13.05.2015 Views

Comparative vs. superlative quantifiers Superlative and comparative ...

Comparative vs. superlative quantifiers Superlative and comparative ...

Comparative vs. superlative quantifiers Superlative and comparative ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

<strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

Bart Geurts<br />

(Nijmegen)<br />

Rick Nouwen<br />

(Frankfurt)<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

◮ <strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>: at least/most 4 sheep<br />

◮ <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>: more/fewer than 5 camels<br />

◮ Attested examples:<br />

[1] We need a president who is fluent in at least one language.<br />

[2] Never eat more than you can lift.<br />

It is usually assumed that these <strong>quantifiers</strong> are interdefinable:<br />

◮ at least 7 bath ducks = more than 6 bath ducks<br />

◮ at most 7 bath ducks = fewer than 8 bath ducks<br />

This is a mistake.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Puzzle #1: Specificity<br />

NPs in <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong> may have specific readings:<br />

[1] I will invite at most 2 people, namely Jack <strong>and</strong> Jill.<br />

Jack <strong>and</strong> Jill will be invited.<br />

[2] I will invite fewer than 3 people, namely Jack <strong>and</strong> Jill.<br />

⇒ Jack <strong>and</strong> Jill will be invited.<br />

[3] ∗I will invite fewer than 2 people, namely Jack <strong>and</strong> Jill.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Puzzle #2: Inference patterns<br />

Barney ate 3 apples.<br />

⇒ Barney ate fewer than 4 apples.<br />

Barney ate at most 3 apples.<br />

⇒ Barney ate more than 2 apples.<br />

Barney ate at least 3 apples.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Puzzle #3: Distributional restrictions<br />

By <strong>and</strong> large, <strong>superlative</strong> modifiers occur more freely than their<br />

<strong>comparative</strong> counterparts:<br />

[1] I might survive a few days {at most/∗fewer than}.<br />

[2] It actually dates back to {at least/∗more than} the 14th century.<br />

[3] Men like me because I don’t wear a brassiere. Women like me<br />

because I don’t look like a girl who would steal a husb<strong>and</strong>.<br />

{At least/∗More than} not for long.<br />

But in some ways <strong>superlative</strong>s are more restricted.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Distributional restrictions (cont.)<br />

Downward entailing contexts<br />

[1] Bach wrote more/fewer than 27 fugues.<br />

Bach wrote at least/most 27 fugues.<br />

[2] Bach didn’t write more/fewer than 27 fugues.<br />

?Bach didn’t write at least/most 27 fugues.<br />

[3] No composer wrote more/fewer than 27 fugues.<br />

?No composer wrote at least/most 27 fugues.<br />

[4] Few composers wrote more/fewer than 27 fugues.<br />

?Few composers wrote at least/most 27 fugues.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Distributional restrictions (cont.)<br />

Quantifiers<br />

[1] {All/Nearly all/Most/?Some/?About 7/∗None} (of the) children<br />

ate at least/most 2 s<strong>and</strong>wiches.<br />

[2] There were so many/few chocolates left that<br />

{(almost) everybody/most guests/?about 7 guests/∗no one}<br />

got at least/most 3.<br />

[3] Before going to bed, she<br />

{(nearly) always/usually/?often/∗occasionally/∗rarely/∗never}<br />

says at least/most 4 prayers.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Puzzle #4: Missing readings<br />

[1] You may take fewer than 3 cards.<br />

a. You are allowed to take 1 or 2 cards (or more).<br />

b. You are allowed to take 1 or 2 cards, but no more.<br />

[2] You may take at most 2 cards.<br />

a. —<br />

b. You are allowed to take 1 or 2 cards, but no more.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Outline of a proposal<br />

◮ The st<strong>and</strong>ard analysis of <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong> is correct:<br />

[1] Wilbur saw more than 4 films.<br />

∃x[#x > 4 ∧ film(x) ∧ see(w, x)]<br />

◮ <strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong> have a bi-modal meaning:<br />

[2] Wilbur saw at least 5 films.<br />

□∃x[5(x) ∧ film(x) ∧ see(w, x)] ∧<br />

⋄∃x[#x > 5 ∧ film(x) ∧ see(w, x)]<br />

[3] Wilbur saw at most 5 films.<br />

⋄∃x[5(x) ∧ film(x) ∧ see(w, x)] ∧<br />

¬⋄∃x[#x > 5 ∧ film(x) ∧ see(w, x)]<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Indefinites <strong>and</strong> numerals<br />

◮ Nouns <strong>and</strong> number words denote properties:<br />

◮ ‖book‖ = λx[book(x)]<br />

◮ ‖three‖ = λx[#x = 3] = λx[3(x)]<br />

✐ Note that this is an ‘exact’ reading.<br />

◮ ‖three books‖ = λx[3(x) ∧ book(x)]<br />

◮ Existential closure turns a predicate into a quantifier:<br />

◮ ‖∅[three books]‖ = λP∃x[3(x) ∧ book(x) ∧ P(x)]<br />

◮ ‖Betty read [∅[three books]]‖ = ∃x[3(x) ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)]<br />

✐ Note that this is an ‘at least’ reading.<br />

◮ Implicature:<br />

◮ ¬∃x[#x > 3 ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)]<br />

◮ Specificity requires existential closure.<br />

◮ Betty has read three books. [May be specific.]<br />

◮ These are three books. [Non-specific only.]<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Digression on number terms<br />

How are we to account for the fact that number terms behave<br />

differently from bona fide scalar expressions?<br />

Some of the options:<br />

◮ Short-circuited implicature (whatever that may be).<br />

◮ Existential closure comes in several flavours, <strong>and</strong> the ‘exactly’<br />

flavour is the default for expressions like ‘three’, ‘half of’, etc.<br />

◮ The lexical meaning of a number term is quantificational <strong>and</strong><br />

‘exact’: type shifting yields first a predicative, <strong>and</strong> then a<br />

quantificational (‘at least’) sense.<br />

♥ Number terms are polysemous between predicative <strong>and</strong><br />

quantificational senses, <strong>and</strong> both are exact, so the ‘at least’<br />

reading must still be derived.<br />

This view is recommended by experts in<br />

Germany <strong>and</strong> the Netherl<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Scales Krifka (1999)<br />

◮ Focus-induced alternatives are ordered.<br />

◮ E.g., if ‘three’ is in focus, we get:<br />

. . . λx[3(x)] ⊲ λx[2(x)] ⊲ λx[1(x)]<br />

✐ Note: this is not an entailment scale.<br />

◮ This ordering is propagated up the derivation tree.<br />

Hence, the alternatives for ‘[three] F books’ are ordered thus:<br />

. . . λx[3(x) ∧ book(x)] ⊲ λx[2(x) ∧ book(x)] ⊲ λx[1(x) ∧ book(x)]<br />

◮ Scalar modifiers operate on such ordered alternatives (cf. ‘only’).<br />

◮ Example: When applied to ‖three‖, ‖more than‖ returns the<br />

union of all the properties that are ‘higher’ than λx[3(x)], i.e.<br />

λx[4(x) ∨ 5(x) ∨ . . .] = λx[#x > 3].<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

<strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

The grammar of scalar <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

◮ Scalar <strong>quantifiers</strong> are st<strong>and</strong>ardly parsed like this:<br />

[[more than three] books]<br />

◮ This is problematic for several reasons. E.g.<br />

[1] Betty read more than [three] F books: she read four.<br />

[2] Betty read more than [three books] F : she read fifteen essays<br />

as well.<br />

◮ Alternative analysis:<br />

[more than [three books]]<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

The semantics of <strong>comparative</strong> modifiers<br />

◮ The argument of a <strong>comparative</strong> modifier is a first-order<br />

predicate: ‘more than happy’, ‘more than three books’, but<br />

‘∗more than Fred’.<br />

◮ This explains why ‘three books’ in ‘more than three books’ does<br />

not allow for a specific construal.<br />

◮ ‖more than α‖ = λx∃α ′ [α ′ ⊲ α ∧ α ′ (x)]<br />

[1] With λx[scalding(x)] ⊲ λx[hot(x)] ⊲ λx[warm(x)],<br />

‖more than warm‖ = λx[hot(x) ∨ scalding(x)]<br />

[2] With . . . λx[3(x)] ⊲ λx[2(x)] ⊲ λx[1(x)],<br />

‖more than [[three] F books]‖ =<br />

λx[[4(x) ∨ 5(x) ∨ . . .] ∧ book(x)] = λx[#x > 3 ∧ book(x)]<br />

So: ‖Betty read ∅[more than [[three] F books]]‖ =<br />

∃x[#x > 3 ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)]<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

‘Fewer than’<br />

◮ ‖fewer than α‖ = λx∃α ′ [α ⊲ α ′ ∧ α ′ (x)]<br />

So: ‖Betty read ∅[fewer than [[three] F books]]‖ =<br />

∃x[#x < 3 ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)]<br />

Unfortunately, this is too weak.<br />

[Actually, it’s a tautology.]<br />

◮ Implicature saves:<br />

¬∃x[#x ≥ 3 ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)]<br />

◮ If this is an implicature it should be cancellable—which it is:<br />

[1] You may take fewer than three cards.<br />

[2] ∃x[#x < 3 ∧ card(x) ∧ take(y, x)]<br />

[3] ¬∃x[#x ≥ 3 ∧ card(x) ∧ take(y, x)]<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

The semantics of <strong>superlative</strong> modifiers<br />

The argument of a <strong>superlative</strong> modifier is any predicate (it may be a<br />

quantifier, for example).<br />

◮ ‖at least α‖ = λX[□α(X) ∧ ∃α ′ [α ′ ⊲ α ∧ ⋄α ′ (X)]]<br />

◮ ‖at most α‖ = λX[⋄α(X) ∧ ¬∃α ′ [α ′ ⊲ α ∧ ⋄α ′ (X)]]<br />

[1] a. Betty read [at least ∅[[four] F books]].<br />

b. □∃x[4(x) ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)] ∧<br />

⋄∃x[#x > 4 ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)]<br />

[2] a. Betty read [at most ∅[[four] F books]].<br />

b. ⋄∃x[4(x) ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)] ∧<br />

¬⋄∃x[#x > 4 ∧ book(x) ∧ read(b, x)]<br />

☞ In either case, the phrase ‘four books’ may be specific.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Modal concord<br />

[1] Hij moet zeker in Parijs zijn.<br />

he must certainly in Paris be<br />

◮ Compositional reading: I suppose he has to be in Paris.<br />

◮ Concord reading: He (definitely) has to be in Paris.<br />

[2] Hij moet misschien in Parijs zijn.<br />

he must perhaps in Paris be<br />

◮ Compositional reading: Perhaps he has to be in Paris.<br />

◮ Concord reading: none<br />

[3] Ze zou misschien wel eens dronken kunnen zijn.<br />

she could maybe wel eens drunk can be<br />

◮ Compositional reading: ⋄. . .⋄(she is drunk) [not available]<br />

◮ Concord reading: ⋄(she is drunk)<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Modal concord with <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

◮ The two conjuncts introduced by a <strong>superlative</strong> quantifier do not<br />

have the same status:<br />

↓<br />

primary operator<br />

□∃x[n(x) ∧ φ(x)]<br />

}{{}<br />

∧ ⋄∃x[#x > n ∧ φ(x)]<br />

principal message<br />

◮ If a <strong>superlative</strong> quantifier combines with a modal expression<br />

whose force is the same as that of its primary operator, the two<br />

operators will fuse by default (modal concord).<br />

◮ Otherwise, we have a double modal (compositional reading).<br />

◮ The modal operators contributed by the quantifier are epistemic<br />

by default, hence will prefer to take wide scope in most cases.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Examples<br />

[1] You may take at most three cakes.<br />

a. ∃x[3(x) ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)] ∧<br />

¬∃x[#x > 3 ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)]<br />

b. ⋄∃x[3(x) ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)] ∧<br />

¬⋄∃x[#x > 3 ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)]<br />

[2] You must take at least three cakes.<br />

a. ⊡∃x[3(x) ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)] ∧<br />

∃x[#x > 3 ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)]<br />

b. □⊡∃x[3(x) ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)] ∧<br />

⋄⊡∃x[#x > 3 ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)]<br />

[concord]<br />

[compositional]<br />

[concord]<br />

[compositional]<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Examples (cont.)<br />

[1] You may take at least three cakes.<br />

a. — [no concord reading]<br />

b. □∃x[3(x) ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)] ∧<br />

⋄∃x[#x > 3 ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)]<br />

[compositional]<br />

[2] You must take at most three cakes.<br />

a. — [no concord reading]<br />

b. ⋄⊡∃x[3(x) ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)] ∧<br />

¬⋄⊡∃x[#x > 3 ∧ cake(x) ∧ take(y, x)] [compositional]<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Modal modifiers<br />

If the modal analysis is correct, it makes sense that <strong>superlative</strong><br />

modifiers sometimes alternate with overt modals:<br />

[1] Hij heeft voor zeker zes kranten gewerkt.<br />

he has for certainly six newspapers worked<br />

‘He has worked for at least six newspapers.’<br />

[2] Hij heeft voor misschien drie kranten gewerkt.<br />

he has for maybe three newspapers worked<br />

‘He has worked for at most three newspapers.’<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Distributional restrictions<br />

If the modal analysis is correct, there should be restrictions on the<br />

distribution of <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong> just as there are on the<br />

distribution of bona fide modals (<strong>and</strong> epistemic ones in particular):<br />

{Each / Most / ?About five / ∗None} of the guests . . .<br />

[1] . . . may have dispatched the butler.<br />

[2] . . . had at least 3 cocktails.<br />

[3] Nabokov might not have written ‘Pnin’. (Only wide scope for ⋄.)<br />

[4] ∗Nabokov didn’t write at least/most 3 novels.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Experimental evidence<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Predictions<br />

If the proposed analysis is on the right track, then <strong>superlative</strong><br />

<strong>quantifiers</strong> should differ from <strong>comparative</strong> ones in that:<br />

◮ they are more complex,<br />

◮ they are acquired later, <strong>and</strong><br />

◮ they license fewer inferences.<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Evidence from acquisition Musolino (2004: Experiment 3)<br />

Materials:<br />

‘The puppet only likes to keep cards with<br />

{exactly/at least/at most/more than} two Ns on them.’<br />

Results (% correct): exactly 2 100<br />

more than 2 88<br />

at least 2 50<br />

at most 2 54<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>


<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Pilot study on reasoning in adults (n = 6!)<br />

Fred had . . .<br />

[1] a. at least 3 beers ⇔ more than 2 beers<br />

b. at most 2 beers ⇔ fewer than 3 beers<br />

[2] a. 3 beers ⇒ more than 2 beers<br />

b. 3 beers at least 3 beers<br />

[3] a. 2 beers ⇒ fewer than 3 beers<br />

b. 2 beers at most 2 beers<br />

[4] a. 3 or 4 beers ⇒ at least 3 beers<br />

b. 1 or 2 beers ⇒ at most 2 beers<br />

[5] a. at least 3 beers ⇒ at least 2 beers<br />

b. at most 2 beers at most 3 beers<br />

c. fewer than 3 beers ⇒ fewer than 4 beers<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong><br />

<strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>comparative</strong> Indefinites, numerals, <strong>and</strong> scales <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers <strong>Superlative</strong> modifiers Experimental evidence<br />

Summary<br />

Key assumptions:<br />

◮ Scalar modifiers are focus-sensitive <strong>and</strong> operate on scales.<br />

◮ <strong>Comparative</strong> modifiers are extensional <strong>and</strong> take first-order<br />

predicates as arguments.<br />

◮ <strong>Superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong> are modals <strong>and</strong> take any type of predicate<br />

as argument.<br />

These assumptions enable us to solve our four puzzles:<br />

Puzzle #1: Specificity<br />

Puzzle #2: Inference patterns<br />

Puzzle #3: Distributional restrictions<br />

Puzzle #4: Missing readings<br />

Bart Geurts & Rick Nouwen: <strong>Comparative</strong> <strong>vs</strong>. <strong>superlative</strong> <strong>quantifiers</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!