18.11.2012 Views

1 Regulating Sex Work Adrienne D. Davis VERY ROUGH DRAFT ...

1 Regulating Sex Work Adrienne D. Davis VERY ROUGH DRAFT ...

1 Regulating Sex Work Adrienne D. Davis VERY ROUGH DRAFT ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Regulating</strong> <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong><br />

<strong>Adrienne</strong> D. <strong>Davis</strong> 1<br />

<strong>VERY</strong> <strong>ROUGH</strong> <strong>DRAFT</strong>: please do not circulate or quote without permission<br />

Most commentators on sex markets focus on the debate between abolitionists and<br />

those who defend and support professional sex workers. This paper, instead, looks at<br />

debates among the pro-sex work camp, uncovering some latent tensions and<br />

contradictions. It shows that, within the sex as labor camp, some stress the labor aspect,<br />

urging that professional sex workers constitute a “vulnerable population,” similar to other<br />

laborers who perform highly risky and/or exploited labor, and should be regulated<br />

accordingly. In this view, sex work would be assimilated into other labor. Others,<br />

though, take a more libertarian approach. They exceptionalize this form of labor, arguing<br />

that because it is sexual it should be exempt from state scrutiny and interference. In sum,<br />

while both agree that professional sex work should be decriminalized, when one turns<br />

from the criminal to the regulatory perspective, the paper shows how libertarians and<br />

assimilationists could not be more opposed. The paper contends that neither of these<br />

views is satisfactory. <strong>Sex</strong> work could very well be legalized—if we have the political<br />

and moral will to do so. The paper explores a regulatory structure that might govern sex<br />

work markets. To do so requires a break with both assimilationism and erotic<br />

exceptionalism.<br />

The paper proceeds in four parts. The first part explores the discourse and debate<br />

over professional sex. It summarizes, briefly, the abolitionist position, often identified as<br />

the dominant feminist position. It then turns its attention to the pro-sex work camp,<br />

teasing out various strains. While most legal discussions of sex work address the debate<br />

between sex work advocates and abolitionists, by focusing within the sex work discourse<br />

this Section reveals a latent tension within it, those who emphasize the sexual part of sex<br />

work to argue for a libertarian end-state, versus those who emphasize the labor part of<br />

sex work and see “work” as a way to demand greater state regulation of sexual<br />

commerce. Thus, while both view “work” as a legitimizing lens, they ultimately envision<br />

starkly different, even contradictory, relationships between sexual commerce and the<br />

state. Thus, while both may urge decriminalization, assimilationists and exceptionalists<br />

are quite opposed.<br />

The second section shows how the rhetoric of sex is “just” labor can be overly<br />

simplistic and terribly misleading. From a policy perspective, merely insisting that sex is<br />

“just” work/that sex be assimilated into work invokes a monolithic, idealized workplace<br />

that ignores the starkly different manifestations of work and its regulation in postindustrial<br />

global economies. This section explores how employment, labor, and<br />

discrimination law regulate the various hazards, risks, conflicts, and disputes that arise in<br />

the modern workplace. In the process, it exposes the complete diversity of work and its<br />

regulation. Although assimilationists clearly have in mind a vision of how “work” is<br />

1 The conceptualization of this project has benefitted immensely from conversations with Susan Appleton,<br />

Scott Baker, Marion Crain, Elizabeth Glazer, John Inazu, Greg Magarian, Eric Miller, Mireille Miller-<br />

Young, Adele Morrison, Anca Parvulescu, Bob Pollak, Jeff Redding, Laura Rosenbury, Peggie Smith,<br />

Susan Stiritz, and Rebecca Wanzo, as well as the Washington University School of Law Faculty<br />

Colloquium and the Washington University Political Theory <strong>Work</strong>shop, the Hofstra Colloquium on Law &<br />

<strong>Sex</strong>uality, and my Ladies Who Do Theory Writing Group—Gretchen Arnold, Marilyn Friedman, Ruth<br />

Groff, and [Linda Nicholson].<br />

1


egulated, their claim to a universal workplace or regulatory structure is a miscue from<br />

how labor law actually functions. <strong>Work</strong>place regulation today is varied, differential, and<br />

under immense contest.<br />

The second half of the paper then turns its attention to whether sex work could be<br />

effectively regulated, once we break from both assimilationism and exceptionalism.<br />

Section III stresses the extent to which sex workplaces are not like most workplaces.<br />

Most workplaces are not characterized by the particularities of sex work, the culture of<br />

alcohol and drinking and drugs; the homosocial “mob” context; the blurred line between<br />

re-negotiations and assaults; a similarly blurred line between on-site/off-site (that is onduty/off-duty)<br />

identities; and employer expectations of “free” services that can combine<br />

to make sex for hire more dangerous for workers than other forms of labor. Crucially, the<br />

danger is coming largely from customers and patrons (and managers and owners) rather<br />

than from machines or mine collapse.<br />

Additionally, the assimilationist/“sex is just work” mantra misses the ways that<br />

sexual services differ from each other, posing what the paper shows to be radically<br />

different regulatory challenges. 2 It rejects schema rooted in moralism that categorize sex<br />

for hire along lines of proximity to intercourse. (Such schema tend to envision sex for<br />

hire on a continuum based on sexual contact between workers and consumers,<br />

envisioning lap-dancing as midway between phone sex and prostitution.) The paper<br />

contends instead that, from a labor and regulatory model, the inquiry would be worker<br />

danger and safety, replacing morality with geography. Taking seriously the challenge of<br />

legalizing, not just decriminalizing sex for hire, the paper suggests a different schema, of<br />

sexual geography. In this model, the most dangerous jobs are those that take place in<br />

purely private spaces, frequently with multiple consumers and little protection for<br />

workers. This would include non-brothel prostitution (street or escort) and out-call exotic<br />

dancing (Duke LAX, two dancers working in a house rented by an athletic team, is<br />

emblematic). The middle category are those forms of sexual services that take place in<br />

commercial establishments open to the public, frequently with multiple workers servicing<br />

multiple consumers, e.g., prostitution in brothels and club dancing, whether contact or<br />

non-contact. In these contexts, management is well-situated to protect workers. Finally,<br />

the least dangerous are those services in which the worker and consumer are in different<br />

geographies, e.g., phone sex and other new media sex, although account must also be<br />

made for the physical proximity of employers and supervisors. Governance should<br />

replace a moral with a danger continuum. 3 In sum, the rhetorical claim that sex work is<br />

“just like” any other work is a miscue, one that distracts us from both the distinctiveness<br />

2 Cf. Laurie Shrage [add cite] (rejecting any unitary meaning of prostitution and instead contending it is<br />

historically and culturally specific). See also Prabha Kotiswaran, Born unto Brothels: Toward a Legal<br />

Ethnography of <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong> in an Indian Red-Light Area, 33 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 579 (differentiating<br />

prostitutes according to their contractual autonomy and relationship to property tenancies); Elizabeth<br />

Bernstein, What’s Wrong with Prostitution? What’s Right with <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong>? Comparing Markets in Female<br />

<strong>Sex</strong>ual Labor, 10 HASTINGS WOMEN’S L.J. 91 (comparing how race, body capital, and other factors shape<br />

street prostitutes experiences in San Francisco). [: should I add Cabezas here? (breaking down monolithic<br />

categories of sex work).]<br />

3 “Danger” or risks from sexually transmitted diseases, however, do continue to map onto the sexual, moral<br />

contact continuum. The paper discusses how these health risks might be managed, drawing from the<br />

pornography industry’s experience with self-regulation, whose effectiveness is highly debated. [ check<br />

Dan Kahan’s work on how questions of science turn into culture wars. Is it relevant?]<br />

2


and the diversity of sex work. Even taking into account the diversity of workplaces, sex<br />

work would almost certainly pose distinctive regulatory challenges. Contrary to the<br />

assimilationists, if markets for sex are to be not merely decriminalized, but also what<br />

many advocates for sex work urge, fully legalized with attendant worker rights and<br />

protections, then we must take account of the particular characteristics and regulatory<br />

challenges posed by commodified sex. 4<br />

Other aspects of sex work, though, might be tougher to regulate. Some sex work<br />

advocates find the idea of brothel or dance club owners or other sex employers taking<br />

account of patrons’ racial or other bodily preferences, as well as their fetishic<br />

preferences, inherently offensive, or “degrading.” If safety standards regulate much<br />

workplace danger, then advocates imagine that the consumer preferences they view as<br />

degrading will be dealt with through the application of anti-discrimination norms (again<br />

one hears, it’s “just like any other workplace, e.g., selling a sweater.” What we uncover<br />

is a latent ambivalence among nominally pro-sex work campers. The quick embrace by<br />

some of this imagined set of regulations manifests their ambivalence: even as they urge<br />

professional sex be denominated as legitimate work, they turn to discrimination law to<br />

delegitimize and eradicate the sexual preferences that comprise this market. This<br />

imagined set of regulations will rid sex markets of outré customer preferences once and<br />

for all, firmly entrenching vanilla as the sexual norm. While many advocates for<br />

legitimized sex markets avoid the language of moralism here, instead urging the “same<br />

protections” for sex bargainers as currently are given to other workers, I argue that, again,<br />

this misunderstands how sex markets work and their distinctiveness. Hence, the Essay<br />

concludes that markets for sex could most likely be regulated, albeit imperfectly, against<br />

some workplace risks, but less so against the “degrading” part. Degradation, that is,<br />

things commentators denominate as “degrading,” may be built into markets for sex.<br />

This paper has two audiences. First, feminists on both sides of the debate: mainly<br />

those who advocate sex for hire as legitimate labor but also those who seek to eradicate it<br />

as violence against women. My hope is to cut through some of the heat and shed some<br />

much-needed light. Second, labor scholars have largely overlooked how recognizing sex<br />

as legitimate labor might challenge and transform workplace organization and<br />

regulation/sex work. 5 Regulation is the implicit key and is what is sought in the<br />

legalization movement (as opposed to those who limit their efforts to decriminalization).<br />

Confronting the ways that commodified sex fits into and yet challenges and transcends<br />

conventional paradigms of labor will yield a more nuanced vision of sex for hire, and also<br />

hopefully shed some light on contemporary contests over labor, discrimination, and<br />

regulatory strategies.<br />

This paper sits at the nexus of several scholarly and political discourses. Of<br />

course, it implicates debates over sex work, which has enjoyed surprisingly little<br />

theoretical attention from law. Notable exceptions include Catharine MacKinnon,<br />

Margaret Baldwin, Martha Nussbaum, Sylvia Law, Kimberly Yuracko, and, more<br />

4 Now, some sex markets are legal, i.e., erotic dancing and phone sex; others are illegal, i.e., prostitution.<br />

Decriminalization is a precursor for illegal activities. Full legalization, or regulation, though, might be<br />

sought for those markets that already are decriminalized.<br />

5 To the extent sex work has come up in labor and employment law scholarship it is mainly in the context<br />

of exotic dancers’ organizing as unions under the NLRA or claiming employee versus independent<br />

contractor status. See infra notes [x] and accompanying text.<br />

3


ecently, Prabha Kotiswaran. 6 It also, though, implicates fairly directly discrimination<br />

discourse, questioning the applicability of Title VII to certain forms of sex work and<br />

contemplating whether appearance employment should continue to enjoy its de facto<br />

exemption. For instance, Russell Robinson has suggested that film casting decisions<br />

could and should be brought within the scope of Title VII, while Deborah Rhode recently<br />

has contended that appearance should enjoy the same anti-discrimination protections as<br />

conventional employment. 7 Relatedly, others have explored whether “intimate<br />

discrimination” violates egalitarian norms. 8 And of course, it will touch on discourses of<br />

racialized sexuality, or what Siobhan Brooks and Adam Green have termed “erotic<br />

capital,” the extent to which desire is inflected by historical structures of subordination. 9<br />

A couple of important caveats. First, to the dismay of many, the Essay does not<br />

intervene in the underlying debate whether sex for hire is legitimate work or systematized<br />

violence and abuse of women. Second, it is not my argument that workplace regulation<br />

is all that is needed to resolve all of the problems presented by sex for hire. As Audrey<br />

Macklin observes: “It is impossible to test this hypothesis by introducing prostitution into<br />

a world where it does not exist.” 10 Third, this paper adopts an explicitly gendered<br />

analysis for two reasons. While there are, of course, male and transgendered sex<br />

workers, they appear less organized than those who identify as women. Men are also less<br />

visible in a debate that often focuses on the gendered effects of sex work and its<br />

criminalization on women. 11 Hence, while this paper takes seriously the need to account<br />

for male and transgendered sex workers, it does not separate out their issues and<br />

concerns, except in some discrete instances. 12<br />

In addition, for several reasons, this paper does not engage meaningfully with<br />

pornography as sex work. First, many who perform in adult films view themselves as<br />

actors to the exclusion of being sex workers. To the extent that this paper is trying to<br />

capture and interrogate the discourse of sex work many pornography performers would<br />

resist this denomination. 13 Second, for the last half century the law has drawn a clear line<br />

between pornography, which is protected under the first amendment, and prostitution,<br />

6<br />

Margaret A. Baldwin, Split at the Root: Prostitution and Feminist Discourses of Law Reform, 5 YALE J.L.<br />

& FEMINISM 47 (1992); Prabha Kotiswaran, Born unto Brothels: Toward a Legal Ethnography of <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong><br />

in an Indian Red-Light Area, 33 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 579; Sylvia A. Law, Commercial <strong>Sex</strong>: Beyond<br />

Decriminalization, 73 S. CAL. L. REV. 523 (2000) (; Catharine A. MacKinnon [decide which to cite here,<br />

from Signs or monographs]; Martha C. Nussbaum, “Whether from Reason or Prejudice”: Taking Money<br />

for Bodily Services, 27 J. LEGAL STUD. 693, 693-94 (1998); Kimberly A. Yuracko, Private Nurses and<br />

Playboy Bunnies: Explaining Permissible <strong>Sex</strong> Discrimination, 92 CAL. L. REV. 147 (2004).<br />

7<br />

Russell Robinson, Casting and Caste-ing: Reconciling Artistic Freedom and Antidiscrimination Norms,<br />

95 CAL. L. REV. 1 (2007). See also Michael J. Frank, Justifiable Discrimination in the News and<br />

Entertainment Industries, Does Title VII Need a Race or Color BFOQ?, 35 U.S.F. L. REV. 473 (2001).<br />

DEBORAH L. RHODE, THE BEAUTY BIAS: THE INJUSTICE OF APPEARANCE IN LIFE AND LAW (2010).<br />

8<br />

See, e.g., Elizabeth Emens, Intimate Discrimination: The State’s Role in the Accidents of <strong>Sex</strong> and Love,<br />

122 HARV. L. REV. 1307 (2009); Lisa C. Ikemoto, Male Fraud, 3 J. GENDER RACE AND JUSTICE 511<br />

(2000); Note, Racial Steering in the Romantic Marketplace, 107 HARV. L. REV. 877 (1994) [look for others<br />

on personals ads].<br />

9<br />

*BROOKS, supra note [x]; [add Adam Green citation].<br />

10<br />

Macklin, supra note [x].<br />

11<br />

[add footnote on trans sex workers, some of whom do I identify as women and therefore incorporated in<br />

that analysis.]<br />

12<br />

On male sex workers, see [craft a footnote]<br />

13<br />

[add quotations/citations on this point.]<br />

4


which is not. <strong>Sex</strong> in the course of creating a movie, video, or photo is considered<br />

“expression,” which cannot be censored based on its content, even if that content is<br />

offensive. 14 Hence, law views those who work in pornography as being paid to create a<br />

protected expression, while those who work in prostitution are paid for sex. 15 Of course,<br />

the pornography/prostitution distinction is unstable and questionable. 16 Many actors in<br />

pornography earn the majority of their living by headlining at exotic dance clubs as “fill<br />

in title.” 17 In this sense, their work in pornography is the platform for a more lucrative<br />

career in sex work. In addition, with regard to the expression/sex distinction, if everyone<br />

14 Roth v. United States, (1957). The exception is obscenity, which is exempt from first amendment<br />

protection because it offends community standards of decency. See Miller [fill in citation and add<br />

parenthetical with 3-prong standard; Under Miller, as long as the work, as a whole, has some “serious<br />

literary, artistic, political, or scientific value,” the first amendment protects its distribution.]. The<br />

distinction was re-visited in the 1980s when California prosecutors argued that an adult film producer was<br />

guilty of pimping because he had hired five women to perform sex acts for a film. The California Supreme<br />

Court ruled that the state’s anti-pandering, or anti-pimping laws were not intended to apply to pornography<br />

and that the acting fees were not paid “for the purpose of sexual arousal or gratification, his own or the<br />

actor.” California v. Freeman, [add citation; also, is more of this a quote than I have captured by my<br />

quotation marks?] (emphasis added). (The sexual gratification of people who watched the movie appeared<br />

to be irrelevant.)<br />

15 Recent legal rulings continue to uphold and even reinforce the pornography/prostitution dichotomy. For<br />

instance, A recent New York ruling reiterated the dichotomy, also noting that “Prostitution is and has<br />

always been intuitively defined as a bilateral exchange between a prostitute and a client.” [add cite; also, is<br />

the next set of quotations from the same case or from the Colb online article about the distinction?] [“Most<br />

of us typically think of prostitution as involving a customer who pays a prostitute for providing sexual<br />

services. We intuit that pornography, by contrast, involves a customer paying an actor for providing sexual<br />

services to another actor./In other words, prostitution is generally understood as the bilateral trading of sex<br />

for money, while pornography involves the customer of an adult film paying money to watch other people<br />

have sex with each other, while receiving no sexual favors himself in return.”; “Most of us typically think<br />

of prostitution as involving a customer who pays a prostitute for providing sexual services. We intuit that<br />

pornography, by contrast, involves a customer paying an actor for providing sexual services to another<br />

actor.] Oregon's Supreme Court overturned laws prohibiting live sex shows in 2005<br />

http://www.deseretnews.com/article/615154044/Oregon-court-overturns-2-sex-show-laws.html<br />

16 For instance, Sherry Colb noted that the New York Penal Law’s definition of a prostitute as one “who<br />

engages or agrees or offers to engage in sexual conduct with another person in return for a fee” would<br />

probably encompass adult film actors. Thus the distinction may not hold up to statutory scrutiny. Sherry F.<br />

Colb, http://articles.cnn.com/2005-08-12/justice/colb.pornography_1_prostitution-ring-sexual-servicespornography/4?_s=PM:LAW.<br />

She also observes that “Though two people may very much want to have<br />

sex with each other in private, the law can intervene to say that they cannot, just because one of them seeks<br />

money and the other gratification, for example. If, however, both members of the couple are in it for the<br />

money, and there is a man with a camera taping them, then the sex is insulated by the Constitution from<br />

legal regulation.” Id.<br />

Of course, in addition to the doctrinal vagueness, to many theorists on both sides of the debate,<br />

pornography is on a continuum with prostitution. See, e.g., ANDREA DWORKIN, Pornography and Male<br />

Supremacy, in LETTERS FROM A WAR ZONE 226, 230 (1993, 1988) (“Politically, culturally, socially,<br />

sexually, and economically, rape and prostitution generated pornography; and pornography depends for its<br />

continued existence on the rape and prostitution of women.”); CATHARINE A. MACKINNON, WOMEN’S<br />

LIVES, MEN’S LAWS 160 (2005) (“Pornography is an arm of prostitution.”). [add cites from other, pro-sex<br />

work side].<br />

17 [add citation].<br />

5


taped prostitution “acts” and posted them on the internet, would the acts then qualify for<br />

the pornography exemption? 18 Finally, pornography is itself increasingly in question as<br />

work. As many have noted, the internet is eroding the line between the conventional<br />

pornography industry and non-commodified sex. <strong>Sex</strong>-act videos are increasingly likely<br />

to be available at no cost and the “actors” unpaid, thereby calling into real question the<br />

extent to which it continues to comprise work. 19 Hence, for all of these reasons, although<br />

there is a sophisticated discourse and academic literature on labor dynamics in adult<br />

films, this paper will largely not engage with them. 20<br />

The fifth and final caveat is one about language. I use the term professional sex<br />

because [fill in]. I use commercial sex, sexual commerce, and commodified sex<br />

interchangeably with professional sex. On the demand side, I call consumers of paid<br />

sexual services customers, patrons, and clients interchangeably. I self-consciously use<br />

the “customer” language to confront and unsettle how a full embrace of market logic and<br />

norms can be unsettling. The denomination “customer” suggests the possible legitimacy<br />

of their preferences for different kinds of sexual services, putting purposeful pressure on<br />

those who advocate for legalizing sex markets to contemplate the logical end of<br />

commodifying sex.<br />

I. DISCOURSES OF LABOR & LIBERTARIANISM<br />

The commodification of activities conventionally associated with women—care,<br />

sex, and reproduction—has long generated debate and controversy, especially among<br />

those whose first principles are feminist, i.e., to sex equality and destabilizing the<br />

sex/gender system. 21 While subject to much critique, care activities have long been<br />

heavily commodified and are largely unregulated, or, more precisely, occur in what<br />

18 Also rejecting the compensation dichotomy, Sherry Colb notes that, “Odd as it may seem, what appears<br />

finally to make all of the difference is the mode of gratification for the person who is paying but not<br />

himself seeking money.” Colb, supra note [x]. Colb contends that the true distinction may lie in the<br />

mechanics of sexual excitement and gratification. [check these quotes: “The ultimate demand for<br />

pornography comes from the viewer of pornography, and what excites him is the watching of the adult<br />

film, rather than any physical act performed on him by another person. The "enjoyment" of pornography is<br />

therefore as "speech," rather than as action.” Though real sex occurred in the making of the pornographic<br />

film, this fact is only relevant insofar as it is known (or believed) by the viewer. If, for example, the entire<br />

film were created with highly realistic computer graphics, but the viewer believed that what he saw was<br />

real, then he would enjoy the material just as much.; Because the impact of pornography occurs through the<br />

mediation of an audience witnessing a performance, rather than an audience receiving physical services<br />

from a performer, pornography and its making qualify as First-Amendment protected speech.]<br />

19<br />

[add academic cites if available]; see also Drowning in Porn, New York Mag. 26 (Feb. 7, 2011) [add a<br />

parenthetical].<br />

20<br />

See, e.g., [please find the iconic cites for academic work on pornography. Look at Constance Penley and<br />

she should be a guide to other scholars. I want to do a race string cite to my colleague, Mireille Miller<br />

Young’s work on race and porn]<br />

21<br />

There are, of course, many, contested definitions of feminism. I use Jodi Green’s adaptation of Gayle<br />

Rubin that feminism is dedicated to destabilizing the sex/gender system. [add cites to Jodi Green and<br />

Gayle Rubin; see if other leading feminists also use this or a similar definition]<br />

6


Elizabeth Emens has called a “litigation-free zone.” 22 Reproduction is currently in a gray<br />

area of regulation and commodification, with increased technological capacities<br />

generating much debate over the legitimacy of such markets and their regulation. 23 The<br />

last of the troika, professional sex, is the subject of this paper and has been particularly<br />

contentious. <strong>Sex</strong> markets are diverse, and so is their treatment by the state. Purchase of<br />

actual sex is currently criminalized, but filming and distribution of sex acts<br />

(pornography), erotic performances which may include sexual acts performed on<br />

customers, e.g., lapdances, erotic massages, and sexual interactions that do not involve<br />

touching (e.g., internet and phone sex) are all legal [check on any limits imposed on new<br />

media sex?]. 24 While sex markets are diverse, the stigma and moralism associated with<br />

them is not. Neither commodified reproduction nor commodified care entail the social<br />

reprobation commodified sex does. 25<br />

A. The Debate over Professional <strong>Sex</strong>: A Primer<br />

Interestingly, many self-identified feminists join conservatives in opposing legal<br />

markets for sex. While conservatives typically condemn professional sex in moral terms,<br />

feminists do so in a different register. 26 Many feminists characterize commodified sex as<br />

22 Emens, Intimate Discrimination, supra note [x], at 1311[do other people make such a distinction?<br />

Maybe early Critical Legal Studies?] [explain answers the cls/Foucault critique that law is always<br />

operative] Care markets are socially acceptable in some large part because “[a]t the political level, live-in<br />

caregivers are widely understood to perform the socially necessary (if devalued) task of child-care. Their<br />

employers are typically middle- or upper-class professionals, a powerful constituency. In contrast, the<br />

labor performed by exotic dancers is alternately viewed as demeaning to women and/or immoral; their<br />

employers and customers lack the respectability and the clout of affluent professional parents.” Macklin,<br />

supra note [x], at 182-183. This means that commodified care work is both socially acceptable and largely<br />

unregulated. See, e.g., MARY ROMERO, MAID IN THE U.S.A. (1992); [add other Romero cites]; Peggie<br />

Smith [add cites]; [add others].<br />

23 For example, contrast Michigan, where statutes prohibit enforcement of surrogacy contracts and<br />

parenthood defaults to the birth mother [or best interests standard?] with California where both the<br />

judiciary and legislature provide mechanisms to enforce such agreements. [add cites]. For discussion of<br />

the legitimacy of surrogacy agreements, see for example [cite Marjorie M. Shultz, add other cites].<br />

24 “Currently, prostitution is legal and regulated in countries such as Austria, Germany, Greece, the<br />

Netherlands, Switzerland, and Turkey.” Chi Mgbako & Laura A. Smith, <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong> and Human Rights in<br />

Africa, 33 FORDHAM INT’L L.J. 1178 (2010). [sale, purchase, and procurement; partial decriminalization]<br />

Other countries distinguish between procurement and delivery and articulating a separate state interest in<br />

regulating procurement methods.<br />

Carmen & Moody [Even in the two jurisdiction where it is legal, aspects are policed by criminal law:<br />

Nevada rental rules, etc are criminal I think] [Contra criminalizing johns: “Why, [prostitutes] ask, should<br />

men be punished for paying them, but not punished for raping or robbing them?” <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong>ers and <strong>Sex</strong><br />

<strong>Work</strong>, supra note [x], at 3.]<br />

25 This is not to say that people do not moralize about these activities—they do. There is often an<br />

expectation that women will render these activities selflessly, that is for free. See, e.g., McClintock, supra<br />

note [x], at 1 (noting not only does “[s]ociety demonize[] sex workers because they demand more money<br />

than women should, for services men expect for free.” but even “Shopping for others is work a woman<br />

generally does for free, and constitutes, as such, the hallmark of gender normality.”) [add cites on the<br />

altruism debate; does Zelizer fit here on The Purchase of Intimacy?]; see also Nussbaum, supra note [x]<br />

(using other forms of labor to question anti-commodification stances towards prostitution.).<br />

26 [moral reform background]<br />

7


abusive of women 27 and a human rights violation 28 —it is an inherently “degraded<br />

exchange.” 29 They reject it as a legitimate form of labor, instead seeking its eradication<br />

and prohibition. According to philosopher Carol Pateman, “When women’s bodies are<br />

on sale as commodities in the capitalist market, the terms of the original contract cannot<br />

be forgotten; the law of male sex-right is publicly affirmed, and men gain public<br />

acknowledgment as women’s sexual masters – that is what is wrong with prostitution.” 30<br />

Catharine MacKinnon has a similar formulation, “Women are prostituted precisely in<br />

order to be degraded and subjected to cruel and brutal treatment without human limits; it<br />

is the opportunity to do this that is exchanged when women are bought and sold for<br />

sex.” 31 Kathleen Barry puts it perhaps most strongly: “The sex men buy in prostitution is<br />

the same sex that they take in rape—sex that is disembodied, enacted on the bodies of<br />

women who, for the men, do not exist as human beings.” Legal philosopher Margaret<br />

Radin makes a different point, that commodified sex cannot exist with our aspirations for<br />

its decommodified form. 32 These insightful and influential feminists conclude that the<br />

27 She continues, “Men decide whether it is sex they pay for, or sex they take by force or with consent.”<br />

KATHLEEN BARRY, THE PROSTITUTION OF SEXUALITY 37 (1995) [hereinafter THE PROSTITUTION OF<br />

SEXUALITY]. Elsewhere, Barry says:<br />

This misogyny, the use of prostitutes to act out one’s contempt for the lower and degraded sex, is<br />

the single most powerful reason why prostitution has always been considered a cultural<br />

universal—the oldest profession, the indestructible institution, the necessary social service. It<br />

intersects with the domination of women at all levels of society.<br />

KATHLEEN BARRY, FEMALE SEXUAL SLA<strong>VERY</strong> 137 (1984). [apparently Barry’s position changed over<br />

time; please incorporate that into this footnote].<br />

28 “The abolitionist position treats all prostitution as a problem of human rights, to be condemned<br />

uncompromisingly, like slavery, and never to be equated with acceptable practices like work, or with<br />

legitimating ideas like consent and contract.” Larson, supra note [x], at 680.<br />

29 Bernstein, supra note [x], at 109.<br />

30 CAROLE PATEMAN, THE SEXUAL CONTRACT 208 (1988). Elsewhere, Pateman elaborates that<br />

“Prostitution is the use of a woman’s body by a man for his own satisfaction. There is no desire or<br />

satisfaction on the part of the prostitute. Prostitution is not a mutual, pleasurable exchange of the use of<br />

bodies, but the unilateral use of a woman’s body by a man in exchange for money.” Id. at 198. In<br />

Pateman’s view, such “sexual contracts” “both established orderly access to women and a division of<br />

labour in which women are subordinate to men.” Id. at 119. See also Laurie Shrage, Should Feminists<br />

Oppose Prostitution?, 99 ETHICS 347 (1989) (“most feminists find the prostitute’s work morally and<br />

politically objectionable. In their view women who provide sexual services for a fee submit to sexual<br />

domination by men, and suffer degradation by being treated as sexual commodities.”).<br />

31 Catharine A. MacKinnon, Prostitution and Civil Rights, 1 MICH. J. GENDER & L. 13, 13 (1993). See also<br />

CATHARINE A. MACKINNON, TOWARD A FEMINIST THEORY OF THE STATE 168 (1991) (“Because the stigma<br />

of prostitution is the stigma of sexuality is the stigma of the female gender, prostitution may be legal or<br />

illegal, but so long as women are unequal to men and that inequality is sexualized, women will be bought<br />

and sold as prostitutes, and law will do nothing about it.”); WOMEN’S LIVES, MEN’S LAWS, supra note [x],<br />

at 159 (“Perhaps when women in prostitution sustain the abuse of thousands of men for economic survival<br />

for twenty years, this will, at some point, come to be understood as nonconsensual as well.”); Andrea<br />

Dworkin, Prostitution and Male Supremacy (1992) (rejecting prostitution as male dominance). [check<br />

MacKinnon (1983)];<br />

32 MARGARET JANE RADIN, CONTESTED COMMODITIES ([add a good quotation for the parenthetical]).<br />

Contrasting prostitution with other forms of disputed commodification Radin says:<br />

The risks of a black market in body parts are slim because the buyer must use a regulated<br />

professional and health care facility to get the part installed. Similarly, even though baby sales are<br />

8


injuries and harms of commodified sex warrant its continued criminalization, and many<br />

contend the state does not do enough to eradicate it. 33 Indeed, for some, ending<br />

prostitution is the “new abolition.” 34 In sum, opposition to sex markets has a long and<br />

rich feminist pedigree. 35<br />

On the other side, different strains of feminist thought argue the legitimacy of<br />

professional sex. Some do so from a pro-sex perspective, arguing that [add quote]. 36<br />

Relatedly, some contend that decriminalized sex exchanges have the potential to subvert<br />

patriarchy, challenging the social mechanisms by which some women are socially slotted<br />

and raised to be “good girls.” In this conceptualization, commodified sex becomes a<br />

“category of radical sexual identity.” 37 Others argue that all women bargain for sex, an<br />

argument that dates back to nineteenth-century critiques of the dichotomy between<br />

marriage and prostitution as a false one. 38 [add quote from Gayle Rubin 39 ] In this view,<br />

routinely arranged in the grey market, parental rights can only be established in court. By<br />

contrast, prohibitions against commercial sex are notoriously difficult to enforce.<br />

Radin, [add cite], at 537 (footnote omitted). Margaret Jane Radin [add cite] (characterizing prostitution as<br />

double bind where both commodification and non-commodication can be harmful). See also ELIZABETH<br />

ANDERSON, VALUE IN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS (1993) (commodified sex has negative influences on<br />

gratuitous sex); Elizabeth Anderson, Is Women’s Labor a Commodity?, 19 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 71 (1990).<br />

33 See also Bernstein, supra note [x], at 93 (“Radical feminists usually have argued that legalization is the<br />

state’s official endorsement and the ultimate patriarchal expression of ‘the traffic in women.’”); Mgbako &<br />

Smith, supra note [x], at 1178 (“The antiprostitution feminist camp characterizes prostitution as an<br />

exploitative institution of patriarchy, a form of sexual slavery and violence against women, and therefore a<br />

violation of women's rights.”).<br />

34 [work on this footnote: Add footnote on abolition, trafficking, slavery as intentional metaphor.] See<br />

supra note [x] [distinguishing procurement, delivery, punishment of consumer]<br />

35 In addition to MacKinnon, Pateman, and Barry, see also Mary Ann Becker, A Review of The Prostitution<br />

of <strong>Sex</strong>uality: The Global Exploitation of Women (reviewing Kathleen Barry), 52 DEPAUL L. REV.<br />

1043, 1044-45 (2003) (“ while pornographic media are the means of sexually saturating society, while rape<br />

is paradigmatic of sexual exploitation, prostitution, with or without a woman's consent, is the institutional,<br />

economic, and sexual model for women’s oppression.”);<br />

36 [add cite]; see also Mary Joe Frug, A Postmodern Feminist Legal Manifesto (An Unfinished Draft), 105<br />

HARV. L. REV. 1045, 1059 (1992) (“The arguments that sex workers are making to assimilate their work<br />

into the wage market appeal to a sexualized femininity that is something other than a choice between<br />

criminalized and maternalized sex or a choice between terrorized and maternalized sex.”).<br />

37 Bernstein, supra note [x], at 112. For instance, COYOTE claims that open markets for sex subvert<br />

gender roles, in which some women are socially slotted and raised to be “good girls.” On the other hand,<br />

“there is nothing transgressive about one who has been socially born and raised to be a ‘bad girl’ and<br />

remaining one.” Id. at 112.<br />

38 This argument has a long pedigree, dating back to nineteenth-century gender activists. See, e.g., [add<br />

cites]; PATEMAN, supra note [x], at 123 (“The husband’s conjugal right is the clearest example of the way<br />

in which the modern origin of political right as sex-right is translated through the marriage contract into the<br />

right of every member of the fraternity in daily life.”); Prabha Kotiswaran, Wives and Whores: Prospects<br />

for a Feminist Theory of Redistribution, in SEXUALITY AND THE LAW: FEMINIST ENGAGEMENTS (Carl F.<br />

Stychin & Vanessa E. Munro eds.,).<br />

39 Gayle Rubin, The Traffic in Women [add full citation]. More subtly, Martha Nussbaum observes that<br />

“most cultures contain a continuum of relations between women and men (or between same-sex pairs) that<br />

have a commercial aspect—ranging from the admitted case of prostitution to cases of marriage for money,<br />

going on an expensive date where it is evident that sexual favors are expected at the other end, and so<br />

forth.” Nussbaum, supra note [x], at 700. But see Nancy Fraser, Beyond the Master/Subject Model:<br />

Reflections on Carole Pateman’s <strong>Sex</strong>ual Contract, 37 SOCIAL TEXT 173, 176 (1991) (“Whereas the<br />

marriage contract involves the withdrawal of major aspects of social reproduction from the cash nexus,<br />

wage labor, prostitution, and ‘surrogacy’ are precisely market transactions.”).<br />

9


all heterosexual women “work” for sex. 40 Still others root their support for sex markets<br />

in liberalism, making agency arguments that women should have the ability to determine<br />

their own trade-offs after discerning and evaluating their options. 41 In fact, one<br />

commentator finds that, ironically, prostitution may be the first time some women feel<br />

empowered to refuse sex. 4243 Those who embrace what they conceive of as erotic<br />

autonomy criticize criminal law for labeling sex workers as sex offenders, despite the<br />

consent of both parties. 44 In this sense they invoke Lawrence-like analyses over the<br />

scope of sexual autonomy and what the state should criminalize. 45 Most recently, some<br />

advocates for transactional sex have made arguments from the “demand” side, pointing<br />

out that sex markets may be the only chance that the disabled and other sexually<br />

marginalized groups have for non-auto erotic sex. 46 Finally, some make antiexceptionalism<br />

arguments, that professional sex is just like any other form of labor and<br />

should be respected and regarded as such.<br />

Of course, these arguments are not mutually exclusive, and there is significant<br />

overlap. In particular, erotic autonomy overlaps with labor discourse. The remainder of<br />

this paper will explore the discourse of professional, commodified sex as legitimate labor.<br />

B. The Labor Claim<br />

40<br />

Indeed, this argument is not limited to heterosexual women, or to women. As argued above, many<br />

people “trade” sex in relationships, short-term and long-term. See supra notes [x] and accompanying text<br />

(rejecting terms sex trade and sex work as failing to distinguish adequately professional sex work between<br />

the negotiations many make for sex). [Note heteronormativity of this claim].<br />

41<br />

[add Nussbaum here, too; from Anca: Laura Kipnis's "Against Love" might be a nice additional touch to<br />

the idea that all women "work at it [sex]" because her argument is that normative, marital love and sex is a<br />

lot of everyday work and an ongoing commerce of affect] One commentator contends that feminist<br />

opposition to sex work flies in the face of feminism’s insistence on women’s agency in other matters<br />

regarding their bodies:<br />

This hypocrisy is evident in the abortion debate. Many feminists champion a woman’s right to<br />

choose—as long it is abortion that is being discussed. But let someone suggest that women have a<br />

right to sell their bodies and suddenly these women no longer advocate choice. Prostitution must<br />

be the same issue for feminists as abortion. It is the right to choice. Both involve the right of a<br />

woman to control what happens to her body. If one claims self-ownership as the basis of a<br />

woman's right to choose an abortion, then the logical implication of such ownership cannot be<br />

limited to abortion. If a woman owns her body, she should be able to choose to do with it what she<br />

will.<br />

Norma Jean Almodovar, For Their Own Good: The Results of the Prostitution Laws as Enforced by Cops,<br />

Politicians and Judges, 10 HASTINGS WOMEN’S L.J. 119, 122 (1999).<br />

42<br />

43<br />

Prabha Kotiswaran notes: “the feminist critique that this work position is undertheorized, with the result<br />

that it falls back on the liberal discourse around choice, consent, work, and the market.” Kotiswaran, supra<br />

note [x], at 581 (citations omitted).<br />

44<br />

[ In this configuration, consent becomes a crucial component of analysis. [Law &<br />

Nussbaum notes from intro] See also Almodovar, supra note [x], at 123 (“For mutually agreed upon<br />

financial transactions it should not matter to anyone outside the relationship how many times sexual<br />

activity occurs, or with how many sexual partners.”); Law, supra note [x], at 526 (“The exchange of sexual<br />

services for money is the only form of consensual adult sexual activity that is systematically subject to<br />

criminal sanctions in the United States at the end of the twentieth century.”).<br />

45<br />

[add citations and analysis]<br />

46<br />

See infra notes [x] and accompanying text.<br />

10


Grounded in labor discourse, the term sex “worker” originated in the 1970s to<br />

legitimate professional sex in the face of the then-dominant feminist thought that objected<br />

to prostitution as exploitation and sought to abolish it and “rescue” the women who did<br />

it. 47 Unlike earlier reform efforts, based on tolerating prostitution either to preserve<br />

men’s sexual privilege or to end women’s victimization at the hands of law enforcement,<br />

the new discourse of sex as labor emerged from the prostitutes’ rights social movement. 48<br />

<strong>Sex</strong> work emerged in this context as “a term that suggests we view prostitution not as an<br />

identity—a social or psychological characteristic. . ., often indicated by ‘whore’—but as<br />

an income-generating activity or form of labor.” 49 Elizabeth Bernstein concurs: “Unlike<br />

the word ‘prostitute,’ with its connotations of shame, unworthiness or wrongdoing, the<br />

terms ‘sex-worker’ tries to suggest an alternative framing that is a ‘normalization of<br />

prostitutes as ‘service workers’ and ‘care-giving professionals.’” 50 More recently, sex as<br />

labor advocates also derive their claim from human rights discourse, which guarantees<br />

choice of occupation as a right. 51<br />

Others embrace the term sex worker to invoke other associations. For instance,<br />

influential theorist Kamala Kempadoo endorses “sex worker,” but analytically substitutes<br />

“gender” for “sex.” In her view, the denomination sex worker “insists that working<br />

women’s common interests can be articulated within the context of broader (feminist)<br />

47<br />

The term is attributed to Carol Leigh, an activist for prostitutes and member of COYOTE. Oliver J.<br />

McKinstry, We’d Better Treat Them Right: A Proposal for Occupational Cooperative Bargaining<br />

Associations of <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong>ers, 9 PA. J. LAB. & EMP. L. 679 n.18 (2007). Many credit the 1975 strike of<br />

prostitutes in France as the start of a movement to conceive of sex bargainers’ rights in the language of<br />

labor. Sylvia Law, however, documents an earlier strike in Hawaiian during World War II, in which<br />

prostitutes used their alliances with the military to resist and renegotiate legal restrictions and police<br />

surveillance. Law, supra note [x], at [pincite]. [check: were they women of color?] For a comparison of<br />

relative weakness of prostitute rights movement with more successful contemporaneous gay and abortion<br />

rights movements, see generally Ronald Weitzer, Prostitutes Rights in the United States: The Failure of a<br />

Movement, 32 SOCIOLOGICAL Q. [pincite] (1991).<br />

See, e.g., [McKinstry, id. (historicizing movement); [add others]. Siobhan Brooks contends the sex labor<br />

movement picked up again in 1990s because of the influx of women into the industry. BROOKS, supra note<br />

[x], at 2. See also [find this cite] (critiquing initial exclusion of global south from discussions); Larson,<br />

supra note [x] (describing how movement transmuted over time); Mgbako & Smith, supra note [x].<br />

48<br />

[add oppositional consciousness stuff] Earlier defenses of prostitution tended to be grounded in either<br />

impulses to “rescue” prostitutes from “fallen lives” or to tolerate prostitution as a socially necessary outlet<br />

for men’s sexual drives. [add cites] As activist Carol Leigh says, “The current movement includes a<br />

recognition of the rights of prostitutes to autonomy and self-regulation.” Carol Leigh, A First Hand Look<br />

at the San Francisco Task Force Report on Prostitution, 10 HASTINGS WOMEN’S L.J. 59 (1999).<br />

49<br />

GLOBAL SEX WORKERS: RIGHTS, RESISTANCE AND REDEFINITION 3 (Kamala Kempadoo & Jo Doezema<br />

eds., 1993).<br />

50<br />

Bernstein, supra note [x], at 111 [Check this quote: McKinistry fn 18???].<br />

51<br />

Interestingly, both sides use human rights frameworks. [add cites to main human rights instruments on<br />

this] While sex work advocates urge a right to work and privacy guarantees, abolitionists invoke a<br />

different set of norms against sexual discrimination, state-sanctioned patriarchy, and rights to be free from<br />

inter-personal violence. The dominant human rights agencies have taken a strong stand against forced<br />

prostitution and trafficking, but have largely remained neutral on the question of prostitution itself. See,<br />

e.g., Nussbaum, supra note [x], at 710 (noting human rights organizations have focused attention on forced<br />

sexual labor and also on alleviating material conditions that give rise to prostitution); A Modern Form of<br />

Slavery: The Human Rights Watch Global Report on Wome’s Human Rights 196-273 (1995; [add other<br />

cites to International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights; Convention on the Elimination of All Forms<br />

of Discrimination against Women; Convention for the Suppression of Traffic in Persons and the<br />

Exploitation of the Prostitution of Others].<br />

11


struggles against the devaluation of women’s work and gender exploitation within<br />

capitalism.” 52 Relatedly, others urge the term “sex worker” to call attention to the<br />

multiplicity of people—men, women, heterosexual, homosexual, transgender, etc.—who<br />

sell sex. 53 Thus some adopt the term sex worker to invoke identitarian or coalitional<br />

discourses and critiques. Overwhelmingly, though, those who urge the sex worker rubric<br />

do so to embrace a discourse of transactional sex as legitimate labor.<br />

Conceptualizing commodified sex as work is urged as one way to combat the very<br />

real ills experienced by many who transact sex—an alternative to both abolition and<br />

ongoing criminalization. This argument emphasizes that sex work should be regarded and<br />

regulated as no different from any other labor. For instance, the World Charter for<br />

Prostitutes’ Rights calls for the “decriminaliz[ation of] all aspects of adult prostitution”<br />

and the regulation of “third parties according to standard business codes.” 54 Indeed, the<br />

legalization movement is a self-proclaimed labor movement. The website for the Live<br />

Nude Girls Unite! documentary takes care to proclaim in its first sentence: “This site is<br />

about a labor film.” 55 Similarly, Monica Moukalif concludes that “the issues that affect<br />

sex work are essentially labor issues common to all marginalized workers.” 56 Proponents<br />

invoke other comparisons to conventional labor as well. “Both the factory worker and<br />

the prostitute survive hard physical labor by separating who they are from what they do.<br />

Just as the person on the assembly line in a factory separates his personality from his<br />

hands and feet and the part of the brain that makes them work, so the willing prostitute<br />

separates her personality from her sexual equipment.” 57 Hence, Moukalif and others give<br />

clear statements of the complete claim of commodified sex as labor.<br />

Yet, within the professional sex as labor camp there is a deep split that has gone<br />

largely unnoticed. Universally, the sex as labor camp urges decriminalization of<br />

professional sex, contending that [check this quote] “criminalization results in<br />

stigmatization, criminalization, and punishment.” 58 They observe that the long-standing<br />

52<br />

KEMPADOO, supra note [x], at 8. See also Tinsman, supra note [x], at [add pincite] (contending sex is<br />

primary way women are exploited in all forms of work).<br />

53<br />

McKinstry, supra note [x], at 683; [check Cabezas at 81].<br />

54<br />

World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights; International Committee for Prostitutes’ Rights February 1985,<br />

Amsterdam, reprinted in 37 Social Text 183 [hereinafter World Charter fro Prostitutes’ Rights]. In fact,<br />

Sylvia Law concludes, “With startling consistency, the prostitutes' rights movement calls for the<br />

decriminalization of all aspects of prostitution.” Law, supra note [x], at 553 (footnote omitted).<br />

55<br />

[cite website].<br />

56<br />

Monica R. Moukalif, No Evil: Applying a Labor Lens to Prostitute Organizing, 20 HASTINGS WOMEN’S<br />

L.J. 253, 258 (2009).<br />

57<br />

Michael Conant, Federalism, the Mann Act, and the Imperative to Decriminalize Prostitution, 5<br />

CORNELL J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 99, 100 (noting differences between sex bargainers and other workers,<br />

including substance abuse and psychological effects) [keep that parenthetical?]; see also Nussbaum, supra<br />

note [x] (rehearsing arguments of how prostitution is similar to and different from other forms of labor).<br />

58<br />

[add check citation]. [decide whether here or in regulation description: Prabha Kotiswaran points out<br />

how criminal, prohibitory laws have become fetishized by both sides of the decriminalization debate.<br />

“While the normative status of sex work remains deeply contested, abolitionists and sex work advocates<br />

alike display an unwavering faith in the power of criminal law; for abolitionists, strictly enforced criminal<br />

laws can eliminate sex markets, whereas for sex work advocates, decriminalization can empower sex<br />

workers.” Kotiswaran, supra note [x], at 579. In sum, contra Foucault’s injunctions against juridical<br />

understandings of modern regulation, “Both camps thus view the criminal law as having a unidirectional<br />

repressive effect on the sex industry.” Kotiswaran, supra note [x], at 613. See also Nussbaum, supra note<br />

12


criminalization of markets for sex has invited organized crime, led to police corruption,<br />

and heightened the vulnerability and isolation of those who bargain for sex. 59 Not only is<br />

prostitutes’ labor criminalized, but often this serves as an obstacle to reporting sexual<br />

assaults as well as to enforcing the contracts for transactional sex they consensually enter.<br />

But, while unanimously endorsing lifting criminal bans on professional sex, sex as labor<br />

advocates disagree whether there is a further role for the state in regulating this market.<br />

Frequently, this is cast as a disagreement between those who limit their arguments to<br />

calls for decriminalization and those who urge full legalization and regulation. 60<br />

Overlooked, though, is the extent to which these positions actually embed contradictory<br />

views of sexual labor itself.<br />

1. Decriminalization<br />

Emblematic of the decriminalization without regulation position, two<br />

commentators insist, “<strong>Sex</strong> workers’ ability to control their lives is most undermined by<br />

state regulations that criminalize, penalize, stigmatize, and therefore isolate sex workers,<br />

rendering them unable to counter harassment and abuse.” 61 In this view, criminalization<br />

then leads to further vulnerability, and those who might like to pursue other options find<br />

they are largely stuck in sex markets. 62 In its strongest form, decriminalization<br />

arguments adopt a sort of libertarian stance, embracing decriminalization but opposing<br />

full legalization, which would entail regulation and protectionism. 63 For instance, the<br />

World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights insists that “It is essential that prostitutes can<br />

provide their services that are absolutely determined by themselves and no one else.” 64<br />

Norma Almodovar puts the case even more bluntly: “Decriminalization would . . . repeal<br />

all existing criminal codes applying to non-coercive adult commercial sex activity. It<br />

would require no new legislation to deal with harmful effects of prostitution, as there are<br />

already plenty of laws which cover problems outside the realm of personal choice.” 65<br />

“From an activist perspective the term legalization as applied to prostitution usually<br />

refers to a system of criminal regulation and government control of prostitutes. In this<br />

system, certain individuals or specific prostitution practices (work venues, etc.) are<br />

explicitly recognized and ‘legitimized’ by law, and practices or individuals outside those<br />

[x], at 708 (“Criminalization and regulation are not straightforwardly opposed; they can be closely related<br />

strategies.”).<br />

59<br />

[is this a cite from Macklin?] [add Barry on Contagious Diseases Act and how it split prostitutes from<br />

their communities by means of ascribing a separate identity]<br />

60<br />

[Decriminalization/legalization split]<br />

61<br />

Mgbako & Smith, supra note [x], at 1193. Elsewhere Mgbako and Smith contend that “Illegality renders<br />

sex workers dependent upon pimps, brothel owners, clients, and police officers.” Id. at 1206.<br />

62<br />

[discuss exit]<br />

63<br />

See, e.g., Fischer, supra note [x], at 526 (equating regulations and restrictions with “condemnation” of<br />

prostitutes).<br />

64<br />

World Charter 183<br />

65<br />

Almodovar, supra note [x], at 132 (emphasis added). Anne McClintock observes: “A recent call has<br />

gone up from some quarters for the legalization rather than the decriminalization of sex work. But most<br />

prostitutes regard legalization as legalized abuse. Despite its benign ring, legalization places prostitution<br />

under criminal instead of commercial law, where it is tightly curtailed by the state and administered by the<br />

police.” McClintock, supra note [x], at 4 (emphasis in original).<br />

13


oundaries are illegal.” 66 The International Prostitute Rights organization is more<br />

specific: “There should be no law which implies systematic zoning of prostitution.<br />

Prostitutes should have the freedom to choose their place of work and residence.” 67<br />

Feminist theorist Anne McClintock concurs: “A central tenet of the prostitution<br />

movement is the demand that sex workers be given the right to exchange sexual services<br />

on their terms and on their conditions, not on the terms of the state, the police, pimps,<br />

male managers, or clients.” 68 Of course, such insistence on complete workplace<br />

autonomy is unrecognizable to most working adults. But, for decriminalization<br />

advocates, this strong libertarian position is justified because of the nature of the “work.”<br />

Implicit in these strong-form claims for a completely deregulated sex market is<br />

the privacy ideology liberalism often associates with sex. Although much-criticized, the<br />

legal protection for women’s sexual autonomy that emerged in the 1960s and 1970s was<br />

grounded in constitutional privacy doctrine. 69 Cultural and social norms of sex as part of<br />

private and not public life supported this, as well. 70 Liberalism similarly promotes<br />

autonomy, freedom, and choice within this sphere, construing these as the definitive<br />

principles that guarantee sexual and reproductive rights. 71 The final piece of the<br />

liberalism troika, consent, plays a similarly fundamental role in constructing sexual rights<br />

and their boundaries. 72 From this ideology some advocates derive a strong, intriguingly<br />

66 Leigh, supra note [x], at 60.<br />

67 http://www.bayswan.org/ICPRChart.html. They also oppose public health regulations of sex work.<br />

“Since health checks have historically been used to control and stigmatize prostitutes, and since adult<br />

prostitutes are generally even more aware of sexual health than others, mandatory checks for prostitutes are<br />

unacceptable unless they are mandatory for all sexually active people.” World Charter 184.<br />

68 Anne McClintock, 37 SOC. TEXT (1993)], 2 (emphasis in original). McClintock also claims, “Removing<br />

sex workers fundamental right to choose—whether to work, how to work, when to work and where to work<br />

is a flagrant infringement of basic working rights, their integrity, their humanity, not a universal and<br />

inherent feature of the sexual exchange.” Id. at 6.<br />

69<br />

70<br />

[Add cites including Olsen and MacKinnon critiques of this.] [add a sentence on how markets usually<br />

public while sex private]<br />

71<br />

[add more citations on sexual autonomy and con law] See, e.g., Nussbaum, supra note [x], at 706<br />

(arguing “the issue of choice is the really important one”). [move: Not surprisingly, many have urged that<br />

the dominance of choice arguments in the feminist defense of abortion and the rejection of choice in<br />

prostitution is nothing short of hypocrisy. See, e.g., Almodovar, supra note [x], at 122 (footnote omitted);<br />

Cynthia Chandler, Feminists as Collaborators and Prostitutes as Autobiographers: De-Constructing an<br />

Inclusive Yet Political Feminist Jurisprudence, 10 HASTINGS WOMEN’S L.J. 135, 136 (1999) (urging<br />

feminist theory should shift focus from “either women’s liberty and choices or the dominating constraints<br />

on women’s lives, to looking at the intersection of both agency and domination on their lives”) (“Many<br />

feminists champion a woman’s right to choose—as long as it is abortion that is being discussed.”).]<br />

72<br />

[integrate with consent footnote above???] [another example of a consent based norm is why workers<br />

should be able to practice whites only, men only sexual work] [David Law point: is erotic capital more<br />

generally monetizable??? As in family court decisions where they monetize a degree, even if the person is<br />

not using it: here, you could be earning x amount based on your erotic capital!] Sylvia Law uses consent to<br />

impose some interesting limits on the professional sex as labor position. While interviewing welfare rights<br />

organizers in Nevada, Law learned that some of them feared that if sex work were fully legalized, the<br />

government would require it as a condition of receiving need-based entitlement programs. Law grounded<br />

an exemption of sex work from universal requirements to labor in liberalism:<br />

A society could address this paradigm conflict by saying that the norm of authentic consent,<br />

generally applicable to sexual relations, should control and that people should not be forced to<br />

engage in commercial sex, as a condition of subsistence. Even if commercial sex is legal, many<br />

women regard it as inconsistent with their deepest sense of self and inconsistent with moral and<br />

14


libertarian position: “A woman’s body belongs to herself and not to the government.<br />

The individual’s rights to own, use and enjoy her body in any manner that she deems<br />

appropriate, as long as she does not violate the rights of others has long been protected in<br />

this country.” 73 Similarly, the International Prostitute Rights charter “affirms the right of<br />

all women to determine their own sexual behavior, including commercial exchange,<br />

without stigmatization or punishment.” 74 Still others register their concerns in an<br />

explicitly feminist register. In language that echoes that of the strongest abolitionists,<br />

scholar Anne McClintock insists, “Legalizing female prostitution serves only to put<br />

women more firmly under male control.” 75 This libertarian view of sex work thus<br />

embraces a hybrid position, often urging commodified sex as labor while simultaneously<br />

claiming the legal and social privacy that sex often brings. In sum, professional sex is<br />

just like any other labor in that it should not be subject to criminal bans and should<br />

instead be a matter of individual choice, but, because it is sex, it should be exempt from<br />

any government regulation or supervision—including zoning, licensing, or public health<br />

protocols. It operates, in effect, as sex, or erotic, exceptionalism. 76<br />

2. Legalization<br />

Other sex work advocates, though, urge not only decriminalized, but fully<br />

legalized and regulated markets for sex. This camp views sex workers as deeply<br />

vulnerable to exploitation and risk and envisions an active role for the state in regulating<br />

sex markets and workplaces. “Like traditional prostitutes, women working in the legal<br />

sex industry have been treated as though they are not entitled to the same legal<br />

protections as other ‘socially accepted’ workers.” 77 Another commentator concurs,<br />

religious principles. We should recognize that choice with respect to sexual relationships is so<br />

integral to individual identity and integrity that sex should not be compelled, even if it could<br />

provide subsistence to a person who would otherwise depend on the state.<br />

Law, supra note [x], at 590. Crucially, Law notes that denying the requirement may reinvigorate sex<br />

exceptionalism/Observing this exceptionalist move, Law then asks the crucial question: “But why should<br />

personal choice be given such high value in relation to sex, if it is denied in relation to many other issues of<br />

profound and legitimate importance to individuals?” Law, supra note [x], at 590 (emphasis added). See<br />

also Baldwin, supra note [x], at [pincite and add parenthetical quote).<br />

73<br />

Almodovar, supra note [x], at 132. Discussing the California Constitution, Almodovar notes it<br />

“explicitly grants a right to privacy, and although this right is not absolute, it should be interpreted to say<br />

that as long as no coercion is involved, any private consenting adult activity is none of the government’s<br />

business. But this is apparently not the case when private activity involves money!” Almodovar , supra<br />

note [x], at 129. See also<br />

74<br />

[get the cite from Law]<br />

75<br />

McClintock, supra note [x], at 4.<br />

76<br />

[elaborate my own use of sexuality exceptionalism and how this is different] Several philosophers,<br />

including Martha Nussbaum, have rehearsed the complexities of the exceptionalist question, debating<br />

whether sex makes work different. See, e.g., Nussbaum, supra note [x], at 694 (“If a producer of opera<br />

should take the position that singers should not be paid, on the grounds that receiving money for the use of<br />

their talents involves an illegitimate form of commodification and even market alienation of those talents,<br />

we would think that this producer was a slick exploiter, out to make a profit from the ill treatment of<br />

vulnerable and impressionable artists.”) (footnote omitted); [add others on how is it different, etc.]<br />

77<br />

Carrie Benson Fischer, Employee Rights in <strong>Sex</strong> <strong>Work</strong>: The Struggle for Dancers’ Rights as Employees,<br />

14 LAW & INEQ. 521, 551 (1996). See also Bindman & Doezema, (“[T]heir vulnerability to human and<br />

labour rights violations is greater than that of others because of the stigma and criminal charges widely<br />

15


“organizing around decriminalization is part of organizing for better occupational health<br />

and safety.” 78 Less tied to sex exceptionalism than libertarians, these advocates view<br />

professional sex work as not meaningfully different from other forms of marginalized<br />

labor. For instance, Monica Moukalif “constructs a margins-oriented labor lens and then<br />

applies it to sex labor discourse,” in the process showing how “[p]rostitutes are<br />

organizing and advocating in ways that could be beneficial to all marginalized<br />

workers.” 79 This camp thus urges assimilating sex work into our existing labor and<br />

employment law regime.<br />

Influential legal feminists Sylvia Law, Jane Larson, and Martha Nussbaum all<br />

embrace versions of this vulnerable populations/assimilationist view. 80 For instance, Jane<br />

Larson views prostitution as a “laboratory” to determine “what makes certain voluntary<br />

labor so dangerous or so exploitative as to violate the worker’s human rights?” 81 Sylvia<br />

Law makes a strong protectionist case when she argues that not only should criminal<br />

prohibitions be repealed, but “legal remedies and programs to protect commercial sex<br />

workers from violence, rape, disease, exploitation, coercion and abuse should be<br />

enhanced.” 82 Finally, Martha Nussbaum combines an assimilationist approach with the<br />

straightforwardly liberal feminist emphasis on choice to make a case for legalized sex<br />

work as a constrained or bounded autonomy claim. 83 In sum, contrary to erotic<br />

exceptionalists, this camp contends sex work is truly no different than other forms of<br />

marginalized labor. 84 Rebelling against the privacy rubric libertarians/exceptionalists<br />

invoke to cloak labor that is sexual, this camp advocates full legalization and assimilation<br />

of sex work into our current regulatory regime.<br />

Thus, while both camps view the labor framework as a way to access both<br />

legitimacy and power for workers in the desire/sex industry there is a split, a<br />

contradiction even, within the movement. For some, “worker” empowerment stems from<br />

full legalization. Seeking to intervene in the oppression and exploitation of a classically<br />

vulnerable population, they envision the full assimilation of sex workers into the labor<br />

and employment regulatory regime. In contrast, erotic exceptionalists manifest a deeply<br />

libertarian view, embracing the labor lens from a classical freedom of contract<br />

perspective, in which the state has little role to play beyond enforcement. While modern<br />

labor contracts are intensely regulated, to libertarians, the sexual contract remains<br />

exceptional. The libertarian camp finds in constitutional and social sexual privacy norms<br />

and liberalism’s emphasis on autonomy and consent support for the classic freedom of<br />

contract position—that the state should not intervene in otherwise voluntary<br />

agreements./This classical libertarianism, unrecognizable to modern democratic<br />

marketplaces, finds support in the sexual nature of contract, which remains exceptional.<br />

attached to sex work.”); <strong>Adrienne</strong> Cuoto, [add cite] 48 (If not viewed as criminals, sex workers are at the<br />

very least considered to maintain “deviant lifestyles, roles and identities.”).<br />

78 Moukalif, supra note [x], at 271.<br />

79 Moukalif, supra note [x], at 253.<br />

80<br />

81 Larson, supra note [x], at 676.<br />

82 Law, supra note [x], at 524.<br />

83 [add a quote in here] Philosopher Martha Nussbaum combines the vulnerability lens with an autonomy<br />

analysis. Martha C. Nussbaum, “Whether from Reason or Prejudice”: Taking Money for Bodily Services,<br />

27 J. Legal Stud. 693, 693-94 (1998).<br />

84 Mgbako & Smith, supra note [x]; [add others].<br />

16


In sum, exceptionalists take a libertarian perspective, while assimilationists embrace a<br />

contradictory, deeply regulatory stance./In sum, erotic libertarians, insisting on privacy,<br />

claim it’s just like any other consensual sexual act. Labor assimilationists, though, say<br />

it’s just like any other work. Just like sex or just like work—that is the underlying<br />

question.<br />

This latent dichotomy between assimilationist and exceptionalist discourses of<br />

professional sex undergirds the remainder of this paper. First, Section II takes seriously<br />

the assimilationist claim that “sex is like any other work.” As facially persuasive as this<br />

argument is to many progressives, it rests on the idea of a monolithic workplace subject<br />

to monolithic regulation. In contrast, what this next Section demonstrates is that modern<br />

workplaces, and work, vary drastically, and are subject to diverse regulatory regimes.<br />

Law regulates work differentially, and it is unclear which model professional sex<br />

advocates seek to invoke. As much as advocates urge us to treat professional sex as any<br />

other labor, sex markets have distinctive characteristics that it would be irresponsible to<br />

ignore in crafting regulatory policy. Nor is sex work itself monolithic; rather it exhibits<br />

vastly different working conditions and risks. Section III will answer assimilationists’<br />

concerns with a set of proposals that will hopefully address the specificity of sex work,<br />

while also taking up the erotic exceptionalists’ claims that because the labor is sexual, it<br />

should be outside of and beyond regulation.<br />

II. PARADIGMS OF LABOR & ITS REGULATION<br />

[Readers: I am well aware from the employment/labor law posse at Wash U that this<br />

section does not get the regulatory structure for employment and labor right. I ask that<br />

you read this section with an eye towards its conceptual template, which sets up the next<br />

section.]<br />

Legal scholar Audrey Macklin characterizes immigrant labor as the “four D’s”:<br />

difficult, dirty, dangerous, and degrading. [Add Macklin quote.] The latter three she<br />

contends also characterize much sex for hire. <strong>Sex</strong> workers often work in unsanitary<br />

workplaces: dancers complain of dirty poles, stage floors, and dressing rooms; prostitutes<br />

often work in unclean hotels, brothels, or worse, on the street, in alleys, or in cars. Even<br />

more so than “dirty” however, charges of danger and degradation pervade arguments to<br />

legalize and regulate sex bargaining as work. 85 <strong>Sex</strong> workers have high rates of assault,<br />

from customers, both employers and other employees, and even from their intimate<br />

partners. In addition, as noted in Section II, many sex workers complain of degrading<br />

work conditions, ranging from sexual harassment (again, from customers, employers, and<br />

other employees) to racial discrimination.<br />

This Section explores these concerns, which are often invoked within the “just<br />

work” discourse. As described in Section I, above, there are distinct discourses of<br />

85 Some contend the work is also “difficult.” Prostitutes who work in brothels sometimes have to work<br />

twelve to fourteen hour shifts, and dancers spend eight hours or more in high heels, which can cause<br />

injuries to their feet. Some commentators have also noted the exhausting nature of the emotional labor<br />

much sex work requires. See infra notes [x] and accompanying text. Still, this concern does not seem to<br />

take the priority that safety, discrimination, and, to a lesser extent, “sanitation” does.<br />

17


legality and labor in different sectors of the desire industry. One invocation of sex for<br />

hire as “just work” is, of course, to urge the decriminalization of sex markets, which at<br />

the most basic level would give sex workers the ability to enforce their contracts.<br />

Currently, not only customers, but also landlords, hotels, and other third parties can evade<br />

their obligations with sex workers because these contracts are illegal. 86 In addition,<br />

because their activities are criminalized, sex traders are under constant surveillance by<br />

the police, who not only arrest them, but also sexually and economically exploit them. 87<br />

(In this sense, many have contended that the police operate much like pimps, but with the<br />

shield and force of law. 88 ) Thus, the ability to work legally and enforce the basic terms<br />

of their contracts would ameliorate some of the fundamental vulnerability and<br />

exploitation sex bargainers experience. Made in this register, freedom of contract, the<br />

claim that sex for hire is “just work” seeks its legitimization, but in the language of the<br />

sexual libertarianism described in Section I. These invocations of sex as labor actually<br />

want to exceptionalize the sexual part, keeping it a “private” and unregulated activity,<br />

rather than a more conventional labor relation.<br />

While, as Section I noted, some invocations of the “just work” discourse are for<br />

libertarian aims, many seek full legalization and regulation of sex markets./But those who<br />

envision not just decriminalization but full legalization of sex markets anticipate a starkly<br />

different, even oppositional, end state. Their invocation of sex as “just like any other<br />

work” is really a recognition claim, that sex bargainers should be considered legitimate<br />

laborers with the protections of the “applicable legal standards relating to labor rights.” 89<br />

This Section explores this set of claims within the context of the relevant state and federal<br />

laws. It breaks Macklin’s “four D’s” down into their recognizable regulatory forms—dirt<br />

and danger, typically addressed by workplace health and safety regulations and workers’<br />

86 Sylvia Law observes:<br />

For some women, the laws against pimping represent a serious burden on personal family<br />

relations. When women who work in commercial sex have voice in the development of public<br />

policy they reject laws making it a crime to live “off the earnings of prostitution.” Many women<br />

work precisely to support their children, parents or friends. Other women who sell sex for money<br />

prefer to have a third person mediate the transaction. That mediation can be benevolently<br />

protective or exploitative. Laws against pimping do not distinguish among the worker;s child,<br />

mom, protective madam or an exploitative sex slaver. Anyone who derives financial benefit from<br />

a commercial sex worker is a criminal.<br />

Law, supra note [x], at 571 (footnote omitted). See also Kotiswaran, supra note [x]; [cite others].<br />

87 [Find the case where rape was charged when the police officers identify themselves as law enforcement<br />

after sexual services have been rendered. They thus consume the service, refuse to pay, and arrest the<br />

bargainer. Is this MacKinnon?] Chancer, supra note[x], at 156 (“Not infrequently, the rapist was a copy:<br />

as agents of social control, police know their actions in relationship to prostitutes are unlikely ever to be<br />

taken seriously, less likely still to be constructed as examples of ‘police brutality’ and punished.”) (footnote<br />

omitted); Leigh, supra note [x], at 69 (“Many women complain of vice officers fondling them or exposing<br />

themselves before arresting them.”); McClintock, supra note [x], at 4 (“Police . . . are on record almost<br />

everywhere for raping prostitutes in vans and precincts, demanding ‘freebies,’ humiliating, harassing, and<br />

hounding the most vulnerable women on the streets.”). Some call for explicit non-enforcement of state<br />

laws at the local level or for implicit deprioritizing. See, e.g., Law, supra note [x], at [pincite] (discussing<br />

San Francisco and New Jersey Task Forces as case studies of local reform); Leigh, supra note [x]<br />

(discussing San Francisco Task Force recommendations to suspend enforcement of state laws against<br />

prostitution and redirecting resources to services for sex workers and enforcing nuisance laws).<br />

88 [add citations]<br />

89 [is this a Macklin quote?].<br />

18


compensation statutes, as well as some collateral tort law on violence, and degradation,<br />

much of which is the province of anti-discrimination law, mainly Title VII, but also the<br />

Americans with Disabilities Act and the Age Discrimination in Employment Act. The<br />

remainder of this Section gives an overview of how health and safety, workers’<br />

compensation, tort, and discrimination law operate. It also briefly summarizes the<br />

guidelines for determining who is an employee, which determines other, crucial benefits<br />

and rights sex bargainers seek. In the end, although the “just work” claim implicitly<br />

suggests a monolithic workplace and set of labor regulations, what the remainder of this<br />

Section reveals is that workplaces are themselves quite diverse and subject to varying<br />

regulation. In sum, the question isn’t whether sex can be work, but, rather, what kind of<br />

work will it be considered?<br />

A.<br />

The sex as labor camp anticipates a host of benefits from legalized status and<br />

regulation, primarily ameliorating the substantive work conditions for sex bargainers. As<br />

an initial matter, at the most basic level, many seek legal recognition of sex workers as<br />

employees, which would entitle them to basic employment benefits, including<br />

unemployment, health insurance, retirement, social security benefits, workers’<br />

compensation, and minimum wage and overtime. 90 Neither prostitutes, whose work is<br />

illegal, nor dancers, whose employers often classify them as independent contractors,<br />

qualify for these benefits under federal and state laws. In addition, the National Labor<br />

Relations Act gives workers classified as employees the right to unionize and collectively<br />

bargain for improved working conditions. Rather than relying solely on the state to<br />

enforce minimal, universal benefits, collective bargaining allows workers to craft terms<br />

and conditions of employment that are tailored to their needs. 91 As Sylvia Law notes,<br />

“One of the most effective ways for commercial sex workers to promote decent working<br />

conditions and protect themselves from violence, abuse, and health and safety hazards, is<br />

to work in a collective context.” 92 Indeed, sex bargainers have sought to unionize in a<br />

variety of contexts, although with little success. 93 Apart from the challenges of<br />

90<br />

Another conceivable benefit claim might be for protection under the Family and Medical Leave Act,<br />

which requires employers to provide workers’ unpaid leave for medical reasons or to care for newborn<br />

children or sick family members. When employees return they must be reinstated in same or equal position<br />

with no loss of accumulated seniority or benefits. Margot Rutman examines the applicability of FMLA to<br />

exotic dancers. She concludes that, even though, “[c]onceivably, the FMLA does apply to exotic dancers,”<br />

because dancers may need more recovery time than other workers because of appearance and physical<br />

requirements of the job, “the overall impact on exotic dancers is not as beneficial as it is in other<br />

environments.” Rutman, supra note [x], at 535-36.<br />

91<br />

Unions have often played a critical role in raising and negotiating over issues of health and safety.<br />

Because they implicate working conditions, safety issues are a mandatory subject of bargaining in<br />

a unionized workplace, and employers are therefore obligated to provide safety information upon<br />

the union’s request. . . . In addition, unions frequently negotiate for improved safety measures, or<br />

alternatively, higher wages to compensate for the risks, through the collective bargaining process.<br />

WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 946.<br />

92<br />

Law, supra note [x], at 598. See also Chun, supra note [x] (advocating unionization as best route to<br />

empowerment for exotic dancers).<br />

93<br />

As detailed in Live Nude Girls Unite! documentary, the Lusty Lady was the first exotic dance club to<br />

successfully unionize. [detail this and other efforts].<br />

19


organizing an itinerant and powerless group of workers, pro-union sex workers even<br />

encounter resistance from unions themselves, which, though desperate for new members,<br />

still often reject sex traders as illegitimate workers. 94 Still, many continue to urge<br />

unionization as sex workers’ best chance to achieve decent working conditions. 95 Thus,<br />

even beyond Macklin’s four-part schema, labor is seen as the first step toward the basic<br />

rights that inure to all workers recognized as employees.<br />

Even more so than basic employee benefits, as Monica Moukalif observes,<br />

“[o]ccupational health and safety is the major organizing point for prostitutes and other<br />

sex labor activists.” 96 The dominant form of “danger” that most risks sex workers’ safety<br />

is violence./One dominant axis of risk that endangers sex workers’ safety is violence.<br />

<strong>Sex</strong> workers have significantly higher rates of assault, rape, and even murder than other<br />

workers. [add quote and citations 97 ] Dancers are subject to sexual assault and other<br />

battery, on the stage, in private lounges and rooms, and even leaving work, in parking<br />

lots or on the street. 98 Even in public parts of clubs, “women are often subject to verbal<br />

harassment and unwanted sexual touching,” which can be a precursor to violence and<br />

make them feel unsafe in their workplaces. 99 Masseuses similarly may be subject to<br />

violence from customers. Finally, the physical assaults, robberies, rapes, and even<br />

murders of prostitutes, whether street-walkers, outcall workers, or brothel or private<br />

bargainers are well-documented. [fill in statistics] Importantly, physical and sexual<br />

assault comes from not only customers and third parties but also club owners, pimps, and<br />

other employees, e.g., bouncers, bartenders, and servers. 100 The statistics bear out that<br />

94 Chun, supra note [x], at [pincite] ([add quote re union bias against sex workers]); Law, supra note [x], at<br />

599 (“[w]here women have sought to organize a union, they have been rebuffed by established labor<br />

organizations.”); Rutman, supra note [x], at 553, 554 (“Exotic dancers, because they are a stigmatized<br />

group of women, often have problems finding outside labor support or unions that will allow them to<br />

join.”).<br />

These authors also describe challenges to organizing sex workers. [add citations regarding itinerant, antiunion,<br />

etc] “As a result of their lack of power to force better working conditions through<br />

the court system, exotic dancers have begun attempts at unionizing so that they can<br />

collectively bargain with their employers.” Rutman, supra note [x], at 553 (footnote<br />

omitted) then describes problems with unionization, pessimistic 553-54, including<br />

difficulty in organizing, retaliation, preference to remain independent contractors fn 352<br />

(voted down union), rejection by unions<br />

95 Others are more skeptical, however. Margot Rutman observes that in the first successful effort to<br />

unionize a dance club, the Lusty Lady, the dancers got 1 sick day and 1 holiday. “The union contract is<br />

impressive because it exists despite the challenges that the exotic dancers faced, but generally, the contract<br />

fails to offer work benefits comparable to those of other more established unions.” Rutman, supra note [x],<br />

at 555.<br />

96 Moukalif, supra note [x], at 270.<br />

97 Maticka-Tyndale describes assaults of dancers in private rooms of clubs, but also notes that “even in the<br />

public areas of clubs, women are often subject to verbal harassment and unwanted sexual touching.”<br />

Maticka-Tyndale, supra note [x], at 95.<br />

98 [add cite] BROOKS, supra note [x], at [pincite] (describing dancers’ concerns); Maticka-Tyndale, supra<br />

note [x], at 95 ([add parenthetical]).<br />

99 Maticka-Tyndale, supra note [x]. See also Exotic Dancing Health and Safety (“While assault is not<br />

tolerated in other workplaces, dancers report that it is not uncommon for bouncers, managers and police to<br />

treat assault in and around a strip-club as an occupational hazard that dancers should expect and “deal with”<br />

without taking action against the perpetrator.”).<br />

100 [add quote and cite]<br />

20


stakeholders in the sex trade, customers, co-workers, and employers, feel entitled to<br />

physically abuse the workers, making sex work among the most dangerous forms of<br />

labor. 101 Many contend that employers do not do enough to keep sex worksites safe and<br />

to protect the workers.<br />

A second axis of risk is “dirt,” or the unsanitary state of many sex workplaces,<br />

which exposes workers to infection and other health risks. Dancers in particular<br />

complain that employers do not properly sanitize the stage poles, floors, club furnishings,<br />

and props with which their bare genital areas come in contact. Moreover, their job<br />

requires intimate contact with customers and their clothing, over which employers have<br />

less control. 102 Constant exposure to body fluids and unsanitized surfaces puts them at<br />

risk for infections and diseases. 103<br />

What Macklin terms “degradation,” too, is a much-contested feature of sexual<br />

labor. Degradation takes many forms. Those with whom sex bargainers interact at<br />

work—customers, employers, and other employees—all can treat them with contempt,<br />

frequently using misogynist slurs and epithets. [add quote from Maticka-Tyndale]<br />

Ironically, then, the stakeholders within this market sector reinforce the image of it as<br />

filled with immoral, sexually promiscuous women who are not entitled to the basic<br />

human respect or dignity accorded other workers. Assimilationists contend that this<br />

behavior, much of it intensely gendered, comprises illegal sexual harassment under Title<br />

VII’s anti-discrimination provisions. For instance, Ann McGinley contends that “[a]<br />

business that creates a risk of serious harassment should develop systems to prevent and<br />

correct harassing behavior.” 104 Other commentators agree that even within sexualized<br />

workplaces workers should be entitled to be free from unwelcome sexual behavior. 105<br />

Assimilationists also identify a second axis of degradation covered by<br />

discrimination law. A pointed critique of sex markets is that they erect hierarchies along<br />

the lines of race and other forms of body capital. Hence, one study of prostitution found<br />

the women sorted along lines of race, with white, Asian, and lighter-skinned black<br />

women dominating the higher-end “strolls” and darker-skinned and older women<br />

relegated to less lucrative, and more harassing and dangerous, ones. 106 Similarly, as the<br />

Live Nude Girls Unite! documentary described, minorities in the dancing industry have<br />

101 [perhaps add comparative paragraph]<br />

102<br />

103<br />

Maticka-Tyndale, supra note [x], at 95, 99; [also check Gall Unionisation website].<br />

104<br />

Ann C. McGinley, Harassment of <strong>Sex</strong>(y) <strong>Work</strong>ers: Applying Title VII to <strong>Sex</strong>ualized Industries, 18 YALE<br />

J.L. & FEM. 65, 98 (2006).<br />

105<br />

See infra notes [x] and accompanying text for discussion of the debate over sexual harassment liability<br />

in sexual workplaces.<br />

106<br />

The predominantly White, Asian and light-skinned Black women on the crowded and brightly lit<br />

Geary-Mason stroll command the highest prices. They are young, slim and expensively dressed;<br />

their tightly-fitted suits, sweater sets and fur or leather coats code them for a relatively upscale<br />

market. Physically, only their shorter-than-average skirts, “big hair” and heavy makeup set them<br />

apart from many of the dressed-up female tourists or theater and restaurant goers who walk past<br />

them, and the differences may be quite subtle. They strive to project an image they describe as<br />

“nice, normal, classy.” Perhaps the main distinguishing characteristic of these women is their<br />

tendency to stand alone, unescorted, or to congregate in all-female groups and smoke between<br />

dates.<br />

Bernstein, supra note [x], at 103 (footnotes omitted). The paper then gives the pricing structures per class.<br />

21


fewer opportunities, and less lucrative ones, than white dancers. Siobhan Brooks’ recent<br />

study of three dance clubs in New York and Oakland found:<br />

When women of color are working in predominately White clubs that offer more<br />

security and are located in areas with higher property values, they often are paid<br />

less than their White counterparts, marginalized as token hires, or employed in<br />

lower-tier job positions. Women of color working in clubs predominately<br />

employing people of color, may make good money, but are subject to unjust<br />

working conditions, customer expectations that services will be cheaper, and<br />

unsafe neighborhood spaces—erotic capital is not separate from institutions or<br />

other forms of capital. 107<br />

Thus, racial groups have very different erotic capital, and this translates into very<br />

different work opportunities in sex markets. Assimilationists such as Brooks make much<br />

of this disparity. She observes: “Racism against Black women in this industry is usually<br />

viewed as normal because, like other appearance- based industries (such as modeling,<br />

acting), the sex industry is based on ideas of customer taste and preference.” 108 Yet she<br />

contends that racialized desire in the erotic industry is no less socially constructed than in<br />

other areas of social interaction, and should be considered impermissible employment<br />

discrimination under Title VII. 109 While less visible in the discourse, presumably older<br />

sex workers and disabled ones experience discrimination, outside of niche or fetish<br />

markets. 110<br />

Degradation of sex workers then takes two forms. Women working in sex<br />

markets are routinely subject to a degree and form of gendered harassment that is<br />

exceptional in other contemporary, domestic workplaces. In addition, disparate treatment<br />

of women with non-normative bodies is pervasive, resulting in hierarchies along lines of<br />

race, age, and ability. 111 Legal norms have shifted in the last forty years, to hold<br />

employers liable for discriminatory practices, including, of course, disparate treatment<br />

and harassment. Assimilationists want access to this set of rules.<br />

In sum, in addition to giving sex laborers the ability to enforce their contracts and<br />

to access basic employee benefits, assimilationists anticipate that recognizing sexual<br />

labor as legitimate work would also give workers protection from dangerous, dirty, and<br />

degrading workplaces. As this next part shows, dirt and danger concerns typically are<br />

regulated in tandem through health and safety regulations. There are some separate,<br />

common law tort rules pertaining to workplace violence, but much of it falls within<br />

workers’ compensation or OSHA regulations. Degradation, as discussed, typically is<br />

107 BROOKS, supra note [x], at 3-4, 101. She finds that clubs where women of color are concentrated have<br />

the worst terms and conditions, e.g., higher stage fees, more harassment, and coerced prostitution. See also<br />

Tanya Kateri Hernandez, <strong>Sex</strong>ual Harassment and Racial Disparity: The Mutual Construction of Gender<br />

and Race, 4 J. GENDER RACE & JUST. 183 (2001) (discussing how race is a work in sex tourism industry).<br />

108 BROOKS, supra note [x], at 99.<br />

109 See also Rutman, supra note [x], at 534 (“Despite the seemingly obvious requirement that dancers be<br />

attractive, Title VII protections still adhere to prevent discrimination against protected classes.”). [See infra<br />

notes [x] and accompanying text.]<br />

110 In fact, the propensity for marginalizing older dancers was one point of contention at the Lusty Lady.<br />

[elaborate how older dancers were treated] See, e.g., Emens, supra note [x], at 1343-45 (describing<br />

“acrotomophilia,” or desire for amputees).]<br />

111 For instance, Margot Rutman speculates: “Obese exotic dancers might be protected under the ADA from<br />

discrimination in some instances.” Rutman, supra note [x], at 534 n.165 [add discussion on dignitary<br />

harms] [disparate impact?]<br />

22


egulated by discrimination law, either sexual harassment or disparate treatment doctrine.<br />

Assimilationists’ claim is that sex workplaces should be regulated “like any other<br />

workplace.” Let’s see, then, how “other workplaces” are regulated.<br />

B. Employee Status<br />

The trilogy of laws collectively known as the National Labor Relations Act gives<br />

workers the right to organize, collectively bargain, and strike, but limits this to those<br />

deemed to be employees, excluding independent contractors. 112 Similarly, the Fair<br />

Labor Standards Act and other labor doctrine limits to employees many of the other<br />

benefits sex bargainers seek, such as minimum wage, retirement and health benefits,<br />

social security, and unemployment. 113 Yet, the legal test for employee status remains<br />

amorphous. As one casebook notes, “The question whether a worker is an independent<br />

contractor or an employee cannot be answered in the abstract and there is no uniform<br />

doctrinal test for status. Instead, the issue must be examined in the context of the<br />

legislative purpose of the particular statutory rights at issue.” 114 [add discussion of<br />

control test and other factors] Under such a test, litigation over employee status is<br />

legion. 115<br />

C. Health & Safety Regulations<br />

<strong>Work</strong>place health and safety are regulated primarily through two sets of doctrine,<br />

state workers’ compensation laws and the federal regulations and guidelines enacted by<br />

the Occupational Health & Safety Act. <strong>Work</strong>ers’ compensation is, in effect, a state-based<br />

insurance system that covers injuries that stem from “accidental injuries” that “arise out<br />

of” or “in the course of” employment. 116 The system has two signal features. First, it<br />

limits employer liability. Importantly, actual loss is not part of the equation, and in the<br />

vast majority of states neither punitive damages nor emotional pain and suffering are<br />

available. 117 In exchange, injured workers do not have to prove employer fault. 118<br />

Instead, an administrative agency addresses claims, typically more rapidly and<br />

inexpensively than litigation would. <strong>Work</strong>ers’ compensation transforms workplace<br />

112<br />

“The theory of the Act was that requiring the exchange of information and establishing a therapeutic<br />

outlet for discussion would encourage employers and unions to resolve their differences through bargaining<br />

rather than through the exercise of economic weapons (the strike and the lockout).” WORK LAW: CASES<br />

AND MATERIALS 2d edition 21-22 (Marion G. Crain et al eds., 2010) [hereinafter WORK LAW].<br />

113<br />

[add citation]<br />

114<br />

WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 74.<br />

115<br />

[add citations]<br />

116<br />

MARION CRAIN ET AL, WORK LAW: CASES AND MATERIALS 2d ed. [pincite] (2010) [hereinafter WORK<br />

LAW] (describing different states’ statutory language). There are some federal iterations as well. See, e.g.,<br />

Federal Employees’ Compensation Act, 5 U.S.C. sects. 8101-93 (federal employees); Longshore and<br />

Harbor <strong>Work</strong>ers’ Compensation Act, 33 U.S.C. sects. 901-50 (ship, harbor, and railroad employees); [add<br />

others?].<br />

117<br />

“[T]he concepts of punishment and deterrence that lie behind punitive damages are absent from the<br />

system.” WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 954. In addition, the exclusivity of remedies rules limit employees<br />

to workers’ compensation claims, barring them from bringing claims through tort suits, which could yield<br />

much greater awards. For further discussion of this doctrine, see infra note [x].<br />

118<br />

See, e.g., WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 953 (it is a “fundamental compromise—no fault compensation<br />

in exchange for limited liability”).<br />

23


liability questions from ones of employer fault and causation (and accompanying<br />

common law tort defenses 119 ) to worker need. While there is significant variance across<br />

states, they now cover most workplaces, providing workers with a safety net. 120<br />

Initially, workers’ compensation was designed to address industrial accidents. As<br />

John Fabian Witt observes, “Nineteenth-century observers believed both that the number<br />

of accidental injuries was increasing and that the cause of the increase was the<br />

mechanization of production.” 121 Coal mining and railroads topped the list for workplace<br />

accidents, followed by logging, bricklaying, and masonry. 122 These industrial accidents<br />

devastated not only the worker, but also their families. “<strong>Work</strong> accidents, it seemed,<br />

threw the ambiguous status of the industrial worker into bold relief, compelling victim<br />

and observer alike to ask hard questions about the relationships among capital, labor, and<br />

the public.” 123 Of course, as the title of Fabian’s book, Crippled <strong>Work</strong>ingmen and<br />

Destitute Widows, suggests, all of this was intensely gendered. The jobs that dominated<br />

the public and regulatory imaginary as “dangerous” were ones limited to male workers.<br />

Similarly, the ideal of a worker who would provide the sole or primary “family wage”<br />

was imagined to be a male head of household. Hence, in its initial formulation, workers’<br />

compensation was actually legally and culturally conceived as workman’s<br />

compensation. 124<br />

Operating alongside state workers’ compensation statutes are federal health and<br />

safety regulations. Following Macklin’s schema, workplace risk can be divided along<br />

two axes, “danger,” or safety, and “dirt,” or health. The Occupational Health & Safety<br />

Agency (OSHA) aggregates the two under its health and safety regulations. Enacted in<br />

1970, Congress charged OSHA with “promulgating regulations, inspecting workplaces,<br />

and prosecuting violations of its regulations and standards.” 125 Unlike workers’<br />

compensation, which functions primarily as a compensation scheme, labor reformers and<br />

Congress conceived OSHA explicitly to deter risk and achieve safer workplaces. 126<br />

OSHA’s goal is to “assure so far as possible every working man and woman in the<br />

Nation safe and healthful working conditions . . . .” 127 However, as some commentators<br />

explain, because of the political difficulties it faces in enacting new regulations, OSHA<br />

“commonly relies on . . . [its] general duty clause” in lieu of enacting specific<br />

119 WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 946 (describing how fellow-servant rule, assumption of risk, and<br />

contributory negligence operated as employer defenses to liability for workplace injuries).<br />

120 “[T]he various state laws vary greatly in their details on such issues as what types of injuries are<br />

compensable and how benefit levels are determined.” WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 953.<br />

121 JOHN FABIAN WITT, THE ACCIDENTAL REPUBLIC: CRIPPLED WORKINGMEN, DESTITUTE WIDOWS, AND<br />

THE REMAKING OF AMERICAN LAW 2 (2004). See also [add other cites]<br />

122 Id. at [pincite].<br />

123 Id. at [pincite].<br />

124 It was also “raced.” [elaborate on exclusion of black families from these patriarchal and paternalist<br />

norms]<br />

125 WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 1000. [add citation to statute] Operating within the Department of<br />

Labor, OSHA oversees private workplaces, regulating “more than 100 million workers in more than eight<br />

million workplaces.” Id. at 1001. In addition, states are authorized to enact their own OSHA’s, using the<br />

federal statute as a floor. Id. [add some other basic background on OSHA]<br />

126 Of course, as an insurance scheme, workers’ compensation, too, has some deterrence function.<br />

Employee pay-outs affect employers’ contributions. [add citation] See generally [add citations on debate<br />

over deterrence effects]<br />

127 29 U.S.C sect. 651(b).<br />

24


egulations. 128 Although criticized by employers and workers alike, OSHA is held<br />

largely responsible for reducing the number of annual workplace fatalities from 70,000 to<br />

approximately 5,000 in the last decade. 129<br />

Together, workers’ compensation and OSHA are the primary mechanisms for<br />

achieving healthy and safe workplaces. Yet, workers receive vastly different degrees and<br />

types of protection, depending on their workplace, the work they do, and the type of risk<br />

they confront in the workplace. <strong>Work</strong>ers receive the most comprehensive protection<br />

from the single-incident industrial injuries initially envisioned by the workers’<br />

compensation system. OSHA has developed adequate standards to address worker risk<br />

posed by machines and other equipment typically found in factories and other<br />

manufacturing workplaces. [add quote or elaborate] In the absence of specific<br />

recommendations, courts have found OSHA’s general duty clause governs much of this<br />

workplace risk. (The question of whether OSHA’s enforcement is effective is a different<br />

matter. 130 ) Ex post, after a single-incident injury, workers’ compensation provides<br />

medical benefits to cover rehabilitation, as well as benefits to cover temporary and<br />

permanent loss of income. As noted above, these benefits are paid according to a predetermined<br />

schedule, and workers receive only partial compensation. Still, between<br />

OSHA’s deterrence rules and workers’ compensation’s ex post benefits, our regulatory<br />

regime covers reasonably well the single-incident workplace risk that inspired it.<br />

However, beyond these single-incident industrial injuries, there remains significant<br />

uncertainty on what kinds of worker injuries are covered and when. “In particular,<br />

coverage of occupational diseases, repetitive stress injuries and mental injuries have<br />

proven controversial.” 131 After decades of struggle, workers won the inclusion of<br />

“disease” in workers’ compensation statutes, yet, “those suffering from work-related<br />

diseases still face considerable hurdles” in obtaining benefits. 132 Hence, even miners<br />

have found it more difficult to recover for black-lung and related diseases than for the<br />

incident-related injuries that inspired the system. 133 OSHA, meanwhile, has struggled to<br />

gain authority over this type of workplace risk. In the 1990s, the agency tried to establish<br />

erogonomic standards to address repetitive-motion injuries, but was hindered by a<br />

powerful employers’ lobby and a hostile Congress. 134 [address chronic disease] In the<br />

end, there is not a uniform regulatory stance toward workplace risk. Single-incident<br />

injuries associated with industrial workplaces are at one end of the spectrum, receiving<br />

the most regulatory attention, while at the other lie the more chronic injuries which have<br />

128<br />

The general duty clause states: “[e]ach employer [] shall furnish to each of his employees employment<br />

and a place of employment which are free from recognized hazards that are causing or are likely to cause<br />

death or serious physical harm to his employees[.]” [add citation] “OSHA has promulgated far fewer<br />

permanent standards than was originally contemplated, and it often relies on other means to enforce its<br />

statutory mandate.” WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 1001, 1004. See also id. at 1005 (describing second<br />

enforcement mechanism, temporary standards).<br />

129<br />

WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 939. “Today OSHA is perhaps best known for being one of the most<br />

criticized agency that regulates the workplace. Id. at 1000.<br />

130<br />

[add discussion and citations on this]<br />

131<br />

WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 955.<br />

132<br />

WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 955.<br />

133<br />

The first two workers’ compensation statutes were for miners. Arthur Larson, The Nature and Origins<br />

of <strong>Work</strong>men’s Compensation, 37 CORNELL L.Q. 206, 231 (1952). [add citations]<br />

134<br />

WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 1004-05. After its ergonomic standard was rescinded by the Bush<br />

Administration, the Department of Labor issued guidelines for discrete industries. Id.<br />

25


ecome “the fastest growing category of workplace injury.” 135 <strong>Work</strong>ers who confront<br />

this type of workplace risk still struggle for regulatory and compensatory relief.<br />

In addition, both workers’ compensation statutes and OSHA have developed<br />

categories of inclusion and exclusion. For instance, professional athletes are statutorily<br />

or functionally excluded from workers’ compensation in many states. Although<br />

frequently injured and disabled from working, courts and legislators have this category of<br />

worker does not warrant coverage because [fill in rationale]. 136 [add others] These<br />

categorical inclusions and exclusions are most apparent, however, when it comes one<br />

primary form of workplace danger identified by sex workers—violence.<br />

Over two million workers are victims of workplace violence each year. 137 In fact,<br />

homicide, not cave-ins or machine malfunctions, is the [fourth] leading cause of<br />

workplace fatalities and the leading cause for women workers. 138 Yet, as numerous<br />

commentators have noted, workplace violence seems to fall through the regulatory<br />

cracks. OSHA is nominally charged with protecting workers from violence in the<br />

workplace. Although the agency does not have specific standards for workplace<br />

violence, its general duty clause imposes a broad obligation on employers to guarantee<br />

their employees a safe working environment. However, as numerous critics have pointed<br />

out, “there has been virtually no enforcement of this duty with regard to workplace<br />

violence.” 139 As with other risk, violence is not equally distributed across workplaces—<br />

workers in late night retail, i.e., convenience stores, health care, and service jobs are the<br />

135 WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 1004.<br />

136 See, e.g., Stephen Cormac Carlin & Christopher M. Fairman, Note, Squeeze Play: <strong>Work</strong>ers’<br />

Compensation and the Professional Athlete, 12 U. MIAMI ENT. & SPORTS L. REV. 95 (1994) (noting how<br />

both workers’ compensation statutes and their own contracts limit professional athletes’ claims for injury);<br />

Rachel Schaffer, Grabbing Them by the Balls: Legislatures, Courts, and Team Owners Bar Non-Elite<br />

Professional Athletes from <strong>Work</strong>ers’ Compensation, 8 AM. U.J. GENDER SOC. POL’Y & L. 623 (2000);<br />

[GERALD HERZ & ROBERT C. BAKER JR., PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES AND THE LAW OF WORKERS’<br />

COMPENSATION: RIGHTS AND REMEDIES; Frederic Pepe & Thomas P. Frerichs, Injustice Uncovered?<br />

<strong>Work</strong>er’s Compensation and the Professional Athlete, in SPORTS AND THE LAW 18, 19 (Charles E. Quirk<br />

ed., 1996) (noting misconception that all professional athletes are overpaid and arguing that professional<br />

athletes need same legal protection as ordinary working people precisely because they do not earn large<br />

salaries); Professional and Amateur Sports 15-1, 15-17, at 15.04 (Gary A. Uberstine ed., 1991) (contrasting<br />

temporary disability benefits and permanent disability benefits)]<br />

137 [add citation]<br />

138 [add citations; compare to 1 million number]. <strong>Work</strong>place violence comprises 15% of all violence in the<br />

country. [add citation] Last decade, “[d]eaths resulting from workplace violence [were] the fastest<br />

growing type of homicide in the United States.” Jules M. <strong>Davis</strong>, Potential Violence to the Bottom Line—<br />

Expanding Employer Liability for Acts of <strong>Work</strong>place Violence in North Carolina, 78 N.C.L. REV. 2053<br />

(2000). “In 1993, the National Safe <strong>Work</strong>place Institute estimated the total annual economic cost of<br />

workplace violence to be $ 4.2 billion.” Id. at 2055. [find more recent stats: “In 1998 alone, 709<br />

homicides, 1.5 million simple assaults, 396,000 aggravated assaults, 51,000 rapes and sexual assaults, and<br />

84,000 robberies resulted from workplace violence.”]<br />

139 Note, Sheryl L. Erdmann, Eat the Carrot and Use the Stick: The Prevalence of <strong>Work</strong>place Violence<br />

Demands Proactive Federal Regulation of Employers, 43 VAL. U.L. REV. 725, 727 ( 2009) (footnote<br />

omitted). See also <strong>Davis</strong>, supra note [x], at 726-27 (“The Occupational Safety & Health Administration<br />

("OSHA") holds employers to a general duty to shield employees from hazards and injury. However, there<br />

has been virtually no enforcement of this duty with regard to workplace violence.”) (footnote omitted). In<br />

addition, in 1995 there was an administrative law ruling that strict liability would not be imposed on<br />

employers for hazards that were not recognized by the employers’ industry. [add citation]<br />

26


most vulnerable to workplace violence. 140 Accordingly, OSHA has issued specific<br />

guidelines and recommendations for two of these high-risk industries, health care and<br />

social service workplaces and late-night retail stores. 141 Still, these guidelines remain<br />

advisory only, and no workplace is subject to mandatory rules from OSHA regarding<br />

preventing workplace violence. 142<br />

In the absence of leadership by OSHA in deterring workplace violence, workers’<br />

compensation has emerged as the “primary compensatory remedy.” 143 <strong>Work</strong>ers’<br />

compensation operates as almost the converse of OSHA: while OSHA has issued<br />

guidelines covering only two high-risk industries, 90% of workers nominally are covered<br />

by workers’ compensation for workplace violence. 144 Yet, state systems have developed<br />

their own doctrinal exclusions, which disproportionately affect some workplaces where<br />

violence is a dominant risk. Ironically, while OSHA identifies all-night retail as a highrisk<br />

industry, many courts have denied workers’ compensation claims for convenience<br />

store assaults as not meeting the requirements that injuries “arise out of” or “in the course<br />

of employment.” 145 [check on other workplace assaults] In some jurisdictions, this has<br />

emerged as a categorical exclusion. 146 For instance, [describe Alabama exclusions].<br />

Moreover, under workers’ compensation there is no recovery for emotional suffering,<br />

which severely limits relief for some workplace injuries. 147 Consider for a moment a<br />

form of violence prevalent in both sex businesses and convenience stores: sexual<br />

assault. 148 Many courts have found that workplace rapes do not “arise from the<br />

employment” and hence are exempt from workers’ compensation benefits. 149 Moreover,<br />

a rape victim may not suffer lasting physical impairment, required for workers’<br />

compensation benefits. The emotional suffering many sexual assault victims experience<br />

is excluded. 150 In sum, workers’ compensation excludes some of the most devastating<br />

140<br />

For homicide, “most of the victims work in retail trade, security services, or transit services<br />

occupations.” Jane Lipscomb et al, Preventing Injuries & Abuse: Perspectives on Legal Strategies to<br />

Prevent <strong>Work</strong>place Violence, 30 J.L. MED. & ETHICS 166, 166 (2002). On the other hand, “[t]he majority<br />

of non-fatal workplace injuries occur in settings in which the victim and the attacker are in a custodial or<br />

client-caregiver relationship, such as in health care or social services.” Id. These statistics also vary<br />

according to geography. For instance, in New York City, in [dates] the workers at greatest risk from<br />

violence were taxi drivers and grocery store workers. Susan L. Pollett, Violence in the <strong>Work</strong>place: Are<br />

Employers Legally Responsible?, 22 WESTCHESTER B.J. 133, 138 (1995).<br />

141<br />

[add citation]<br />

142<br />

“Many groups, including labor unions, police departments, industry representatives, professional safety<br />

associations, and federal and state agencies, have begun to recognize that Occupational Safety and Health<br />

Administration (OSHA) inspectors should use the general duty clause of the Occupational Safety and<br />

Health Act (OSHAct) as a cudgel to force employers to address workplace violence more effectively.”<br />

Robert S. Goldberg, Comment: Victims of Criminal Violence in the <strong>Work</strong>place: An Assessment of Remedies<br />

in the United States and Great Britain, 18 COMP. LAB. L. 397, [add pincite] (1997).<br />

143<br />

Goldberg, supra note [x], at (footnote omitted).<br />

144<br />

[add citation]<br />

145<br />

See, e.g., WORK LAW, supra note [x], at 974-75.<br />

146<br />

See, e.g., Goldberg, supra note [x], at [pincite].<br />

147<br />

“In cases of workplace violence, where injuries are emotionally damaging to the victim, workers'<br />

compensation is wholly inadequate as a remedy.” [cite].<br />

148<br />

[add statistics on rape and rape/homicide in convenience stores]<br />

149<br />

It is an interesting question whether court would be more likely to conclude that sexual assaults in sex<br />

workplaces meet the link to employment. This is addressed infra notes [x] and accompanying text.<br />

150<br />

[add citation]<br />

27


violence that employees experience. Thus, the “danger” many sex workers fear most,<br />

violence, is ineffectively and sporadically regulated by existing labor law.<br />

Stepping into this regulatory void, other state and federal regulations target some of<br />

the most dangerous workplaces. For instance, responding to a massive increase in<br />

violence against workers at all-night convenience stores, Florida passed the Convenience<br />

Business Security Act, which imposed security obligations on stores that had experienced<br />

a violent incident. 151 Florida’s statute has emerged as a model for other states. 152<br />

Similarly, the state of Washington passed a statute that imposes certain obligations on<br />

health care employers to prevent workplace violence. 153 Violence against workers at<br />

abortion clinics led both the federal government and the state of California to enact clinic<br />

access laws that give “local police and district attorneys a clearer mandate to prosecute<br />

anti-abortion violence.” 154 Finally, many commentators have responded to the regulatory<br />

void by urging a return to the common-law system as the best option for victims of for<br />

workplace violence. 155<br />

In sum, not all work or workers are treated alike when it comes to risk. Some injuries<br />

are the object of both deterrence and compensatory regulation. But workers susceptible<br />

to other kinds of risk continue to struggle for legal cognition. This differential is<br />

particularly noteworthy with regard to workplace violence. Some industries enjoy<br />

special, targeted regulation to ameliorate workplace violence. 156 However some of the<br />

most dangerous workplaces are ones where the “danger” is largely unregulated or the<br />

injury is incompensable. Hence, the notion of an ideal “workplace” is a miscue when it<br />

comes to health and safety regulation.<br />

D. Discrimination<br />

If danger concerns are governed by a complex interplay of compensatory state<br />

insurance schemes, federal occupational health and safety regulations, and common law<br />

litigation, then the workplace “degradation” identified by sex work advocates is typically<br />

within the province of discrimination law. Several federal laws curb the extent to which<br />

employers can discriminate against their workers. Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of<br />

1964 prohibits employers from discriminating in hiring, promotion, termination, training,<br />

151<br />

152 [add citations]<br />

153<br />

154 See, e.g,, [add citation] (discussing operation of clinic access laws).<br />

155 And finally, while declining to impose obligations on employers, some states offer various common-law<br />

routes to recovery against employers for victims of workplace violence. <strong>Work</strong>ers and their survivors have<br />

enjoyed mixed success under both contract and tort theories of breach of duty to provide security and<br />

negligent hiring and retention. An initial hurdle, however, to common-law recovery is the workers’<br />

compensation system and its exclusivity of remedies rule, which prevents employees from seeking full<br />

compensation or compensation for the severe mental and emotional suffering that accompany workplace<br />

violence. [fill in from notes]<br />

156 More broadly, several states have enacted statutes that permit employers to act on behalf of their<br />

employees and get temporary restraining orders against individuals for harassment and stalking. See, e.g.,<br />

[California, Arkansas, Colorado, Georgia, Indiana, Nevada, Rhode Island, and Tennessee]<br />

28


and other employment terms on the basis of race, sex, religion, color, or national<br />

origin. 157 Passed shortly after Title VII, the Age Discrimination in Employment Act of<br />

1967 bars employment discrimination against workers aged 40 or older. 158 The final<br />

piece of employment discrimination legislation came in 1990 with the Americans with<br />

Disabilities Act (ADA), a broad mandate prohibiting discrimination, including in the<br />

workplace. 159 Taken together, these anti-discrimination laws sharply limit the extent to<br />

which employers can indulge their preferences and biases, and, equally crucially, the<br />

preferences and biases of their customers. Yet, there are some important exceptions that<br />

do not operate equally among the legislation.<br />

Although regulated under different statutory regimes, age, religion, national<br />

origin, and sex all are subject to a bona fide occupational qualification exemption (bfoq).<br />

This means that employers can discriminate if the characteristic is related to the “central<br />

mission” or “essence” of the business. 160 Classic examples of age bfoq’s include<br />

retirement ages for bus drivers and airline pilots, both of which courts have upheld as<br />

[add quote]. “Authenticity” of a service or product is another bfoq. Religion and<br />

national origin are most commonly exempted under authenticity bfoq’s. Hence, the<br />

Catholic Church can hire only Catholics (and men) as priests, and Chinese restaurants can<br />

hire Chinese chefs. 161 Authenticity also reaches gender, as filmmakers can hire men to<br />

play male parts. 162 In fact, the gender bfoq for Hollywood is even included in a comment<br />

in the EEOC Guidelines. 163<br />

Apart from authenticity, which gender shares with religion, national origin, and,<br />

presumably, age, gender has developed its own, complex, jurisprudence on bfoq’s. As<br />

Kimberly Yuracko points out, this is especially apparent in the service sector. Unlike,<br />

say, manufacturing, where customers typically differentiate among products, in service<br />

work, customers can develop strong preferences for particular kinds of workers or<br />

characteristics. 164 Employers develop and exploit these preferences to market their<br />

business, in ways the law has deemed both legitimate and illegitimate. 165<br />

157 [add citation]<br />

158 [add citation]<br />

159 [add citation]<br />

160 Yuracko defines the “essence” of a business as follows: “inherent meaning, shared social meaning,<br />

employer-defined and customer-defined.” Yuracko, supra note [x], at [pincite].<br />

161 In one controversial decision, the religion bfoq was even extended to hiring a philosophy professor at a<br />

religious university. [add citation and articles discussing] Consistency, however, is required. Hence, a<br />

Chinese restaurant that hired French, Italian, and Japanese chefs could not then exclude Mexican<br />

applicants. [add citation]<br />

162 Mary Anne Case called it “bizarre that sex is considered a BFOQ, in the interests of ‘authenticity or<br />

genuineness,’ for the job of actor or actress . . . . After all, the very essence of this job is to be something<br />

one is not. All that a producer should be allowed to require is that the pretense be convincing.” Mary Anne<br />

C. Case, Disaggregating Gender from <strong>Sex</strong> and <strong>Sex</strong>ual Orientation: The Effeminate Man in the Law and<br />

Feminist Jurisprudence, 105 YALE L.J. 1 (1995). Russell Robinson elaborates, “Actors generally do not<br />

face authenticity requirements regarding many character traits; for example, an actor need not be gay or<br />

have a disability or pregnant in order to play a character with that trait. Indeed, good acting is often defined<br />

as the ability to pull off a role quite different from the actor’s own identity.” Robinson, supra note [x], at<br />

31-32.<br />

163 The Guidelines purport to authorize sex discrimination in casting insofar as it is “necessary for the<br />

purpose of authenticity or genuineness.” [add citation]<br />

164 Kimberly Yuracko notes, “Two types of customer preferences define each business: preferences for<br />

products and preferences for people. Businesses are shaped most obviously by customer preferences for<br />

29


Gender stereotypes provide a fascinating case in point. Employer efforts to<br />

justify discriminatory practices based on gender stereotypes, including both nurturing and<br />

sexual titillation, were rejected by courts in a famous series of 1970s cases. Faced with<br />

airlines’ efforts to limit the position of flight attendant to young, “attractive” women,<br />

courts held they could not exclude men from the position of flight attendant nor subject<br />

women flight attendants but not men to weight restrictions. 166 Yet, the sex bfoq remains<br />

robust in other service sectors. 167 Courts have upheld gender as a valid criterion for<br />

discrimination for nurses who work in labor and delivery rooms, nursing home attendants<br />

who bathe and dress patients, restroom attendants, and, in some cases, for prison<br />

guards. 168 Importantly, the courts cite as the relevant factor the employer’s reasonable<br />

regard for its patrons’ privacy. 169 A second exemption is for workplaces where the<br />

business is “sexual gratification.” Courts have upheld the right of employers in the sex<br />

business to employ only women (or, presumably, only men). 170 Yet here, courts are<br />

careful to distinguish businesses that sell sexual gratification from those that sell sexual<br />

titillation along with another service, such as meals, air flights, etc. Employer efforts to<br />

assert bfoq’s in what Kimberley Yuracko terms “plus-sex” businesses rarely win. 171<br />

certain goods and services. A business will not stay afloat if there is no customer demand for its good or if<br />

its service does not meet customer expectations. Businesses are also shaped, however, by customer<br />

preferences for certain types of employees or service providers. Customer preferences to have certain<br />

services provided by employees of a particular sex may, for example, be grounded in (1) a belief that<br />

individuals of one sex are superior in all or particular activities to individuals of the other sex, (2) socially,<br />

or perhaps biologically, conditioned feelings of discomfort at having certain services performed by an<br />

individual of a particular sex, (3) a desire to experience or avoid sexual titillation, or (4) a sense of socially<br />

or aesthetically appropriate gender roles.” Yuracko, supra note [x], at [pincite]. Of course, many<br />

businesses may use their workers to try to link their products to an idea or image. Frequently, this is an<br />

effort to turn a product into a service. [add examples; thinking of Saturn]<br />

165<br />

Marion Crain describes employer efforts to differentiate their business and create consumer loyalty<br />

through the “brand.” [fill in] See, e.g., Dianne Avery & Marion Crain, Branded: Corporate Image, <strong>Sex</strong>ual<br />

Stereotyping, and the New Face of Capitalism, 14 DUKE J. GENDER L. & POL’Y 13 (2007) ([add<br />

parenthetical quote]). See also Marion Crain, Managing Identity: Buying into the Brand at <strong>Work</strong>, 95 IOWA<br />

L. REV. 1179 (2010) (describing how employers use “brand” to induce worker loyalty in absence of<br />

traditional incentives such as retirement benefits and job security).<br />

166<br />

[add citations]<br />

167<br />

[only limited success in manufacturing, etc]<br />

168<br />

For privacy, Yuracko develops a spectrum from touching (labor room and other care givers) to seeing to<br />

embarrassment but not touching or seeing (rest-room attendants). She contends [fill in]. Yuracko, supra<br />

note [x], at [pincite]. See also Frank, supra note [x], at [pincite] (noting that “within the privacy cases, the<br />

courts deem the interests of ordinary customers in their privacy to be less than those of patients in nursing<br />

and health care facilities”).<br />

169<br />

“The courts that have permitted the privacy-based sex BFOQ believe that the very sex of the excluded<br />

individuals prevents them from giving customers adequate privacy. Accordingly, the test for the privacybased<br />

sex BFOQ is whether the excluded applicants can satisfactorily respect the privacy of customers in<br />

the performance of the job.” Franks, supra note [x], at 490. While Yuracko notes the “symmetry” in<br />

privacy preferences, Franks notes that the privacy bfoq defense typically only is applied to women’s<br />

privacy preferences, not to men’s. Id. at [pincite]; Yuracko, supra note [x], at [pincite].<br />

170<br />

[add citations, including dicta from Wilson v. Southwest alluding to permissibility of gender<br />

discrimination in strip clubs]<br />

171<br />

“Attempts to discriminate on the basis of sex in hiring for plus-sex businesses are virtually always<br />

unsuccessful.” Yuracko, supra note [x], at n.28. She claims that airlines and related cases demonstrate that<br />

“courts simply do not permit employers to explicitly sell sexual titillation along with other goods and<br />

services.” Id. at [pincite]. Yuracko also believes that most employers would not risk association as a<br />

30


Hence, privacy and sexual gratification are noteworthy as the only areas of Title VII<br />

where customer “tastes for discrimination” trump workers’ rights to equal treatment. 172<br />

Importantly, though, employers cannot defer to their own or their customers’<br />

racial preferences or biases. Unlike sex, neither race nor disability has a bfoq exemption.<br />

The standard for disability is that employers must make “reasonable accommodations”<br />

and not deny an opportunity to an otherwise qualified individual. 173 And race is<br />

straightforward: [add judicial quote re no bfoq for race]. Yet, when it comes to<br />

“authenticity,” there appear to be some implied bfoq’s for race in employment. For<br />

instance, commentators have speculated that law enforcement can fairly limit undercover<br />

agents by race, i.e., limit Klan infiltration to white officers. 174 There also seem to be<br />

implied exemptions in the appearance-industries. Most notably, Russell Robinson and<br />

Michael J. Franks have both observed that race seems to enjoy an implied bfoq for race in<br />

the highly influential and profitable filmmaking industry. 175 Writing in 2001 and 2007,<br />

neither author found any litigation regarding the very prevalent racial preferences in<br />

casting decisions. 176 As Robinson observes, “Indeed, when it comes to casting, an entire<br />

industry effectively disregards Title VII.” 177 Noting the prevalence of racial<br />

specifications in casting breakdowns, 178 he continues, “the EEOC carves out casting as an<br />

arbitrary exception to the normal requirement that an applicant be considered as an<br />

individual and not saddled with group-based stereotypes and the ban on catering to<br />

sexual gratification business. “Businesses explicitly selling sexual titillation may do so only by positioning<br />

themselves within the traditionally marginalized and stigmatized sex industry. Businesses that seek to bring<br />

sexual titillation into the mainstream by combining sexual titillation (and sex-based hiring) with the sale of<br />

other goods and services are not permitted to exist.” Id. at 196. Ann McGinley, on the other hand, is not as<br />

sanguine about the plus-sex/sexual gratification dichotomy. McGinley finds “[t]he lines between sex work,<br />

work in a highly sexualized environment, and other work requiring employees to ‘sell’ their sex or gender<br />

to give up control over their intimate emotions are hazy.” McGinley, supra note [x], at 95 (footnote<br />

omitted). Instead, “[o]ften, a woman’s job prospects and ability to advance within an enterprise are linked<br />

to her setting the proper gender tone on the scale of commodification.” Id. at 94 (footnote omitted).<br />

172<br />

Kimberly Yuracko, however, disputes this as the real reason for the distinction. Instead, she contends<br />

[add].<br />

173<br />

[add citation]<br />

174<br />

Some have also suggested that newspapers might send white reporters to interview Klan members. [add<br />

citations] Russell Robinson observes that “A few courts have suggested without holding that Title VII<br />

could permit a BFOQ for race in certain contexts, like police forces and prison security.” Russell K.<br />

Robinson, Casting and Caste-ing: Reconciling Artistic Freedom and Antidiscrimination Norms, 95 CALIF.<br />

L. REV. 1, 41 (2007).<br />

175<br />

Michael J. Franks, Justifiable Discrimination in the News and Entertainment Industries: Does Title VII<br />

Need a Race or Color BFOQ?, 35 U.S.F. L. REV. 473 (2001); Robinson, supra note [x].<br />

176<br />

Franks, supra note [x], (“There is not a single reported case in which an actor has sued a director for<br />

race-based casting decisions, even though it is common.”); Robinson, supra note [x] (noting his research<br />

“did not turn up a single published decision in which a court adjudicated an actor’s Title VII claim of race<br />

or sex discrimination.”). [fill in Hunter Tylo pregnancy discrimination suit; jury decision for $4.8 million,<br />

which many speculate was based on Spelling’s accommodation of previous pregnant actresses; (cite<br />

Russell’s UCLA brief)].<br />

177<br />

Robinson, supra note [x], at 5.<br />

178<br />

Robinson contrasts race and sex specifications in casting breakdowns. “This common sequencing<br />

suggests that sex forms the foundation of a character more than the traits that follow, such as race and<br />

age.”; 45.2% of breakdowns had racial code, versus 94% for gender and "”women over 40 [who] are as<br />

much a minority as any ethnic group.”” Robinson, supra note [x], at 19.<br />

31


customer preferences.” 179 While not litigated, another appearance-industry, modeling,<br />

appears to enjoy a similar bfoq. Fashion designers routinely exclude non-white models<br />

from highly lucrative runway shows and advertising campaigns, or, alternatively, use race<br />

to organize their shows. Since they are not casting “characters” they cannot turn to the<br />

authenticity bfoq, and it is curious why, as with the film industry, there is not any<br />

litigation. In sum, while nominally there are not bfoq’s for race discrimination, the<br />

reality is that appearance industries routinely make hiring and other employment<br />

decisions based on race without fear of litigation. 180<br />

A second form of sex discrimination prohibited by Title VII is sexual harassment,<br />

another characteristic of their workplaces that sex workers hope fuller regulation would<br />

ameliorate. In 1986 the Supreme Court recognized that sexual harassment, whether<br />

conditioning terms and conditions on sex or creating a hostile work environment,<br />

comprised impermissible sex discrimination under Title VII. 181 The standard for sexual<br />

harassment is that employers will be liable for failing to prevent unwelcome sexual<br />

advances. [fill in] In particular, employers are found liable where “sexual provocation<br />

was not an essential part of the job and invited customer harassment.” 182 While a<br />

nominally universal norm, parties dispute whether there should be different standards,<br />

depending on the type of workplace. 183<br />

In sum, anti-discrimination law operates in two registers. Formally, age, religion,<br />

national origin, and sex each have bfoq’s. Bfoq’s for sex are complex and unpredictable,<br />

with some courts giving some deference to both privacy and sexual gratification. Race<br />

and disability nominally do not have bfoq’s, but several commentators conclude that race<br />

has an implied bfoq for appearance-based industries.<br />

In the end, then, an overview of labor regulation suggests the diversity of<br />

workplaces. It is unclear which, exactly, sex bargainers invoke when they claim “just<br />

labor,” although a safe guess is they seek to invoke the archetypal manufacturing<br />

workplace, which is subject, at least formally, to the strictest form of regulations for<br />

Advocates urge conceiving commodified sex as “just labor” to achieve a variety<br />

of effects. For anyone interested in social justice ameliorating the conditions of those I<br />

the sex industry should be an easy cause to support. Yet, there are some unperceived<br />

downsides to this framework. The sex as “just” labor then tends to elide and obscure the<br />

179 Robinson, supra note [x], at 34. Compare Robinson, supra note [x], at 40 (“advocate[ing] a different<br />

approach that acknowledges First Amendment concerns and focuses not on whether a female can<br />

‘authentically’ play a male, but on whether the sex of the character could be changed without doing<br />

substantial harm to the narrative.”) with Franks, supra note [x], at 498 (“Despite Congress’ omission of<br />

race from the BFOQ provision, people accept the reasonableness and morality of recognizing a BFOQ for<br />

race, at least in some instances involving the entertainment industry. Indeed, to demonstrate the necessity<br />

of a race BFOQ, some scholars use as their prime example the need to employ black actors to portray black<br />

characters.”).<br />

180 See Franks or Robinson (speculating on reasons for absence of litigation). Even Deborah Rhode, in her<br />

recent book urging that appearance should be impermissible under discrimination law, makes an exception<br />

for the “appearance” industries of acting, modeling, and stripping. RHODE, supra note [x], at [pincite].<br />

181 See, e.g., Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57 (1986). Prior to the Supreme Court’s ruling,<br />

some appellate courts had recognized sexual harassment as a viable cause of action under Title VII. [add<br />

citations].<br />

182 [add citation]<br />

183 See infra notes [x] and accompanying text.<br />

32


diversity of workplaces. Within these, regulation against both danger and degradation<br />

take very different forms, according to the workplace. It is unclear that the mere fact of<br />

recognizing sex as labor will yield the regulatory effects advocates envision. In addition,<br />

as the next Section shows, not only are there a diversity of workplaces, but there are also<br />

a <strong>Sex</strong> workplaces differ not only from many other workplaces, but also from each other.<br />

The next Section explores both the diversity of sex workplaces, and the distinctive<br />

challenges of regulating them, in order to contemplate whether and how sex workplaces<br />

could be more effectively regulated in order to ameliorate both danger and degradation.<br />

Within this, the particular manifestations of sex workplaces may not fit seamlessly.<br />

III.PROFESSIONAL SEX: A NEW MODE OF WORK<br />

“[J]ust what is so unique about sex-work?” 184<br />

Determining the status of prostitution is complicated. While some countries<br />

completely criminalize prostitution, in most sex work has some sort of legally liminal<br />

status, in which aspects of it are criminalized and others are not. 185 Importantly, many<br />

jurisdictions differentiate between prostitution itself, i.e., selling sex, brothels, or<br />

operating an establishment in which prostitution occurs, and “pimping,” defined<br />

variously as “assistance” or “living off the earnings of prostitution,” "controlling<br />

prostitution for gain,” or “exploitative” or “coercive” behavior. 186 In one study, of 100<br />

countries surveyed, thirty-eight currently completely criminalize prostitution. 187 In every<br />

country that criminalizes prostitution, brothel ownership and pimping likewise are<br />

illegal. 188 Liability and penalties vary by country, and, within some countries, by<br />

jurisdiction. 189 In [where should Nicaragua go in this paragraph???] seven countries<br />

184 Tinsman, supra note [x].<br />

185 Procon.org is a website that surveyed 100 countries, seeking to be “inclusive of major religions,<br />

geographical regions, and policies towards prostitution."<br />

http://prostitution.procon.org/view.resource.php?resourceID=000772 See also [let’s add some other<br />

sources/cites with parentheticals; maybe some human rights and/or ngo’s?]. Germany exemplifies how<br />

difficult it can be to discern the status of prostitution. Some set Germany’s legalization date at 1927, when<br />

the country passed its Law for Combating Venereal Diseases. Others though insist that the relevant date is<br />

the 2002 passage of the Prostitution Act because prior to that, although prostitution was legal under the<br />

German Constitution, both regulations and court decisions restricted the legal and social welfare rights of<br />

prostitutes because prostitution was considered in violation of Germany's moral code. [add the relevant<br />

cites to Germany.]<br />

186 [add cites to these quotations]. See also [add cite] (defining pimping as "lives wholly or in part on the<br />

avails of prostitution of another person."). Rationales differ. Some jurisdictions target brothels and<br />

pimping to prevent “organized” prostitution. Others [add other rationales].<br />

187 [add cite to procon website]. These include China, Egypt, India, both North and South Korea, Jamaica,<br />

Afghanistan, Slovenia and Romania, and Kenya and South Africa.] [eventually we’ll need to add cites to<br />

the countries themselves, but not right now].<br />

188 In China prostitution is criminalized “as a social practice that abrogates the inherent rights of women to<br />

personhood.” (Taiwan, on the other hand, legalized prostitution in 2009.) [add other examples of<br />

rationales].<br />

189 In Egypt, the penalty for prostitutes is 3-36 months in prison and/or a fine. In Iran, prostitutes can be<br />

imprisoned, lashed, or executed by stoning; brothel owners can be imprisoned for up to ten years, and<br />

customers also face criminal penalties. [can you find some other examples apart from Egypt and Iran that<br />

demonstrate the array of penalties?] Some countries impose only fines [add examples?] Some countries<br />

33


prostitution, brothels, and pimping all are legal. 190 Another forty countries have partially<br />

decriminalized sex work, otherwise known as restricted legality. In addition to the<br />

brothel/pimping differentiation, 191 countries can restrict legality by geography, 192<br />

gender, 193 jurisdiction, 194 “role,” that is buying or selling, 195 sex act, 196 and the role of the<br />

differentiate punishment by gender or by role, i.e., prostitutes and customers. [add examples]. [also find a<br />

country where penalties differ by jurisdiction: maybe Australia and U.S.?]<br />

190190<br />

These eight are Ecuador, Germany, Greece, Indonesia, the Netherlands, New Zealand, and Venezuela.<br />

[add procon cite; and again, eventually we’ll want the cites to the countries themselves.] As in<br />

jurisdictions that have criminalized sex work, jurisdictions that have legalized it embrace different<br />

rationales. For instance, Argentina’s constitution provides, "The private actions of people that do not<br />

offend in any way the public order and morality, nor damage a third person, are only reserved to God, and<br />

are exempt from the authority of the magistrates." [add other, different rationales].<br />

191<br />

For instance, in ten countries, prostitution and brothel ownership are legal, but pimping is not. See, e.g.,<br />

[add cite to procon] (Belgium, Columbia, Costa Rica, El Salvador, Guatemala, Panama, Peru, Singapore,<br />

Switzerland, and Turkey). [what about Italy and Israel, which only speak to pimping, which they<br />

criminalize?] Other countries criminalize both brothels and pimping. [which countries are these?]. As<br />

noted above, in no country is pimping legal if brothel ownership is not. See supra note [x] and<br />

accompanying text.<br />

192<br />

Several countries ban prostitution from “public” places. France and Canada both explicitly restrict<br />

prostitution to “private” places and make solicitation in public places illegal. In the United Kingdom<br />

"persistent" solicitation in public places is illegal, as is “kerb crawling.” Finland [fill in]. [which country<br />

says this? “Selling and purchasing sex in public is illegal.”] Other countries, such as Singapore, take the<br />

opposite approach, limiting prostitution to designated “red-light districts.” [add procon and country cites].<br />

In Mexico, prostitution is legal, but many cities restrict it to certain districts. [add procon and country<br />

cites].<br />

193<br />

Some countries engender the criminalization or liability for prostitution. In Bangladesh female<br />

prostitution is legal but male prostitution is not. [add procon and country cites]. In Egypt, the man,<br />

assumed to be the customer, is considered a witness and is exempt from punishment in exchange for<br />

testifying against the prostitute, assumed to be a woman. [add procon and country cites]. [find other<br />

gendered examples].<br />

194<br />

In Mexico and Australia, prostitution is left to the individual states, although it is criminalized in the<br />

former and legal in the latter. [eventually we’ll add cites to these; for now just put in the procon cite]. The<br />

United States leaves the status of prostitution to the individual states, but it is criminalized everywhere<br />

except for eleven rural counties in Nevada, with populations of less than 250,000. See supra note [x], and<br />

accompanying text. Between 1980 and 2009, “indoor” prostitution was legal in Rhode Island because of an<br />

unintentional legislative loophole. The state enacted new legislation criminalizing all prostitution in<br />

November 2009. [we’ll need cites to all of the Rhode Island stuff]. Some municipal jurisdictions, such as<br />

San Francisco, intermittently contemplate decriminalization. [add cite to Prop K debate]. See also Law,<br />

supra note [x], at [pincite]. [figure out after previous section is done] Some call for explicit nonenforcement<br />

of state laws at the local level or for implicit deprioritizing. See, e.g., Law, supra note [x], at<br />

[pincite] (discussing San Francisco and New Jersey Task Forces as case studies of local reform); Leigh,<br />

supra note [x] (discussing San Francisco Task Force recommendations to suspend enforcement of state<br />

laws against prostitution and redirecting resources to services for sex workers and enforcing nuisance<br />

laws).]<br />

195<br />

In some countries, selling sex is legal, but buying it is criminalized. This is the case in Iceland,<br />

Malaysia, Norway, and Sweden. [is this next statement accurate?] These countries recently introduced this<br />

differentiation, influenced in large part by feminist/sex work advocacy groups.<br />

196<br />

For instance, Japan criminalizes only intercourse; other sexual acts are legal. [add procon and country<br />

cites].<br />

34


states. 197 Finally, the “status” of prostitute can influence other rights and capabilities,<br />

almost universally negatively. 198<br />

Despite the complexity of how countries impose and implement criminalization,<br />

the overwhelming majority have a limited vision of regulatory options. They are limited<br />

to complete criminalization, or variations on decriminalization. 199 Those that have<br />

moved from decriminalization to active “legalization” through regulation mainly limit it<br />

to mandating age limits, health requirements, and registration on sex workers. 200 A very<br />

few countries have, following the erotic exceptionalist call, legalized prostitution without<br />

enacting any other accompanying regulation. 201 More often, the absence of regulation<br />

appears to be a regulatory vacuum than an intentional alignment with exceptionalism. 202<br />

The lone exception is New Zealand, whose Occupational Health and Safety agency has<br />

issued a comprehensive set of guidelines for the sex industry. 203 In sum, the regulatory<br />

imagination seems extraordinarily constrained. What would an approach look like, that<br />

197<br />

In Turkey, the brothels are state-owned, and it is illegal to “shelter a person for prostitution.” [add<br />

procon and country cite].<br />

198<br />

For instance, in Turkey sex workers cannot be married and their children are barred from occupying<br />

high rank in the army or police, or marrying persons of such rank, although they can work in other areas of<br />

government service. [add procon and country cites]. In the United States, prostitution can preclude an<br />

alien from obtaining a visa. Immigration and Nationality Act, 8 U.S.C. 1001, et. seq., as amended (naming<br />

as ineligible for a visa anyone who “is coming to the United States solely, principally, or incidentally to<br />

engage in prostitution, or has engaged in prostitution within 10 years of the date of application for a visa,<br />

admission, or adjustment of status.”). In Nevada, prostitutes cannot [check on this: I think they are<br />

restricted re where they can live, etc. Check India too].<br />

199<br />

[fix this] Prabha Kotiswaran points out how criminal, prohibitory laws have become fetishized by both<br />

sides of the decriminalization debate. “While the normative status of sex work remains deeply contested,<br />

abolitionists and sex work advocates alike display an unwavering faith in the power of criminal law; for<br />

abolitionists, strictly enforced criminal laws can eliminate sex markets, whereas for sex work advocates,<br />

decriminalization can empower sex workers.” Kotiswaran, supra note [x], at 579. In sum, contra<br />

Foucault’s injunctions against juridical understandings of modern regulation, “Both camps thus view the<br />

criminal law as having a unidirectional repressive effect on the sex industry.” Kotiswaran, supra note [x],<br />

at 613. Elsewhere, Prabha Kotiswaran cautions “irrespective of our political positions on sex work, it is not<br />

possible to sustain a corresponding preference for regulation without acknowledging that legal rules are<br />

perpetually ensnared in complex rule networks and without studying the disparate effects of the most wellmeaning<br />

legislative proposals at the most minute level of negotiations between sex workers and other<br />

stakeholders in the sex industry.” Id. at 625. See also, Law, supra note [x], at [add pincite] (describing<br />

suggested feminist reforms, including equal criminalization, criminalizing pimping, [add others]).<br />

200<br />

Compare Austria (requiring prostitutes to register, undergo periodic health examinations, be 19 years old<br />

or older, and pay taxes); Latvia (requiring monthly health check); Netherlands (prostitutes must be over 18<br />

and clients must be over 16 and prostitutes must register and pay taxes); Singapore (requiring mandatory<br />

health checks, that prostitutes be 16 years or older, and confine their work to designated districts);<br />

Switzerland (requiring prostitutes register with city authorities and health authorities and get regular health<br />

checks). Other countries impose far more intrusive requirements and restrictions. In Turkey and Greece,<br />

health checks can be as often as twice a week and in Turkey workers must carry an identity card indicating<br />

the dates of his or her health checks. Costa Rica has minimal requirements. Prostitutes “must be over 18<br />

years old and carry a health card showing how recently they had a medical check-up.” [find some<br />

interesting variations on these].<br />

201<br />

See, e.g., [fill in Brazil code and regulation].<br />

202<br />

Some countries do not address or define prostitution at all, leaving its status unclear. This is the case in<br />

long-standing nations such as Bulgaria, Spain, and Indonesia, as well as newer ones. In Kyrgyzstan, for<br />

instance, prostitution is not a crime but its exact legal status is unclear. [we’ll need the procon and<br />

eventually the country citations for these].<br />

203<br />

A GUIDE TO OCCUPATIONAL HEALTH AND SAFETY IN THE NEW ZEALAND SEX INDUSTRY [add citation].<br />

35


took sex seriously as work, while simultaneously confronting the real and high<br />

vulnerability its workers experience?<br />

A. Markets for <strong>Sex</strong><br />

Section II argued that assimilationists’ insistence that sex work be regulated like “any<br />

other labor” ignores the diversity of workplaces. This section makes an additional point.<br />

In the strong form version the homogeneity of labor claim insists and in the weak form<br />

assumes that sexual labor is no different from other, non-sexual work. But, as this next<br />

part shows, sex workplaces are not like most workplaces. Rather, they are distinct in<br />

ways that have regulatory significance.<br />

<strong>Sex</strong> workers, typically women or trans, cater to a customer base that is<br />

overwhelmingly male. 204205 <strong>Sex</strong> work is not alone in these ratios, but it can engender<br />

distinct dynamics that pose real risk to the workers. For instance dancers frequently work<br />

for multiple customers simultaneously, either in clubs or for parties—bachelor, fraternity,<br />

work, etc.—at outcall locations. 206 These customers often patronize them in all-male<br />

groups, seeking and expecting homosocial bonding through drinking and verbal and/or<br />

physical sexual interaction with the dancer(s). As several sociological studies have<br />

found, participants in these spaces may experiment with and negotiate social norms and<br />

expectations of masculinity that differ from and would be sanctioned and deemed<br />

unacceptable in other social contexts. 207 [see if you can find anything on not unlike<br />

“mobs” that turn on one outsider and lots of insiders?] Customers’ significant alcohol<br />

consumption can further loosen social inhibitions and lubricate behavior that puts<br />

workers at risk of both verbal abuse and violence. 208 Heightening the risk to workers, in<br />

clubs not only are the customers often intoxicated but dancers’ “labor” may entail<br />

“hustling” drinks from customers, which the dancers are then expected to drink. 209<br />

Unlike other workers, some sex professionals are expected to labor in a state in which<br />

their own judgment is definitionally impaired. 210211212 This particular combination of<br />

204 “an overwhelmingly female work force that services an overwhelmingly male clientele. (Male<br />

prostitutes also work for predominantly male customers.)” Chancer 151; [craft footnote on gender ratios<br />

and dynamics; where can we find this?]<br />

205 Trans.<br />

206 [some men, often regulars, patronize on their own; start by looking at Siobhan Brooks’ book]<br />

207 [find quote that the behavior is risky to the dancers.]<br />

208 The service is also contingent on the customer’s own performance and body. Many men anticipate and<br />

expect erections and orgasm from their paid sexual encounters. Not all sex work requires this; specialized<br />

and fetish markets, for instance may not. Other work also relies on bodily exertions, innate talents, or<br />

developed skills from customers. Personal trainers, sports coaches, and x each rely on some type of<br />

physical exertion and talent or skills from their client. Still, sexual expectations can create a different and<br />

the stress it can induce on the customer. This can be a prompt for violence, as it undoubtedly is not among<br />

trainees or athletes taking lessons who feel they are not performing to the social or trainer’s expectations.<br />

209 [add citation]<br />

210 In contrast, most workers do not work in an intoxicated state, and indeed, doing so would be grounds for<br />

termination./As an initial matter, in most workplaces, workers are not permitted to drink alcohol. In fact,<br />

drinking on the job would be grounds for termination from many jobs (although there are some curious<br />

exemptions: many professionals may drink or are expected to drink when entertaining clients). This rule<br />

extends to those who work in market sectors that serve alcohol, including restaurant, casino, and bars<br />

[check this]./ Even workers who serve alcohol, i.e., food servers, bartenders, liquor salespeople, and casino<br />

workers, typically have restrictions or limits imposed on how much and when they can drink themselves.<br />

36


gender ratios, homosociality, and alcohol consumption has heightened hazards for<br />

dancers in particular and also other sex professionals who work in similar contexts.<br />

A second distinctive characteristic of the work is the dangerous blurring of when sex<br />

professionals are “on” or “off” duty. 213 In sex work, part of what is being “sold” is a<br />

fantasy of interpersonal connection. 214 Customers purchase vastly differing fantasies, but<br />

overwhelmingly the scenario entails erotic attraction and personal interest in them by the<br />

worker. 215 Good sex workers deliver the fantasies their customers want. It should not be<br />

surprising that some customers confuse the fantasy with reality and attempt to pursue the<br />

relationship beyond the commodified contract. 216 (This happens to other service workers<br />

as well, who may be stalked or harassed by clients or customers, but the risk is higher in<br />

sex work, given that the fantasy is embedded in an actual sexual relationship and interest,<br />

feigned or not. 217 ) One regular customer at a dance club in New York, who often<br />

volunteers to escort dancers to the subway or to hail a cab after their shifts, observed,<br />

“It’s leaving the club that’s dangerous.” 218 Heightening the risk is the fact that some<br />

employers appear to purposely blur lines between work/off-work. They may demand<br />

sexual favors, or “entertainment,” for themselves or for friends, as a condition of<br />

employment or receiving favorable treatment, such as good shifts or referrals to clients. 219<br />

In contrast, factory workers typically are not asked to make widgets for the boss after<br />

hours. Both of these dynamics are exacerbated by the attribution to sex professionals of<br />

an identity as always available and willing, or, alternatively, as a less valuable human<br />

being because she has commodified her sexuality. Both beliefs can lead to threatening<br />

behavior towards workers, including stalking, harassing, even assault and murder. 220<br />

211 Meth case here?<br />

212 New Zealand on prostitutes: It is strongly recommended that sex workers (as is the case with any<br />

other workers) do not use alcohol on the job, as this may impair judgment<br />

and could result in sex workers making decisions that may affect the<br />

health and safety of themselves and clients.<br />

213 “Even as the wage contract establishes the workers as subject to the boss’s command in the employment<br />

sphere, it simultaneously constitutes that sphere as a limited sphere. The boss has no right of direct<br />

command outside it.” Fraser 176-77<br />

214 As Nancy Fraser says, “what is sold is a male fantasy of ‘male sex-right,’ one that implies its<br />

precariousness in actuality. Far from acquiring the right of command over the prostitute, the john gets only<br />

the staged representation of such command. A staged representation of command, however, involves a<br />

performative contradiction. The fantasy of mastery that is sold through prostitution is undermined even as<br />

it is enacted.” Fraser, supra note [x], at 179.<br />

215 But see [domination fantasies.]<br />

216<br />

217 Add brooks footnote<br />

218 BROOKS, supra note [x], at 96.<br />

219 Good shifts for dancers; outcall dispatchers for dancers and prostitutes. <strong>Sex</strong> is also expected off the job.<br />

For instance, dancers in Minneapolis claimed their supervisors demanded sexual favors in exchange for<br />

employment related requests such as time off. Fischer, supra note [x]. Sanchez, supra note 21, at 567<br />

(reporting that men who serve as agents for exotic dancers frequently insist upon sex as a condition for a<br />

referral); [add others]. One particular strong critique characterizes it as “a continuous course of<br />

circumstances beginning with work and ending with injury.” [add citation].<br />

220 Maticka-Tyndale at 96. Law professors also have blurred on-site/off-site identities. [Elaborate]<br />

37


While many customers get and respect the boundaries between “on” and “off” work, the<br />

nature of the work lends itself to confusion, thereby heightening risk. 221<br />

Similarly, the line between re-negotiating terms and harassment or assault likewise<br />

can be blurry. A dancer who is asked to perform a sexual act on a client may prefer not<br />

to do so, be offended, or even feel threatened or coerced. Another dancer, or the same<br />

dancer in different circumstances, might be open to the request, depending on the price<br />

point, client, or context. The same is true for a prostitute who has agreed in advance to a<br />

certain sexual act but who may or may not be open to requests to expand the menu.<br />

While workers in non-sexual contexts might characterize the request for additional work<br />

or more work or different work as unpleasant, exploitative, and/or coercive, law and<br />

society do not typically perceive such requests as criminal behavior the way that<br />

violations of sexual contracts can easily cross into sexual assault. 222<br />

A third meaningful distinction stems from the fact that sexual labor entails a social<br />

stigma that is almost unique. [add quote that links up to the isolation point that comes<br />

next] The stigma results in significant social isolation as it interferes in other social<br />

relationships with friends and family and, importantly, with other workers. For instance,<br />

dancers trying to unionize have found their organizing efforts rejected by several<br />

unions. 223 In addition, while other workers who labor in stressful or high-risk jobs can<br />

find solace from family, friends, and community, many sex professionals hide their work<br />

from those closest to them, resulting in profound social isolation. 224 Some scholars also<br />

attribute the isolation to the extreme control that employers exert over sex workers which<br />

“leads to the erosion of other relationships and thwarts personal autonomy.” 225226227 In<br />

221 “Even as the wage contract establishes the workers as subject to the boss’s command in the employment<br />

sphere, it simultaneously constitutes that sphere as a limited sphere. The boss has no right of direct<br />

command outside it.” Fraser 176-77<br />

222 Two hypotheticals may suffice. Imagine a law professor/yoga instructor whose student requests<br />

additional tutoring outside of class. The professor may or may not feel that the request is appropriate. He<br />

may or may not comply with the request. If he does comply, he may or may not charge additional fees, or<br />

negotiate a different deal. Alternatively, imagine a mine worker. The supervisor requests that the miner<br />

work late, or perhaps go deeper into the mine than agreed to. We can imagine that union rules might<br />

determine the outcome of the request, assuming those rules are adhered to. Alternatively, we can imagine<br />

the miner sticking to the agreed upon deal, or doing the additional, different work for more money or<br />

overtime. In both instances, the worker might feel the request was inappropriate and ask that going forward<br />

the agreed to contract will govern the interaction. The interaction would need to be an extreme one,<br />

though, to become criminal in nature. (Unless the union contract was being violated, which is itself a<br />

reason some employees strongly prefer a union shop. Or don’t.)<br />

223<br />

224 “[B]ecause of the stigmatized nature of their work, many dancers cannot tell their families or friends<br />

about what they do for a living.” Chun, supra note [x], at 233. (can’t go home to families because families<br />

are implicated, if coerced? [(or, same for other forms of labor; honor piece? Carl’s china example???)]<br />

225 See also In her essay on exotic dancers, Sarah Chun finds they are “vulnerable to exploitation by the<br />

clubs that employ them because they lack the usual support networks that workers in other industries rely<br />

on for advice and encouragement.” Chun, supra note [x], at 233(footnote omitted); see also<br />

McGinley, supra note [x], at 83 (footnote omitted) (“Even though legalized prostitution is<br />

accepted and even condoned by residents because the brothels are good for the local<br />

economy, the prostitutes are stigmatized and prostitution is hidden.”).<br />

226 Baldwin, supra note [x], at 197 (footnote omitted).<br />

38


fact, anti-prostitution activist and scholar Margaret Baldwin contends that the isolation of<br />

women who work in the sex industry is not unlike that of battered women. 228 Baldwin<br />

also speculates that “[p]rostitution and stripping also require women to create an illusion<br />

of personal interest in the customer, a dynamic that in and of itself hedges the difference<br />

between work and personal life.” 229 Importantly, the stigma runs both ways, to also<br />

afflict customers, who are largely unwilling to admit they consume commodified sexual<br />

services. 230 Unlike those who consume fossil fuels produced by coal miners, “[m]any<br />

people watch pornography, but few are willing to write to their assemblyperson about<br />

it.” 231<br />

Of course some contend this stigma is a product of the criminalization of sexual<br />

labor. Stigma is associated with most illegal activities (and many legal ones associated<br />

with lower classes) and can be exacerbated by gender. 232 Yet other criminalized<br />

activities do not incur the intensity of the stigma associated with sex work. Some lawbreakers,<br />

including drug dealers and even, ironically, pimps, enjoy cultural<br />

romanticization. In contrast, the stigma associated with commercial sex appears to stem<br />

from deep-seated biases, discomforts, and ambivalences about sex, which, while<br />

culturally specific, are almost universal in their attribution of differential meaning to men<br />

and women and particularly to prostitutes. 233<br />

Finally, while autonomy is a concern for all workers, sex work puts a distinct spin on<br />

it. 234 Feminists have fought long and hard for consent to be the determining principle in<br />

the legal governance of sex. 235 These liberal iterations of sexual agency and autonomy<br />

that characterize our current legal and moral moment mandate that a person can change<br />

their mind and withdraw consent at anytime, including during a sexual encounter. 236 In<br />

keeping with this autonomy premium, sex professionals insist they should be able to<br />

refuse their services to any customer for any reason and change their mind and withdraw<br />

consent at any time while a sexual service is being provided. 237 Importantly, they include<br />

among these reasons racial and gender preferences and biases. <strong>Sex</strong> workers may, and do,<br />

restrict their clientele based not only on a potential customer’s gender (which should not<br />

surprise us), 238 but race as well. 239 Disability proves to be is a fascinating category of its<br />

227<br />

Indeed, Some abolitionists oppose the “labor” rubric do so because of the ill effects of sex work on<br />

participants, which they characterize as akin to post-traumatic stress disorder. Others would say it’s the<br />

nature of the work/the subordinating circumstances.<br />

228<br />

[add cite]<br />

229<br />

Baldwin, supra note [x], at 198 (footnote omitted).<br />

230<br />

[comics; fred cherry]<br />

231<br />

Rutman, supra note [x], at 558 (footnote omitted).<br />

232<br />

Martha Nussbaum offers an interesting contrast with the stigma she associates with domestic workers.<br />

[contrast with Nussbaum on stigma]<br />

233<br />

[add footnote]<br />

234<br />

[check with marion re germinal pieces on worker autonomy]<br />

235<br />

Consent governs not only rape law, but also sexual harassment [am I missing other sexual regimes?]<br />

236<br />

237 [add quotes].<br />

238 Some sex workers do not discriminate on the basis of the sex or gender of customers, regardless of their<br />

own orientation. Others, though, do. Many sex professionals who identify as straight do not provide<br />

sexual services to women, and those who identify as lesbian may limit their clientele to women.<br />

239 [footnote re these]. See also age?<br />

39


own in sexual commerce. 240 Thus, sex professionals largely embrace and insist on the<br />

same norms of personal choice and preference that govern non-commodified intimacy.<br />

But this puts sex professionals in direct conflict with anti-discrimination and consumer<br />

protection law.<br />

The 1964 Civil Rights Act prohibits discrimination [insert language] against<br />

consumers. Similarly, [add other protections from consumer law]. The Americans with<br />

Disabilities Act requires “reasonable accommodations” and prohibits discrimination on<br />

the basis of the disability. Finally, the ADEA [fill in relevant portion.] This means that<br />

workers in the service industry cannot refuse to serve customers based on race/gender<br />

and other suspect characteristics. Indeed, doing so triggers legal liability for their<br />

employer. Sole proprietors face the same restrictions. [is that right?] In addition, when<br />

it comes to service workers’ completing a contract or transaction, while specific<br />

performance is off-limits as a legal remedy, there are other constraints on workers’ rights<br />

to refuse service. 241 Declining to serve a customer could be grounds for termination or<br />

other sanctions. Thus the sexual nature of sex work may be in tension with some of the<br />

standard anti-discrimination and other egalitarian measures that protect customers and<br />

consumers of paid services.<br />

Thus, while it may be tempting to “view[] them through the same labor lens as<br />

other workers,” sex workplaces are not like “most” workplaces/sex work is not like<br />

“most” work. 242 Contrary to the essentialist assimilationist claim, most workplaces are<br />

not characterized by the particularities of sex work: the culture of alcohol, drinking, and<br />

drugs; the homosocial “mob” context; the blurred line between legitimate re-negotiations<br />

and criminal assaults; a similarly blurred line between on-site/off-site (that is on-duty/offduty)<br />

identities; and employer expectations of “free” services that all can combine to<br />

create distinct risks and hazards. Nor does most work entail the stigma and resulting<br />

isolation or threaten entrenched liberal norms of autonomy in the same way. The<br />

assimilationist claim obscures the distinctive characteristics of much sexual labor and the<br />

distinct regulatory challenges it poses. The remainder of this Section explores a potential<br />

regulatory structure that would try to take account of and ameliorate these risks.<br />

B. [insert heading]<br />

On the one hand, sex professionals share many basic working conditions with nonsexual<br />

workers, e.g., exploitation by management, weak rights, dangerous and unsanitary<br />

working conditions, as well as other gender-based harms, e.g., wearing stiletto heels and<br />

sexual harassment. Many existing workplace regulations would also apply to sex<br />

workplaces. For example, exit signs and fire extinguishers are mandatory in brothels and<br />

dance clubs as they are in factories and restaurants. As other commercial sexual<br />

establishments emerge, they would be subject to these same regulations. Other<br />

requirements will be relatively easy to enforce, for instance that stages, poles, sex toys,<br />

beds, i.e., “equipment,” be safe and meet specified standards of hygiene. 243 However<br />

240 [add surrogate material]<br />

241 For instance, barring extenuating circumstances, taxi drivers typically cannot just drop a customer off<br />

anywhere, and restaurants must serve their patrons. [think about this one]<br />

242 Moukalif 254<br />

243 [Elaborate how OSHA would apply; maybe lift from condom stuff re porn?]<br />

40


other types of risks and hazards, such as the violence, harassment, and discrimination<br />

described in Section II.A and III.A, tend to be specific to or intensified by sex work.<br />

Ameliorating and managing these would require a different regulatory structure.]<br />

[Readers: I have an extended summary of new regulation from New Zealand and am<br />

contemplating whether to insert it here]<br />

As described in Sections II.A and III.A, violence poses one of the biggest risks to<br />

sex professionals’ well-being. But violence threatens some sex workers more than<br />

others. Isolation poses the biggest threat. Elizabeth Bernstein finds that “while it is true<br />

that streetwalkers are at exceptionally high risk of physical violence, by their own<br />

accounts, the chief danger exists when they’re alone with a john—in a car or hotel<br />

room—not standing on the street.” 244 Audrey Macklin’s study of lap-dancing in Canada<br />

observes the same dynamics at work: “It requires little imagination to recognize that the<br />

risk of harm to performers in the form of non-consensual contact could only be<br />

exacerbated in circumstances where the patron and the performer are secluded from<br />

observation.” 245 The empirical evidence bears out these observations: [double-check the<br />

empirics on brothel, in-home, and street prostitution violence] Hence, although some<br />

municipal codes associate public sexual acts with “indecency,” from the workers’<br />

perspective, the more “private” the sexual activity, the greater the risk. 246 In this view,<br />

the degree of risk correlates not with the type of activity but with the isolation of the<br />

interaction.<br />

We might map this sexual geography as follows. Organizational forms in which<br />

workers have no personal contact with clients, and importantly no personal contact with<br />

employers or third party intermediaries/managers, have the least risk. This would<br />

include sex professionals who provide phone sex or new media sexual services, as long<br />

as they remain anonymous to customers and have limited interactions with their<br />

employers or intermediaries. 247 The latter caveat is important as employers can pose as a<br />

great a threat as do customers. 248 In sum, in sexual geographies with no physical or face<br />

to face interactions, the risk of violence is minimal. 249 Activities within this institutional<br />

form ought not require significant regulation to protect workers, other than clear rules and<br />

protocols to preserve anonymity. 250<br />

244<br />

She continues, “In this regard, the pimps are of little or no use . . .” Bernstein, supra note [x], at 107<br />

(footnote omitted).<br />

245<br />

Macklin continues, “The curtain shielding what happens on the other side of it from the public and,<br />

therefore, judicial scrutiny is precisely what heightens the performer’s vulnerability; the parallels between<br />

the regulation of public and private space in these cases and historic patterns of judicial treatment of<br />

domestic violence are patent.” Macklin, supra note [x].<br />

246<br />

See, e.g., [add cites to municipal codes from a couple of prominent jurisdictions: check NY, LA, SF,<br />

Chicago, etc. Just 3 will do.]<br />

247<br />

Phone sex from labor/safety perspective probably unobjectionable (kids at home; safety; multi-tasking;<br />

available to all regardless of age, looks, etc)<br />

Authenticity/performativity: doing laundry or on the treadmill (heavy breathing)<br />

248<br />

See supra<br />

249<br />

But see [fill in citation that prsottitutes/sex workers are at higher risk of violence from partners, etc]<br />

250 Phone lines, etc.<br />

41


In contrast to this institutional form, face-to-face sexual services that occur in<br />

commercial establishments can pose a greater risk to workers. Brothels typically have<br />

private rooms in which the prostitutes provide services to clients; similarly, some dance<br />

clubs offer separate rooms or lounges for customers who want private lap-dances or<br />

massages. It is during these interactions, while isolated from others, that clients are most<br />

likely to assault or threaten workers. [find a good quote] In addition, as described above,<br />

many assaults and threats against sex professionals occur when they are leaving the<br />

establishment, i.e., in parking lots, on the street, etc.<br />

Although commercial establishments have a heightened risk of violence, these<br />

institutions are arguably the easiest to regulate for worker safety. Mandatory protections<br />

in sexual commercial establishments might include bodyguards, panic buttons, a security<br />

service, escorts out of the workplace, and surveillance if appropriate. 251 [fill in other<br />

relevant guidelines from New Zealand?] All of the regulations of this institutional form<br />

rest on two principles. The first is to ameliorate the risk correlated with isolation through<br />

surveillance and/or empowering the worker to quickly call on others. The second is to<br />

make the operator, not the worker, responsible for the risk reduction. As in other<br />

workplaces compliance with these requirements would be a condition of licensing for<br />

operators of these establishments. 252 “Scores” akin to restaurant sanitation ratings could<br />

be publicly posted to alert workers and customers alike to the potential for conditions that<br />

might compromise their safety.<br />

It is the final institutional form that generates the greatest risk of violence. In this<br />

sexual geography, workers physically interact with clients but outside of dedicated<br />

commercial establishments. Unlike those who work in brothels or clubs, these sex<br />

workers largely provide their sexual services in private homes, theirs or their clients’,<br />

rented spaces such as hotel rooms, or on the street or other public places. 253 They might<br />

work independently or for a third party intermediary, such as an escort service or [what is<br />

the term for an agency that sends outcall dancers?]. The defining characteristic of this<br />

sexual geography is its absence of an institutional infrastructure. Unlike brothel or club<br />

workers, outcall, street, and home-based workers serve clients in unregulated private<br />

contexts without any structural supports. These workers may serve multiple clients<br />

simultaneously, but do so without co-workers, managers, or even other customers who<br />

have a stake in the on-going stability of the enterprise, including the safety of its<br />

workers. 254 The presence of other stakeholders can provide formal or informal security<br />

for sex workers. In addition, in outcall or street work, unlike brothels and clubs, the law<br />

cannot mandate a thick security apparatus—panic buttons, security guards or bouncers,<br />

surveillance—because there is no stable worksite to regulate. <strong>Sex</strong> professionals working<br />

out of their own home have greater control over their circumstances, but even they may<br />

struggle to reduce risk. 255 If the worker is an independent contractor, working without a<br />

251<br />

Some brothels and clubs already include these safeguards. <strong>Work</strong>ers recognize and discuss risk<br />

management as they differentiate among worksites. See, e.g., BROOKS, supra note [x], at [pincite.] [Contra<br />

the bodyguard concern, informal practices at brothels include “a madam’s stationing herself near a room if<br />

she is concerned about the safety of a particular prostitute.” McGinley 105 fn omitted]<br />

252<br />

253<br />

Duke LAX rented house.<br />

254<br />

Domestic worker literature.<br />

255<br />

Many high-end prostitutes would resist this regulation, contending that they rely on closely monitored<br />

referral networks to carefully screen their clients and protect themselves. My point is that if they<br />

42


manager or intermediary, then she must absorb the costs of security completely on her<br />

own and cannot achieve the economies of scale that brothel and club operators can<br />

achieve with security systems and guards. Independent sex professionals may also resist<br />

revealing their profession to others and may resist the security apparatus that could<br />

compromise their privacy. Hence, because of its lack of institutional infrastructure and<br />

isolation, this sexual geography poses the greatest risk of violence and is the hardest to<br />

regulate.<br />

Recognizing these particular risks posed by outcall work, New Zealand has issued<br />

specific guidelines and protocols that include panic buttons, cell phones, as well as<br />

recommendations to carry flashlights in case of poor lighting. 256 [check other<br />

recommendations re outcall workers] Another protocol might be check-in systems, in<br />

which sex workers can confidentially document their schedule with the relevant customer<br />

information. This could function akin to an answering service or we could anticipate<br />

software companies creating applications that would store such information on the<br />

internet. (Regulations might also mandate body guards for outcall workers and those<br />

who work out of their own homes or other isolated venues, although this might make the<br />

cost unaffordable to most customers.) Finally, hotels could target sex work, offering<br />

rooms that provide security akin to brothels. For both third party intermediaries and sole<br />

proprietors, adhering to regulations would be a condition of licensing.<br />

In sum, when viewed on a continuum of sexual geographies, the more isolated the<br />

work the more danger it presents to the worker. Virtual interactions and minimal<br />

physical interactions with third party intermediaries are the safest as long as workers<br />

preserve their anonymity. Commercial establishments, i.e., club dancing and brothel<br />

prostitution, can pose significant risks but are the most susceptible to regulatory<br />

interventions that can increase worker safety. Regulations can require operators to<br />

provide a thick security apparatus as a condition of licensing. Finally, unlike brothels and<br />

clubs, in informal sexual geographies without a stable infrastructure workers are at the<br />

most risk. There is no stable worksite to regulate, i.e., require panic buttons, security,<br />

surveillance, and the worker is isolated from others who might provide formal or<br />

informal security. These workplaces will pose the greatest regulatory challenge, but New<br />

Zealand’s protocols provide a starting point. No regulation will eliminate the risk of<br />

violence of course; that is as impossible as it is in non-sexual workplaces. However, by<br />

taking seriously the institutional forms violence takes in sexual workplaces, we can<br />

certainly align sex work with the harm reduction approach found in other workplace<br />

safety regulation.<br />

Others have differentiated forms of sex work. 257 Yet, none of these differentiate<br />

professional sex along its institutional or organizational form, or what I call its sexual<br />

geography. The innovation of the sexual geography approach is that it replaces the<br />

common sex work classifications with one based on institutional form and risk. Most<br />

classifications of sex work tend/distinguish it according to legality or morality. In<br />

miscalculate, there are no protections in place from client violence. In particular, those who work out of<br />

their homes are vulnerable to stalking and harassing behavior.<br />

256 From the health axis of risk management, the New Zealand guidelines also encourage outcall workers to<br />

inspect the premises and [fill in]. See infra note [x] and accompanying text.<br />

257 And sex workers themselves have finely tuned senses of internal differentiation. Dancers often distance<br />

themselves from prostitutes[Strippers separate from].<br />

43


contrast, this geographic approach to risk is counter-intuitive in at least two ways. First,<br />

it defies the approach to sex work that classifies it along a continuum of proximity to<br />

penetration. It also departs from approaches that categorize sex work according to its<br />

legality. Hence, scholars, activists, and sex workers distinguish prostitution from the<br />

legal forms of professional sex: dancing, phone sex, etc. 258 In contrast to both of these<br />

categorization schemes, the sexual geography approach replaces a morality with a risk<br />

analysis. In this sense it is also attuned to the internal structure of sex work. As Prabha<br />

Kotiswaran notes, “<strong>Sex</strong> workers are highly internally differentiated according to their<br />

mode of organization of sex work and their relationship to the institution of the<br />

brothel.” 259 Her work emphasizes the spatial dimensions. 260 In sum, the sexual<br />

geography approach blurs the lines between prostitution and other legal forms of sex<br />

work in favor of a risk-based approach to regulation. 261<br />

258<br />

Even absent criminal law complications, there are vast differences among trades within the sex<br />

work industry. Consider, for example, organized dancing in direct contrast to organized<br />

prostitution. Exotic dancing is generally legal and is performed at a specific worksite (club) for a<br />

set hourly duration. Exotic dancers who work at a club or specific worksite arguably have a single<br />

employer—the club/site owner. Prostitution, however, is generally illegal, performed on a per<br />

client basis, and not necessarily at a single location for a set duration. Prostitutes are arguably selfemployed.<br />

Moukalif, supra note [x], at 255. [<strong>Adrienne</strong>: add others].<br />

259 581. Prabha Kotiswaran identifies several axes of differentiation: wage (per shot); conditions of labor,<br />

i.e., bonded labor, sharing income with brothel keeper, or independent; she also incorporates scale of the<br />

institution as influencing the autonomy of worker. Kotiswaran, supra note [x], at [pincite]. Kotiswaran’s<br />

approach also foregrounds the effects of regulation on both internal and external stakeholders. See also<br />

Law, supra note [x] ([discuss Law’s brothel descriptions as institutions]).<br />

260 “The brothel is an institution involving a particular configuration of the organization of labor, both<br />

sexual and social, backed up by a set of living and working arrangements, practices, ideas, norms,<br />

ideologies, and consciousness that are unique to the sex industry. These structural and cultural aspects of<br />

brothel-based sex work are fundamentally shaped by the spatial concentration of brothels in a red-light<br />

area. Unlike institutions such as the school, family, church, military, or prison that can be characterized as<br />

public or private, the brothel operates at the crossroads of the market and the family, harboring both sex<br />

workers and brothel keepers as well as their families. This permeates every aspect of institutional life<br />

within the brothel. For example, brothel rents reflect commercial levels, but the living conditions of the<br />

property do not approximate standards of commercial property since the brothel is the living space of its<br />

sex workers and brothel keepers, who are its laboring and entrepreneurial classes, respectively. Similarly,<br />

unlike the family where the wife socially reproduces her husband, in a brothel the sexual labor of several<br />

women, managed by the entrepreneurial labor of a brothel keeper (often a woman herself), socially<br />

reproduces a collectivity of male customers. At the same time, the brothel's economy, like that of the<br />

family, includes the labor invested by the brothel keeper in reproducing the sex workers as laborers as well<br />

as the reproductive labor that both sex workers and brothel keepers invest in their families who reside with<br />

them in the brothel.” Kotiswaran, supra note [x], at 585-86 (footnote omitted).<br />

261 “The commercial sex industry is a very broad field. Even within the realm of prostitution, the specific<br />

issues, and thus the most effective methods of organizing, vary by the type of sex work. Consider the<br />

differences that arise due to location choice alone. While street-and indoor-based prostitutes share many<br />

issues in common, practical organizing tactics must vary between the groups. An indoor-based prostitute<br />

may very well benefit from the use of an occupational-cooperative structure. But such a model is not<br />

necessarily realistic for the street-based prostitute who may benefit more from a structure like that of a<br />

worker center. Thus, even though both groups of workers may be looking toward the same policy and<br />

advocacy goals, the structures that best meet those goals necessarily vary.” Moukalif 269 (footnotes<br />

omitted). See also “The common sense understanding of prostitution therefore seems to center on a general<br />

44


Let me anticipate some objections. [Readers: the paper next rehearses autonomy,<br />

pragmatic, and intrinsic nature of the violence objections]<br />

In sum, the assimilationist claim obscures the diversity of sex work. It does not<br />

take account of the very real differences in commodified sex and how those translate into<br />

worker risk. By the same token, erotic exceptionalists ignore the very real hazards posed<br />

by sex work, insisting that the sexual nature of the labor should shield it from regulation.<br />

I have strong sympathy with both of these views. Yet, neither does very much to<br />

accomplish my goals of reducing the very real risks of sex work. To combat and manage<br />

this risk, this section has proposed a sexual geography approach parses sex work<br />

according to its institutional form and how that affects worker risk. Mapping sex work in<br />

this way provides a pragmatic approach to harm reduction. It should also appeal to<br />

feminists, on both sides of the debate, in that it suspends the typical classifications<br />

grounded in morality of continuum of heterosexual penetration in favor of assessment of<br />

danger. 262<br />

C. Discrimination<br />

The final major workplace challenge is discrimination. As described in Section II,<br />

[fill in their complaints.] Can harassment and discrimination be regulated and<br />

ameliorated in sexual labor? Yes and no. Let me elaborate.<br />

1. <strong>Sex</strong>ual Harassment<br />

As discussed earlier, sexual harassment is prevalent in sexual markets, and sex<br />

workers are particularly vulnerable to it. 263 As in other workplaces, unwanted and<br />

unwelcome sexual propositions and behavior comprise impermissible harassment. This is<br />

relatively straightforward to implement in cases of quid pro quo harassment, in which<br />

employers and intermediaries demand sex in exchange for employment or favorable<br />

terms. In fact, in sexual workplaces quid pro quo rules should be rigorously enforced<br />

precisely because of the prevalence of the practice and the particular vulnerability of sex<br />

workers to it. This is a prime area in which law can play a crucial role in shifting cultural<br />

norms and combating operators’ views of sex workers as their own personal sex slaves.<br />

In sum, there is nothing about the sexual nature of the labor that should subject workers<br />

to quid pro quo demands. In contrast, hostile environment doctrine is not such a neat fit<br />

with professional sex work.<br />

notion of exchange of money for sexual services or gratification. Under this perspective of prostitution,<br />

nude dancing for the sexual gratification of club patrons clearly is a form of prostitution despite the fact<br />

that it does not explicitly fit into the Minnesota statutory definition of prostitution because it does not by<br />

definition require sexual contact or penetration.” Fischer, supra note [x], at n.35; garb (contending antiprostitution<br />

statutes could be drafted to regulate porn films). McGinley article helps with blurring<br />

lines of prostitution, dancing, etc. and going to my geography focus instead<br />

262 [find cite: Tyra Banks show on hierarchy of sex workers: porn; prostitutes; strippers; etc, along an<br />

implied continuum of heterosexual penetration].<br />

263 See supra notes [x] and accompanying text.<br />

45


Some scholars contend that hostile environment doctrine should apply to sex<br />

workplaces, although the “welcomeness” standard should be adjusted to take account of<br />

the sexual nature of the work. 264 Ann McGinley is the strongest proponent of this<br />

view. 265266 She argues that because the work is sexual, [sexual conduct and advances in<br />

and of themselves cannot constitute a hostile environment.] “Behavior that creates a<br />

cause of action for sexual harassment in a non-sexualized workplace may actually<br />

constitute agreed-upon terms or conditions of the employment of workers in sexualized<br />

workplaces.” 267 /“There can be no alteration of a term or condition of employment if<br />

acquiescing to certain behavior is at term or condition of the job.” Hence, the<br />

assessment of sexual harassment should rest on workplace expectations. 268 “Because the<br />

essence of the business and the prostitutes’ role in the business is selling sexual acts to<br />

customers, sexual harassment will depend in large part on the negotiations and behavior<br />

agreed upon by the prostitute and the john.” 269 For both dancers and prostitutes she<br />

proposes that sexual harassment liability should turn on whether the complained of<br />

behavior is a term or condition of the job. 270 Staring, comments on body parts, sexual<br />

propositions, and general lewd comments all could be terms and conditions of a sex<br />

workplace. 271 Indeed, “[a]n exotic dancer who strips in a gentlemen’s club should<br />

reasonably expect more customer sexual behavior than the blackjack dealer or the<br />

cocktail waitress.” Still, “aggressive sexual behavior such as derogatory name-calling,<br />

clearly unwanted touching, stalking, or physical assault may alter those terms or<br />

conditions of the dancer’s employment and may create a legally cognizable hostile work<br />

environment.” 272 In these instances, employers have an obligation to implement<br />

procedures and policies to protect workers. 273274<br />

264 See Law: Some observers argue that women who work at Hooters, or in other contexts in which sexual<br />

titillation is a significant part (or all) of the service offered, assume the risk of sexual harassment, and that<br />

employers cannot reasonably be held responsible when it occurs. 416 Others assert that even when a woman<br />

is hired to offer some forms of sexual observation, conversation, or physical contact, the woman should<br />

nonetheless be free to determine what is welcomed, and that employers should be responsible for customer<br />

behavior that is unwelcome, beyond the scope of employment and reasonably known to the employer.;<br />

Even if sexual harassment law applies to erotic dancers, nude dancers, and commercial sex workers as a<br />

matter of theory and doctrine, women asserting such claims would face formidable practical difficulties of<br />

proof, both in showing that [*597] customer behavior was unwelcome and that the employer had<br />

reasonable opportunity to know and prevent it. 419 ]<br />

265 She contends that, “[w]hile the context of sexualized work environments is significantly different from<br />

non-sexualized work environments, Title VII should account for this context in determining whether a<br />

hostile work environment exists, rather than rejecting a cause of action altogether.” McGinley 92<br />

266 (McGinley article asks three questions: does T7 cover women working in sexualized environments, and<br />

if so, which women to cover? Finally, what should the standard be?); McGinley (“whether Title VII should<br />

recognize and redress sexual harassment suffered by employees at the hands of customers where the work<br />

is sexual in nature and/or the environment is highly sexualized.”)<br />

267 McGinley 68<br />

268 She makes this argument for both sex workers and others.<br />

269 McGinley, supra note [x], at 86.<br />

270 “There can be no alteration of a term or condition of employment if acquiescing to certain behavior is at<br />

term or condition of the job.” McGinley 99; McGinley’s 3 questions to pose re harassment on p. 102<br />

271 See also “For example, a term or condition of employment for exotic dancers in gentlemen’s clubs may<br />

require tolerating hooting or staring from the audience.” 102.<br />

272 104<br />

273 “an employer’s knowledge of a condition that poses a threat of harm to an employee may<br />

be viewed as deliberate or intentional when the employer permits the condition to continue.”<br />

46


When confronting harassment by customers, the fact finder should therefore consider<br />

the three-way relationship between the supervisor, the customer, and the worker. If<br />

the supervisor punishes or otherwise discriminates against women who refuse to<br />

accept harassing customer behavior or if there is an expectation that the employee not<br />

complain or respond negatively to the customer’s harassment, the jury should<br />

consider this fact as evidence that the woman did not welcome the behavior, even<br />

though she may have acquiesced to it. 275<br />

In the end, “[b]ehavior that creates a cause of action for sexual harassment in a nonsexualized<br />

workplace may actually constitute agreed-upon terms or conditions of the<br />

employment of workers in sexualized workplaces,” 276 but employers still have an<br />

obligation to police behavior that is not an expected part of the job.<br />

McGinley’s approach differs starkly from that of other commentators’. For instance,<br />

some have contended that, by its nature, sex work should be exempt from sexual<br />

harassment liability. In this view, exotic dancers, prostitutes, and other sex workers have<br />

“assumed the risk” of harassment, which should excuse employers from liability. 277 [add<br />

quote]. 278 Alternatively, Kelly Cahill characterizes their comparatively generous tips as<br />

“combat pay.” 279 McGinley opposes the assumption of risk and combat pay defenses.<br />

She charges that exempting these workplaces from liability for sexual harassment<br />

constitutes a windfall for employers: “advocacy of the assumption of risk defense fails to<br />

recognize that employers whose businesses rely on the display of masculine practices<br />

consciously create and benefit from an environment in which harassment is likely to<br />

occur.” 280 Because sexual commercial establishments rely on the fantasy that “the dancer<br />

is sexually and personally interested in the customer” to maintain their profits, “[t]o<br />

maintain this fantasy, the club walks a fine line between permitting the customers to<br />

believe that the exotic dancers are completely available to the customers and protecting<br />

the dancers from sexual harassment and criminal assault.” 281 The assumption of risk and<br />

combat pay constructions “it place[] on women the responsibility of regulating the<br />

sexualized aggression of heterosexual men without placing any responsibility on the<br />

individual men, on the employer, or on society in general.” 282 Reinforcing this point,<br />

274 Anna Nicole Smith: “consensual”; clubs might ban it though, or leave it up to the worker<br />

275 McGinley, 99<br />

276 McGinley 68<br />

277 See, e.g., Joshua Burstein, Testing the Strength of Title VII <strong>Sex</strong>ual Harassment Protection: Can It<br />

Support a Hostile <strong>Work</strong> Environment Claim Brought by a Nude Dancer?, 24 N.Y.U. REV. L. & SOC.<br />

CHANGE 271 (1998); Kelly Ann Cahill, Note, Hooters: Should There be an Assumption of Risk Defense to<br />

Some Hostile <strong>Work</strong> Environment <strong>Sex</strong>ual Harassment Claims?, 48 VAND. L. REV. 1107 (1995); Jeannie<br />

Sclafani Ree, Redressing for Success: The Liability of Hooters Restaurant for Customer Harassment of<br />

Waitresses, 20 HARV. WOMEN’S L.J. 163 (1997).<br />

278 See also As Yuracko says, “it is unlikely that if a strip club was held liable for not preventing sexual<br />

harassment of its strippers by customers it would be ordered to have its strippers wear clothes.”<br />

279 [add the relevant quote].<br />

280 McGinley, supra note [x], at 91.<br />

281 78 (footnote omitted);] Mcginley 81; Emotional labor point: In fact, “[i]f they were<br />

not prostitutes, may of htem state that they would like ot be social workers, nurses,<br />

teachers, or day care professionals.” McGinley 85 fno<br />

282 McGinley 91. [here?] See also Yuracko 229 (“Even if the law allows businesses to create jobs that<br />

involve selling sex appeal, why is it that so often women alone are perceived to have that sex appeal?”).<br />

47


from a “cost of accidents” perspective, the operator who “create[] the sexualized<br />

environment is on notice that customers will likely harass her employees and has the<br />

means to prevent and correct such harassment” 283 Finally, McGinley notes the class<br />

discrimination lurking in the assumption of risk defense. The best economic option for<br />

some working-class women may be to work in “sexy” work environments, and<br />

assumption of risk doctrine imposes a penalty on them for trying to find economic<br />

security. 284285<br />

2. Disparate Impact<br />

That leaves disparate impact discrimination claims. [fill in] As described above,<br />

racial discrimination against sex workers is present not just in hiring but terms and<br />

conditions of employment such as assignments of shifts, lucrative assignments such as to<br />

private lounges, and referrals to desirable customers. In addition, there is the expectation<br />

that racial or ethnic minorities will perform racial fantasies. In the context of exotic<br />

dancing, Siobhan Brooks notes [add quote]. 286 Brooks and others contend this<br />

discrimination violates Title VII and should be enjoined by courts. Can someone<br />

legitimately prefer one sex worker to another based on appearance? If so, what role does<br />

race play? This Section attempts to answer this vexed question.<br />

On its face, the argument to apply anti-discrimination norms to sex work is an<br />

attractive one. The assimilationist claim is very strong. As one leading sex theorist<br />

argued, lawyers no different than prostitutes or club dancers in that “Law firms aren’t<br />

allowed to hire only white lawyers on the ground that most of their clients are white and<br />

would prefer to work with lawyers of the same race, and I doubt that courts would allow<br />

that excuse if any other racial or ethnic group were involved. So why not apply the same<br />

reasoning to sex and sexual services?” 287 Brooks, who led the first Title VII suit brought<br />

by dancers, concurs: [add quote]. In this view, the assimilationist claim is very strong.<br />

<strong>Sex</strong> work is no different from other service jobs in which anti-discrimination norms bar<br />

283 McGinley 67<br />

284 McGinley 90<br />

285 McGinley’s approach also challenges the hardline drawn by Kimberly Yuracko, who also takes<br />

sexual contexts into account in assigning workplace liability. In assessing disparate treatment doctrine,<br />

Yuracko draws a clear line dividing workplaces that provide sexual gratification from those that provide<br />

only sexual titillation. In contrast, McGinley rejects Yuracko’s “plus-sex” binary/dichotomy in favor of<br />

more nuanced consideration of how sex and emotional labor are at work, finding more of a continuum.<br />

The common thread among these jobs is that either the job or the environment in which the job is<br />

performed is sexual. All of these women either trade on their sexuality or sell sex outright at<br />

work. But sexuality is not the only job requirement. Each job has other requirements, some<br />

gendered and some not. Moreover, in varying degrees, [add] require the worker to compromise<br />

her own emotional independence and to engage in emotional labor, managing the emotions of the<br />

customers to elicit a certain response. While differing in intensity and degree of managerial<br />

supervision, this emotional labor resembles the behavior expected of flight attendants, fast food<br />

workers, insurance salesmen, and paralegals . . . . Requiring emotional labor in service jobs blurs<br />

the line between jobs in sexualized industries and those in non-sexualized industries.<br />

McGinley, supra note [x], at 89.<br />

286 Russell Robinson has made similar observations about acting. notes this in expectations of colored<br />

actors to perform in ways that satisfy stereotypes @ 18) 286<br />

287 [where is this quote from?] 229 (footnote omitted).<br />

48


discriminatory preferences, however strong, by both employers and customers.<br />

Importantly, one of the big innovations of discrimination law is that employers cannot<br />

use customers’ “taste for discrimination” as a rationale to discriminate against employees.<br />

However, what should be made of the assimilationist claim in regard to<br />

discrimination law”? Three aspects of sex work should give us pause about the<br />

assimilationist claim. Taken together, these three suggest that perhaps there should be an<br />

erotic exemption/an exemption for erotic work.<br />

[Readers: I am still thinking this through and will share my thoughts on it during the<br />

workshop]<br />

IV. POLITICAL FEASIBILITY, OR, IMAGINING SOSHA<br />

This Section turns its attention to the question lurking behind this entire paper: the<br />

political feasibility of regulating professional sex in the ways suggested in Section III.<br />

Rather than making sweeping arguments about the pragmatics of cognizing sex work, it<br />

breaks the feasibility calculus concerns down into their component parts—<br />

administrability, political will, substitution effects, and, briefly, concerns over<br />

endowments. It will address each of these in turn, using two “case studies,” pornography<br />

and mining.<br />

A. Administrability<br />

Although this paper has not included pornography in its discussion and analysis, a<br />

recent conflict raises some of the potential challenges posed by regulating sex work.<br />

Earlier this spring the city of Los Angeles began to contemplate whether policing<br />

condom usage in pornography should be a municipal role. 288 After the private clinic that<br />

had monitored HIV and other health status for the pornography industry “abruptly shut its<br />

doors” in December of 2010, city lawmakers voted to draft an ordinance that would<br />

require condoms in adult films made in the city. 289 Los Angeles’s plan would end the<br />

pornography industry’s long-standing self-regulation: “The city law would be the first to<br />

impose safety standards specifically on the pornographic film industry, which has largely<br />

been allowed to police itself.” 290 After several adult-film actresses contracted HIV in the<br />

1990s, suing production companies, the industry implemented a mandatory testing<br />

regime, creating a not-for-profit clinic that established a health status data base, funded<br />

by the industry. 291 The adult film industry has long touted the efficacy of its self<br />

288 Ian Lovett, Condom Requirement Sought for <strong>Sex</strong>-Film Sets, N.Y. Times, Feb. 10, 2011, at A18. The<br />

proposed ordinance would implement mandatory condom usage as a condition of issuing film permits. [fill<br />

in re ordinance]<br />

289 One city councilman said bluntly, “We can’t keep our heads in the sand any longer. These people<br />

should be using condoms. Period.” Lovett, Condom Requirements Sought for <strong>Sex</strong>-Film Sets, supra note<br />

[x], at A18. [add check susan’s email re this]<br />

290 Id..<br />

291 The industry created Adult Industry Medical Healthcare Foundation after several actresses contracted<br />

HIV in the 1990s and sued production companies. Structured as a non-profit clinic, it was financed by<br />

contributions from production companies [conflict of interest???], and performers who had not been test4ed<br />

49


egulation, citing only five instances of HIV among performers since 2004. 292 Yet critics<br />

contend that “Testing just acts as a fig leaf for producers, who suggest that it is a<br />

reasonable substitute for condoms, which it is not.” 293 They note that, apart from HIV,<br />

sexually transmitted diseases are diagnosed in a quarter of all performers each year and<br />

are seven times higher than in general population. 294 Observers predict that the Los<br />

Angeles plan will spark a regulatory stand-off, as the city lacks jurisdiction over public<br />

health, while county officials claim they lack the resources to effectively monitor condom<br />

usage. 295 Meanwhile, the California division of OSHA has had its own conflicts with the<br />

industry. Since 2004 the state’s agency “has maintained that existing state workplace<br />

safety laws require condoms and other protections for performers in the pornographic<br />

film industry.” 296 Yet, here, as elsewhere, OSHA is plagued with little oversight and<br />

enforcement power. 297 Not surprisingly, faced with this new regulatory regime, the film<br />

industry is threatening to leave the state for more “friendly” jurisdictions. As for the<br />

clinic, which “abruptly” closed after a performer tested positive for HIV, it has re-opened<br />

as a for-profit clinic, now under the auspices of the California Medical Association.<br />

However, the incident raises the broader question of “who, if anyone, should be ensuring<br />

their safety.” 298<br />

This case study suggests the potential challenges of monitoring and enforcing markets<br />

for professional sex. If all sex work were to be legalized, some laws would apply to it as<br />

they would to any other form of labor, e.g., requirements for exit signs and asbestos<br />

levels. 299 But regulating the substance of sex markets and how they operate is a different<br />

matter. The California condom controversy suggests several things about the<br />

administrability of a regulatory regime for other professional sexual labor.<br />

First is jurisdiction. Currently, the regulation of work is a complex mix of federal,<br />

state, and local law. In addition, some industries self-regulate. As described in Section<br />

II, the availability of various bodies of federal law, including OSHA and Title VII, will<br />

turn as an initial matter on whether sex workers are classified as employees and also the<br />

size of the workplace. The federal regimes employ differing criteria, and it is not clear<br />

that all sex professionals will qualify as employees under all tests. 300 Beyond this initial<br />

litmus test, the experience with regulating condoms in the pornography industry suggests<br />

other constraints. While the OSHAct’s general duty clause would cover many health and<br />

safety issues, the agency’s own statements identified the obstacles in effectively<br />

regulating the pornography industry. The agency simply lacked the resources to monitor<br />

and remediate violations. It is unclear that other sex work would be different.<br />

within the last 30 days were not supposed to be hired. Only 5 cases of HIV since 2004, when there was an<br />

outbreak. Clashes with county health officials; now opened as for profit under oversight of California<br />

Medical Association and some criticisms against county health department.<br />

292<br />

Id..<br />

293<br />

Michael Weinstein, President of AIDS Healthcare Foundation, quoted in New York Times. Id..<br />

294<br />

Id.<br />

295<br />

State health regulators have convened a committee, but not yet acted. Id.<br />

296 Id.<br />

297 OSHA issued only handful of fines for filming unprotected sex. Id.<br />

298 Id.<br />

299 There still will be the question of whether and when sex workers are “employees.”<br />

300 See supra notes [x] and accompanying text.<br />

50


Alternatively, sex work could be regulated primarily under state law. State<br />

regulatory schemes take different forms. [fill in other ways for states to assert<br />

regulation? State osha’s?] Another option are state-based licensing schemes. Licenses<br />

[fill in definition] Requiring a license to perform sex work might be the least intrusive<br />

form of state regulation and yet the most comprehensive. A license can be required of<br />

commercial establishments and sole proprietors alike. Licensing can establish highly<br />

specific standards of a variety of behaviors, conduct, and interactions. State-issued<br />

licenses govern professions as diverse as lawyers, doctors, realtors, sale of liquor, hair<br />

dressers, caterers, and interior decorators. Licensing takes different forms. In markets<br />

involving the provision of services a standard component is to require some standardized<br />

training and a proficiency test, such as the bar exam. We could envision that sex worker<br />

training would include at the most basic level safe-sex practices, ensuring their own<br />

safety, ethics, hygiene, and perhaps instruction in counseling. 301<br />

Licensing may also have a secondary, collateral effect on sex work—legitimizing<br />

it. As suggested earlier, some sex professionals urge that their work is akin to that of<br />

professional therapists. <strong>Sex</strong> work is a profession with a high quotient of human need<br />

fulfillment, and sex workers are the last stage in the delivery of that fulfillment. 302 “As<br />

sex workers have themselves suggested, one goal would be for prostitution to become a<br />

kind of sex therapy, professionalized and no longer stigmatized.” 303 These sentiments<br />

envision the legalization of sex work not only legitimizing sex work, but actually<br />

unmasking it for the high-status work it is. 304<br />

Finally, the licensing option answers sex exceptionalists’ insistence that sex work<br />

should be a litigation-free zone. 305 Contrary to the libertarian impulses, private contracts<br />

are not exempt from scrutiny and regulation. 306 Currently, 23% of American workers<br />

require licenses to do their jobs. More than 1,100 professions require licenses, including<br />

florists, manicurists, shampoo specialists, interior designers, and of course, doctors and<br />

lawyers. 307 It would seem quite odd that a state would require a license to wash hair or<br />

arrange flowers, but that those engaged in sexual acts with the potential exchange of body<br />

fluids, not to mention the risk of violence, should be exempt. In fact, requiring licenses<br />

301 Ethics of therapists and social workers might be particularly useful in their emphasis on…/The ethical<br />

component is an intriguing one. Other professions provide model ethical codes, including social workers<br />

and therapists. Both of these professions enjoin their practitioners to follow three norms: the client, the<br />

relationship, and self-care. The combination of the three can result in recommendations/mandates to limit<br />

the number of hours/clients, [fill in others]. [work on this footnote].<br />

302 [add the quote on the most successful prostitutes are those who can connect with their clients and their<br />

needs]<br />

303 Chancer, supra note [x], at 161. In fact, [Firefly and categories of sex worker that feature in science<br />

fiction]. [compare sex surrogates]<br />

*Companion: trained at a monastic institute; take applications from customers; they are high status, and<br />

exotic, as exemplified by being cast as Indian (not black!); licensed<br />

*hustler: had companion training but used it to become a con woman<br />

*broken off from companion ship to open independent brothel; vulnerable and victimized but independent]<br />

304 [compare sex surrogates; Susan Stiritz]<br />

305 Emens, supra note [x], at [add pincite].<br />

306 Non-exceptionalism example of private contract to mine coal and a private contract for sex work: state<br />

might fairly regulate them both because of “risk.”<br />

307 Wall Street Journal (cited in The Week, Feb. 18, 2011).<br />

51


actually gives sex workers themselves the ability to help establish the standards that will<br />

govern the profession.<br />

This leads to yet another regulatory option, self-regulation. As described above,<br />

pornography has been emblematic of self-regulation, and indeed, holds itself up as a<br />

poster child for that approach. [fill in]<br />

In addition to jurisdiction, a second possibility suggested by the California condom<br />

controversy is the creation of a dedicated agency to administer the regulation. <strong>Sex</strong><br />

workers themselves endorse such a turn. Several organizations have urged creating<br />

separate and discrete agencies and commissions to monitor the sex work industry. The<br />

World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights urges, “There should be a committee to insure the<br />

protection of the rights of prostitutes and to whom prostitutes can address their<br />

complaints. This committee must be comprised of prostitutes and other professionals like<br />

lawyers and supporters.” 308 Exotic dancing organizations largely concur: “Provisions<br />

exist under the Occupational Health and Safety Act that are relevant to club owners and<br />

dancers. The current requirements, however, are often too general to be applied as<br />

measurable standards. Public Health Units need to establish specific criteria for what<br />

constitutes adequacy or sufficiency under each provision so that dancers and club owners<br />

alike know when they have met the standards for occupational health and safety.” 309<br />

Whether they envision federal or state regulation is unclear, and perhaps irrelevant, as<br />

many of these organizations are international ones. Collectively they call for OSHA-like<br />

regulatory structures that can be attentive to the specificities of sexual work and<br />

empathetic to the concerns of the workers. 310<br />

There are precedents for such targeted agencies. Some workplaces are so challenging<br />

or pose such specific risks that Congress has created a separate agency to address their<br />

workers’ health and safety needs. A classic example is the Mine Safety and Health Act,<br />

which regulates mining, an archetypically risky workplace. As noted in Section II, the<br />

severe hazards and injuries in mining prompted the first two workers’ compensation<br />

laws. 311 The first comprehensive miner safety act was passed in 1969 and amended in<br />

1977, seven years after the passage of OSHA. 312 According to the legislative history,<br />

“the existence of unsafe and unhealthful conditions and practices in the Nation’s coal or<br />

other mines is a serious impediment to the future growth of the coal or other mining<br />

industry and cannot be tolerated.” 313 Protection for miners has certainly waxed and<br />

waned over the years. At the moment, they seem to enjoy a fairly robust set of<br />

protections, although enforcement varies. 314 But are professional sex workers likely to be<br />

treated like miners? Can we imagine an STD Fund akin to the Black Lung Fund? This<br />

raises the next question, of political capital and will.<br />

B. Political Feasibility<br />

308<br />

World Charter 184<br />

309 Exotic Dancing Health and Safety<br />

310<br />

(many of the organizations are international ones, so they would not be contemplating our federal<br />

structure.)<br />

311<br />

[add citation]. Although passed seven years after OSHA, MSHA updated the Coal Mine Safety and<br />

Health Act of 1969.<br />

312<br />

[cite the statute and as amended]<br />

313<br />

[find cite] 799 (footnotes omitted).<br />

314<br />

See infra notes [x] and accompanying text.<br />

52


For several reasons, historically miners have received special regulatory attention.<br />

Through-out the twentieth century, when coal was the nation’s primary source of energy,<br />

their labor was perceived as highly valuable. The nation valorized miners, politically and<br />

culturally. Their efforts to assert their rights provoked violent resistance from the mining<br />

companies and legendary stand-offs, now immortalized in the history of unionization. 315<br />

Importantly, miners were also what Joan Williams has called ideal workers. 316 They<br />

inspired workers’ compensation because they were bread-winning men who performed<br />

crucial labor for the economy, whose workplace deaths left economically devastated<br />

families. 317 Finally, during the heyday of mining, its substantial environmental costs<br />

were not widely perceived. In other words, the substantial externalities mining imposes<br />

were invisible. All of this translated into political influence. [add quote from the Witt<br />

book] 318 Of course, MSHA was not a palliative. Miners continue to struggle against<br />

both corruption and lack of enforcement, and several recent incidents demonstrate how<br />

such dedicated agencies can be even more susceptible to industry capture. 319 In sum,<br />

MSHA can be understood as a product of miners’ substantial, if contested, political<br />

influence. 320<br />

The analogy to mining, an archetypically risky form of labor, and one that has<br />

enjoyed substantial, if not completely effective, regulation, is helpful in thinking about<br />

the political feasibility of regulating sex work. While mining may be an iconic form of<br />

labor, it is less clear that most Americans view sex work as of similar social value. To<br />

the contrary, sex work occurs against the strong gravitational pull of marriage and the<br />

firm entrenchment of sex in the private sphere. Prostitution has long been cast as a threat<br />

to the companionate model of marriage that arose in the late eighteenth century. [Add<br />

cites to historic criticisms]. Today’s critiques have hardly changed in tenor or fervor.<br />

Feminists and social conservatives alike condemn prostitution as threatening “family<br />

values.” For instance, [add example of response to Spitzer from both feminist and social<br />

conservative perspectives]. Moreover, the commodification of sex, that is, the<br />

occurrence of sex in markets, is also separately and roundly condemned. [add quotes<br />

from Radin et al] Thus, in today’s nominally sexually “enlightened” era, no less than in<br />

Victorian times, prostitution is viewed as a threat to marriage and its role in preserving<br />

the social order, or, from a more feminist lens, the possibility of marriage as a site of<br />

gender egalitarianism. In stark contrast, most workers labor firmly in the so-called public<br />

sphere and do not do so against this powerful gravitational pull.<br />

In addition, sex professionals are viewed in many ways as the opposite of the “ideal<br />

worker.” People find it difficult to envision prostitutes as women with families, let alone<br />

as the primary bread-winner, which many of them are. To the contrary, as just described,<br />

315<br />

[add cites].<br />

316<br />

[add citation to Joan]<br />

317<br />

[add quotation and citation from Witt]<br />

318<br />

See also Robert H. Stropp, Jr., Walkaround Rights for Miners’ Representatives Under MSHA: A<br />

Compatible Statutory Scheme, 96 W. VA. L. REV. 795 (1994).<br />

319<br />

[add examples re the recent mining disasters and how they were attributed to underenforcement.] In the<br />

wake of this political maelstrom, Don Blankenship, CEO of the Massey Mines, was forced to resign. [two<br />

sets of books, plus lack of enforcement].<br />

320<br />

Miners are a labor conundrum. On the one hand, among the most vulnerable and exploited of workers.<br />

On the other hand, special status.<br />

53


prostitutes are viewed as threatening to families. Much political work would need to be<br />

done for the public to perceive prostitution as work that supports, rather than threatens,<br />

families. In sum, unlike miners and other iconic workers, sex professionals have<br />

notoriously low political capital. 321<br />

Finally, there is the question of externalities, or non-internalized costs of<br />

professional sex, and how these shape public perception. With mining, until quite<br />

recently, the broader social benefits were clear. Without a comprehensive grasp of the<br />

environmental costs, mining seemed to yield a clear net benefit to the political economy.<br />

Hence the idolization of miners. What are the social benefits of commodified sex? And<br />

do they outweigh the costs?<br />

Many feminists object to prostitution’s spill-over effects on other women in<br />

society that are not borne by the industry. Sylvia Law makes the case:<br />

Elevating the status of sex industry work to an employment relationship neglects<br />

to address its sexually exploitative nature. Through legitimization, the legal<br />

system may send a message to American girls that sex work is a socially<br />

acceptable option for earning a living. This contradicts a central focus for many<br />

feminists: the desire that girls grow up knowing that they are more than sex<br />

objects, that they deserve respect and attention for more than their sexuality. 322<br />

In this view, transactional sex affects and shapes the menu of sexual bargains women<br />

might strike, including marriage and dating, as well as non-sexual workplace options and<br />

terms. Importantly, these effects are imposed on women who do not work in, or directly<br />

benefit from, sex markets. Another opponent characterizes transactional sex as “a<br />

misleading contract because, uncontrolled by the woman who is a party to it, it extends<br />

far beyond the specific transaction and payment for it. The contract is not only between<br />

the woman selling sex and the client buying it from her, but between the woman selling<br />

sex and the society in which she lives.” 323 Similarly, in contrasting prostitutes and<br />

professors, Martha Nussbaum observes, “the professor of philosophy, if a female, both<br />

enjoys reasonably high respect in the community and also might be thought to bring<br />

credit to all women in that she succeeds at an activity commonly thought to be the<br />

preserve only of males. She thus subverts traditional gender hierarchy, whereas the<br />

321 [ironic given their connections to many powerful political men]. See also LEVITT & DUBNER, supra<br />

note [x], at 31-32 (“[U]nlike the sugar and steel industries, [prostitution] holds little sway in Washington’s<br />

corridors of power—despite, it should be said, its many, many connections with men of high government<br />

office. This explains why the industries fortunes have been so badly buffeted by the naked winds of the<br />

free market.”).<br />

322 Fischer, supra note [x], at 552. Fischer continues “providing legal protection in sex work has<br />

drawbacks. Specifically, it fails to acknowledge the inherently degrading and dehumanizing character of<br />

the industry and in fact further supports its legitimacy as a commercial venture. Furthermore, granting sex<br />

workers rights as employees is only a partial response to the harm of working in the sex industry and may<br />

impede comprehensive reform.” Id. at 552. [perhaps there is an analogy to casinos and externalities?]<br />

323 Almog, supra note [x], at 734. Almog elaborates:<br />

[T]he contractual approach ignores the enormous losses entailed by the social infamy that attaches<br />

to prostitution. It is concerned only with the visible, thin upper shell of the prostitution contract-the<br />

sum or economic return for which a woman consents to sell sex—and disregards the<br />

underlying, more substantial layers of the transaction. The contractual approach is indifferent to<br />

the true cost borne by a woman that sells sex, and by her alone—the loss of social respectability<br />

and transition to an inferior, branded, humiliating status.<br />

Id. at 727.<br />

54


prostitute, while suffering stigma herself, may be thought to perpetuate gender<br />

hierarchy.” 324 Another philosopher, Margaret Radin, posits a “domino effect,” in which<br />

[fill in]. 325 Finally, Laurie Shrage offers particularly harsh criticism: “Just as an Uncle<br />

Tom exploits noxious beliefs against blacks for personal gain, and implies through his<br />

actions that blacks can benefit from a system of white supremacy, the prostitute and her<br />

clients imply that women can profit economically from patriarchy.” 326<br />

A related concern is that legalized sex markets will yield another externality—the<br />

intensification of current race and gender norms that feminists find repugnant.<br />

Mainstream sex markets value and valorize mainstream beauty norms. These shift over<br />

time, but some, for instance youth and whiteness and “ability,” remain fairly static.<br />

Hence, as discussed in Section III, non-white women, older women, and disabled women<br />

all find themselves disadvantaged in sex markets. Not only is it more difficult for them<br />

to find work, but they are often paid less, labor in less savory markets, and find<br />

themselves consigned to niche or fetish markets that may or may not require stereotypical<br />

performances that many workers find offensive. Of course, it is not inexorable that<br />

legalization will reinforce market norms. However the last fifty years have seen limits of<br />

feminist efforts to perform counter-education projects in the pornography and exotic<br />

dancing markets. For all of the above reasons, many feminists contend the externalities<br />

warrant sex work’s on-going criminalization. It is unclear how the externalities<br />

associated with sex work will weigh against discerned benefits, which will need to be<br />

clearly articulated.<br />

Of course, others strongly resist the attributions of these externalities.<br />

Responding to Radin, Sylvia Law observes that:<br />

Images and reality of degradation of women, violence, and exploitative sexuality<br />

are pervasive in U.S. culture. But it is difficult to see commercial sex as the main<br />

culprit. Despite the fact that the U.S. is expensively committed to the prosecution<br />

of commercial sex, the commodified discourse that Radin fears is pervasive in the<br />

magazines at the supermarket check-out line, on commercial airlines, in network<br />

television, and, in more explicit forms, on cable TV, the Internet and at<br />

newsstands. Indeed these pedestrian forms of sexual commodification may be<br />

more pernicious than commercial sex simply because they are so ordinary. It is<br />

not clear that legalization of commercial sex would lead to an increase in sex<br />

commodification talk, even if advertising were not banned. 327<br />

324324 Nussbaum, supra note [x], at 705. [Stigma rationale for prohibiting sex discrimination (doctors and<br />

flight attendants) w3ould seem to be strong re strippers! (“the social message that women are primarily<br />

objects for men's sexual gratification” Yuracko 151); Mikulski 20 “If there was one thing I could do, it<br />

would be to get rid of the stigma.”)]<br />

325 [add Radin citation]. But see [add citation] (contending that Radin’s “’domino effect’ argument<br />

implicitly suggests that the exploitation of mostly poor women that results from the criminalization of<br />

commercial sex is counter-balanced by benefits to people whose sexual and economic lives are closer to the<br />

visionary ideal she articulates.”) (footnote omitted).<br />

326 Shrage, supra note [x], at 356-57. But see Chancer, supra note [x], at 164 (“Shrage’s blaming of the<br />

prostitute for “Uncle Tomming” and reinforcing a patriarchal system makes no more sense than it would to<br />

accuse other underground economic workers of collusive capitalism.”).<br />

327 Law, supra note [x], at 538-39 (footnote omitted). Chancer concurs:<br />

In terms of gender, the stigmatization also singles out prostitutes from other women who also use<br />

their bodies to reap rewards in a society common with Hollywood actresses for beauty, for<br />

example, with models, singers, Madonna (her ‘good girl’ name purposefully ironic in this context)<br />

55


Some pro-sex work theorists accuse feminists who oppose it of not being concerned with<br />

“overcoming the oppression of all women,” which is what feminism is supposed to be<br />

about. 328 Anne McClintock contends that “[e]mpowering sex workers empowers all<br />

women, for the whore stigma is used to discipline women in general; and encouraging<br />

society to respect sex workers encourages society to respect all women.” 329 Finally,<br />

under some definitions of feminism, prostitution might be lauded for its potentially<br />

positive effects in subverting and destabilizing the current sex/gender system. 330<br />

C. Endowments [& Bargaining Power?]<br />

I began this Section by observing that the controversy over condom mandates in<br />

the pornography industry, a long-standing legal sex market, suggests the difficulty in<br />

administering a regulatory regime for sex markets. On the other hand, the opposite might<br />

be true. Institutional endowments form differently in legal versus illegal markets. One<br />

effect of decriminalization is to disrupt the endowments that have become entrenched in<br />

the shadow of illegality. In fact, decriminalization is often urged explicitly to disrupt<br />

these interests as evidenced in instances as diverse as the legalization of alcohol,<br />

gambling, and the emerging legal markets for marijuana. 331 Hence, part of pimps’ power<br />

over prostitutes comes from their close and complex relationships with law enforcement<br />

institutions. 332 It is unclear how current endowments would transform in legalized<br />

markets for sexual labor. Thus, prostitution might actually be easier to regulate than<br />

pornography because the current institutional endowments will be disrupted, it will take<br />

some time for them to re-form and re-organize in the legal economy.<br />

D. Substitution Effects<br />

Of course, there are limits to regulation. Equally important are its unintended effects.<br />

<strong>Sex</strong> work comprises a labor sector that is highly susceptible to substitution effects. That<br />

is, as the costs of operating a legal business increase, employers, workers, and customers<br />

migrate, or substitute, to the underground, illegal economy. In economic language,<br />

changing the cost structure of a market produces an equilibrium response. Classic<br />

examples include markets for house-keeping and yard work. <strong>Work</strong>ers in these sectors<br />

self-sort into four markets. They can work for a legal company, independently and<br />

and followers, and withhuge numbers of women who spend billions on cosmetics and surgical<br />

procedures in their struggle to prolong sexiness into old age. In each of these cases, like sex<br />

workers, women are also either taking pleasure in the power of temporarily sexy and salable<br />

bodies, or attempting to find such power. Thus, from the standpoint of feminist theory, it is<br />

inconsistent to indict only the prostitute for collusion with patriarchy unless millions of other<br />

women are also viewed just as critically.<br />

Chancer, supra note [x], at 165.<br />

328 Chancer, supra note [x], at 156 (emphasis in original). Elsewhere Chancer contends “For all these<br />

reasons, then, it strikes me that feminism would be most consistent with its own goals of representing the<br />

interests of all women to the extent that it rigorously avoided reproaching prostitutes for coping within<br />

gender-skewed conditions.” Chancer, supra note [x], at 166 (emphasis in original).<br />

329 McClintock, supra note [x], at [add pincite].<br />

330 [add cite to Jody Green on this definition; Gayle Rubin and Judith Butler too? Katherine Franke in law?]<br />

331<br />

332<br />

See also LEVITT & DUBNER, supra note [x], at 40-41 (discussing negotiations between pimps and police)<br />

[change to Venkatesh].<br />

56


legally, independently “underground,” or underground for a company. <strong>Work</strong>ers opt for<br />

underground labor for a variety of reasons. Of course some do not have a choice, i.e.,<br />

they may lack the paperwork for legal labor or are coerced into illegal markets. Others,<br />

though, are enticed into illegal labor by autonomy, convenience, or “wedge” effects, i.e.,<br />

a substantial difference between the amount the employer pays into the system and the<br />

amount the worker receives.<br />

Market sectors that are either capital intensive and/or require a fixed business site<br />

have the lowest substitution effects. For instance, a manufacturing plant cannot easily go<br />

“underground.” Similarly, restaurants must operate out of a specific site. 333 This lack of<br />

mobility means they cannot easily evade inspection. (Of course, with manufacturing,<br />

there is a different substitution effect at work, outsourcing to a different, less regulated<br />

jurisdiction, whether domestic or foreign. However, outsourcing exchanges one legal<br />

sector for another; it does not go completely underground.) One of the arguable reasons<br />

that mining can be so heavily regulated is that it is unsusceptible to substitution effects.<br />

It is both capital intensive and site specific. Mining companies are not mobile—they<br />

must be situated where the natural resources are located. In addition, they invest heavily<br />

and, unlike manufacturing, cannot outsource the work.<br />

In contrast, sex work would seem to be the opposite of mining. <strong>Sex</strong> work requires<br />

neither a high investment of conventional capital nor does most of it require a fixed<br />

business site. 334 It requires little capital (dance clubs and brothels can be run out of<br />

almost any space) and is not site specific, i.e., sex can occur in a home, leased or rented<br />

premises, or even the street or car, and is highly mobile, it is highly susceptible to<br />

substitution to the underground economy. Thus, like housekeeping, yard work, and drug<br />

dealing, sex work is highly susceptible to substitution effects. Hence, there is a concern<br />

that if decriminalized and then regulated, sex work would remain in the underground<br />

economy. My gamble, though, is that because much sex work already is illegal, the<br />

effects would flow the other way. Instead of people fleeing the legal sector for the illegal<br />

one, we are trying to induce people to move out of the underground economy to the legal<br />

one. At least some owners, workers, and customers, I am betting, would prefer the lower<br />

risk and lesser stigmatization of a legal market, as opposed to an illegal one. While it<br />

may be true that the more regulations that are imposed, the less illegal work will<br />

“substitute up” to legal markets, it is also the case that some who currently opt out of<br />

professional sex because of the criminal and other risks would almost certainly be drawn<br />

into a decriminalized, legalized, fully regulated market. [find any empirical data on what<br />

happens in legalized jurisdictions?] [Or alternatively, a different kind of substitution<br />

effect would take place, the classic race to the bottom in which, like the highly mobile<br />

pornography industry, regulation precipitates a move to a more friendly jurisdiction.]<br />

Importantly, there is also substitution between different sectors of sex markets, e.g.,<br />

brothel, outcall, and street prostitution (or in dancing, club versus outcall). [I have to<br />

think this through: For instance, one would hypothesize that increasing regulation of<br />

brothel/dance clubs through body guards, etc. will increase the substitution to outcall. 335 ]<br />

333 Pop up restaurants, “underground restaurants,” and trucks are the exceptions.<br />

334 The exception would be dance clubs.<br />

335<br />

Experience suggests that if brothels are closed street prostitution and escort services become more<br />

popular. Thus, as a practical matter, the question is whether we prefer street prostitution and escort<br />

57


There is an interesting divide within the sex work industry. In the case of prostitution,<br />

some workers seem to value community, predictability, and safety and choose to work in<br />

brothels. Others, though, place a premium on autonomy, discretion, and privacy, and<br />

prefer outcall work. In fact, many outcall prostitutes are drawn to the work because of<br />

the relative autonomy compared to other options. 336 A similar dynamic is at work in<br />

dance markets.<br />

E. Summary<br />

In sum, contrary to invocations of professional sex as “just work,” the political<br />

feasibility calculus turns on several factors. Important questions include whether a<br />

regulatory regime would be best administered by federal, state, or self-regulation need to<br />

be determined, as does whether a dedicated agency is feasible or desirable. Political will<br />

also needs to considered, which entails a variety of issues, including public perception of<br />

sex work and sex professionals, the gravitational pull of marriage and the relegation of<br />

sex to the private sphere, and the management of externalities and spill-over effects.<br />

Finally, substitution effects demonstrate that not all work can be regulated to the same<br />

degree of efficacy. <strong>Sex</strong> work may be a classic instance of where there is a highly elastic<br />

trade-off between regulation and substitution. Thus, all work can be regulated, but,<br />

because of administrability concerns, political will, and substitution effects, not all work<br />

can regulated to the same degree of efficacy.<br />

CONCLUSION<br />

By casting it as labor, sex as work advocates hope to lay claim to an array of<br />

effects—including normalizing and legitimizing the practice; changing endowments<br />

through enforceability; and accessing legal regulation to ameliorate some of the worst<br />

aspects of contemporary sex markets. But is the factory floor really like the sex<br />

worksite(s)? Almost certainly not. And yet, the commodified sex as labor claim/analogy<br />

is revelatory—about both the discourse and the regulation of commodified sex.<br />

[conclude conclusion!]<br />

services to brothels. Street prostitution raises the most serious risks of violence, sexually<br />

transmitted disease, and offence to community sensibility and public life. Thus, the Inquiry<br />

recommended that prohibitions on street solicitation be retained, but within a context that allowed<br />

alternative means of negotiating commercial sex relations.<br />

Law, supra note [x], at [add pincite].<br />

336<br />

[add quotes]. See also Nussbaum, supra note [x], (emphasizing discretion and autonomy in prostitution<br />

compared to other work).<br />

58

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!