10.01.2013 Views

Kevin Cole - University of San Diego

Kevin Cole - University of San Diego

Kevin Cole - University of San Diego

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Because the Framers embraced multiple<br />

values, Breyer needs to explain what justifies<br />

the preeminence <strong>of</strong> political participation,<br />

other than the fact that he deems it<br />

more important. But Breyer provides no<br />

explanation.<br />

Similar problems arise when Breyer<br />

moves to interpreting particular constitutional<br />

clauses. Breyer believes that judges<br />

should focus on the general purposes <strong>of</strong><br />

provisions. But the general purposes <strong>of</strong> a<br />

clause are <strong>of</strong>ten highly disputed matters,<br />

as there is no clear way <strong>of</strong> determining<br />

what these purposes were. For example,<br />

when discussing the constitutionality <strong>of</strong><br />

affirmative action, Breyer claims that the<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> the Equal Protection Clause<br />

(and the Civil War Amendments generally)<br />

was to allow blacks to “participate<br />

fully with equal rights in the democratic<br />

political community.”<br />

But the Equal Protection Clause is at<br />

least as plausibly viewed as having a different<br />

purpose—either establishing colorblind<br />

laws or guaranteeing to minorities<br />

full civil rights (but not special political<br />

rights)—neither <strong>of</strong> which would support<br />

his justification for affirmative action.<br />

Again, Breyer does not explain why his<br />

chosen purpose is the correct one. (And<br />

neither would his opponents using the<br />

very same rationale.)<br />

Breyer also argues that one should determine<br />

whether a law promotes or retards<br />

these general purposes based on its modern<br />

real world consequences, not on what<br />

the Framers believed would have furthered<br />

their purposes. But the consequences<br />

<strong>of</strong> laws are hotly contested.<br />

While Breyer assumes that affirmative<br />

action will allow blacks to more fully participate<br />

in political life, opponents <strong>of</strong> affirmative<br />

action credibly maintain that it<br />

renders blacks less influential by diminishing<br />

their accomplishments and creating<br />

greater racial animosity. Once again,<br />

Breyer gives no reason why his view<br />

should prevail, except that he, naturally,<br />

thinks it is the correct view.<br />

Breyer’s focus on general purposes allows<br />

judges to select the values that the<br />

Constitution furthers and his focus on<br />

modern real world consequences allows<br />

them to assert how laws will in fact operate.<br />

With control over the facts and values,<br />

Breyer’s “active” judge has virtually boundless<br />

authority over the Constitution’s content.<br />

Thus, it is no surprise that Breyer’s<br />

tour through the Constitution—from<br />

affirmative action, to campaign finance, to<br />

federalism, to separation <strong>of</strong> church and<br />

state—only reaches destinations that<br />

Breyer appears to endorse politically.<br />

Interestingly, Breyer’s tour fails to make<br />

one important stop—his majority opinion<br />

for the Court in Stenberg v. Carhart, which<br />

struck down a ban on partial birth abortions.<br />

One might argue that Stenberg is<br />

inconsistent with Breyer’s active liberty<br />

purposivist approach, because the opinion<br />

protects what seems to be a personal decision<br />

unrelated to political participation.<br />

But perhaps Breyer can avoid this inconsistency.<br />

Breyer might argue that terminating<br />

pregnancies is necessary for women to<br />

work and thereby to participate fully in<br />

politics. Alternatively, Breyer never says<br />

that active liberty is the only important<br />

value. So he might argue that another purpose<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Fourteenth Amendment is to<br />

protect individual rights, which in the<br />

modern world requires giving those rights<br />

a modern interpretation. In other words,<br />

Breyer’s approach might be so flexible that<br />

there is no decision, including Stenberg, that<br />

it can’t be made consistent with.<br />

Having articulated this extremely flexible<br />

interpretive approach, one would expect<br />

that Breyer would defend it against<br />

objections. It is here where Breyer’s book is<br />

particularly unsuccessful. One major problem<br />

with the vast discretion that Breyer<br />

confers on judges is that it is inconsistent<br />

with the active liberty that is the primary<br />

concern <strong>of</strong> his book. Judicial activism is<br />

generally thought to undermine democracy,<br />

because it deprives the people <strong>of</strong><br />

their ability to set policy through their<br />

representatives—either through statutes or<br />

through constitutional amendments. Even<br />

if a statute or constitutional provision is<br />

currently unpopular and needs revision,<br />

the Court’s decision to update it will deprive<br />

the people <strong>of</strong> the opportunity to do<br />

the updating and they are likely to update<br />

it in a different way than the Court does.<br />

Far from defending the broad discretion<br />

he would give to judges, Breyer seems to<br />

be in denial about it. Breyer actually claims<br />

that, as compared to originalism (which<br />

tellingly he mistakenly refers to as “literalism”),<br />

his approach does not significantly<br />

increase the subjectivity <strong>of</strong> judicial decisions.<br />

Given the enormous power that<br />

Breyer confers on judges, this is astounding.<br />

Moving almost into the realm <strong>of</strong> selfparody,<br />

Breyer illustrates the alleged<br />

restraints on judges with his opinions from<br />

recent Establishment Clause cases. In two<br />

opinions that were so subjective that no<br />

other justice agreed with both <strong>of</strong> them,<br />

Breyer concluded that the Ten Commandments<br />

could be placed on the grounds <strong>of</strong><br />

the Texas State Capital, but not inside a<br />

Kentucky state courthouse.<br />

It is one thing to argue that judicial discretion<br />

is necessary, because the political<br />

process suffers from maladies and therefore<br />

more powerful judges are needed.<br />

That position, although mistaken, at least<br />

confronts the issues forthrightly. It is another<br />

thing for Breyer to deny that his<br />

activist approach empowers courts and<br />

to make that approach part <strong>of</strong> his argument<br />

for furthering political participation.<br />

Breyer’s arguments here suggest that he either<br />

is oblivious to the fact that he is imposing<br />

his will on the nation or does not<br />

believe that he seriously needs to justify<br />

his actions. In neither case are his actions<br />

worthy <strong>of</strong> a Supreme Court Justice.<br />

Originally published on December 19, 2005, in<br />

TCS Daily.<br />

ADVOCATE USD LAW / 23:1 ❖ 19

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!