19.06.2013 Views

ÉTIENNE GILSON AND THE ACTUS ESSENDI

ÉTIENNE GILSON AND THE ACTUS ESSENDI

ÉTIENNE GILSON AND THE ACTUS ESSENDI

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Dewan: Gilson and the actus essendi<br />

point in adding to the affirmation of its reality that, over and above being supremely real,<br />

it exists. 29<br />

Here, Gilson is presenting to us the minds of thinkers who have not gone as far<br />

as Thomas Aquinas. God’s essence is “the perfection of entity itself” and<br />

“existence” JUST posits it in actual reality. Existence seems to add no new<br />

important target of metaphysical analysis.<br />

At this point Gilson summarizes the three arguments of 1.3.4. And upon them<br />

he comments:<br />

Dialectically speaking, the justification of the conclusion is faultless: “God is His own<br />

being, and not only His own essence.” There must therefore be some reason why it has<br />

failed to win universal approval, and the reason is that all such dialectical demonstrations<br />

presuppose the notion of being proper to Saint Thomas Aquinas. If the ultimate meaning<br />

of the word “being” is the act of being, the esse or actus essendi in virtue of which alone<br />

things can be called “beings,” then all the arguments of Thomas Aquinas are convincing<br />

and all lead to a necessary conclusion. To those who perceive that to be is, in every thing,<br />

the ultimate act that causes it to be a being, the demonstration becomes crystal-clear. One<br />

should rather say that there is nothing left to demonstrate. He whose true name is HE<br />

WHO IS necessarily is, so to speak, 30 by essence, the very act of being itself in its<br />

absolute purity. God does not own it, He is it. 31<br />

Here one cannot but agree that everything depends on one’s understanding of the<br />

notions and their implications. This is true of any demonstration in any matter.<br />

I would hardly agree, however, that there is nothing left of the demonstration. It<br />

is an argument which presupposes that we know what is meant by the esse of<br />

things, and even presupposes that we find in some things that their essence is<br />

other than their esse. 32 Thus, for example, the second argument in the body of ST<br />

1.3.4 has as a key premise:<br />

… it is necessary that esse itself be compared to the essence which is other than it as act<br />

to potency. 33<br />

29<br />

ECP, p. 118.<br />

30<br />

My italics on this expression: Gilson regularly seems to wish to downplay “per<br />

essentiam,” “by essence,” said of God.<br />

31<br />

ECP, p. 119.<br />

32<br />

Cf. John M.Quinn, O.S.A., The Thomism of Etienne Gilson: A Critical Study, Villanova,<br />

PA: Villanova University Press, 1971. I agree entirely with Quinn that Gilson’s approach<br />

to the real distinction between esse and essence in caused things is wrong. As Quinn says,<br />

if the identity of esse and essence in God is not based on the already known real distinction<br />

in other things, then that doctrine of identity loses all its force. [80-81] But Quinn thinks<br />

[83] that the reversal of order by Gilson, attempting to start with God, is what “accounts<br />

for Gilson’s hesitancy a about whether the real distinction is demonstrable.” I believe that<br />

I offer a better reason, viz. Gilson’s failure to identify Thomas’s esse with the actual<br />

existence of the essence, what Gilson calls the “state” of existence.<br />

33<br />

The Latin runs:<br />

…Oportet … quod ipsum esse comparetur ad essentiam quae est aliud ab ipso sicut<br />

actus ad potentiam. [Ottawa ed. 19a1012]<br />

81

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!