02.02.2013 Views

Tools and Techniques in Modal Logic Marcus Kracht II ...

Tools and Techniques in Modal Logic Marcus Kracht II ...

Tools and Techniques in Modal Logic Marcus Kracht II ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

1.4. General <strong>Logic</strong> 21<br />

the relation Σ ⊢Cn ϕ def<strong>in</strong>ed by Σ ⊢Cn ϕ iff ϕ ∈ Cn(Σ) is a consequence relation, that<br />

is to say, 〈L, ⊢Cn〉 is a logic. Moreover, two dist<strong>in</strong>ct consequence operations determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ct consequence relations <strong>and</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct consequence relations give rise to<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ct consequence operations.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, call any set of the form Σ ⊢ a theory of ⊢. By (trs.), theories are closed<br />

under consequence, that is, Σ ⊢ not only conta<strong>in</strong>s all consequences of Σ but also all<br />

of its own consequences as well. We may therefore say that the theories of ⊢ co<strong>in</strong>cide<br />

with the deductively closed sets. Given ⊢, the follow<strong>in</strong>g can be said about<br />

⊢–theories.<br />

(top.) L is a ⊢–theory.<br />

(<strong>in</strong>t.) If Ti, i ∈ I, are ⊢–theories, so is � 〈Ti : i ∈ I〉.<br />

(sub.) If T is a ⊢–theory, σ a substitution then<br />

σ −1 [T] = {ϕ : ϕ σ ∈ T} is a ⊢–theory.<br />

(cmp.) If Ti, i ∈ I, is an ascend<strong>in</strong>g cha<strong>in</strong> of ⊢–theories then<br />

� 〈Ti : i ∈ I〉 is a ⊢–theory.<br />

Aga<strong>in</strong>, the correspondence is exact. Any collection T of subsets of L satisfy<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(top.), (<strong>in</strong>t.), (sub.) <strong>and</strong> (cmp.) def<strong>in</strong>es a consequence operation Σ ↦→ Σ ⊢ by Σ ⊢ =<br />

� 〈T : T ∈ T, T ⊇ Σ〉 which satisfies (ext.), (mon.), (trs.), (sub.) <strong>and</strong> (cmp.). The<br />

correspondence is biunique. Different consequence operations yield different sets of<br />

theories <strong>and</strong> different collections of theories yield different consequence operations.<br />

The theories of a logic form a lattice. This lattice is algebraic if the consequence<br />

relation is f<strong>in</strong>itary. The converse does not hold; this has been shown by Burghard<br />

Herrmann <strong>and</strong> Frank Wolter [103].<br />

Exercise 8. Give a detailed proof of Theorem 1.4.3.<br />

Exercise 9. Let R be a set of axioms or 1–ary rules. Show that ∆ ⊢ R ϕ iff there exists<br />

a δ ∈ ∆ such that δ ⊢ R ϕ.<br />

Exercise 10. Show that every consistent logic is conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a Post–complete logic.<br />

H<strong>in</strong>t. You need Zorn’s Lemma here. For readers unfamiliar with it, we will prove<br />

later Tukey’s Lemma, which will give rise to a very short proof for f<strong>in</strong>itary logics.<br />

Exercise 11. Show that <strong>in</strong> 2–valued logic<br />

ϕ1 ↔ ψ1; ϕ2 ↔ ψ2 ⊢ ϕ1 ∧ ϕ2 ↔ ψ1 ∧ ψ2<br />

ϕ1 ↔ ψ1; ϕ2 ↔ ψ2 ⊢ ϕ1 ∨ ϕ2 ↔ ψ1 ∨ ψ2<br />

ϕ ↔ ψ ⊢ ¬ϕ ↔ ¬ψ<br />

Thus if ϕ ≡ ψ is def<strong>in</strong>ed by ⊢ ϕ ↔ ψ, then ≡ is a congruence relation. What is the<br />

card<strong>in</strong>ality of a congruence class? H<strong>in</strong>t. We assume that we have ℵ0 many propositional<br />

variables. Show that all congruence classes must have equal card<strong>in</strong>ality.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!