14.01.2013 Views

Rupturing Concepts of Disability and Inclusion

Rupturing Concepts of Disability and Inclusion

Rupturing Concepts of Disability and Inclusion

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CONCEIVING A QUILT: CREATING A METHOD<br />

nurture <strong>of</strong> such artifacts as memories, histories, stories, photographs <strong>and</strong> unconditional<br />

close loving relationships are testament to that.<br />

In many situations, therefore, inclusion is an ideal state – something imagined<br />

<strong>and</strong> sought, not yet arrived at, but continuously strived for. This research contends<br />

that not only do socio-ethical spaces <strong>of</strong> exclusion <strong>and</strong> inclusion exist, but also that<br />

‘traditional’ socio-ethical spaces espoused to be inclusive, construe to sustain<br />

structural exclusion for people with disability, particularly intellectual disability.<br />

To elaborate, a conceptual theoretical <strong>and</strong> multidisciplinary approach will expose<br />

the implicit exclusion within traditional methods, resulting in their inadequacy <strong>and</strong><br />

incompetency to address inclusion. The irony <strong>of</strong> this situation should not go<br />

unnoticed. As has already been articulated, non-inclusion or exclusion for people<br />

with intellectual disability has traditionally been explained because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

perceived inadequacy <strong>and</strong> incompetency <strong>of</strong> these persons to be rational individuals.<br />

However, I am suggesting that it is not a notion <strong>of</strong> impaired bodies that presents<br />

barriers to Ethical <strong>Inclusion</strong>: rather, it is impaired ethical theorising. Therefore, I<br />

assert that the fraudulence <strong>of</strong> aporetic ethical foundations in contemporary<br />

disability practices must be confronted for ethical transformation.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>ound Exclusion <strong>and</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> inclusion mapped under the three broad<br />

categories – Technical <strong>Inclusion</strong>, Legislative <strong>Inclusion</strong> <strong>and</strong> Ethical <strong>Inclusion</strong>, embrace<br />

different dominant themes <strong>of</strong> inquiry. For example, Pr<strong>of</strong>ound Exclusion <strong>and</strong> Technical<br />

<strong>Inclusion</strong> embrace a socio-historical positivist critique, Legislative <strong>Inclusion</strong> - a<br />

socio-political interactionist, interpretavist or phenomenological critique, <strong>and</strong> Ethical<br />

<strong>Inclusion</strong> – a socio-political-ethical-structuralist critique. Methodologically, these<br />

different themes <strong>of</strong> inquiry cannot be ignored; but rather need to be embraced <strong>and</strong><br />

exp<strong>and</strong>ed to enable an adequate analysis <strong>of</strong> the conceptualisation <strong>and</strong> ethical<br />

significance <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> inclusion to emerge. Undertaking a complex <strong>and</strong><br />

multidisciplinary approach recognises that the inclusion-exclusion dualism is<br />

experienced not only within socio-temporal, socio-relational, socio-visual or sociopolitical<br />

spaces, but also that these spaces together are components <strong>of</strong> a wider<br />

embracing, but conceivably dominant <strong>and</strong> restrictive, socio-ethical space – a space<br />

traditionally not embracing <strong>of</strong> the particularities <strong>of</strong> embodied identities. Diprose<br />

reinforces this assertion when she states that ethics is <strong>of</strong>ten thought <strong>of</strong> as “either the<br />

study <strong>of</strong> the logical status <strong>of</strong> our moral judgements or as setting down a set <strong>of</strong><br />

universal principles for regulating behaviour”, assuming that “individuals are<br />

present as self-transparent, isolated, rational minds <strong>and</strong> that embodied differences<br />

between individuals are inconsequential.” 114 Branson <strong>and</strong> Miller would contend,<br />

then, that this approach to ethics constitutes “epistemic imperialism” for its embeddedness<br />

in Western society <strong>and</strong> its propensity to organise ‘reality’ in a particular<br />

way. This, they identify, necessitates an “unitary, logocentric, phallogocentric<br />

orientation,” appropriating <strong>and</strong> devaluing ‘others’ by processes <strong>of</strong> “packaging,<br />

labeling, <strong>and</strong> controlling.” 115 This indeed emerges as impaired ethical theorising.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong>, though, Diprose contests that even if it is granted that ethics<br />

is about moral principles <strong>and</strong> moral judgment, ethics is also about location, position<br />

<strong>and</strong> place. This research will encompass this latter statement within its exploration<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ethical significance <strong>of</strong> inclusion. It is imperative that the hegemonic genesis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the traditional approaches to applied ethics <strong>and</strong> the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> their orthodoxy<br />

27

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!