21.09.2018 Views

International Legal Evangelism: Intelligence, Reconnaissance & Missions

International Legal Evangelism: Intelligence, Reconnaissance & Missions

International Legal Evangelism: Intelligence, Reconnaissance & Missions

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

another, and that choice may be guided by some independent sense of the moral<br />

quality of the consensus.<br />

In a stylized case, we may find that 45% of nations allow a successful siege<br />

to end in the slaughter of a city’s defenders if they were offered, at a late stage in<br />

the siege, an opportunity to surrender the city with impunity, while 40% of<br />

countries may in these circumstances prohibit the slaughter of defenders who ask<br />

for quarter after the city’s walls have been breached. Both consensuses are partial.<br />

But we may regard the latter as the law of nations, even though it is numerically<br />

inferior on account of its embodying a morally superior standard. We trade off the<br />

extent of support against the moral quality of the position. At an extremity, of<br />

course, this becomes pure natural law moralizing. But in the stylized case I have<br />

mentioned, it is more like Rawlsian reflective equilibrium or Dworkinian<br />

interpretation of global practice. 145<br />

That’s Gentili in the late 16 th century. Much the same is true of Hugo<br />

Grotius, writing a generation later. Grotius too made progress in the international<br />

realm not by asking (as a moral philosopher might) what the natural law values and<br />

principles are, but by asking what people have taken them to be and what they<br />

have done in the world with the answers that they happen to have come up with.<br />

He too was interested in the way something like positive law emerged from the<br />

practice of nations, more particularly from those aspects of national practice where<br />

nations could be seen to have been asking themselves scrupulously and honorably<br />

what is right and wrong (so far as war and peace are concerned). True, his<br />

understanding of all this was leavened by his own strong first-order moral sense<br />

(his own direct natural law enquiries); but it was never dominated by that sense to<br />

the exclusion of any consideration of actual practice and custom. Grotius took<br />

practice, custom, and opinion seriously in the way that a pure natural law enquiry<br />

cannot. And for that reason he was far better positioned to understand, from a<br />

natural law point of view, how positive law might come into existence and flourish<br />

in this realm.<br />

We can reflect on all this from a jurisprudential, a moral, and a theological<br />

perspective. Jurisprudentially, I come back to something I said in Lecture One.<br />

Sometimes when humans are at their most ferocious and hard-hearted, they still<br />

manage—perhaps in spite of themselves—to pay homage in their practice to<br />

strands of normativity and restraint. It was, I said, the mission of thinkers like<br />

Grotius and Gentili to sift through the historical evidence of war-mongering to<br />

discern, recover, and make articulate as law, elements of restraint that were there<br />

anyway—half-hearted, haphazard, no doubt, impure, certainly, and sometimes<br />

insincere. Still that is how legality enters the world.<br />

<br />

145 Rawls, TJ, __ and Dworkin, Law’s Empire, __.<br />

<br />

60

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!