04.11.2014 Views

Asian-Arab philosophical dialogues on globalization, democracy ...

Asian-Arab philosophical dialogues on globalization, democracy ...

Asian-Arab philosophical dialogues on globalization, democracy ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

2<br />

Asia-<str<strong>on</strong>g>Arab</str<strong>on</strong>g> Philosophical Dialogues <strong>on</strong> Globalizati<strong>on</strong>, Democracy and Human Rights<br />

government—was meant to be minimal: seen chiefly as protectors of private property, political regimes<br />

were said to govern best when governing least. The dismal experiences of the twentieth century with<br />

populist and totalitarian governments have reinforced the liberal preference for political or public<br />

minimalism—despite occasi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cessi<strong>on</strong>s to “welfare” programs during times of ec<strong>on</strong>omic hardship.<br />

As a result of these experiences and developments, the noti<strong>on</strong> of individual freedom has come to be<br />

equated prep<strong>on</strong>derantly with “negative liberty” (to use Isaiah Berlin’s phrase) or the freedom to be left<br />

al<strong>on</strong>e—with <strong>on</strong>ly limited allowance made for active or “positive freedom” (mainly <strong>on</strong> the level of voting<br />

rights and lobbying). In his study of John Dewey (who opposed this entire trend), Raym<strong>on</strong>d Boisvert has<br />

sketched the stereotype of the minimalist liberal: “an individual with no roots and little c<strong>on</strong>nectedness<br />

to community; . . . a highly competitive individual fixated <strong>on</strong> narrow purposes whose practice is marked<br />

by expedience rather than c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>al ethics”. 1<br />

On a sophisticated level, aspects of democratic minimalism can be found even in the writings of<br />

theorists or intellectuals otherwise str<strong>on</strong>gly committed to democratic politics. As stated above, an<br />

example is Robert Dahl’s celebrated text A Preface to Democratic Theory (first published in 1956). In the<br />

very Introducti<strong>on</strong> to his study, Dahl delineates two basic approaches in this field: a “maximizing” theory<br />

(relying either <strong>on</strong> ethical principles or formal axioms) and a purely “descriptive-empirical” and to that<br />

extent minimalizing approach. Traditi<strong>on</strong>al political theory, he notes, has tended to be “maximizing”<br />

by emphasizing “internal checks”—such as c<strong>on</strong>science and ethical dispositi<strong>on</strong>s—to restrain possible<br />

excesses of governmental power. This approach, however, has g<strong>on</strong>e out of fashi<strong>on</strong> since the<br />

revoluti<strong>on</strong>ary period and, in America, since the writings of James Madis<strong>on</strong>. From Madis<strong>on</strong>’s perspective,<br />

the traditi<strong>on</strong>al ethical approach was simply no l<strong>on</strong>ger viable given the increasingly competitive and<br />

interest-based character of modern politics. 2 Another example of a democratic theorist leaning in the<br />

minimalist directi<strong>on</strong> is Giovanni Sartori, well known for his text The Theory of Democracy Revisited. Like<br />

Dahl’s study, Sartori’s text distinguishes at the outset between a “prescriptive” or normative c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong><br />

and a “descriptive” or empirical c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>—with the latter versi<strong>on</strong> involving greatly reduced demands<br />

<strong>on</strong> democratic politics. In his view, to introduce normative expectati<strong>on</strong>s is likely to overburden the<br />

democratic regime such as to render it unviable. In view of the alleged danger associated with public<br />

ethics, Sartori prefers to employ “minimalist” language and to leave phrases like “political morality, social<br />

morality, professi<strong>on</strong>al ethics” aside. Democracy or “democratic machinery” coincides for him—and many<br />

other empirical theorists—with voting behavior, pursuit of individual interests through pressure groups<br />

and political parties, and public policy-making <strong>on</strong> the basis of these interests. 3<br />

An even more resolutely minimalist approach is propagated by a perspective which, in recent times,<br />

has increasingly gained prominence in the social sciences: rati<strong>on</strong>al choice theory. This outlook basically<br />

transfers neo-classical ec<strong>on</strong>omic assumpti<strong>on</strong>s to social and political life. As can readily be seen, what<br />

is jeopardized or called into questi<strong>on</strong> by this model is not <strong>on</strong>ly public ethics, but politics, particularly<br />

democratic polities, as such. For, even when seen as a minimally shared regime, <strong>democracy</strong> is bound to<br />

be a burden or hindrance for the ambiti<strong>on</strong>s of an unrestrained ec<strong>on</strong>omic agenda. No <strong>on</strong>e has articulated<br />

this burden more forcefully than William Riker, a founder of this model, in his book Liberalism Against<br />

Populism (of 1982). As Riker states at the outset: “The theory of social [or rati<strong>on</strong>al] choice is a theory about<br />

the way the tastes, preferences, or values of individual pers<strong>on</strong>s are amalgamated and summarized into<br />

the choice of a collective group or society”. Since these preferences are not ethically ranked, the primary<br />

focus is <strong>on</strong> something measurable or quantifiable: in ec<strong>on</strong>omics m<strong>on</strong>etary profit, in politics “the theory<br />

of voting” which is the core of liberal (or libertarian) <strong>democracy</strong>, barring any interference with voting<br />

preferences. Like Dahl, Riker distinguishes between a normative-ethical and an empirical or “analytical”<br />

c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of politics—placing rati<strong>on</strong>al choice clearly in the sec<strong>on</strong>d category. 4<br />

1 Boisvert, Raym<strong>on</strong>d D. and Dewey, John. 1998. Rethinking Our Time. Albany, NY, State University of New York Press,<br />

p. 51-52. Compare also Berlin, Isaiah. 1977 Four Essays <strong>on</strong> Liberty. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, Oxford University Press; and for a critique<br />

Taylor, Charles. 1979. What’s Wr<strong>on</strong>g With Negative Liberty? Alan Ryan (ed), The Idea of Freedom, Essays in H<strong>on</strong>or of<br />

Isaiah Berlin. Oxford, Oxford University Press. .<br />

2 See Dahl, Robert A. 1956. A Preface to Democratic Theory. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, p. 2, 18-19. To Dahl’s<br />

credit, <strong>on</strong>e has to acknowledge that he stressed not <strong>on</strong>ly formal procedural limits but also “inherent social checks<br />

and balances”. He also refers (p. 22, 82-83) to an “underlying c<strong>on</strong>sensus <strong>on</strong> policy” existing “prior to politics”. But the<br />

origin of this c<strong>on</strong>sensus is not disclosed.<br />

3 Sartori, Giovanni. 1987. The Theory of Democracy Revisited, Vol. 1. Chatham, NJ, Chatham House Publ., p. 12-13, 17-18,<br />

241-242; vol. 2, p. 476-477.<br />

4 Riker, William H. 1982. Liberalism Against Populism: A C<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tati<strong>on</strong> Between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory<br />

of Social Choice. Prospective Heights, IL, Waveland Press, p. 1-3.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!