09.10.2013 Views

Erfahrung und Analyse Experience and Analysis - Austrian Ludwig ...

Erfahrung und Analyse Experience and Analysis - Austrian Ludwig ...

Erfahrung und Analyse Experience and Analysis - Austrian Ludwig ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

VALUE-PREDICATES AND<br />

VALUE-PROPERTIES<br />

John F. Drummond, Bronx, New York<br />

Husserl’s moral theory st<strong>and</strong>s on two pillars: an account of<br />

evaluative intentionality <strong>and</strong> an analogy between formal<br />

logic <strong>and</strong> formal axiology. This paper explores Husserl’s<br />

account of the analogy between formal logic <strong>and</strong> formal<br />

axiology in order to reveal features of evaluative intentionality.<br />

The analogy appeals to the similarity between the<br />

grammar of “cognitive” judgments <strong>and</strong> “evaluative” judgments.<br />

However, this grammatical similarity masks important<br />

logical differences that point in turn to important<br />

phenomenological <strong>and</strong> ontological differences. The paper<br />

attempts to discern these differences by investigating a<br />

series of logical distinctions regarding adjectives, the<br />

“predicates” belonging to the judgments. This investigation<br />

will point to some conclusions about the ontological status<br />

of “value-properties.” More important, these logical <strong>and</strong><br />

ontological differences necessarily point to differences in<br />

the manner in which “cognitive” <strong>and</strong> “evaluative” experiences<br />

disclose their objects. The affective dimension of<br />

meaning involved in judgments of value introduces new<br />

structures into the objectivity, the normativity, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

“truth” of evaluative experiences <strong>and</strong> judgments. The<br />

affective dimension of experience transforms not only our<br />

experience but the ontological possibilities at work in the<br />

experienced world.<br />

METZGER, KANT AND<br />

THE PERCEPTION OF CAUSALITY<br />

Maurizio Ferraris, Turino, Italy<br />

Allow me to tell you a true story, related to me by Paolo<br />

Bozzi.<br />

In 1943-1944, Wolfgang Metzger was serving in the army<br />

in Cassino, Italy. One day he went to the toilet in the<br />

barracks where his company was quartered, <strong>and</strong> when he<br />

was done he flushed the toilet. At that very moment a<br />

grenade hit the barracks, so that Metzger got the<br />

impression that by flushing the toilet he had been the<br />

cause of the disaster. Metzger saw such causality, just as<br />

one sees a chair or a color.<br />

One way to straighten out the whole matter would be to<br />

claim that Metzger had been victim of some kind of optical<br />

illusion. But if we try to look into it more carefully, we<br />

realize that deep in Metzger’s toilet lies a radical attack<br />

against the last stronghold of Kant’s transcendental<br />

philosophy namely the fact that there is at least one thing<br />

which is not in the world but which is supplied by thought,<br />

namely causality.<br />

EINGEBILDETE EMPFINDUNGEN:<br />

WITTGENSTEINS ANALYSE EINES<br />

PHILOSOPHISCHEN ‚TRIEBES’<br />

Eugen Fischer, München, Deutschl<strong>and</strong><br />

Der späte Wittgenstein beh<strong>and</strong>elt philosophische „Probleme,<br />

die durch ein Mißdeuten unserer Sprachformen<br />

entstehen“ (PU 111), durch Fehlinterpretationen, zu denen<br />

wir systematisch getrieben werden von verschiedenen<br />

„Trieb[en], das Arbeiten unserer Sprache mißzuverstehen“<br />

Abstracts<br />

(PU 109). Anh<strong>and</strong> einer <strong>Analyse</strong> von Wittgensteins Untersuchung<br />

des ‚Lesens’ (PU 156-78) soll dieser Aufsatz<br />

erklären, was ein solcher Trieb ist, <strong>und</strong> wie er den Eindruck<br />

von Problemen erzeugen kann, wo keine sind. Diese<br />

Erklärung der Entstehung <strong>und</strong> Natur der von Wittgenstein<br />

beh<strong>and</strong>elten (Schein-)Probleme wird die ‚therapeutischen’<br />

Aspekte seines Ansatzes erhellen, die derzeit im Mittelpunkt<br />

der Diskussion stehen (Creary & Read, The New<br />

Wittgenstein, 2000; Ammereller & Fischer, Wittgenstein at<br />

Work. Method in the „Philosophical Investigations“, 2004).<br />

ULTIMATE JUSTIFICATION IN<br />

HUSSERL AND WITTGENSTEIN<br />

Dagfinn Føllesdal, Oslo, Norway<br />

Husserl is often regarded as a f<strong>und</strong>amentalist in epistemology,<br />

holding that we can obtain a priori, infallible<br />

knowledge. Wittgenstein is known for his advocacy of the<br />

opposite view, arguing in Über Gewissheit <strong>and</strong> other<br />

places that there are no infallible fo<strong>und</strong>ations for knowledge.<br />

Wittgenstein proposed instead another way of rebutting<br />

scepticism.<br />

In this paper it will be argued that Husserl was not a<br />

fo<strong>und</strong>ationalist in the above sense, but had a view similar<br />

to, but also interestingly different from that of Wittgenstein.<br />

In Husserl’s position, the Lifeworld plays a role similar to<br />

that of a form of life in Wittgenstein. But here, too, there<br />

are interesting differences. It will be argued that several of<br />

these differences go significantly in Husserl’s favor.<br />

IDENTIFYING, DISCRIMINATING OR<br />

PICKING OUT AN OBJECT:<br />

SOME DISTINCTIONS NEGLECTED<br />

IN THE STRAWSONIAN TRADITION<br />

Martin Francisco Fricke, Coyoacán, México<br />

In a strict <strong>and</strong> philosophically adequate sense of<br />

“identification”, to identify means to say or realise that two<br />

things are the same. Several quotes in Strawson’s<br />

Individuals suggest that Strawson wishes to use the strict<br />

notion of identification where he explains what is<br />

necessary for the <strong>und</strong>erst<strong>and</strong>ing of reference. However, it<br />

is artificial <strong>and</strong> implausible to interpret Strawson’s notion of<br />

speaker-hearer identification in the strict sense. Moreover,<br />

there seems to be an incoherence in the fact that a strict<br />

identification introduces a new reference which has to be<br />

<strong>und</strong>erstood in order to <strong>und</strong>erst<strong>and</strong> the identification. Evans<br />

does not use the strict notion of identification. This enables<br />

him to claim that <strong>und</strong>erst<strong>and</strong>ing reference requires<br />

identification in the sense of discriminating knowledge.<br />

Picking out is generally equated with distinguishing.<br />

However, this might be wrong. A picking out constitutes a<br />

distinguishing fact; but the picker does not have to be<br />

aware of this fact in order to do the picking.<br />

9

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!