03.05.2013 Views

Lexical Semantics of Adjectives - CiteSeerX

Lexical Semantics of Adjectives - CiteSeerX

Lexical Semantics of Adjectives - CiteSeerX

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

13<br />

fact that the adjectives inherit much <strong>of</strong> the noun meaning does not come as a shocking surprise, and<br />

the fact that these features <strong>of</strong> the adjectives are shared by the related nouns seems less significant.<br />

(12) +def: Markovian, Mexican -def: national, feline<br />

+concrete: aquatic, lunar -concrete: dramatic, linguistical<br />

+animate: senatorial, Chomskian -animate: rural, electric<br />

+human: Markovian, presidential -human: Bostonian, bovine<br />

+masc: paternal, masculine +fem: maternal, feminine<br />

+common: financial, monthly -common: Persian, Chomskian<br />

Similarly, the (9v) observation on the adjectives inheriting, in a sense, the thematic roles (cases, as<br />

per Levi 1978: 27) from the originating noun is both true and trivial (13):<br />

(13) agentive: presidential refusal, editorial comment<br />

objective: constitutional amendment, oceanic study<br />

locative: marginal note, marine life<br />

dative [genitive?]/possessive: feminine intuition, occupational hazard<br />

instrumental: manual labor, solar generator<br />

The primary reason (9iii-v) are more or less superfluous is that these nominal properties are not<br />

actually useful for describing adjectives. They affect the syntactic behavior <strong>of</strong> nouns in important<br />

ways. With adjectives, they may at most marginally influence the rare use <strong>of</strong> oblique constructions,<br />

such as prepositional phrases, as adjective modifiers. Miller and Fellbaum (1991: 209) are right<br />

when, crediting Levi (1978) for the criteria for distinguishing the nonpredicating adjectives, they<br />

disregard these three criteria.<br />

(9vi) is a statement about the nonnominalization <strong>of</strong> nonpredicating adjectives. It provides an important<br />

diagnostic test for predicativeness/nonpredicativeness: only the former adjectives can be<br />

nominalized, as in (14i) vs. (15i) or (14ii) vs. (15ii) (cf. Levi 1978: 29, Miller and Fellbaum 1991:<br />

209, Bartning 1976: 112ff, Dell 1970: 189ff, and, <strong>of</strong> course, Quirk et al. 1985: 436 again).<br />

(14) (i) the rudeness <strong>of</strong> the engineer<br />

(ii) the politeness <strong>of</strong> the lawyer<br />

(15) (i) *the mechanicalness <strong>of</strong> the engineer<br />

(ii) *the corporateness <strong>of</strong> the lawyer<br />

The nonpredicating/predicating distinction has been dealt with by various schools <strong>of</strong> linguistic<br />

thought, and it was taken to the extreme by the Montegovian tradition, where the nonpredicating<br />

and predicating adjectives were assigned to two different syntactic categories (Montague 1974:<br />

211ff): attributive adjectives make common nouns out <strong>of</strong> common nouns (CN/CN); predicative adjectives<br />

are one-place predicates (t//e). Siegel (1976a,b, 1979), the main Montegovian voice on adjectives,<br />

discusses the ambiguity <strong>of</strong> beautiful in (16) as that between the absolute meaning (17i)<br />

and relative meaning (17ii):<br />

(16) Olga is a beautiful dancer<br />

(17) (i) Olga is beautiful and Olga is a dancer<br />

(ii) Olga is beautiful as a dancer (dances beautifully)<br />

The absolute meaning is also known as ‘intersective’ and the relative meaning as ‘nonintersective’

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!