10.04.2013 Views

Did St. Thomas Aquinas Justify the Transition from 'Is' to 'Ought'

Did St. Thomas Aquinas Justify the Transition from 'Is' to 'Ought'

Did St. Thomas Aquinas Justify the Transition from 'Is' to 'Ought'

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

21<br />

0. A Short His<strong>to</strong>ry of <strong>the</strong> Problem<br />

In every system of morality, which I have hi<strong>the</strong>r<strong>to</strong> met with, I have always remark’d,<br />

that <strong>the</strong> author proceeds for some time in <strong>the</strong> ordinary way of reasoning, and<br />

establishes <strong>the</strong> being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs;<br />

when of a sudden I am surpriz’d <strong>to</strong> find, that instead of <strong>the</strong> usual copulations of<br />

propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an<br />

ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is, however, of <strong>the</strong> last<br />

consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or<br />

affirmation, it is necessary that it should be observ’d and explain’d; and at <strong>the</strong> same<br />

time that a reason should be given, for what seems al<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r inconceivable, how this<br />

new relation can be a deduction <strong>from</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, which are entirely different <strong>from</strong> it. But<br />

as authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume <strong>to</strong> recommend it <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention wou’d subvert all <strong>the</strong> vulgar<br />

systems of morality, and let us see, that <strong>the</strong> distinction of vice and virtue is not<br />

founded merely on <strong>the</strong> relations of objects, nor is perceiv’d by reason (T, 302).<br />

This argument caused a furore in philosophy and is known <strong>to</strong> this day as “Hume’s<br />

Law.” It is still regarded as controversial and is usually unders<strong>to</strong>od as follows: it is<br />

impossible <strong>to</strong> infer an “ought” directly <strong>from</strong> an “is.” This is <strong>to</strong> say, that between “ought”<br />

and “is” <strong>the</strong>re is so considerable a dicho<strong>to</strong>my that it is impossible <strong>to</strong> deduce imperative<br />

phrases <strong>from</strong> descriptive ones. There is thus an inferential gap between moral and<br />

nonmoral claims (<strong>the</strong> “Is/Ought Gap”) or between fact and value. 24 No moral<br />

conclusion can be derived <strong>from</strong> exclusively nonmoral premises. Hence, a moral<br />

conclusion can be derived only <strong>from</strong> premises containing at least one moral statement.<br />

Although Hume himself did not do so, we may specify <strong>the</strong> following on <strong>the</strong> basis of his<br />

writings: <strong>the</strong> inferential gap is accompanied by a logically independent belief about <strong>the</strong><br />

inherently motivational character of moral considerations. This latter belief is called an<br />

“internalist assumption.” The “internalist assumption” is based on a commonsense view<br />

that “normal” people will not be indifferent <strong>to</strong> moral considerations. Within Hume’s<br />

system, this assumption is developed in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> suggestion that we should derive moral<br />

rules <strong>from</strong> <strong>the</strong> “moral sense.” Moral sense for Hume is <strong>the</strong> natural capacity <strong>to</strong> feel a<br />

distinctive kind of approbation and disapprobation when considering features of<br />

character <strong>from</strong> “<strong>the</strong> general point of view” (that is, independently of one’s own self-<br />

interest). This feeling is activated primarily by natural sympathy with those who are<br />

affected by <strong>the</strong> character traits in question. He argues, <strong>the</strong>refore, that values are <strong>the</strong><br />

projections of natural human desires or sentiments. Moral values are one kind of value<br />

and <strong>the</strong>ir main characteristic is that <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> projections of desires that aim at <strong>the</strong><br />

common good of society. Through <strong>the</strong> observation and analysis of <strong>the</strong>se desires or<br />

24 For an example of <strong>the</strong> diverse interpretations of this <strong>the</strong>sis see W. D. Hudson (ed.), The Is/Ought<br />

Thesis, (New York: Macmillan, 1969).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!