no positive evidence of

‘free, equitable and documented consent’, (Savoy & Sarr: 105-106) needs to be

repatriated. This covers examples of lootings and coerced sales that I have explored

earlier in this paper and that would not always be covered by Aberdeen’s guidelines.

Indeed, the University’s guidance does not take into account the fact that, in certain

cases such as Ataï’s skull, repatriation is also a highly symbolic recognition of past

violence. In the same way, Savoy and Sarr do not really take into account the future

material positive results for source communities that can by themselves justify

repatriation.

This suggests that, to assess whether a museum is entitled to keep an object or

not, our judgement needs to include both its provenance, problematic or not, and the

possible outcomes for both the institution and the source community. I am convinced

that this is possible, and that it will open the way for museums to acknowledge and

teach the history of their collections, even when this is painful. It is time to change our

vision on museum’s categorisation of objects. This will also finally allow us to

understand how these objects can still help source communities to forge new

postcolonial identities. The museum, and more precisely the so-called ethnographic

museum, will have to evolve to accommodate the plurality of meanings and voices that

come with the objects they exhibit.

72 73

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!