08.06.2014 Views

Report Template - Jubilee Centre

Report Template - Jubilee Centre

Report Template - Jubilee Centre

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ROYALISTS, REPUBLICANS, FIFTH MONARCHISTS AND LEVELLERS<br />

choosing the public’s good. Passion must be<br />

subordinate to reason, which must be exalted “unto the<br />

throne of empire.” 108 For this to occur, “orders of<br />

government as, like those of God in nature” must be<br />

established. 109 These orders are the natural civil<br />

capacities of dividing and choosing, which Harrington<br />

claims God distributed among men.<br />

To demonstrate these orders, Harrington resorts to an<br />

unlikely illustration of a private and simple division of a<br />

cake between two girls, both of whom have an interest<br />

in acquiring as much of the cake as possible. 110 If they<br />

can agree from the outset that one will divide the cake<br />

and the other choose a piece, then both will receive an<br />

equal portion. Why? Regardless of who initiates the<br />

division, the parts will surely be equal because it is in<br />

the interest of the one dividing to make an equal<br />

division. If one girl divided the cake unequally she<br />

would most certainly forfeit the greater portion since it<br />

would be in the interest of the other to take the larger<br />

piece. An equal division insures that both parties will<br />

receive what is in their best interest, and hence common<br />

right. Harrington believed this simple illustration<br />

clarified “the whole mystery of a commonwealth, which<br />

lies only in dividing and choosing,” and part of God’s<br />

natural ordering. God “distributed” mankind “forever<br />

into two orders, whereof the one hath the natural right<br />

of dividing, and the other choosing.” 111 If this natural<br />

division could be institutionalised, authority would also<br />

be balanced.<br />

Constitutionally, “dividing and choosing, in the<br />

language of the commonwealth, is debating and<br />

resolving.” 112 Harrington claims that “the debate of the<br />

few” represents “the wisest debate,” and “the result of<br />

the many . . . is the wisest result.” God Himself “who<br />

doth nothing in vain,” actually “divided mankind unto<br />

the few, or the natural aristocracy, and the many, or the<br />

natural democracy.” 113 These natural orders translate<br />

institutionally into an aristocratic senate that debates<br />

and proposes laws and a democratic assembly that<br />

resolves and enacts them. 114 He summarises the essence<br />

of a commonwealth as consisting “of the senate<br />

proposing, the people resolving, and the magistracy<br />

executing, whereby partaking of the aristocracy as in the<br />

senate, of the democracy as in the people, and of<br />

monarchy as in the magistracy, it is complete.” 115<br />

Equality in Commonwealth Structure:<br />

Rotation and the Election of Magistrates<br />

Rotation relates to the successive elections of<br />

magistrates, or alterations in the composition of rulers<br />

in the superstructures through popular suffrage and<br />

ballot, and guards against a “prolongation of<br />

magistracy.” Popular suffrage through “an equal<br />

rotation” transfers the equality established through the<br />

agrarian into “the branch, or exercise of sovereign<br />

power.” 116 Harrington summarises Oceana as an equal<br />

commonwealth, or “a government established upon an<br />

equal agrarian, arising unto the superstructures or three<br />

orders, the senate debating and proposing, the people<br />

resolving, and the magistracy executing by an equal<br />

rotation through the suffrage of the people given by<br />

ballot.” 117<br />

Harrington concludes that his “reasoned”<br />

commonwealth, Oceana, represents “the first example<br />

of a commonwealth that is perfectly equal”; history does<br />

not evidence the existence of such a model. He does<br />

not consider Israel’s Commonwealth to have been<br />

completely equal since she lacked rotation in her<br />

Sanhedrin whose membership was established for life.<br />

But Oceana was equal in its entire constitution, or<br />

“equal both in the balance or foundation and in the<br />

superstructures,” meaning her “agrarian law and in her<br />

rotation.” 118 Together, they represent “the fundamental<br />

laws of Oceana, or the centre of this commonwealth.” 119<br />

Writing Politics out of Israel:<br />

Moses’s Model Commonwealth<br />

Harrington confirms his natural orders scripturally from<br />

the Hebrew Commonwealth, which he meticulously<br />

details in chapter 2, Book 2 of The art of lawgiving,<br />

entitled “Showing What Commonwealth Israel Was.”<br />

His reading of Israel’s Polity is incorporated<br />

paradigmatically as a civil exemplar into the<br />

constitutional details of Oceana, though he never<br />

intended to assimilate every particular.<br />

108<br />

Harrington, Prerogative, 415.<br />

109<br />

Harrington, Oceana, 172.<br />

110<br />

See Prerogative, 415.<br />

111<br />

Harrington, Oceana, 172; See Prerogative, 416.<br />

112<br />

Ibid., 174; See Prerogative, 416.<br />

113<br />

Harrington, Prerogative, 416; See Oceana, 173.<br />

114<br />

Ibid., 417; See Oceana, 174.<br />

115<br />

Harrington, Oceana, 174.<br />

116<br />

Ibid., 181, 231; See Prerogative, 472.<br />

117<br />

Ibid., 181; See Prerogative, 424 and Art, 613.<br />

118<br />

Ibid., 184, 180.<br />

119<br />

Ibid., 231.<br />

25

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!