20.07.2013 Views

Question 1 What did Marx mean with his formu - University of Utah

Question 1 What did Marx mean with his formu - University of Utah

Question 1 What did Marx mean with his formu - University of Utah

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2007fa 71<br />

<strong>Marx</strong> describes the second peculiarity <strong>with</strong> the definition: concrete labor is the expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> abstract labor. T<strong>his</strong> <strong>mean</strong>s that abstract labor such as writing a book expresses the concrete<br />

labor which would be the printing <strong>of</strong> the book which then creates the value for paper.<br />

<strong>Marx</strong> defines the third peculiarity: a privately produced commodity in equivalent form<br />

counts as its opposite, directly social labor. An example <strong>of</strong> t<strong>his</strong> might be a mining company<br />

that mines gold and so has direct social powers <strong>mean</strong>ing they can directly exchange for all<br />

other commodities.<br />

Hans: Your third point is good, the other two are worthless. Just to avoid confusion by the readers, abstract and<br />

concrete labor are not the same as mental and physical labor, and paper has value even if it is not printed or written<br />

on.<br />

Message [152] referenced by [161] and [201]. Next Message by MichaelM is [174].<br />

[160] Melissa: graded A– T<strong>his</strong> is peculiar. In <strong>Marx</strong>’s words the three peculiarities <strong>of</strong> the<br />

equivalent form are as follows:<br />

1- “Use value becomes the form <strong>of</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> its opposite, value”.<br />

2- “Concrete labor is the expression <strong>of</strong> abstract labor.”<br />

3- “A privately produced commodity in its equivalent form counts as its opposite, directly<br />

social labor.”<br />

How I interpret these three peculiarities is as follows:<br />

1-For my example I am going to use the two commodities flour and bread. Both <strong>of</strong> these<br />

commodities have their own different use value. Let’s say the baker wants to exchange a loaf<br />

<strong>of</strong> bread for one pound <strong>of</strong> flour. By accepting t<strong>his</strong> <strong>of</strong>fer and exchanging one pound <strong>of</strong> flour<br />

for one loaf <strong>of</strong> bread, the market now has an idea <strong>of</strong> how much labor is required to produce<br />

one pound <strong>of</strong> flour, it is equivalent to one loaf <strong>of</strong> bread. The bread has an equivalent form <strong>of</strong><br />

one pound <strong>of</strong> flour.<br />

2-If the bread and the flour are exchanged it is for the fact that both commodities require<br />

human labor. The baker would not exchange <strong>his</strong> bread for something that does not have<br />

human labor in it, such as water.<br />

3-Now let’s say that the baker is producing bread for <strong>his</strong> own use, to better <strong>his</strong> family and<br />

social status. If he bakes too much bread and exchanges it for another commodity, the bread<br />

now has social worth. It can be exchanged socially to “purchase” other commodities, acting<br />

like money.<br />

Hans: I am struck that you use water as example for a commodity that has no labor in it. A lot <strong>of</strong> labor is necessary<br />

before water can come out <strong>of</strong> the faucet in your home. The most critical issue <strong>of</strong> global warming for <strong>Utah</strong> is that the<br />

area will become increasingly arid. The winter snowpack in our mountains is a gift <strong>of</strong> nature which will be difficult<br />

and expensive to replace. Water is a precious, and potentially a very expensive, commodity.<br />

Ashley: While reading t<strong>his</strong> submission, I thought <strong>of</strong> the same thing that Hans thought <strong>of</strong>. How can water be an<br />

example <strong>of</strong> something that does not require labor? I see it as having the same characteristics as flour in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

using labor. I think the point that you were trying to make is that if you were to go to a lake or an ocean, it doesn’t<br />

cost anything for you to take water there, however, you can’t get flour just anywhere. It requires labor to make flour<br />

because it doesn’t come like that in its natural form. It’s not like water where you can drink it in its natural form.<br />

Flour has to be made. Is that what you were trying to say?<br />

Other than that, I agree <strong>with</strong> what you are saying. You can figure out the value <strong>of</strong> one item in comparison<br />

to another when it is exchanged in the market. Along the same lines, if a baker produces bread, and has excess<br />

amounts <strong>of</strong> it, it’s a great idea for them to use it as a social worth.<br />

72 2007fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Good work, Ashley, trying to understand how Melissa came to say what she was saying. T<strong>his</strong> is part <strong>of</strong><br />

“immanent critique:” if someone comes to a conclusion other than your own, you are trying to understand why that<br />

person came to that conclusion.<br />

Message [160] referenced by [161] and [163]. Next Message by Melissa is [181].<br />

[161] Hans: Spontaneous Mirroring and Spontaneous Mystification. In section 3 <strong>of</strong><br />

the first chapter, <strong>Marx</strong> describes how the commodity owners, by exchanging their commodities,<br />

spontaneously mirror the inner structure <strong>of</strong> their relations <strong>of</strong> production on the surface<br />

<strong>of</strong> the market. Two examples <strong>of</strong> t<strong>his</strong> mirroring:<br />

(1) The invisible commonality and inner measure in all commodities, their value (congealed<br />

abstract labor), is reflected on the surface as their exterior common measure in money.<br />

(2) At the beginning <strong>of</strong> t<strong>his</strong> class I admonished you that whenever you think <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

you must be aware that each commodity has two separate aspects, its use-value and<br />

its exchange-value. Now you can see t<strong>his</strong> inner separation reproduced in the separation <strong>of</strong><br />

the world <strong>of</strong> commodities into the ordinary commodities (use-value) and money (exchangevalue).<br />

Such mirroring is not unusual. Examples can be found in all sciences and in real life<br />

where things, through their activity, reveal their inner structure. It is much more unusual if<br />

things can be effective for a long time <strong>with</strong>out revealing themselves. Capitalism is unusual<br />

in t<strong>his</strong> second sense. It is a social order which can only thrive because and as long as<br />

individuals in capitalism do not understand their own social relations. That is why <strong>Marx</strong><br />

explores in section 4 <strong>of</strong> the first chapter the limits <strong>of</strong> t<strong>his</strong> spontaneous mirroring, i.e., the<br />

mystification inherent in the commodity relations.<br />

T<strong>his</strong> mystification does not start in section 4. Already in section 3, <strong>Marx</strong> shows that the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the value form has a contradictory character: it reveals the inner relations<br />

more and more accurately on the side <strong>of</strong> the relative form <strong>of</strong> value, but at the same time it<br />

mystifies them if one looks at the other pole, the equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value. Let me explain.<br />

If an ordinary commodity expresses its value in a certain amount <strong>of</strong> the general equivalent,<br />

it reveals the structure in which it is embedded. It says that it has something in common<br />

<strong>with</strong> all other commodities that has nothing to do <strong>with</strong> its use-value. It says that in t<strong>his</strong> relationship<br />

<strong>with</strong> other commodities its labor does not count as useful labor but abstract labor.<br />

And it says that t<strong>his</strong> labor will only get social credit if it fits into the social division <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

But if you look at it from the other side, from the side <strong>of</strong> the money commodity (gold),<br />

then the underlying social structure is mystified rather than revealed. Now it is the special<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, namely, it being gold, which gives it value, i.e., direct access<br />

to every other commodity. The private labor producing gold does not need to pass the test<br />

whether it fits into the social division <strong>of</strong> labor, but it gives immediate social powers. T<strong>his</strong><br />

labor has these powers not because it is the expenditure <strong>of</strong> abstract human labor, but because<br />

it is the specific concrete labor <strong>of</strong> producing gold.<br />

I just repeated the three peculiarities <strong>of</strong> the equivalent form. In view <strong>of</strong> t<strong>his</strong> dissonance<br />

between form and content <strong>of</strong> the private labor producing gold, it is not surprising that t<strong>his</strong><br />

weirdness has been eliminated since <strong>Marx</strong> wrote Capital. Today we are no longer in a<br />

commodity money regime. The value <strong>of</strong> money is no longer guaranteed by the labor going

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!