16.05.2014 Views

heidegger's being and time and national socialism - Philosophy ...

heidegger's being and time and national socialism - Philosophy ...

heidegger's being and time and national socialism - Philosophy ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

128. In the lecture course An Introduction to Metaphysics<br />

in summer 1935, Heidegger adopts Kurt Riezler’s<br />

Parmenides interpretation from 1934, in which<br />

Riezler made his suggestion regarding the question<br />

who were the Greeks that we were supposed to repeat.<br />

Riezler used Heidegger’s notion of truth to interpret<br />

Being in Parmenides as that which holds together<br />

the opposites <strong>and</strong> thus maintains, or produces,<br />

an Ausgleich between right <strong>and</strong> left (similar to the<br />

way in which Scheler after his turn <strong>and</strong> Tillich dem<strong>and</strong>ed<br />

a politics of Ausgleich; see Fritsche, Historical<br />

Destiny <strong>and</strong> National Socialism, 142–48,<br />

173–87). Thereafter Heidegger makes the first chorus<br />

in Sophocles’ Antigone talk about the conscienceless<br />

revolutionaries, <strong>and</strong> uses his Sophocles<br />

interpretation to turn his <strong>and</strong> Riezler’s Parmenides<br />

interpretation upside down <strong>and</strong> find in Parmenides<br />

his notion of historicality, according to which the<br />

sphere of Ausgleich, society, is, as the sphere of<br />

Schein (seeming), that opposite which has to be destroyed<br />

in the name of the re-realization of the other<br />

opposite, community, which includes rank as opposed<br />

to the egalitarianism of society. See ibid.,<br />

200–01; Johannes Fritsche, “Heidegger in the Kairos<br />

of ‘the Occident,’” The Graduate Faculty <strong>Philosophy</strong><br />

Journal 22 (1999): 3–19.<br />

129. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 436; Sein und Zeit, 384.<br />

130. Fritsche, Historical Destiny <strong>and</strong> National Socialism,<br />

47, 55–60.<br />

131. Ibid., 134, 349–51n24; see below, last section.<br />

132. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 318–19, 342; Sein und<br />

Zeit, 273–74, 296.<br />

133. See above, n. 21.<br />

134. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 54; Sein und Zeit, 31.<br />

135. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 219; Sein und Zeit, 175.<br />

136. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 326; Sein und Zeit, 281.<br />

137. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 335–41; Sein und Zeit,<br />

289–95.<br />

138. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 348; Sein und Zeit, 301.<br />

139. See the reference to the problem in the first section of<br />

the chapter on historicality (Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong><br />

Time, 424–29; Sein und Zeit, 372–77).<br />

140. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 434; Sein und Zeit, 382.<br />

141. Fritsche, Historical Destiny <strong>and</strong> National Socialism,<br />

xii.<br />

142. Heidegger definitely knew Scheler but most probably<br />

also Tönnies <strong>and</strong> other texts.<br />

143. Löwith’s interpretation from 1948 was published<br />

only in the USA (see Fritsche, “From National Socialism<br />

to Postmodernism,” 105).<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

282<br />

144. See above, n. 21.<br />

145. Fritsche, Historical Destiny <strong>and</strong> National Socialism,<br />

47, 55–60, 140–42, 289–92n66 <strong>and</strong> passim.<br />

146. At Pennsylvania State University in 2002, a graduate<br />

student who had come there because of John Sallis<br />

<strong>and</strong> Charles Scott wanted to write his course paper<br />

on Aristotle’s theory of knowledge to show, as he put<br />

it, that Aristotle was not yet entangled in the subjectobject<br />

split. Especially since he was not particularly<br />

familiar with Aristotle <strong>and</strong> had not yet read On Soul,<br />

I recommended him to be very cautious regarding the<br />

notoriously dark chapters 4 <strong>and</strong> 5 of Book III. His<br />

paper culminated in statements about sentences from<br />

these very chapters. I explained to him at great length<br />

that these sentences could mean many things but precisely<br />

not what he claimed. In the second draft of his<br />

paper, he had not changed anything except that he<br />

had added that, at that point, Aristotle had used the<br />

wrong words. When I asked him whether he knew<br />

Greek, he answered in the negative. When I explained<br />

to him that his procedure was not appropriate,<br />

he began crying <strong>and</strong> complained that I challenged<br />

his “academic integrity.”<br />

147. Ibid., 174–75.<br />

148. Ibid., 323n57. Even after his reassessment of<br />

Heidegger’s philosophy, John D. Caputo repeats a<br />

postmodern interpretation in which the Parisian<br />

deconstructive mood happily merges with the American<br />

idol of the self-made man: “Dasein gives itself a<br />

fate.” Demythologizing Heidegger (Bloomington:<br />

Indiana University Press, 1993), 81.<br />

149. Ibid., 11.<br />

150. Ibid., 1, 16, 36–38.<br />

151. Fritsche, Historical Destiny <strong>and</strong> National Socialism,<br />

197–203, 216–224.<br />

152. Heidegger, Being <strong>and</strong> Time, 265; Sein und Zeit, 222;<br />

see—also for the details of the full quote (“always, as<br />

it were, a kind of robbery”)—Johannes Fritsche,<br />

“With Plato into the Kairos before the Kehre: On<br />

Heidegger’s different Interpretations of Plato,” in C.<br />

Partenie <strong>and</strong> T. Rockmore, eds., Heidegger <strong>and</strong><br />

Plato: Toward Dialogue (Evanston: Northwestern<br />

University Press, 2005), 140–77, here 144–46; even<br />

<strong>and</strong> especially in An Introduction to Metaphysics the<br />

Greeks are adventurous conquerors but now they are<br />

so because they obey a call (ibid., 148–49).<br />

153. Ibid., 144–46.<br />

154. Ibid., 143 (also in §6 of Being <strong>and</strong> Time the prevalent<br />

tone is that the tradition between us <strong>and</strong> the Greeks<br />

has to be destroyed to release the Greeks <strong>and</strong> regain

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!