05.04.2013 Views

Screen Memory - Department of English

Screen Memory - Department of English

Screen Memory - Department of English

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Screen</strong> <strong>Memory</strong><br />

At just the moment Proust was seeking salvation in<br />

hypermnesia, Freud was projecting memory as a<br />

consummate and perpetual trickster that transforms<br />

everything in accordance with needs <strong>of</strong> which we<br />

are not aware.<br />

Terdiman<br />

Freud deserves a crucial place in this survey because he<br />

severely destabilized classical notions <strong>of</strong> memory. Freud’s<br />

theorizing about memory was itself, Terdiman suggests, a response<br />

to memory crisis: “when memory fails or we fear its failure, we<br />

devise hermeneutics to remedy that gap”:<br />

When, in dreams, in parapraxes, in hysteria, and in the<br />

other transference neuroses, the present unexpectedly<br />

becomes inexplicable on its own terms, Freud discovered<br />

he could productively invoke the covert persistence <strong>of</strong><br />

1


the past and the determinations <strong>of</strong> a memory whose<br />

extent and intensity no one before him had ever<br />

conceived as so ubiquitous or so sovereign (1993:247).<br />

More than creative memory, more, even, than the confusion <strong>of</strong><br />

memory and fantasy, Freud tried to demonstrate dynamics <strong>of</strong><br />

fabrication in the psyche that could cunningly duplicate the<br />

effects <strong>of</strong> memory (even duplicating its stamp <strong>of</strong> authenticity).<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> was a “hypocritical counterfeiter,” a version <strong>of</strong><br />

Descarte’s malin génie (Terdiman 1993:292). <strong>Memory</strong> was not<br />

natural or original, but a species <strong>of</strong> calculated after-effect.<br />

Freud also textualized memory: it was not transparent but layered<br />

and coded. A strict believer in the indelibility <strong>of</strong> memory, he<br />

also made memory much more inaccessible, subject to a fierce<br />

dynamic <strong>of</strong> desire; what counted as memory for him was outside <strong>of</strong><br />

or under the storehouse.<br />

The instrument <strong>of</strong> this undoing was an entity Freud called<br />

the screen memory, signifying that the memory in question was not<br />

a memory at all but a screen for an inaccessible memory. To the<br />

rememberer, the movie playing on the screen feels natural. The<br />

clue to its falsity is a surface paradox: that it is really quite<br />

insignificant as memories go, but held on to as if it were<br />

significant.<br />

<strong>Screen</strong> memories are usually childhood memories carrying<br />

pleasant reminiscences. Not only are screen memories pleasant,<br />

2


they also tell a relatively insignificant story; and this is the<br />

screening designed to protect their catastrophic importance. Like<br />

so many items in Freud’s mental universe, they must be read<br />

through their opposites; in this case: after childhood,<br />

unpleasant, significant. The subject <strong>of</strong> memory is thus a huge<br />

enigma for Freud.<br />

After finishing the essay, Freud told Wilhelm Fliess that he<br />

had liked the paper “immensely” while producing it, “which does<br />

not augur well for its future” (1985:351). Approaching the<br />

subject in a spirit <strong>of</strong> common-sense rationalism, he assumes that<br />

memories are retained and reproduced in direct proportion to<br />

their importance. In the case <strong>of</strong> childhood memories this law<br />

seems to be reversed, and Freud pretends to be astonished by<br />

these “mnemic images, whose innocence makes them so mysterious”:<br />

“I feel surprised at forgetting something important; and I feel<br />

even more surprised, perhaps, at remembering something apparently<br />

indifferent” (3.306 and 303). We find, Freud says, such<br />

displacement strange to contemplate.<br />

<strong>Screen</strong> memories, then, work to conceal “an unsuspected<br />

wealth <strong>of</strong> meaning . . . behind their apparent innocence”: “They<br />

relate to [repressed] impressions <strong>of</strong> a sexual and aggressive<br />

nature, and no doubt also to early injuries to the ego<br />

1<br />

(narcissistic mortifications)” (3.309 and 23.74). Freud<br />

characterized them as “‘mnemic residues’ which take on a<br />

3


compulsive quality as they act to protect the subject from<br />

repressed trauma or desire” (19.20 and Furnari).<br />

These memories are <strong>of</strong> course not completely fabricated; they<br />

incorporate actual memory-traces. Each <strong>of</strong> the details that makes<br />

up the representation, Serge Leclaire states, “is evidently<br />

borrowed from a different context and assembled into the<br />

uncertain composite image” (78). <strong>Screen</strong> memories are apparent<br />

memories <strong>of</strong> one's earliest years that are actually formed during<br />

other periods <strong>of</strong> emotional arousal. The retrogressive screen<br />

memory is constructed at the site <strong>of</strong> a later event, out <strong>of</strong><br />

psychic events from many periods <strong>of</strong> our lives, and organized into<br />

a strong, clear memory: “In these [later] periods <strong>of</strong> arousal, the<br />

childhood memories did not, as people are accustomed to say,<br />

emerge; they were formed at that time. And a number <strong>of</strong> motives,<br />

with no concern for historical accuracy, had a part in forming<br />

them, as well as in the selection <strong>of</strong> the memories themselves"<br />

(3.322).<br />

In 1899, Freud proclaimed a law <strong>of</strong> childhood amnesia which<br />

stipulated that memory does not function until the fourth or<br />

fifth year and if a memory carrying an earlier date stamp does<br />

arise, it is invariably false. This is not due to fading memory<br />

or psychological development, but blockage (distinguishing, as he<br />

says so, between a memory and a memory-trace). <strong>Memory</strong> is, in<br />

fact, operative much earlier:<br />

4


No one calls in question the fact that the experiences<br />

<strong>of</strong> the earliest years <strong>of</strong> our childhood leave<br />

ineradicable traces in the depths <strong>of</strong> our minds. If,<br />

however, we seek in our memories to ascertain what were<br />

the impressions that were destined to influence us to<br />

the ends <strong>of</strong> our lives, the outcome is either nothing at<br />

all or a relatively small number <strong>of</strong> isolated<br />

recollections which are <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>of</strong> dubious or enigmatic<br />

importance (3.303). 2<br />

By way <strong>of</strong> contrast, Vico had claimed that children have<br />

exceptionally strong memories, and Ribot felt that “The earliest<br />

memories are the most secure and solid <strong>of</strong> all” (Roth 1989:56).<br />

Diderot had simply declared that “The time <strong>of</strong> childhood is the<br />

time <strong>of</strong> memory” (Poulet 198). And certainly no childhood amnesia<br />

operates in Proust when he is blessed with the receipt <strong>of</strong> his<br />

entire childhood in Combray.<br />

Like most entities in Freud’s mental universe, screen<br />

memories both conceal and express past meaning. They are a double<br />

formation: “Two psychical forces are concerned in bringing about<br />

memories <strong>of</strong> this sort. One <strong>of</strong> these forces takes the importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the experience as a motive for seeking to remember it, while<br />

the other--a resistance--tries to prevent any such preference<br />

from being shown” (3.306-7).<br />

In addition to pleasure and triviality, screen memories are<br />

5


also characterized by an unusual sharpness <strong>of</strong> image and produced<br />

in a register <strong>of</strong> clarity--“too clearly, one is inclined to say”<br />

(3.305). In the analysis <strong>of</strong> the specific dream behind his 1899<br />

essay on this subject, Freud exaggerates the qualities <strong>of</strong><br />

pleasure and clarity, convicting the unconscious <strong>of</strong> being a comic<br />

artist. Of the dandelion episode at the center <strong>of</strong> the memory, he<br />

writes,<br />

Now what is there in this occurrence to justify the<br />

expenditure <strong>of</strong> memory which it has occasioned me . . .<br />

. Altogether, there seems to me something not quite<br />

right about this scene. The yellow <strong>of</strong> the flowers is a<br />

disproportionately prominent element in the situation<br />

as a whole, and the nice taste <strong>of</strong> the bread seems to me<br />

exaggerated in an almost hallucinatory fashion. I<br />

cannot help being reminded <strong>of</strong> some pictures that I once<br />

saw in a burlesque exhibition. Certain portions <strong>of</strong><br />

these pictures, and <strong>of</strong> course the most inappropriate<br />

ones, instead <strong>of</strong> being painted, were built up in three<br />

dimensions–-for instance, the ladies’ bustles (3.311-<br />

312).<br />

The memory is one <strong>of</strong> the subject at play in a meadow <strong>of</strong><br />

dandelions with a boy and girl cousin, John and Pauline, his<br />

half-brother Emmanuel’s children. At a nearby cottage “two women<br />

are standing chatting busily, a peasant-woman with a handkerchief<br />

6


on her head and a children's nurse.”<br />

We are picking the yellow flowers and each <strong>of</strong> us is<br />

holding a bunch <strong>of</strong> flowers we have already picked. The<br />

little girl has the best bunch; and, as though by<br />

mutual agreement, we--the two boys--fall on her and<br />

snatch away her flowers. She runs up the meadow in<br />

tears and as a consolation the peasant-woman gives her<br />

a big piece <strong>of</strong> black bread. Hardly have we seen this<br />

than we throw the flowers away, hurry to the cottage,<br />

and ask to be given some bread too. And we are in fact<br />

given some; the peasant-woman cuts the loaf with a long<br />

knife. In my memory the bread tastes quite delicious--<br />

and at that point the scene breaks <strong>of</strong>f (3.311).<br />

Freud distinguished three types <strong>of</strong> screen memory: an early<br />

memory screening an equally early experience, a late memory<br />

screening a childhood event [the “pushed forward” variety], and<br />

retrogressive screen memory, in which a childhood memory screens<br />

a later concern (3.320). Freud suggested that C. F. Meyer's novel<br />

The Monk's Wedding<br />

magnificently illustrates the process occurring in<br />

later years in the formation <strong>of</strong> fantasies . . . . a new<br />

experience is in fantasy projected back into the past<br />

so that the new persons become aligned with the old<br />

ones, who become their prototypes. The mirror image <strong>of</strong><br />

7


the present is seen in the fantasied past, which then<br />

prophetically becomes the present (1985:320).<br />

The 1899 essay is almost wholly concerned with this third<br />

type: an innocent childhood memory that was ignited by some later<br />

trauma and a substitute memory <strong>of</strong> childhood composed to hold that<br />

later trauma in its coils. Freud’s translator James Strachey<br />

found this emphasis to be a “curious thing,” since “the type <strong>of</strong><br />

screen memory mainly considered in the present paper . . . almost<br />

disappears” from the psychoanalytic record, to be replaced by a<br />

second type, the “pushed forward” memory (3.302). The second type<br />

<strong>of</strong> screen memory soon comes to be regarded as the regular type,<br />

and it is the only type <strong>of</strong> screen memory that Freud deals with in<br />

The Psychopathology <strong>of</strong> Everyday Life only two years later. 3<br />

Why did Freud feature only one <strong>of</strong> three types <strong>of</strong> screen<br />

memories in this essay and why was this choice almost immediately<br />

cancelled in (and by) the development <strong>of</strong> psychoanalysis? The<br />

answer seems obvious: with the abandonment <strong>of</strong> the seduction<br />

theory in 1897 and the development <strong>of</strong> a theory <strong>of</strong> infant<br />

sexuality (by 1899), the period <strong>of</strong> early childhood became the<br />

only period in which serious repression occurred and thus the<br />

period whose memories had to be most rigorously screened by<br />

memories <strong>of</strong> the “pushed forward” variety. 4<br />

The subject <strong>of</strong> the 1899 essay, is fully in possession <strong>of</strong> his<br />

childhood memories, or so he believes:<br />

8


I have at my disposal a fair number <strong>of</strong> early memories<br />

<strong>of</strong> childhood which I can date with great certainty . .<br />

. all these memories <strong>of</strong> mine relate to my birthplace<br />

and therefore date from my second and third years. They<br />

are mostly short scenes, but they are very well<br />

preserved and furnished with every detail <strong>of</strong> sense-<br />

perception, in complete contrast to my memories <strong>of</strong><br />

adult years, which are entirely lacking in the visual<br />

element (3.309).<br />

Freud is the patient in fact if not in behavior; this therapeutic<br />

transcription was quasi-autobiographical.<br />

The patient soon comes to know that the experience<br />

registered by this memory never occurred. All the analyst has to<br />

do to dispel it is ask whether this memory had recurred<br />

“periodically since his childhood, or whether it had perhaps<br />

emerged at some later time,” and the patient immediately knows<br />

that this childhood memory never occurred in his earlier years<br />

(3.312). He can, however, identify its later trigger, “the<br />

occasion which led to my recovering this and many other<br />

recollections <strong>of</strong> my earliest childhood”: a return visit to<br />

Frieburg at seventeen where he nourished a secret love for<br />

Gisella Fluss, the fifteen-year old daughter <strong>of</strong> the family with<br />

whom he had previously stayed (3.312-23). He then recalls a<br />

second “occasion” three years later when he again saw the two<br />

9


playmates <strong>of</strong> the childhood memory-scene. There was no love on<br />

this occasion: he was at the University, “a slave to my books. I<br />

had nothing left over for my cousin.” He believed, however, that<br />

his father and uncle had made a plan for him to marry the girl<br />

(3.314).<br />

The childhood memory emerged on the second occasion,<br />

attached to two experiences: desire for Gisela and shame over the<br />

financial crisis that had originally caused his father to<br />

relocate the family. Freud tells his alter ego that he “projected<br />

the two phantasies on to one another and made a childhood memory<br />

<strong>of</strong> them. The element about the alpine flowers is as it were a<br />

stamp giving the date <strong>of</strong> manufacture. I can assure you that<br />

people <strong>of</strong>ten construct such things unconsciously––almost like<br />

works <strong>of</strong> fiction” (3.315). Freud’s later experience <strong>of</strong> certain<br />

yellow flowers in the Alps had helped to trigger this childhood<br />

recollection <strong>of</strong> the meadow scene with its dandelions when he was<br />

aged three and still in Freiburg. 5<br />

Do screen memories connect us to our childhood in any way?<br />

Freud hesitates among various answers. At times he is positive<br />

that there is a connection: "Not only some but all <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

essential from childhood has been retained in these memories . .<br />

. . They represent the forgotten years <strong>of</strong> childhood” (12.148). In<br />

the essay, Freud <strong>of</strong>fered a compromise position:<br />

You have accepted my assertion that every suppressed<br />

10


phantasy <strong>of</strong> this kind tends to slip away into a<br />

childhood scene. But suppose now that this cannot occur<br />

unless there is a memory-trace the content <strong>of</strong> which<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers the phantasy a point <strong>of</strong> contact–-comes, as it<br />

were, half way to meet it . . . . So the phantasy does<br />

not coincide completely with the childhood scene. It is<br />

only based on it at certain points. That argues in<br />

favor <strong>of</strong> the childhood memory being genuine (3.318-19).<br />

Freud resists concluding that screen memories are false but,<br />

in his vacillations, thoroughly undermines the validity <strong>of</strong><br />

childhood memory. The final sentences <strong>of</strong> the essay suggest that<br />

there is no such memory, only screen memories projected back into<br />

a mythical childhood: “The raw material <strong>of</strong> memory-traces out <strong>of</strong><br />

which [the screen memory] was forged remains unknown to us in its<br />

original form.” And the recognition <strong>of</strong> this fact, he concludes,<br />

"must diminish the distinction we have drawn between screen<br />

memories and other memories derived from our childhood." Freud<br />

ends the essay with a radical challenge to the integrity <strong>of</strong> early<br />

memories: “It may indeed be questioned whether we have any<br />

memories at all from our childhood: memories relating to our<br />

childhood may be all that we possess. Our childhood memories show<br />

us our earliest years not as they were but as they appeared at<br />

the later periods when the memories were aroused” (3.322).<br />

In an 1898 letter to Fliess, Freud had declared childhood to<br />

11


e constitutionally mantled in forgetfulness because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

crucial work that is done in the “prehistoric period <strong>of</strong> life,”<br />

the constitution <strong>of</strong> our curiously angular psychology. Childhood<br />

is “the source <strong>of</strong> the unconscious and alone contains the<br />

aetiology <strong>of</strong> all the psychoneuroses, the period normally<br />

characterized by an amnesia analogous to hysterical amnesia”<br />

(1.274).<br />

Freud’s conclusions are confirmed by “Diverse and wide-<br />

ranging studies” that agree<br />

that childhood amnesia for most events before the age<br />

<strong>of</strong> four or five is universal . . . . True, most <strong>of</strong> us<br />

possess a set <strong>of</strong> internal pictures <strong>of</strong> those early<br />

times. But these pictures seem to fall into several<br />

classes: (a) memories stimulated or created by photos<br />

or family lore which may or may not be our memories;<br />

(b) frightening or otherwise intense or traumatic<br />

experiences which seem to be recallable due to the<br />

sheer impact certain events had on our lives; and (c)<br />

so-called "screen" and "telescoped" memories, which are<br />

the most common memories <strong>of</strong> early childhood (Hedges<br />

15).<br />

The second category is presumably the “seduction,” which Freud is<br />

in the process <strong>of</strong> abandoning. 6<br />

James Strachey noted that the concept <strong>of</strong> "screen memories"<br />

12


was closely related to other psychoanalytic concerns, other<br />

“problems concerning the operation <strong>of</strong> memory and its distortions,<br />

the importance and raison d’être <strong>of</strong> phantasies, the amnesia<br />

covering our early years, and, behind all this, infantile<br />

sexuality” (3.301). It also resembles other psychoanalytic<br />

formations, like the symptom, the fetish, nächtraglichkeit, and<br />

the dream.<br />

Like the symptom, the screen memory is produced by a<br />

compromise between the thrust <strong>of</strong> repressed contents and the ego’s<br />

defense against them, a substitute formation that both obscures<br />

and reproduces the original content. Freud claimed the fetish to<br />

be a “screen memory,” a “remnant and precipitate” that conceals<br />

“a submerged and forgotten phase <strong>of</strong> sexual development” (7.154).<br />

Nächtraglichkeit describes the ways in which an incomprehensible<br />

or traumatic infantile experience is nonetheless somehow retained<br />

unconsciously and reactivated as screen memory at a later time in<br />

a different context: “the delay which is in the beginning”<br />

Derrida called it (1978:203). Nächtraglichkeit is the mechanism<br />

for “pushing back” that produces the screen memory discussed in<br />

the essay. In “Recollecting, Repeating and Working Through”<br />

(1914), Freud stated that screen memories represent the forgotten<br />

years <strong>of</strong> childhood “as adequately as the manifest content <strong>of</strong> a<br />

dream represents the dream-thoughts" (148). The dream is another<br />

formation analogous to the screen memory; made out <strong>of</strong> memory but<br />

13


passing as something else. 7<br />

The falsification <strong>of</strong> the past produced in screen memories<br />

plays its part in the construction <strong>of</strong> subjectivity (or, as Lacan<br />

would have it, “resubjectified” through the “mnemonic<br />

catastrophe” <strong>of</strong> nächtraglichkeit): the innocent, pleasant, clear<br />

principles <strong>of</strong> existence thus displayed would obviously support a<br />

particular myth <strong>of</strong> childhood and human nature (Smith 85). <strong>Screen</strong><br />

memories are part <strong>of</strong> a system (perhaps the system itself) that<br />

produce narratives <strong>of</strong> normality, <strong>of</strong> a glowing childhood.<br />

But if screen memories are partly or wholly false, is there<br />

an alternate concept <strong>of</strong> true memory in the Freudian system? In<br />

the screen memory essay, Freud pays lip service to “normal”<br />

memory, a memory that is abruptly bracketed by the existence <strong>of</strong><br />

these aberrations, but it is unclear whether he really credits<br />

its existence. Is the state <strong>of</strong> childhood memory the condition <strong>of</strong><br />

all memory? Leclaire seems to think so: “The practice <strong>of</strong> analysis<br />

forces us to recognize that all the recollections registered in<br />

what we call memory always create . . . a limit or a screen,<br />

beyond which unfolds the scene <strong>of</strong> another memory” (76). Terdiman<br />

puts an extreme case:, conscious “recollection exhibits a<br />

positively wanton disloyalty to the truth. There seems no<br />

seduction before which its representations will not yield”<br />

(1993:291). Forgetting also seems to be traumatic for Benjamin, a<br />

form <strong>of</strong> repression; as he says, “forgetting is never innocent”<br />

14


(Bogaç 73). 8<br />

There is another systematic split in psychoanalysis–-<br />

conscious/unconscious–-and it also is crucially inflected by<br />

memory. In a seemingly paradoxical turn, memory belongs only to<br />

the unconscious: Freud “only acknowledged memory ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is<br />

unconscious, denying to consciousness even the capacity <strong>of</strong><br />

memory” (Leclaire 76). In one sense, the rationale for this<br />

seeming paradox is almost simple-minded, the sort <strong>of</strong> mathematical<br />

thinking that lay behind Augustine’s cavern, Déscartes’<br />

intellectual memory, or Bergson’s soul: that consciousness is not<br />

sufficiently capacious to store all our perceptions and thoughts,<br />

“Consciousness has no capacity for the retention <strong>of</strong> anything”<br />

(Freud 5.540).<br />

A more complex version <strong>of</strong> this difference, according to<br />

Terdiman, is that the unconscious “lodges an integral and<br />

unchanging reproduction <strong>of</strong> the past (though not the past our<br />

conscious self has lived), whereas consciousness circulates a<br />

mobile and ungroundable representation <strong>of</strong> these contents to which<br />

direct access is theoretically impossible. These two memories<br />

cohabit within us but cohere nowhere” (1993:289-90). The process<br />

<strong>of</strong> nächtraglichkeit allowed Freud to conclude that leaving a mark<br />

in memory and being conscious <strong>of</strong> something are independent<br />

processes: “such memory-traces, then, have nothing to do with the<br />

fact <strong>of</strong> becoming conscious” (18.25). The impression <strong>of</strong> an<br />

15


experience leaves “behind a laborious [memory] trace which has<br />

never been perceived, whose meaning has never been lived in the<br />

present, i.e. has never been lived consciously” (Derrida<br />

1978:214).<br />

This may explain why for Proust and Benjamin as well as<br />

Freud what we retrieve from memory is something we have never<br />

experienced: “Concerning the mémoire involontaire, its images do<br />

not only come without being called up; rather, they are images<br />

which we have never seen before we remember them”; “<strong>Memory</strong><br />

fragments are <strong>of</strong>ten most powerful and enduring when the incident<br />

which left them behind was one that never entered consciousness”<br />

(Benjamin in Cadava 100 and Freud 18.27-28).<br />

Finally, in a psychic system where memory is always false<br />

and forgetting tragic, how can memory also be held up as the key<br />

to healing? Obviously, what we have here are two systems in<br />

tandem, another version <strong>of</strong> Freud's dual archaeological model <strong>of</strong><br />

Rome as the visible city <strong>of</strong> ruins and Pompeii as the lost city,<br />

buried whole. Psychoanalysis, like Christianity or Marx’s<br />

political economy, betrays itself as a transcendental system in<br />

which memory is actually only false and ideally only true. The<br />

course <strong>of</strong> treatment is governed only by the former; the goal <strong>of</strong><br />

treatment dreams only <strong>of</strong> the latter: the recovery <strong>of</strong> memory as<br />

the recovery <strong>of</strong> health. The goal <strong>of</strong> psychoanalysis is<br />

remembering, an end to neurosis (an end to personal history).<br />

16


Freud and Josef Breuer worked with an enlightenment model whereby<br />

hysterical symptoms evaporated after “bringing clearly to light<br />

the memory <strong>of</strong> the event by which it [the trauma] was provoked and<br />

in arousing its accompanying affect" (2.6).<br />

17


Collective <strong>Memory</strong><br />

The very idea <strong>of</strong> unique memories rooted in the<br />

autobiographical past <strong>of</strong> an individual self may itself<br />

by the result <strong>of</strong> particular Western narrative practices<br />

and conventions.<br />

Jens Brockmeier<br />

A seemingly irresistible desire to pluralize memory has led<br />

to the growth <strong>of</strong> a second body <strong>of</strong> memory studies that looks at<br />

memory as collective, social, cultural, historical or national.<br />

Given the stunning fit between memory and subjectivity, this<br />

1<br />

desire to relocate memory in a collective seems perverse. The<br />

meanings <strong>of</strong> a phrase like “collective memory” range from the<br />

literal to the metaphoric and the ordinary to the mystical.<br />

Shadowing ordinary notions <strong>of</strong> collective memory, there is <strong>of</strong>ten a<br />

second, uncanny variant: in anthropology collective memory refers<br />

to a society’s sense <strong>of</strong> its past but also the vaguer notion <strong>of</strong> a<br />

past as an agency, preserving itself into the present and shaping<br />

social thought and feeling.<br />

1


A deeply mystical version <strong>of</strong> memory held sway in the<br />

nineteenth century, in the belief, for example, that memory<br />

persisted after the death <strong>of</strong> its original holder. The final<br />

sentence <strong>of</strong> Ewald Hering’s 1870 lecture on organic memory to the<br />

Vienna Imperial Academy <strong>of</strong> Science was, “Man’s conscious memory<br />

comes to an end at death, but the unconscious memory <strong>of</strong> Nature is<br />

true and ineradicable: whoever succeeds in stamping upon her the<br />

impress <strong>of</strong> his work, she will remember him to the end <strong>of</strong> time”<br />

2<br />

(Otis 26). Transmitted atmospherically, memory could drift<br />

through the material cosmos; Charles Babbage, John William Draper<br />

and others believed that the universe contained an Akashic memory<br />

(from the Sanskrit word for space) that stored every thought,<br />

word and action that had ever occurred in it (Lowenthal 19). In<br />

Tony Morrison’s Beloved, memory adheres to the places where stark<br />

experience occurred: “The past, its memory, is out there still,<br />

real enough to capture the living in its grip . . . . what's<br />

more, if you go there--you who never was there--if you go there<br />

and stand in the place where it was, it will happen again; it<br />

will be there for you, waiting” (36). This version <strong>of</strong> memory was<br />

not exclusively human or animal but referred to a general<br />

function <strong>of</strong> all organic matter.<br />

Collective memory was more commonly conceived <strong>of</strong> as having<br />

been transmitted genetically or biologically: as “racial” or<br />

“organic” memory. Nietzsche and other contemporary thinkers<br />

2


elieved that “man carries within himself the memory <strong>of</strong> all past<br />

generations” (Barash 716). It was carried along the trail <strong>of</strong><br />

blood: one inherited memories from ancestors just as one<br />

inherited their physical features. Herbert Spencer <strong>of</strong>fered the<br />

universality <strong>of</strong> some knowledge (i.e., fear <strong>of</strong> snakes), which<br />

cannot be tied to experience or education, as the basis for this<br />

belief (Young 1996:92). Racial memory also drew on Ernst<br />

Haeckel’s notion <strong>of</strong> epigenesis, the idea that a species’<br />

evolutionary history is recapped in the embryological development<br />

<strong>of</strong> its individual member. Freud and Jung both subscribed to<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> racial memory, Freud in Totem and Taboo and Moses and<br />

Monotheism, particularly, and Jung in his theory <strong>of</strong> archetypes. 3<br />

The concept <strong>of</strong> racial memory has also been put to political use,<br />

to prop nationalism or attack differences.<br />

Throughout history, the body has been perceived as a<br />

receptacle <strong>of</strong> memory, from the memory <strong>of</strong> bodily<br />

movement, such as walking, to the memory <strong>of</strong> past events<br />

in physical scars, to the memory <strong>of</strong> one’s genetic<br />

history in every cell . . . . the immune system as a<br />

system <strong>of</strong> memory, remembering, for instance, the<br />

viruses it has previously encountered (Sturken 12 and<br />

220).<br />

Organic memory was stored in the body not the brain. According to<br />

Henry Maudsley who introduced the concept in 1867, memory exists<br />

3


in every part <strong>of</strong> the body, even in “the nervous cells which lie<br />

scattered in the heart and in the intestinal walls.” Three years<br />

later Hering claimed that every cell contained the memory <strong>of</strong> the<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> all its parent cells (Kern 40). These beliefs are<br />

to be distinguished from a more ordinary body memory whereby,<br />

say, the body remembers to stand or bow as a gesture <strong>of</strong> respect.<br />

As the quotation from Sturken indicates, biological memory, the<br />

memory that drives heredity, has been scientifically recuperated<br />

with the application <strong>of</strong> computers to biology; the “archival<br />

ordering <strong>of</strong> the body's code,” DNA, discovered in the 1950s, opens<br />

a new act in the drama <strong>of</strong> organic memory (Guertin).<br />

These and other conjectures underwrote a series <strong>of</strong> Romantic<br />

tropes: the eternal tidal expansion <strong>of</strong> experience in Poe’s “The<br />

Power <strong>of</strong> Words,” for instance, or the haunted portraits in the<br />

tales <strong>of</strong> Nathaniel Hawthorne, and, at the turn <strong>of</strong> the century,<br />

the haunted-house tale generally. This collaboration continued<br />

into the Modern period when unconscious (and ancestral) memory<br />

became a standard motif in the work <strong>of</strong> Proust, Joyce, and Mann.<br />

A less mystical version <strong>of</strong> racial memory, “cultural memory,”<br />

as presented by nineteenth-century mythographers and art<br />

historians like Aby Warburg, conceives <strong>of</strong> memory working<br />

intertextually across the ages. For Warburg and Benjamin,<br />

crystallizations <strong>of</strong> the past are scattered throughout the present<br />

in small, symbolic cultural details, like street names, which<br />

4


preserve the memory <strong>of</strong> the heroes and deities <strong>of</strong> antiquity. In<br />

the form <strong>of</strong> art, these symbols <strong>of</strong> civilization preserve “intense<br />

basic experiences” <strong>of</strong> primitive life (Gombrich 243).<br />

It is likely that the purely secular notion <strong>of</strong> collective<br />

memory entered Western thought as a metaphoric deposit <strong>of</strong> racial<br />

memory. The major players in this twentieth-century development<br />

were the sociologist Halbwachs, the art historian Warburg, and,<br />

later, the historian Nora. The emergence <strong>of</strong> such a concept may<br />

very well have been an inevitable consequence <strong>of</strong> the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> the social sciences, anthropology, sociology, and history.<br />

Halbwachs began as a student <strong>of</strong> Bergson but later switched<br />

his intellectual allegiance to Emile Durkheim. In 1922 he wrote<br />

Collective <strong>Memory</strong>, the pioneer study <strong>of</strong> the workings <strong>of</strong> group<br />

memory; a second book on the subject, The Social Frameworks <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Memory</strong>, was published in 1925. For Halbwachs, memory was not an<br />

attribute that belongs to one in the way that vision does.<br />

Individual memory was a secondary, phantasmic, effect: a “man who<br />

remembers alone what others do not remember,” Halbwachs wrote,<br />

“resembles somebody who sees what others do not see. It is as if<br />

he suffers from hallucinations” (Boyer 26). The individual was<br />

nothing but the “crossroads <strong>of</strong> collective memories” (Tai<br />

2001a:52).<br />

Many writers agree that collective memory is metaphor not<br />

memory because the collective lacks such an agency; so, for<br />

5


example, Yosef Yerushalmi--“Just as ‘the life <strong>of</strong> a people’ is a<br />

biological metaphor, so too ‘the memory <strong>of</strong> a people’ is a<br />

psychological metaphor”; Susan Sontag--“not remembering but<br />

stipulating that this is important”; and Amos Funkenstein--<br />

Consciousness and memory can only be realized by an<br />

individual who acts, is aware, and remembers. Just as a<br />

nation cannot eat or dance, neither can it speak or<br />

remember . . . . The employment <strong>of</strong> “collective memory”<br />

can be justified only on a metaphorical level–-and this<br />

is how historians <strong>of</strong> old have always employed it–-as a<br />

general code name for something that is supposedly<br />

behind myths, traditions, customs, cults, all <strong>of</strong> which<br />

represent the “spirit,” the “psyche,” <strong>of</strong> a society, a<br />

tribe, a nation (Boyarin 23, Sontag 2003:86 and Gedi<br />

34-35).<br />

Collective memory can also be thought <strong>of</strong> as a combination or<br />

consolidation <strong>of</strong> individual memories, a category <strong>of</strong> abstraction.<br />

Robert Bevan considers it to be “a bundle <strong>of</strong> individual memories<br />

that coalesce by means <strong>of</strong> exchanges between people and develop<br />

into a communal narrative” (15).<br />

For others, collective memory is not simply a metaphoric<br />

analogue. Qualitative differences have been proposed between the<br />

two memories: collective memory is more intersubjective and<br />

dialogical than personal memory, more “act than object, and more<br />

6


ongoing engagement than passive absorption and playback” (Lambeck<br />

1996:239). Many <strong>of</strong> the terms are not transferable, so we are<br />

warned to keep collective memory free from the taint <strong>of</strong><br />

psychoanalysis. “The concept <strong>of</strong> trauma, as well as the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

repression,” Wulf Kansteiner writes, “neither captures nor<br />

illuminates the forces that contribute to the making and unmaking<br />

<strong>of</strong> collective memories” (187). Nancy Wood reminds us that while<br />

personal memory is governed by the laws <strong>of</strong> the unconscious public<br />

memory “testifies to a will or desire on the part <strong>of</strong> some social<br />

group or disposition <strong>of</strong> power to select and organize<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the past” (2). But even studies that warn us<br />

to avoid psychologizing collective memory, Klein points out, “do<br />

precisely this: “Freudian vocabularies are far more common than<br />

4<br />

Halbwachsian or even Lacanian ones” (135). Historians like Anne<br />

Rigney insist that a collective memory with no analogical<br />

relationship to personal memory can be theorized. It is not the<br />

only instance <strong>of</strong> a memory without rememberers. Mikhail Bakhtin<br />

attributed this facility to language (“Our practices and language<br />

remember,” he wrote) and Warburg to imagery (Cole 27). 5<br />

Like memory itself, collective memory has a range <strong>of</strong><br />

meanings: it can refer to the fact that our memories are woven<br />

out <strong>of</strong> social strands (shared items <strong>of</strong> knowledge and experience,<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> language itself, etc.); it can simply mean that<br />

memories can be validated and fleshed out through social<br />

7


exchange; or, at the other extreme, it can refer to the process<br />

by which memories suture the rememberer into particular social<br />

groups. In the case <strong>of</strong> language particularly, the individual<br />

speaker is always being colonized by the group, already inhabited<br />

by the other; our experience is not the unmediated reality we<br />

believe it to be. Our memories are filled with alien contents,<br />

for example, other people’s recollections passing as our own, For<br />

Hamlet, memories are not individual possessions but shared<br />

commonplaces:<br />

Yea, from the table <strong>of</strong> my memory<br />

I'll wipe away all trivial fond records,<br />

All saws <strong>of</strong> books, all forms, all pressures past,<br />

That youth and observation copied there” (877).<br />

Halbwachs insisted that people inhabit a social arena when<br />

they remember:<br />

. . . it is in society that people normally acquire<br />

their memories. It is also in society that they recall,<br />

recognize, and localize their memories . . . . if we<br />

examine a little more closely how we recollect things,<br />

we will surely realize that the greatest number <strong>of</strong><br />

memories come back to us when our parents, our friends,<br />

or other persons recall them to us (1992:38).<br />

We have as many kinds <strong>of</strong> memory as there are groups that we<br />

belong to, and these groups inflect their common memories in<br />

8


different ways. Conversely, these groups are the products <strong>of</strong><br />

collective memory: the family, for example, the fundamental<br />

social group, is held together by shared memories at least as<br />

much as shared genes (Kihlstrom 5). “On the very same day, the<br />

birth <strong>of</strong> the Prophet is . . . jointly remembered by Muslims in<br />

Malaysia, Guyana, and Sierra Leone. By the same token, on Good<br />

Friday, Christians all over the world come to recall the<br />

Crucifixion together, as a single community” (Zerubabel 4).<br />

For Halbwachs, the main social categories that generate<br />

collective memory are religious community, social class, and<br />

family, but many other groups and groupings–-by generation,<br />

gender, relationship and friendship--function in this way. <strong>Memory</strong><br />

belongs to the group even though members may disagree about the<br />

details <strong>of</strong> a common experience, particularly, popular culture has<br />

it, the gender couple, as in the song “I Remember it Well” from<br />

Gigi where the man’s and the woman’s memories <strong>of</strong> their early<br />

relationship are totally at odds. Halbwachs’s collective memory<br />

was a product <strong>of</strong> consensus and made no room for conflict, but<br />

most current models have room for a range <strong>of</strong> consolidating<br />

processes, “sharing, discussion, negotiation, and <strong>of</strong>ten conflict”<br />

(Brundage 4).<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> is social not merely because <strong>of</strong> its content and its<br />

acquisition but because it operates through cultural frameworks<br />

that condition even those memories that appear to be the most<br />

9


private; it is “constructed along the lines <strong>of</strong> old chains <strong>of</strong><br />

associations laid down in the mind: schemata, models, paradigms”<br />

6<br />

(Cole 25). Bartlett called these frameworks schemata, and for<br />

Halbwachs they were “social contexts and relationships at a given<br />

moment in time when a memory is made, which colour and inflect<br />

the memory itself” (Russell 13).<br />

We acquire group memories by hearing people talk about them,<br />

by participating in commemorations and rituals or by reading<br />

about them or viewing their representations. Collective memory is<br />

an anthology <strong>of</strong> different kinds <strong>of</strong> mental and communication<br />

events, “multimedia collages” consisting in part <strong>of</strong> “a mixture <strong>of</strong><br />

pictorial images and scenes, slogans, quips, and snatches <strong>of</strong><br />

verse, abstractions, plot types and stretches <strong>of</strong> discourse, and<br />

even false etymologies” (Kansteiner 190 and Fentriss 47). These<br />

memories are brought to us by what Confino calls “memory<br />

carriers,” semiotic systems like commemorations, popular movies,<br />

or scholarly works <strong>of</strong> history, and the two primary routes are art<br />

and politics: on the one hand, artists “from whose imagination<br />

new representations <strong>of</strong> collective experience enter into public<br />

currency via cultural gatekeepers such as the publishing and<br />

movie industries,” and, on the other, “institutionalized forces<br />

such as governments, political parties and pressure groups”<br />

(Confino 1997a:1395 and Boutine 6).<br />

As a consequence <strong>of</strong> all this, we “own” memories <strong>of</strong> events<br />

10


that we did not or could not have experienced, events that<br />

happened to groups to which we would later belong (this<br />

concatenation begins to fulfil the mythic promise <strong>of</strong> organic<br />

memory). “You do not need to have stormed the Bastille,” Confino<br />

writes, “in order to celebrate 14 July as a symbol <strong>of</strong> national<br />

identity”:<br />

Even in the midst <strong>of</strong> such a commemoration there is<br />

nothing within us that we could properly call a<br />

“memory” or “remembering.” And yet in this and other<br />

similar instances, the call to commemorate evokes a<br />

string <strong>of</strong> memories (lessons, narratives, allusions)<br />

that underwrite the emotional connection (1997b:8 and<br />

1997a:1400).<br />

Jews who never suffered from Nazism, African Americans who never<br />

experienced slavery--in some sense they own those memories by<br />

virtue <strong>of</strong> their identification with those groups. Marianne Hirsch<br />

calls this more abstract process “postmemory,”<br />

a powerful and very particular form <strong>of</strong> memory precisely<br />

because . . . [it is] mediated not through recollection<br />

but through an imaginative investment and creation . .<br />

. . Postmemory characterizes the experience <strong>of</strong> those<br />

who grow up dominated by narratives that preceeded<br />

their birth, whose own belated stories are evacuated by<br />

the stories <strong>of</strong> the previous generation shaped by<br />

11


traumatic events that can be neither understood nor<br />

recreated” (22).<br />

How far back can these memories go? While collective memory<br />

at most attains to three generations, cultural memory reaches far<br />

back into the past: Jan Assmann divides collective memory into<br />

collective and cultural memory and has the latter take us back to<br />

ancient traditions and myths, to what Freud called the childhood<br />

memories <strong>of</strong> the nation (2006:48). What is being remembered is a<br />

body <strong>of</strong> knowledge that defines the community and is deemed<br />

necessary for its continuity. So, for example, Assmann writes,<br />

“What the children <strong>of</strong> Israel must not forget is . . . the story<br />

<strong>of</strong> the exodus from Egypt . . . . To make sure that this memory<br />

does not die with them, it has to be transmuted into . . . the<br />

symbolic forms <strong>of</strong> cultural memory,” the Passover seder<br />

(2006:18). 7<br />

Despite Halbwachs’ balanced picture <strong>of</strong> collective memory fed<br />

by all the groups to which we belong, we know that certain groups<br />

are particularly powerful in establishing this body <strong>of</strong><br />

understanding and belief. Collective memory is not something that<br />

just happens; it is <strong>of</strong>ten orchestrated as a politics <strong>of</strong> memory by<br />

dominant elites who control powerful modes <strong>of</strong> representation.<br />

Most theorists take for granted a top-down process <strong>of</strong> influence<br />

that follows the terrain <strong>of</strong> power. But some also believe that<br />

resistance and interference from lower strata enter into the<br />

12


equation.<br />

There are few satisfactory models <strong>of</strong> how collective memory<br />

is constructed, how it is received, and what factors govern its<br />

endurance. Unlike its near synonyms, myth and tradition,<br />

collective memory is an active stratum <strong>of</strong> mentality, constantly<br />

8<br />

in the process <strong>of</strong> reformulation. Like personal memory,<br />

collective memory is determined by present needs and desires and,<br />

in their service, distorts or invents the past. As examples,<br />

David Thelen relates that in the relatively prosperous 1970s<br />

Americans recalled the 1930s not as a time <strong>of</strong> misery and struggle<br />

but as a time when people had been closer to each other, warmer<br />

and more caring, and John Foster and Wayne Froman cite the very<br />

late appearance <strong>of</strong> the Amistad mutiny <strong>of</strong> 1839-42 as a central<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the cultural memory <strong>of</strong> Sierra Leone (Thelen 1124 and<br />

Foster 90).<br />

Because collective memory is not memory it must circulate in<br />

the public realm in material form before it can lodge itself in<br />

our minds: in documents, memorials, commemorations, rituals,<br />

slogans or songs; “rules, laws, standardized procedures, and<br />

records . . . . books, holidays, statues, souvenirs” (Schudson<br />

1992:51). George Washington remains an important part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

American collective consciousness, for example, because he is<br />

commemorated through the celebration <strong>of</strong> his birth, the Washington<br />

Monument and his pr<strong>of</strong>ile on quarters and dollar bills (Johnson<br />

13


37).<br />

Libraries and museums are the great repositories <strong>of</strong><br />

collective memory. Cinema, television, and now the internet are<br />

the most powerful agents in its construction and dissemination,<br />

although this non-confrontational, semi-conscious, non-<br />

referential, and decentralized process is extremely<br />

difficult to reconstruct after the fact . . . . The<br />

media <strong>of</strong> representation tend to disappear from the<br />

consciousness <strong>of</strong> the audience in the process <strong>of</strong><br />

consumption. Radio listeners, for instance, regularly<br />

forget the source <strong>of</strong> their memories . . . and <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

attach them to other sources” (Kansteiner 194-95).<br />

If memory constructs subjectivity for the individual it<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers a corresponding group identity to the collective in which<br />

it is somehow archived. Collective memory is the glue that holds<br />

groups and societies together. The cultivation <strong>of</strong> certain texts,<br />

images, objects, and rituals “serves to stabilize and convey that<br />

society’s self-image,” and this allows a society to become<br />

visible to itself and others (Assmann 1995:132). Jan Assmann<br />

calls this form <strong>of</strong> memory “bonding memory,” and finds its<br />

theoreticion to be Nietzsche: “Just as Halbwachs has shown that<br />

people need bonds in order to develop a memory, Nietzsche has<br />

shown that people need a memory in order to be able to form<br />

9<br />

bonds” (2006:5). It is the form <strong>of</strong> memory incorporated into the<br />

14


discipline <strong>of</strong> anthropology.<br />

But if a particular body <strong>of</strong> memory is the identifying<br />

property <strong>of</strong> a group, isn’t it also always being modified to<br />

justify the existence <strong>of</strong> that group, to apologize for its past<br />

mistakes and elide its shames? Writing <strong>of</strong> the family album,<br />

Bernadette Flynn finds that while it “allows the construction <strong>of</strong><br />

narratives <strong>of</strong> collective family memory out <strong>of</strong> freestanding images<br />

. . . it most always constitutes a story <strong>of</strong> domestic life from<br />

which conflicts and difficulties are erased” (online). Meditating<br />

on the left’s fetishization <strong>of</strong> its own pantheon <strong>of</strong> heroes and<br />

heroic moments, Ahmet Bayazitoglu asks if there is “a way <strong>of</strong><br />

remembering that is not a narcissistic reification?” (online).<br />

National memory<br />

Collective memory has been held to be the primary form <strong>of</strong><br />

plural memory, developed to stabilize and solidify the nation-<br />

state, which is built on shared memories <strong>of</strong> joy and suffering,<br />

and above all <strong>of</strong> collective sacrifices. Collective memory is<br />

nationalism’s project, shared by people who have never seen or<br />

heard <strong>of</strong> one another. National memory trumps the corresponding<br />

memories <strong>of</strong> other groups, which may, for example, hold the Great<br />

Depression in memory in their own ways: still, there will also be<br />

a national version <strong>of</strong> this memory that tends to hold sway. After<br />

the American Civil War, through the mid-twentieth century,<br />

15


American conservatives fashioned a memory <strong>of</strong> slavery, a benign<br />

fiction <strong>of</strong> honorable masters and contented slaves–-a perspective<br />

that effectively silenced “alternative memories <strong>of</strong> violence,<br />

exploitation and cruelty” (Climo 28).<br />

As defined by The Popular <strong>Memory</strong> Group (a Birmingham study<br />

groups that works at the boundaries <strong>of</strong> collective and oral<br />

memory), national memory refers to representations <strong>of</strong> the past<br />

that “achieve centrality” within the public domain, because<br />

“Their institutional propagation by the national and local state,<br />

the culture industries, or the public media ensure their scope to<br />

make public meanings for vast audiences” (Ashplant 13). The<br />

players in this game consist <strong>of</strong> various “status groups who become<br />

society’s symbolic bankers and whose efforts to preserve sites or<br />

artifacts <strong>of</strong>ten assume the character <strong>of</strong> symbolic crusades”<br />

(Barthel 152). National memory is thus a map <strong>of</strong> the vectors <strong>of</strong><br />

power in a social system.<br />

In the early modern period, Europeans were somehow made to<br />

internalize a nation and “in a remarkably short time” it became<br />

an everyday mental property–-“a memory as intimate and authentic<br />

as the local, ethnic, and family past” (Confino 1997a:1402). Once<br />

this happened, Le G<strong>of</strong>f adds, the capital city becomes “the center<br />

<strong>of</strong> a politics <strong>of</strong> memory” and the king deploys “a program <strong>of</strong><br />

remembering <strong>of</strong> which he is the center” (60). The nation and its<br />

new form <strong>of</strong> memory gave meaning to human life after religion<br />

16


waned; the nation, Peter Fritzsche writes,<br />

can be usefully thought <strong>of</strong> as a memory system that<br />

enabled individuals to recognize their lives in<br />

nonrepeatable, historical time. Because <strong>of</strong> their<br />

boundedness in time and space, national narratives have<br />

an unusual ability to organize remembrance and to make<br />

the past sensible . . . . At the same time, the very<br />

forcefulness <strong>of</strong> the representative powers <strong>of</strong> the nation<br />

10<br />

have worked to disable other narratives (108).<br />

National memory is frequently charged with bias, with being<br />

the champion <strong>of</strong> and apologist for dominant elites. Nations<br />

remember largely what suits them, so Japan remembers the bombings<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hiroshima and not its own prior history <strong>of</strong> militarism. America<br />

remembers Japan’s history <strong>of</strong> imperialism but not the dark side <strong>of</strong><br />

the Enola Gay episode. Control <strong>of</strong> the national memory is a<br />

crucial weapon <strong>of</strong> the ruling class, since, as Foucault has<br />

stated, “If one controls people’s memory, one controls their<br />

dynamism . . . . It is vital to have possession <strong>of</strong> this memory,<br />

to control it, administer it, tell it what it must contain” (25-<br />

26).<br />

Societies, therefore, expend great energy to control the<br />

circulation <strong>of</strong> recollection, generally by supervising the<br />

mechanisms <strong>of</strong> memory exchange. For the U. S., Gary Taylor<br />

instances a variety <strong>of</strong> regulatory mechanisms, including the<br />

17


Freedom <strong>of</strong> Information Act, the Federal Communications<br />

Commission, the antitrust division <strong>of</strong> the Justice <strong>Department</strong>, the<br />

Central Intelligence Agency and the Interior <strong>Department</strong>’s<br />

Register <strong>of</strong> Historic Buildings (1996:15). In addition to the<br />

obvious, highly visible, forms <strong>of</strong> national memory, Matsuda<br />

discusses a second type: “What Max Weber would refer to as the<br />

‘domination through knowledge, specifically rational,’ which<br />

characterized modern bureaucratic organizations, the knowledge <strong>of</strong><br />

the file” (121-22). This might be called “institutional memory”<br />

and would include the fingerprint system, the census, mechanisms<br />

<strong>of</strong> surveillance, registries, and transcipts.<br />

Dominant forms <strong>of</strong> memory tend to be melodramatic, already on<br />

their way to nostalgia. Svetlana Boym makes a distinction between<br />

collective memory and national memory: the latter tends “to make<br />

a single teleological plot out <strong>of</strong> shared everyday recollections.<br />

The gaps and discontinuities are mended through a coherent and<br />

inspiriting tale <strong>of</strong> recovered identity” (53). Very little <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ruck and welter <strong>of</strong> history gets into it.<br />

National memory has been further accused <strong>of</strong> being a<br />

deliberately false and manipulative narrative, a progressive<br />

melodrama in which nationals are always right and foreigners<br />

always wrong--devoted to supporting an impossibly ideal image <strong>of</strong><br />

a people, their leaders and their past. War memorials embody what<br />

John Mack calls “the egoism <strong>of</strong> victimization.” Commemoration in<br />

18


general “seeks most <strong>of</strong>ten to supply us with heroes to worship or<br />

with enemies to detest; it deals in desecration and consecration”<br />

(Perlman 27 and Todorov 2003:133). And there is <strong>of</strong>ten an intense<br />

struggle (around the bombing <strong>of</strong> Hiroshima and Nagasaki, say, or<br />

the 9/11 attacks) to keep unflattering information out <strong>of</strong> memory.<br />

Are there collective screen memories? Many writers have<br />

pluralized this concept as well as a way <strong>of</strong> explaining ideology.<br />

For example, historian Daniel Biork claims such are the stirring<br />

memories <strong>of</strong> the American Revolution, masking the trauma <strong>of</strong> this<br />

national childhood event (Biork 276). National memory is thus a<br />

primary example <strong>of</strong> what Marx and Engels called “false<br />

consciousness”--or nostalgia, which Marx termed “memory’s lie”<br />

(Sennett 11). There are more benign ways <strong>of</strong> viewing this<br />

manipulation: Halbwachs, for example, suggested that “society can<br />

live only if there is sufficient unity <strong>of</strong> outlooks among the<br />

individuals and groups comprising it . . . This is why society<br />

tends to erase from its memory all that might separate<br />

individuals, or that might distance groups from each other”<br />

(1992:182-83).<br />

Time itself can break up these melodramas. The founding myth<br />

<strong>of</strong> postwar France, for example, that the French who had<br />

collaborated with the Nazis were limited to a few misfits while<br />

the majority <strong>of</strong> citizens resisted and eventually drove the German<br />

armies from France was dislodged by the 1970s when this<br />

19


comforting illusion was shattered by The Sorrow and the Pity and<br />

Lacombe Lucien (Golsan 25). Austria’s attempt to cast itself as a<br />

victim <strong>of</strong> Nazi aggression crumbled as its role in Nazism was<br />

11<br />

increasingly acknowledged in public discourse.<br />

Remembering the nation has <strong>of</strong>ten taken the ironic form <strong>of</strong><br />

simply inverting an accessible, actual history, e.g., the stories<br />

<strong>of</strong> native American aggression designed to justify the genocidal<br />

slaughter <strong>of</strong> the tribes or stories that blame the fall <strong>of</strong><br />

American business empires on labor unrest and governmental<br />

regulations. In Renato Rosaldo’s essay on “imperialist nostalgia”<br />

agents <strong>of</strong> a dominant culture conjure up fond recollections <strong>of</strong> the<br />

old ways that they are in one way or another responsible for<br />

destroying. Algerian pied noirs repressed any memory <strong>of</strong> racial<br />

tensions, remembering “Algeria as a ‘paradise without colonial<br />

sin,’ a land where everyone, Arabs and Europeans, lived in<br />

harmony and plenty” (Greene 243).<br />

According to Aleida Assmann, monuments are part <strong>of</strong> a culture<br />

that is stage-managing itself (Holthorf). The practice that most<br />

sustains national memory is commemoration, one <strong>of</strong> the primary<br />

forms taken by nostalgia, “the ultimate attempt to master the<br />

past and render it innocuous forever” (Ankersmit 166). But<br />

commemoration has a tendency to freeze into permanent forms that<br />

cannot be changed without cries <strong>of</strong> sacrilege–-although dynastic<br />

changes, like the collapse <strong>of</strong> the Soviet empire, can radically<br />

20


alter the commemorative map--and is thus also a way <strong>of</strong> forgetting<br />

(Todorov 2001:21). As Casey writes: “To commemorate a war such as<br />

the Civil War or Vietnam is at the same time not to remember its<br />

many horrors, its unspeakable and even unthinkable mutilations<br />

and agonies. For an individual to recall the horrors is to<br />

undermine participation in the public event <strong>of</strong> commemoration”<br />

(xii).<br />

One <strong>of</strong> clearest sign <strong>of</strong> the crisis <strong>of</strong> memory has been the<br />

acceleration, intensification, and amplification <strong>of</strong><br />

commemoration. Commemoration intensified after the first world<br />

war, elevating all citizens who had fallen in nationalist wars to<br />

a post <strong>of</strong> honor. The most basic commemorative text in a culture<br />

is its sequence <strong>of</strong> holidays which become ever heavier with<br />

anniversaries. In The Invention <strong>of</strong> Tradition, Eric Hobsbawm<br />

discovered that “an astonishing number” <strong>of</strong> the ceremonies and<br />

rituals “that define the ‘traditional’ pole <strong>of</strong> nineteenth-century<br />

society . . . . were simply created wholesale” (e.g. the tartans,<br />

12<br />

kilt and bagpipe <strong>of</strong> Scotland) (Terdiman 1993:36). Now that<br />

tourism has become a major industry for most nations memory is<br />

its primary commodity. Stories about the past are “appropriated<br />

by transnational corporatism, tourism, multicultural nationalism,<br />

and many other forces, ultimately domesticating their unsettling<br />

qualities and endorsing only the ideas <strong>of</strong> pluralism that produce<br />

an illusion <strong>of</strong> harmonious diversity” (Fujitani 21-22).<br />

21


Collective amnesia<br />

Amnesia was also pluralized in the twentieth century, when<br />

it came to be regarded as a social disease. Modernity and<br />

postmodernity are said to carry heavy charges <strong>of</strong> it, so much so<br />

that we are frequently told that we have now lost our sense <strong>of</strong><br />

the past. John Frow describes postmodernity as “the time <strong>of</strong> a<br />

fall from . . . history into amnesia” (218). But Marx and his<br />

followers had already written amnesia into the psychology <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism: “Ideology and amnesia have long been linked,”<br />

Nicholas Dames writes, “from Lukács’s analyses <strong>of</strong> the structural<br />

forgetting embedded in reification to Althusser’s well-known<br />

argument that ideology ‘has no history’” (2001:17). “All<br />

reification is a forgetting,” Adorno and Horkheimer had declared,<br />

and Herbert Marcuse announced (after Adorno) that “the spectre <strong>of</strong><br />

man without memory . . . is more than an aspect <strong>of</strong> decline–-it is<br />

necessarily linked with the principle <strong>of</strong> progress in bourgeois<br />

society” (Jay 229 and 234).<br />

Earlier, the historical novel <strong>of</strong> Scott and Hugo was <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

occasioned by an inability (in Waverley and Nôtre-Dame de Paris)<br />

to find any signs <strong>of</strong> the past in the present as a result <strong>of</strong><br />

radical social change. The absence <strong>of</strong> memorial signs produces the<br />

amnesia that Eliot described in Silas Marner: “Minds that have<br />

been unhinged from their old faith and love have perhaps sought<br />

this Lethean influence <strong>of</strong> exile in which the past becomes dreamy<br />

22


ecause its symbols have all vanished, and the present too is<br />

dreamy because it is linked with no memories” (1978:22).<br />

Richard E. Sullivan lists as the occasions <strong>of</strong> such amnesia<br />

“massive migrations <strong>of</strong> peoples across the face <strong>of</strong> the earth, both<br />

voluntary and forced,” the “rapid emergence <strong>of</strong> world<br />

interdependency,” the “astounding developments in mass<br />

communications” which “have drowned us in the present to the<br />

point where our minds have no room for remembering” and<br />

“incessant waves <strong>of</strong> new material products.” He goes on to assert<br />

that “Even more deadly to collective remembering have been two<br />

potent intellectual movements”: the brightening <strong>of</strong> the future<br />

through the idea <strong>of</strong> progress and the darkening <strong>of</strong> the past<br />

through modern determinism in the form <strong>of</strong> social Darwinism and<br />

Marxism (98).<br />

Radical change and upheaval lead to either amnesia or a form<br />

<strong>of</strong> false memory Nora calls “historicized memory” (10). Genocide<br />

and violent exile break the human chains <strong>of</strong> communication so that<br />

“cultural memories, identities, and practices do not flow simply<br />

or predictably from one generation to the next or from the<br />

homeland to the diasporic people” (Landsberg 2004:10). It also<br />

follows that such disruption should lead to memorial hoarding:<br />

Whereas middle-class families in Britain and the United<br />

States had shown little concern about their origins<br />

before the nineteenth-century, after 1800 a feeling <strong>of</strong><br />

having been ravaged by time turned “living rooms into<br />

23


family portrait galleries” and “attics into archives” .<br />

. . . the early nineteenth-century [also] witnessed an<br />

explosion <strong>of</strong> autobiographical writing, diary keeping,<br />

scrapbook pasting, and portrait taking. Families took<br />

more care to commemorate personal occasions such as<br />

birthdays, holidays and Christmas (Fritzsche 111).<br />

Territories that have suffered great historical upheaval are also<br />

likely to retreat into memory; for example, the American South,<br />

at least in the popular imagination, which, like Tennyson’s<br />

lotos-eaters, chose “To muse and brood and live again in memory”<br />

(79).<br />

Forced forgetting, however, is at least as old as history.<br />

As a weapon against imperial tyranny, the Roman Senate instituted<br />

the damnatio memoriae, removing the name <strong>of</strong> a defiant emperor<br />

from archival documents and monumental inscriptions (Le G<strong>of</strong>f 67-<br />

68). After the hated Domitian was assassinated, the Roman Senate<br />

immediately had images <strong>of</strong> him torn down and mentions <strong>of</strong> his name<br />

chipped out <strong>of</strong> inscriptions in order to remove all memory <strong>of</strong> him<br />

from the world (Weinrich 33). Monuments have been razed long<br />

before the fall <strong>of</strong> the Soviet Empire or the invasion <strong>of</strong> Iraq: a<br />

famous instance was the fall from favor <strong>of</strong> Tiberius’s aide,<br />

Sejanus (as described by Juvenal), and the melting down <strong>of</strong> his<br />

equestrian statue: “Then from that face which was second in the<br />

entire world are made pitchers and basins, frying pans and<br />

bedpans” (Hedrick 99).<br />

24


Commemoration is only one <strong>of</strong> the systems designed to anchor<br />

national memory; another is censorship, socially dictated<br />

forgetting, which may be even more important. Ernest Renan laid<br />

this rule down:<br />

Forgetting, and I would even say historical error, are<br />

essential factors in the creation <strong>of</strong> a nation; in this,<br />

the progress <strong>of</strong> historical studies is <strong>of</strong>ten a danger<br />

for nationalité. Historical investigation, in effect,<br />

brings to light facts <strong>of</strong> violence which took place at<br />

the origin <strong>of</strong> all political formations, even those<br />

whose consequences were the most beneficial. Unity is<br />

always brutally created (Matsuda 206).<br />

Renan further pointed out that there was a fundamental procedural<br />

forgetting that holds the people <strong>of</strong> a nation in place: they<br />

“forget that they are not inevitable and that their internal<br />

fissures may be as significant as their external boundaries”<br />

(Olick 117).<br />

Although empires have been systematically obliterated and<br />

lost to memory (e.g., the Incas), the “tyrants <strong>of</strong> the twentieth<br />

century,” Todorov writes, seek “to capture memory systematically<br />

and to bring even its most secret repositories under control . .<br />

. . The traces <strong>of</strong> what once existed have been either erased or<br />

doctored or transformed, lies and inventions replace reality”<br />

13<br />

(2003:113 and 11). The image <strong>of</strong> a toppling statue following a<br />

25


egime change is familiar television fare: The Chinese communist<br />

government tried to destroy all places <strong>of</strong> memory, “such as<br />

temples and monasteries, after the occupation <strong>of</strong> Tibet in 1951"<br />

(Misztal 18). Is this so different from the digital removal <strong>of</strong><br />

the World Trade Center from television and movies? Milan Kundera<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers the following wry example <strong>of</strong> a doctored image: “After the<br />

Communist coup in Czechoslovakia in February <strong>of</strong> 1948 the fur hat<br />

on Party leader Klement Gottwald’s head was the only trace that<br />

remained <strong>of</strong> former Foreign Minister Vlado Clementis because it<br />

had started to snow and he gave Gottwald his hat” (Sayer 76).<br />

Censorship has become an all-embracing policy for nations;<br />

the modern landscape is pocked with absences and disappeared<br />

people, monuments, histories, images. Contemporary states monitor<br />

memory in an ongoing way in the name <strong>of</strong> national security and<br />

engage in techniques <strong>of</strong> disinformation. In George Orwell’s 1984,<br />

Winston Smith puts facts that are embarrassing to the present<br />

conduct <strong>of</strong> the state down a “memory hole” (188). Czech writer<br />

Ivan Klíma notes that “In our country, everything is forever<br />

being remade: beliefs, buildings, and street names” (Sayer 76-<br />

77). One <strong>of</strong> the more extraordinary stories <strong>of</strong> memory manipulation<br />

came out <strong>of</strong> the Korean War, under the name <strong>of</strong> brainwashing.<br />

Brainwashing was one <strong>of</strong> several imaginary events that made the<br />

writing <strong>of</strong> cold war history possible; it was a phantasmal<br />

rediscovery <strong>of</strong> state force which America used to frighten itself<br />

with during the early 1950s. According to Robert J. Lifton,<br />

26


popular writings established brainwashing as "an all-powerful,<br />

irresistible, unfathomable, and magical method <strong>of</strong> achieving total<br />

control over the human mind" (Biderman 549):<br />

The word was seized upon by the public, not only to<br />

refer to the actions <strong>of</strong> the POWs [in Korea] but to<br />

describe such phenomena as the forced public confession<br />

<strong>of</strong> Cardinal Mindszenty in Hungary in 1949, [and] the<br />

earlier forced confessions during the Moscow Show<br />

Trials <strong>of</strong> 1936-1938 . . . and to every type <strong>of</strong><br />

Communist propaganda and indoctrination (James<br />

1986:242).<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> and history<br />

Despite the circulation <strong>of</strong> a term like “historical memory,”<br />

memory and history have been engaged in a serious struggle for<br />

several decades. Mnemosyne was originally goddess <strong>of</strong> both memory<br />

and history. Herodotus, “the father <strong>of</strong> History," wrote his work,<br />

he said, in order to preserve memory--opening in this way: "These<br />

are the researches <strong>of</strong> Herodotus <strong>of</strong> Halicarnassus, which he<br />

publishes, in the hope <strong>of</strong> thereby preserving from decay the<br />

remembrance <strong>of</strong> what men have done" (3).<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> also has has a long history as the handmaiden <strong>of</strong> its<br />

sister art, as a source <strong>of</strong> material to be reworked by the other<br />

more disciplined practice. As Le G<strong>of</strong>f writes: “<strong>Memory</strong> is the raw<br />

27


material <strong>of</strong> history. Whether mental, oral, or written, it is the<br />

living source from which historians draw” (xi). Popular history<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten appeals to memory as a form <strong>of</strong> wisdom (those who do not<br />

remember the past are doomed to repeat it) or an invocation to<br />

revenge (Remember the Alamo! The Maine! Pearl Harbor! Never<br />

forget!).<br />

Hegel distinguished the two as parallel intellectual<br />

currents, memory the subjective and history the objective (Jonker<br />

15). Halbwachs saw them as opposites, since there was a break in<br />

the continuity “between the society reading this history and the<br />

group in the past who acted in or witnessed the event” (Hutton<br />

1993:76). He thought that history focuses on change, memory on<br />

continuity. History, writes Michel de Certeau, tends to depict<br />

the past as “other than ourselves, memory as the same” (1988:16).<br />

If there is no other difference between history and memory, there<br />

is a difference between their nominal subjects: what happened in<br />

the past and how we remember it.<br />

R. G. Collingwood had also declared them distinct, but<br />

believed in the clear superiority <strong>of</strong> history. “<strong>Memory</strong> is not<br />

history, because history is a certain kind <strong>of</strong> organized or<br />

inferential knowledge, and memory is not organized, not<br />

inferential at all” (252). If memory now lords it over history,<br />

it has been a long-awaited shift in the balance between these two<br />

mentalities. In the work <strong>of</strong> Halbwachs and Nora, memory and<br />

history are not even two separate but equal activities: memory is<br />

28


everything, history is less than nothing. That is why, according<br />

to Nora, memory “is always suspect in the eyes <strong>of</strong> history, whose<br />

true mission is to demolish it, to repress it” (3). In a high<br />

Platonizing vein, both declared that history, memory’s poor<br />

synthetic substitute, only becomes necessary when the reign <strong>of</strong><br />

memory fails, and this is the occasion <strong>of</strong> great loss. History<br />

begins when memory is lost: the condition <strong>of</strong> history is the<br />

disappearance <strong>of</strong> the past from the present. <strong>Memory</strong>, on the other<br />

hand “‘reincarnates,’ ‘resurrects,’ ‘recycles,’ and makes the<br />

past ‘reappear’ and live again in the present (Spiegel 162).<br />

Nora equates memory with presence and continuity in all<br />

their fragility, history with the opposite:<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> is life, always embodied in living societies and<br />

as such in permanent evolution, subject to the<br />

dialectic <strong>of</strong> remembering and forgetting, unconscious <strong>of</strong><br />

the distortions to which it is subject, vulnerable in<br />

various ways to appropriation and manipulation . . . .<br />

History, on the other hand, is the reconstruction,<br />

always problematic and incomplete, <strong>of</strong> what is no longer<br />

(3).<br />

Yosef Hayim Yerushalmi similarly distinguishes collective memory<br />

from historical recollection: the former unbroken and perpetually<br />

available, while the latter is the act <strong>of</strong> recovering that which<br />

has been forgotten (197-98). <strong>Memory</strong> is to history as nature is to<br />

artifice, an “organic” flow versus “calculated accounts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

29


past” (Davis 1989:2).<br />

According to Nora and others, living memory has been<br />

replaced by artificial, deliberately fabricated memory-sites,<br />

lieux de mémoire–-a reincarnation <strong>of</strong> the loci memoriae <strong>of</strong> the art<br />

<strong>of</strong> memory. They “arise out <strong>of</strong> a sense that there is no such thing<br />

as spontaneous memory, hence that we must create archives, mark<br />

anniversaries, organize celebrations, pronounce eulogies, and<br />

authenticate documents because such things no longer happen as a<br />

14<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> course” (Nora 7). The memory left over, the memory<br />

that co-exists with history, is false; “True” memory “subsists<br />

only in gestures and habits, unspoken craft traditions, intimate<br />

physical knowledge, ingrained reminiscences, and spontaneous<br />

reflexes” (Nora 8).<br />

“Just when this rupture took place,” Peter Fritzsche writes,<br />

“is not clarified by Nora, but his sturdy artisanal metaphors”<br />

suggest that one <strong>of</strong> the fictions <strong>of</strong> loss that he has in mind is<br />

“the onset <strong>of</strong> the industrial revolution and the sustained<br />

movement from the countryside to the city, which suggests<br />

sometime in the first half <strong>of</strong> the nineteenth century”(92).<br />

Whenever it occurred, the fall is marked by a dominance <strong>of</strong><br />

writing: the last two centuries have been periods devoted to the<br />

institutionalization <strong>of</strong> memory in every discipline, producing<br />

ever-swelling archives. 15<br />

History is writing; in its most accomplished state,<br />

30


narrative. In a postmodern age that is characterized by a<br />

distrust <strong>of</strong> grand narratives, memory is again the valorized mode:<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> is partial, allusive, fragmentary, transient,<br />

and for precisely these reasons is better suited to our<br />

chaotic times . . . . The moments that produce it are<br />

those that, as with the Vietnam War and the AIDS<br />

crisis, “disrupt master narratives <strong>of</strong> American<br />

imperialism, technology, science, and masculinity.”<br />

History is modernism, the state, science, imperialism,<br />

androcentrism, a tool <strong>of</strong> oppression; memory is<br />

postmodernism, the “symbolically excluded,” “the body,”<br />

“a healing device and a tool for redemption” (Sturken<br />

in Klein 138).<br />

Remembrance “must not proceed in the manner <strong>of</strong> a narrative or<br />

still less that <strong>of</strong> a report,” Benjamin declared, “but must, in<br />

the strictest epic and rhapsodic manner, assay its spade in ever-<br />

new places, and in the old ones delve to ever-deeper layers”<br />

(1978:26). Halbwachs believed that memory came to us in<br />

fragments, “formed on the tactics <strong>of</strong> surprise, ruptures, and<br />

overturnings,” as Christine Boyer puts it (68).<br />

Narrative betrays even history, so one common argument goes,<br />

because it is then shaped more by the laws <strong>of</strong> its own<br />

construction than the truth <strong>of</strong> the past. “The most powerful form<br />

<strong>of</strong> forgetting,” Michael Roth writes, “is narrative memory itself,<br />

for it is narrative memory that assimilates (filters,<br />

31


econfigures) the past into a form that can be ‘integrated’ into<br />

the present. Narrative memory, which is at the core <strong>of</strong> historical<br />

representation both on paper and on film transforms the past as a<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> retaining the past” (1995a:100). The argument<br />

against historical narrativity was set by Hayden White. It arises<br />

out <strong>of</strong> a desire to have real events display the<br />

coherence, integrity, fullness, and closure <strong>of</strong> an image<br />

<strong>of</strong> life that is and can only be imaginary. The notion<br />

that sequences <strong>of</strong> real events possess the formal<br />

attributes <strong>of</strong> the stories we tell about imaginary<br />

events could only have its origin in wishes, daydreams,<br />

reveries (1987:24).<br />

Within the context <strong>of</strong> film theory, Christian Metz developed<br />

a model <strong>of</strong> memory in which, between the end <strong>of</strong> a film and the<br />

lighting <strong>of</strong> the theatre, an instantaneous act <strong>of</strong> narrativization<br />

organizes the diverse understandings and associations we have had<br />

<strong>of</strong> the stream <strong>of</strong> images. It is a model based on Freud’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

nachträglichkeit, and it can be applied to other imaginative<br />

experiences, like reading a novel: “the very issue <strong>of</strong><br />

authoritative meanings in a story can be raised only once the end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the story is known. With a novel, for instance, it is only at<br />

the end that one can tell the adumbrations from the false leads;<br />

things fall into place in retrospect” (McCole 276).<br />

Others argue that memory is just as dependent on narrative<br />

32


as history, that narrative is the natural form <strong>of</strong> remembering.<br />

According to Bachelard, for example,<br />

It is reasoning about our past which serves to compose<br />

together disconnected instants, forming a temporal<br />

narrative. This involves a process <strong>of</strong> reflection which<br />

creates a sense <strong>of</strong> time–-it is not time or duration<br />

itself which gives coherence to a disconnected past. We<br />

take events out <strong>of</strong> the temporal flow in order to reason<br />

with them . . . . Events do not simply lay themselves<br />

out along a temporal flow–-they must be ordered<br />

(Russell 11).<br />

There is no original memory which is later transformed through<br />

narrative; memory cannot be thought apart from narrative: it<br />

“does not have any concrete existence in itself and it is always<br />

contiguous to the act <strong>of</strong> being narrated . . . . In short, we do<br />

not make stories out <strong>of</strong> our memories, because memories exist only<br />

16<br />

within our narratives” (Sepulvida 174). Collective memory,<br />

certainly, is only narrative.<br />

Various other binaries are used to proclaim the superiority<br />

<strong>of</strong> memory. History is frozen on the page before us, while memory,<br />

Halbwachs argued, “always occurs behind our backs, where it can<br />

neither be appropriated or controlled” (Boyer 67). <strong>Memory</strong> is<br />

concrete, history is abstract: “<strong>Memory</strong> is the history that cannot<br />

be written, that eludes codification, that remains stubbornly<br />

discreet and that refuses consistency and fixity” (Lambeck<br />

33


2003:211). Nora states that “<strong>Memory</strong> is rooted in the concrete: in<br />

space, gestures, image, and objects. History dwells exclusively<br />

on . . . changes in things and in the relations among things”<br />

(3). <strong>Memory</strong> is more than history, it contains the excess <strong>of</strong> the<br />

past: “the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> historical consciousness continually<br />

exceeds those documentable moments which result in texts and<br />

narratives” (Crane 46).<br />

History is detached and uncommitted while memory is<br />

emotional and politically active. James credited memory with a<br />

warmth and intimacy that could not be found in history, and<br />

Steven Ostovich insists that memory is an “activity in [Hannah]<br />

Arendt's sense <strong>of</strong> this term . . . . Memories are not simply the<br />

usable raw materials or resources for writing history. Rather,<br />

the activity <strong>of</strong> remembering is itself part <strong>of</strong> political life”<br />

(Warnock and Ostovich 245). That politics is certainly<br />

democratic: Halbwachs regarded history as scholarship for the<br />

very few while the collective memory <strong>of</strong> the past is shared by the<br />

whole community.<br />

Le G<strong>of</strong>f, however, warns us against the contemporary<br />

valorization <strong>of</strong> memory:<br />

Recent, naive trends . . . give preference in some<br />

sense to memory, on the ground that it is more<br />

authentic, “truer” than history . . . . [Because the]<br />

workings [<strong>of</strong> memory] are usually unconscious, it is in<br />

reality more dangerously subject to manipulation . . .<br />

34


than the discipline <strong>of</strong> history itself . . . . To<br />

privilege memory excessively is to sink into the<br />

unconquerable flow <strong>of</strong> time (xi-xii).<br />

Most <strong>of</strong> the binaries in play in this field <strong>of</strong> discourse can<br />

and have been inverted to assert the supremacy <strong>of</strong> history over<br />

memory. <strong>Memory</strong> is faulty, prone to error and fading–-unlike the<br />

written text, memories change in time--while history is stable,<br />

the result <strong>of</strong> a solid process <strong>of</strong> investigation and its own<br />

inscription. Michael Frisch and his fellow researchers summed up<br />

the objections <strong>of</strong> others to oral history: “memory was unreliable<br />

as a historical source because it was distorted by physical<br />

deterioration and nostalgia in old age, by the personal bias <strong>of</strong><br />

both interviewer and interviewee, and by the influence <strong>of</strong><br />

collective and retrospective versions <strong>of</strong> the past” (Frisch<br />

1994:33). Peter Novack claims that collective memory simplifies,<br />

“sees events from a single, committed perspective; is impatient<br />

with ambiguities <strong>of</strong> any kind,” while history renders “the<br />

complexity <strong>of</strong> the past . . . . To understand something<br />

historically is to be aware <strong>of</strong> its complexity, to have sufficient<br />

detachment to see it from multiple perspectives, to accept the<br />

ambiguities, including moral ambiguities, <strong>of</strong> protagonists’<br />

motives and behavior” (3-4). But, conversely, one could also say<br />

that testimony (memory on behalf <strong>of</strong> the community) complicates<br />

the simplicities <strong>of</strong> history.<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> is subject to its own psychic laws, so for Dominick<br />

35


LaCapra history is a corrective to memory because it “attempts to<br />

retrieve what it has repressed or ignored, and supplements it in<br />

ways that may provide a measure <strong>of</strong> critical distance on<br />

experience and a basis <strong>of</strong> responsible action” (1994:195). As<br />

Freud demonstrated in his study <strong>of</strong> screen memories, memory is<br />

achronological, liable to work in loops--forward as well as<br />

sideways and backward. “<strong>Memory</strong>,” historian Mona Ozouf has<br />

remarked, “is largely indifferent to a linear unrolling, the<br />

calendar is not its religion” (Matsuda 10). Later commemorations<br />

<strong>of</strong> an event, for example, can be imported into folk memory and<br />

projected back on the original event. And to further complicate<br />

matters, for collective memory, much <strong>of</strong> “memory” is written by<br />

“history.” This collective memory, however, is a mock effigy <strong>of</strong><br />

the real thing, as Nora objected, a resuscitated collective<br />

memory frozen in a stereotypical form.<br />

The dominant binary so magisterially set in place by<br />

Halbwachs and Nora (i.e. memory as real experience and history as<br />

mediated representation) has come under critique as romantic,<br />

nostalgic, and reactionary (see Frow 222 and Levy 89-90). Nora’s<br />

work has been called a “hopelessly nostalgic master narrative”<br />

that obscures “the historicity <strong>of</strong> its own stance vis-à-vis the<br />

premodern past” (Hess 40). Finally, the opposition <strong>of</strong> memory and<br />

history has been challenged, simply because it is a binary in<br />

which memory and history are continually made to play out the<br />

stark, unresolvable opposition between nature and culture. Once<br />

36


we shake ourselves free from the melodrama <strong>of</strong> differences, both<br />

activities look like similar highly mediated discourses separated<br />

only by institutional differences.<br />

Counter-memory<br />

Control <strong>of</strong> collective memory is one <strong>of</strong> the great ends <strong>of</strong><br />

groups, classes, and societies engaged in national or global<br />

politics. Contesting the nation as the primary site <strong>of</strong> collective<br />

memory for many peoples is the global village, represented by<br />

minority populations who have come into their voice and power<br />

strongly motivated by a feeling that they have been left out <strong>of</strong><br />

memory, including their own. Jay Winter feels that in some ways<br />

counter-memory has replaced national memory; that although, for<br />

example, commemoration has traditionally celebrated the<br />

historical winners, there have recently “been many other<br />

instances <strong>of</strong> commemoration as an expression <strong>of</strong> the tragic history<br />

<strong>of</strong> persecuted minorities,” the Jewish, gay, African-American and<br />

Japanese-American communities, for example:<br />

Commemoration no longer serves those centripetal forces<br />

that made the nation in the previous century into the<br />

most important social and historical agent, but the<br />

centrifugal forces that are generally considered to be<br />

the defining characteristics <strong>of</strong> postmodernism.<br />

Contemporary commemoration and the return to memory<br />

37


that is expressed by it were both born on the grave <strong>of</strong><br />

the state as the center <strong>of</strong> all creative politics<br />

(Winter 74 and Ankersmit 171).<br />

As Walter Benjamin wrote, the task <strong>of</strong> remembrance is “to save<br />

what has miscarried” (Jay 22).<br />

Group identity is worked out against the dominant discourse.<br />

At every moment, countless revisionist versions <strong>of</strong> countless<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficial narratives are circulating in rich ambient play.<br />

National memory may be deemed false not only because it is shaped<br />

by national desires and the laws <strong>of</strong> narrative but also because it<br />

is rhetorically totalizing, intent on absorbing the entire past.<br />

Another effect <strong>of</strong> narrative is to make the past feel told, fully<br />

understood, what Claude Lanzmann calls an “absolute obscenity in<br />

the project <strong>of</strong> understanding” (Roth 1995b:209).<br />

Utterances and images that articulate the memories <strong>of</strong><br />

relatively powerless groups, usually written in resistance to<br />

dominant narratives, are commonly referred to as counter-<br />

17<br />

memories. National memory and counter-memory meet and struggle<br />

at various sites <strong>of</strong> contention:<br />

In the United States, monuments such as the Vietnam War<br />

Memorial, special displays such as the Enola Gay<br />

exhibit, commemorative occasions such as the<br />

Christopher Columbus quintecentennial (?), the decision<br />

to honor Martin Luther King Jr. through a public<br />

holiday, and attempts to create theme parks out <strong>of</strong><br />

38


hallowed sites such as Gettysburg have all been the<br />

focus <strong>of</strong> intense scrutiny, negotiation and contestation<br />

(Tai 2001a:9).<br />

This other more diffuse and multivoiced discourse represents a<br />

democratization <strong>of</strong> memory: “For those who regard the national<br />

‘heritage’ as a sacred text,” John Gillis reminds us, this<br />

democratization “is equivalent to pr<strong>of</strong>anation, or, what is worse,<br />

18<br />

cultural suicide” (Tai 2001b: and Gillis 19).<br />

What should ideally come out <strong>of</strong> this struggle? Do the<br />

various versions ultimately combine in a new totalizing<br />

narrative, a more or less acceptable authoritative version <strong>of</strong> the<br />

past? Do they arrange themselves in sequences <strong>of</strong> probability or<br />

do they just keep multiplying? This last is the conservative<br />

nightmare, but it is also the condition <strong>of</strong> history in<br />

postmodernity. However, memory and counter-memory may not lay<br />

themselves out so neatly against one another; counter-memory,<br />

Svetlana Boym reminds us, is “not merely a collection <strong>of</strong><br />

alternative facts and texts but also an alternative way <strong>of</strong><br />

reading by using ambiguity, irony, doublespeak . . . [and]<br />

private intonation” (62).<br />

As opposed to the specious comfort <strong>of</strong> the closure <strong>of</strong>fered by<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficial narrative, counter-memory, it has been argued, <strong>of</strong>fers<br />

true healing. It allows for empowerment, the re-enchantment <strong>of</strong><br />

experience, and the possibility <strong>of</strong> properly mourning the past.<br />

Discussing the Truth and Reconciliation Commission hearings in<br />

39


South Africa, the writer Njabulo Ndebele was hopeful that “the<br />

narratives <strong>of</strong> memory” which are brought forth will help establish<br />

a more truthful understanding <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> apartheid.<br />

The dynamics and therapeutics <strong>of</strong> counter-memory are most<br />

brilliantly presented by Toni Morrison in her slavery novel,<br />

Beloved, as it works to create new national memory, to provide<br />

(quoting Catherine Hall) its share <strong>of</strong> the “‘memory work’ which<br />

which needs to be done so that African Americans and white<br />

Americans can recover the history <strong>of</strong> slavery and understand its<br />

foundational place in the construction <strong>of</strong> the United States”<br />

(31). In the novel, the black community is scattered by<br />

suffering, so “disremembered and unaccounted for,” that the story<br />

to be passed on “is not a story to pass on”; if it is not re-<br />

remembered, Morrison suggests, “it will haunt and disrupt<br />

contemporary society” (Morrison 274-5 and Hall 31).<br />

Truth and reconciliation hearings like those in South Africa<br />

have also been held in Chile and Serbia. And these line up with<br />

current philosophical interest in the ethics <strong>of</strong> memory: memory as<br />

an act <strong>of</strong> justice, because, as Christa Wolf says in her memoir, A<br />

Model Childhood, “memory is not a solid block fitted into our<br />

brain once and for all; rather, perhaps–-if big words are<br />

permitted–-a repeated moral act”(143).. In his Ethics <strong>of</strong> <strong>Memory</strong>,<br />

Avishai Margolit considers the inscription in our ethical code <strong>of</strong><br />

an absolute obligation to remember. Regarding the Holocaust,<br />

Margolit asks if we also have an obligation to forgive and if<br />

40


forgiveness does not inevitably lead to forgetting. His<br />

conclusion in this case is that we do have an obligation to<br />

forgive–“an obligation founded in the duty that we have to<br />

ourselves to prevent the deformity <strong>of</strong> our own lives”–-but he does<br />

not admit that this includes forgetting (Barker ).<br />

Dangerous memory<br />

Into the sea <strong>of</strong> repressed “rememory” that Morrison lays down<br />

as a condition <strong>of</strong> African American life comes the dialectical<br />

image <strong>of</strong> Beloved, murdered at her mother's hand. Not content to<br />

remain a mere memory trace, frozen in history forever as “the<br />

crawling-already baby" <strong>of</strong> two, she arrives in corporeal form as a<br />

young woman <strong>of</strong> twenty, and<br />

disrupts the lives <strong>of</strong> Sethe, Denver and Paul D just as<br />

the pleasure <strong>of</strong> their reunion threatens to override<br />

once and for all the horror <strong>of</strong> their past. . . . she<br />

embodies and brings with her the Then, the collective<br />

memory, and the collective rage, <strong>of</strong> the slaves forced<br />

from their ancestral homes, piled in ship holds for the<br />

Middle Passage, brutalized by the system <strong>of</strong> slavery<br />

(Nutting online).<br />

Ankersmit posits an extreme opposition between memory and<br />

history as unconscious and conscious. <strong>Memory</strong> “stands for all that<br />

was repressed, ignored, or suppressed in the human past and<br />

41


therefore by its very nature could never attain to the . . .<br />

domain <strong>of</strong> ‘history’ in the traditional sense” (154). In defiance<br />

<strong>of</strong> memory’s many connections to subjectivity, at times it emerges<br />

violently, threatening to undo the subject. Memories flash up to<br />

overwhelm or undermine the subject and put a temporary halt to<br />

simple, progressive narrative understanding. Steven Ostovich<br />

calls this “dangerous memory,” and, according to the theologian<br />

Johann Baptist Metz, such memories “break through the centre-<br />

point <strong>of</strong> our lives and reveal new and dangerous insights for our<br />

present. They illuminate for a few moments and with a harsh<br />

steady light the questionable nature <strong>of</strong> things we have apparently<br />

come to terms with” (241).<br />

In The Content <strong>of</strong> the Form, White identifies these radical<br />

visitations with the traditional sublime–-that which is too<br />

terrible to be known (Megill 53). Saul Friedlander distinguishes<br />

common memory (after Lawrence Langer), “which tends to establish<br />

coherence, closure and possibly a redemptive stance,” and deep<br />

memory: “that which remains essentially inarticulable and<br />

unrepresentable, that which continues to exist as unresolved<br />

trauma just beyond the reach <strong>of</strong> meaning” (Friedlander 1992:41 and<br />

Young 1998:666-67). An apt contemporary image for dangerous<br />

memory might be the Japanese monster figure Godzilla who,<br />

Yoshikuni Igarashi has argued, represents<br />

wartime memory that haunted postwar Japan. Godzilla’s<br />

monstrous body stood in for the memories <strong>of</strong> war and<br />

42


loss that could not be recuperated by the resurgent<br />

Japanese nationalism <strong>of</strong> the 1950s . . . . <strong>Memory</strong><br />

returned to the city <strong>of</strong> Tokyo as a monstrous body,<br />

mercilessly destroying what had been reconstructed<br />

since the war” (16 and 154).<br />

Freud’s repressed or traumatic memory and Benjamin’s<br />

dialectical images are also versions <strong>of</strong> dangerous memory:<br />

“Central to the differently nuanced modernisms <strong>of</strong> Benjamin and<br />

Freud was a view <strong>of</strong> memory as a hidden substratum whose meanings<br />

might run counter to those <strong>of</strong> surface understanding–-<strong>of</strong> ideology,<br />

19<br />

or <strong>of</strong> consciousness” (Radstone 2003b:168). “Traumatic memory,”<br />

Winter writes, “was a time bomb that once detonated could wreck<br />

lives and families. Its evident and troubling existence<br />

undermined more comforting or <strong>of</strong>ficially sanctioned memories,<br />

heroic narratives about war, about the reintegration <strong>of</strong> soldiers<br />

20<br />

into peacetime society” (84). Dangerous memories are<br />

unconscious and involuntary memories. Recovered memories <strong>of</strong><br />

childhood abuse are a controversial contemporary form <strong>of</strong><br />

dangerous memory; critics declare they emerge from nothing deeper<br />

than therapeutic insinuation.<br />

Benjamin was one <strong>of</strong> the early chroniclers <strong>of</strong> dangerous<br />

memory and its great poet. He adapted the notion from his reading<br />

<strong>of</strong> Proust, but his dialectical image was a subversive version <strong>of</strong><br />

Proust’s involuntary memory; he called it “Humankind's<br />

involuntary memory” (Rieusset-Lemarié). In his "Theses on the<br />

43


Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History," he wrote that “The past can be seized<br />

only as an image which flashes up at the instant when it can be<br />

recognized and is never seen again” (1969:255). Benjamin’s<br />

storyteller creates dialectical images that “fuse past and<br />

present, images that shock the reader into a critical awareness<br />

<strong>of</strong> what has been left out . . . and now must be reclaimed and<br />

redeemed”–-an image in “which the Then and the Now come together<br />

into a constellation like a flash <strong>of</strong> lightning” (Nutting and<br />

Bejamin 1989:50).<br />

Benjamin also wrote <strong>of</strong> a recovery <strong>of</strong> memory “When the half-<br />

light <strong>of</strong> habit denies the plate the necessary light for years,<br />

until one day, from an alien source it flashes as if from burning<br />

magnesium powder, and now a snapshot transfixes the room’s image<br />

on the plate”; “Like ultraviolet rays, memory shows to each man<br />

in the book <strong>of</strong> life a script that invisibly and prophetically<br />

glossed the text” (Benjamin 1978:56-57 and 89). 21<br />

If history is responsible narrative, then dangerous memory<br />

(perhaps all memory) is disruptive, working toward narrative’s<br />

subversion. Derrida opened his lectures on memory with the<br />

following question, “Why do those who love Mnemosyne lack the<br />

ability to tell stories? Is it possible to narrate a history out<br />

<strong>of</strong> our memories?” (Sepulvida 168). <strong>Memory</strong> is disruptive for two<br />

reasons: At its best it is involuntary, as Proust declared; it<br />

speaks through us against our will. Secondly, it is assaultive,<br />

in line with Freud’s and Benjamin’s recasting <strong>of</strong> experience in<br />

44


modernity--no longer a tranquil flow, but a battery, a series <strong>of</strong><br />

shocks. <strong>Memory</strong> for Benjamin “is unable to deliver a full<br />

reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the past. It recovers “images which are<br />

detached from their original contexts and which are like torsos<br />

and broken statues in the gallery <strong>of</strong> a Renaissance collector”<br />

22<br />

(Emden 219-20). As Nutting says, Benjamin’s dialectical images<br />

interrupt and destabilize the comforting narrative <strong>of</strong> history:<br />

“Progressive history, which looks ever-forward and sees its past<br />

only in terms <strong>of</strong> its present and future effects, omits mention <strong>of</strong><br />

past injustices and facilitates the devastation <strong>of</strong> the oppressed”<br />

(online). Dangerous memories are performed in a minor historical<br />

mode (“the Leidensgeschichte or history <strong>of</strong> suffering”) that runs<br />

under the “history <strong>of</strong> progress” (Ostovich 243).<br />

Dangerous memories are <strong>of</strong>ten belated effects <strong>of</strong> the great<br />

traumas <strong>of</strong> modernity, like Hiroshima (a flashbulb memory par<br />

excellence) or the Holocaust. Michael Schudson observes that<br />

“There are two kinds <strong>of</strong> studies <strong>of</strong> collective memory--those that<br />

examine the Holocaust, and all the others” (Perlstein 16). That<br />

event is posed by contemporary students <strong>of</strong> memory as a unique,<br />

virtually transcendental, moment, occurring in history yet<br />

marking an outside or an end to history: an event, Hayden White<br />

writes, which escapes “the grasp <strong>of</strong> any language even to describe<br />

it and <strong>of</strong> any medium–-verbal, visual, oral, or gestural–-to<br />

represent it, much less <strong>of</strong> any historical account adequately to<br />

explain it” (date:30). LaCapra considers Auschwitz to be an event<br />

45


where “an extreme threshold or outer limit <strong>of</strong> transgression was<br />

crossed,” and Klein regards the attempted Nazi extermination <strong>of</strong><br />

the Jews as the “ultimate traumatic decentering <strong>of</strong> history and<br />

subjectivity” (LaCapra 1998:6 and Klein 139). 23<br />

Given such attitudes, the Holocaust can only be held in<br />

place by memory, not history. History, with its all-knowing<br />

subject position and its appropriating language, is felt to be<br />

disrespectful to such events (Ankersmit 178). History is the Nazi<br />

extermination all over again: “In short, the totalizing gestures<br />

that are part and parcel <strong>of</strong> the Hegelian subject appear to<br />

replicate a certain fascist gesture and to evade the fundamental<br />

trauma <strong>of</strong> the Holocaust by recouping some meaning from it”<br />

(Eisenstein 13).<br />

Although other genocides have been quite easily forgotten<br />

and dropped from Western collective memory, arguments exposing<br />

this particular exceptionalist claim seem to carry no force; the<br />

Holocaust is protected by a “double-binding injunction perhaps<br />

best articulated by Elie Wiesel: ‘Never Forget/you can never<br />

know’” (Spiegel 158). “For Levinas it is the immemorial, for<br />

Lyotard the unrepresentable, for Blanchot the catastrophe that<br />

erases the possibility <strong>of</strong> knowledge,” Frow writes, and yet, he<br />

notes, just the opposite seems to be the case; the Holocaust is<br />

also a ubiquitous trope in Western culture: “It is an<br />

overwhelming fact <strong>of</strong> our daily lives, constantly referred to both<br />

in scholarly and political cultures and in the mass media. There<br />

46


are Holocaust museums and memorials in most countries <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Western world”(241). Yet this horrific uniqueness, Friedlander<br />

warns, has a term to it: “With the passage <strong>of</strong> two or three<br />

decades at most, the memory <strong>of</strong> the Shoah will be essentially<br />

ritualized for some and historicized for the great majority, like<br />

any other past event saved from oblivion. The destruction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Jews <strong>of</strong> Europe will become an empty formula and, in any case,<br />

‘mere history’” (1993:48). 24<br />

Collective memory does not so much claim to be an accurate<br />

account <strong>of</strong> an event (actually, it does claim to be that but we do<br />

not credit that claim as we do the similar claim <strong>of</strong> history), as<br />

an accurate account <strong>of</strong> how it is remembered. Personal memory,<br />

therefore, can correct history but collective memory never can.<br />

Perhaps counter-memory and dangerous memory should not be aligned<br />

with collective memory but opposed to it. The relationship<br />

between the larger and lesser concepts is slippery. The phrase,<br />

after all, is invoked to refer to counter-memories that challenge<br />

an <strong>of</strong>ficial record, as well as the opposite: the dominant meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> an event within a culture at that time, against which wave<br />

after wave <strong>of</strong> revisionary history is written. Michael Lambeck<br />

finds “a curious tension between looking to memory for a new<br />

source <strong>of</strong> authority . . . and looking to memory in order to defer<br />

and displace the very idea <strong>of</strong> certainty and authority”<br />

(2003:211). Ge<strong>of</strong>frey Hartman distinguishes between two senses <strong>of</strong><br />

collective memory, between a collective memory which is bound up<br />

47


with community, as Halbwachs proposed, and a public memory<br />

“dominated by the media that all but destroys the former” (Bal<br />

xvii).<br />

<strong>Memory</strong> as theological<br />

Remorse--is <strong>Memory</strong>--awake--<br />

Her Parties all astir--<br />

A presence <strong>of</strong> Departed Acts--<br />

At window--and at Door--<br />

Emily Dickinson<br />

Counter-memory and dangerous memory are considered to be<br />

redemptive. One last binary should be mentioned as dividing<br />

history from memory: history as secular and memory as sacred.<br />

Klein argues that memory is always implicitly a theological<br />

concept, that “the secularization and privatization <strong>of</strong> memory”<br />

cannot really unhook it from that context (132). He infers from<br />

its genealogy that the work we wish memory to do is “to re-<br />

enchant our relation with the world and pour presence back into<br />

the past”: “It is no accident,” Frow also writes, “that much <strong>of</strong><br />

the vocabulary Nora uses to describe memory–-that <strong>of</strong> piety, <strong>of</strong><br />

ritual, <strong>of</strong> the relation to the ancestors–-is religious, and<br />

evokes a continuity <strong>of</strong> passage between the living and the dead”<br />

(Klein 145 and Frow 223).<br />

For Nora and others, memory and history encode the more<br />

general opposition <strong>of</strong> sacred and secular: “If we still dwelled<br />

among our memories,” he says, “Every one <strong>of</strong> our acts, down to the<br />

48


most quotidian, would be experienced, in an intimate<br />

identification <strong>of</strong> act and meaning, as a religious repetition <strong>of</strong><br />

sempiternal practice” (2). The mystical “true” memory that Nora<br />

invokes is one in which there is no separation between the<br />

present and the past. As in Mircea Eliade’s realm <strong>of</strong> the sacred,<br />

the past inhabits the present (but blissfully, without weight or<br />

pain), and the long run <strong>of</strong> historical time collapses under its<br />

grace.<br />

Judaism and Christianity have been described as “religions<br />

<strong>of</strong> remembrance.” “Divine acts <strong>of</strong> salvation situated in the past<br />

form the content <strong>of</strong> faith and the object <strong>of</strong> rites.” Deuteronomy<br />

calls the faithful to remember in the Old Testament, and in the<br />

New, “The Last Supper founds redemption on the remembrance <strong>of</strong><br />

Jesus,” a command to the disciples, “Do this in remembrance <strong>of</strong><br />

me” (Le G<strong>of</strong>f 69 and Weinrich 22). A “plethora <strong>of</strong> memorial<br />

injunctions eventually becomes condensed into the Six<br />

Remembrances that observant Jews still recite each day,” and the<br />

injunction “Remember!” appears in the Christian bible 170 times<br />

(Schwarz 57 and Heller 231). For Yerushalmi and others, the Jews<br />

were the archetypal people <strong>of</strong> memory, a people who had only<br />

recently adapted themselves to living with history.<br />

Coda: The Postmodern Turn<br />

Modernism was hostile to memory in its art and architecture,<br />

49


ut its literature contained extensive memory palaces in the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> Proust, Mann, and Joyce in particular. Postmodern literature,<br />

according to Fredric Jameson, is saturated with the presence <strong>of</strong><br />

the past, but it is a paper-thin and unruly past circulating as<br />

pastiche. Klein on the other hand seems to suggest that our<br />

current interest in memory is essentially postmodern and quite<br />

essentialist: “The new memory work displaces the old hermeneutics<br />

<strong>of</strong> suspicion with a therapeutic discourse whose quasi-religious<br />

gestures link it with memory’s deep semantic past” (141). For<br />

Klein, the postmodern turn is a return to premodern community<br />

(via the Internet) and orality (via electronic imaging).<br />

A more familiar postmodern establishment, heralded by Freud,<br />

claims there is no difference between memory and one <strong>of</strong> its<br />

others, fantasy--that indeterminacy rules in its production<br />

(several earlier moments in the history <strong>of</strong> memory discourse have<br />

brushed up against this conclusion). Like the screen memory,<br />

postmodern memory is produced at the site <strong>of</strong> remembering. It does<br />

not retrieve the past but recreates it–-an already familiar<br />

conclusion. As Belinda Barnet writes, “There is no lived memory,<br />

no originary, internal experience stored somewhere that<br />

corresponds to a certain event in our lives. <strong>Memory</strong> is entirely<br />

reconstructed by the machine <strong>of</strong> memory” (online).<br />

In the postmodern world not only has the concept <strong>of</strong> an<br />

archive been abandoned for “memorial dynamism,” but even the<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> an indelible trace is no longer meaningful ( ). If the<br />

50


metaphor <strong>of</strong> the archive persists it is the archive as<br />

pandemonium, as infinite wandering in Borgesian tales like “The<br />

Secret Miracle” or “The Library <strong>of</strong> Babel.” In Alain Resnais’s<br />

1957 film, Toute la mémoire du monde, the camera drifts across<br />

library stacks and storage rooms filled with endless rows and<br />

piles <strong>of</strong> useless and forgotten print.<br />

In the postmodern turn we lose the past, but this connection<br />

had originally been an act <strong>of</strong> faith on the order <strong>of</strong> Locke’s<br />

belief that perceptions actually correspond to the qualities <strong>of</strong><br />

objects. Why, then, continue to bother about a past that is so<br />

far removed from the noble concept staked out by philosophy and<br />

history? The past is now a commodity, the “date-mark” <strong>of</strong> Freud’s<br />

day dreams or Barthes’s “effect <strong>of</strong> the real”--necessary but<br />

meaningless (Freud 9.147 and Barthes 1968). Beckett’s work is<br />

emblematic <strong>of</strong> this turn: His narrator “cannot remember the past,<br />

because he has no identity except the one assigned to him from<br />

his surroundings. He repeatedly chooses silence rather than<br />

assimilate himself into an oppressive collective memory” (Remmler<br />

27).<br />

51

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!