16.05.2014 Views

heidegger's being and time and national socialism - Philosophy ...

heidegger's being and time and national socialism - Philosophy ...

heidegger's being and time and national socialism - Philosophy ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

264<br />

possibility at stake “must be taken over by Dasein<br />

alone . . . [Dasein] is thus forced by that very anticipation<br />

into the possibility of taking over from<br />

itself its ownmost Being, <strong>and</strong> doing so of its own<br />

accord.” 87 Since Dasein itself must by itself take<br />

over its ownmost <strong>being</strong>, taking care of things <strong>and</strong><br />

solicitude fail in this situation. However, as he<br />

without delay continues, this does not mean that<br />

taking care of things <strong>and</strong> solicitude are irrelevant<br />

to authentic <strong>being</strong>. To the contrary, they belong to<br />

the condition of the possibility of existence in<br />

general. 88 As is obvious, Heidegger appropriates<br />

here Kant’s notion of the will <strong>and</strong> autonomy. As,<br />

in Kant, one must, at the end, not listen to anything<br />

other than one’s conscience within oneself,<br />

Heidegger stipulates that, when it comes to<br />

achieving authenticity, nothing exterior to oneself,<br />

nothing outside of oneself can be of<br />

help. The site of one’s ownmost <strong>being</strong> is within<br />

oneself, the impulse to take it over can come only<br />

from this site <strong>and</strong> not from outside, <strong>and</strong> it is only<br />

the individual Dasein itself that can make the effort,<br />

which, again, does not exclude that one’s<br />

ownmost <strong>being</strong> contains relations to other<br />

Dasein, authentic relations. As will become clear<br />

in the next step, Heidegger’s discussion of conscience,<br />

it must be an autonomous act of Dasein<br />

itself to give up its autonomy. Finally, as to the issue<br />

of double forgetting, Heidegger distinguishes<br />

from the authentic underst<strong>and</strong>ing of<br />

death laid out in §53 the ordinary one, <strong>and</strong> claims<br />

that the latter is derivative <strong>and</strong> covers up the former.<br />

89<br />

In the second chapter of Division Two,<br />

Heidegger discusses the call of conscience <strong>and</strong><br />

the answers of authentic <strong>and</strong> inauthentic Dasein.<br />

Authentic Dasein wants to have conscience, <strong>and</strong><br />

obeys the call of conscience while inauthentic<br />

Dasein tries to evade the call. 90 Inauthentic<br />

Dasein treats guilt as something from which one<br />

can cleanse oneself by paying back the equivalent.<br />

By contrast, authentic Dasein knows that it<br />

has to accept its nullity <strong>and</strong> essential <strong>being</strong> guilty<br />

without <strong>being</strong> able or entitled to remove it. 91 As in<br />

the case of all the existentials in Division One <strong>and</strong><br />

the <strong>being</strong> toward death in Division Two, also<br />

inauthentic underst<strong>and</strong>ing of conscience performs<br />

a double forgetting. It presupposes essential<br />

<strong>being</strong> guilty but perverts it, 92 <strong>and</strong> performs “a<br />

covering up the phenomenon in two ways.” 93<br />

Heidegger refers to Kant’s notion of conscience<br />

as a court procedure as the inauthentic underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

of the call, 94 <strong>and</strong> uses for this inauthentic<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing formulas, such as “‘trial,’”<br />

“talk[ing] about,” “a voice which is ‘universally’<br />

binding,” “world-conscience,” “reckoning up<br />

claims <strong>and</strong> balancing them off [ausgleichenden<br />

Verrechnens von Ansprüchen],” “that concern in<br />

which we reckon things up [besorgendes Ausgleichen],”<br />

“‘Life’ is a ‘business’, whether or not<br />

it covers its costs,” “concernfully reckoning up<br />

‘guilt’ <strong>and</strong> ‘innocence’ <strong>and</strong> balancing them off<br />

[besorgenden Verrechnens und Ausgleichens],”<br />

“as if Dasein were a ‘household’whose indebtedness<br />

simply need to be balanced off [ausgeglichen]<br />

in an orderly manner so that the Self<br />

may st<strong>and</strong> ‘by’ as a disinterested spectator,” <strong>and</strong><br />

the “idea of a business procedure that can be regulated.”<br />

95 Heidegger is talking here about the normative<br />

foundations of modernity, <strong>and</strong>, again, he<br />

is saying nothing new. In terms of the old distinction<br />

between proportional justice <strong>and</strong> arithmetical<br />

justice, 96 modernity rests on arithmetical justice<br />

<strong>and</strong> the implied equality of the different<br />

actors, in all areas of life <strong>and</strong>—“‘universally’<br />

binding” <strong>and</strong> “world-conscience”—worldwide.<br />

In the economy, one receives in return the equivalent<br />

to one’s service or money, <strong>and</strong> has no further<br />

claims on the other thereafter. In politics, everyone<br />

has equal rights <strong>and</strong> voting power, <strong>and</strong> in the<br />

parliaments the different groups reach, through<br />

talking, an agreement or a compromise, Ausgleich,<br />

“with which everyone can live.” As to justice,<br />

everyone has the right to a hearing in court,<br />

where both parties have to argue their cause <strong>and</strong><br />

where an impartial judge decides the case, <strong>and</strong><br />

everyone has the right after serving their sentence<br />

to be re-accepted as someone who is again<br />

free of guilt <strong>and</strong> can start all over again. Liberals<br />

<strong>and</strong> leftists approved, defended, <strong>and</strong> fought for<br />

the application of equality <strong>and</strong> arithmetical justice<br />

in all areas while rightists resisted it. Again,<br />

Scheler is a case in point. Before his turn, he saw,<br />

as many rightists, in democracy a sign that the<br />

mentality of society—in his words, “English<br />

cant”: treat everything as an opportunity for mak-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!