15.08.2013 Views

Ω-Theory: Mathematics with Infinite and Infinitesimal Numbers - SELP

Ω-Theory: Mathematics with Infinite and Infinitesimal Numbers - SELP

Ω-Theory: Mathematics with Infinite and Infinitesimal Numbers - SELP

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CHAPTER 1. Ω-CALCULUS<br />

The two operations F ↦→ mF <strong>and</strong> m ↦→ Fm are one the inverse of the other, <strong>and</strong><br />

in this corrispondence the principal (resp. non principal) ultrafilters corresponds to<br />

the principal (resp. non principal) maximal ideals.<br />

We are interested in ultrafilters that are in correspondence <strong>with</strong> maximal ideals<br />

m ⊃ i0. We explicitely observe that those ultrafilters have an additional, interesting<br />

property: they are fine.<br />

Definition 1.10.16. A filter F on Pfin(A) is fine if, for all a ∈ A, {X ∈ Pfin(A) :<br />

{a} ⊆ X} ∈ F.<br />

This property has particular importance, since the proof of part 2 of Theorem<br />

1.9.9 depends on the identification of eventually equal functions, <strong>and</strong> this identification<br />

is possible because the nonprincipal maximal ideals extend i0. This hypothesis<br />

is essential in order to have a model in which Axiom 2 of Ω-Calculus holds.<br />

1.11 A model for Ω-Calculus<br />

Thanks to the results of the previous section, we can focus in constructing a nonprincipal<br />

fine ultrafilter on Pfin(Ω) in a way that Numerosity Axiom 1 holds. Then,<br />

we’ll use the corrispondence of Proposition 1.10.15 to obtain a nonprincipal maximal<br />

ideal that will give rise to a model of Ω-Calculus in which Numerosity Axiom 1<br />

holds.<br />

We start by constructing a particular family of sets ΛR ⊂ Pfin(R), which will be<br />

essential to define the desired ultrafilter. In order to define ΛR, we will start <strong>with</strong> a<br />

subfamily ΛQ, <strong>and</strong> then we’ll define ΛR in a way that ΛQ = ΛR ∩ P(Q).<br />

We begin by posing <br />

p<br />

<br />

λn = : p ∈ Z, |p| ≤ n2<br />

n<br />

or, more explicitely,<br />

<br />

λn = −n, − n2 − 1 1 1<br />

, . . . , − , 0,<br />

n n n , . . . , n2 <br />

− 1<br />

, n<br />

n<br />

Now, we define the family ΛQ in the following way:<br />

ΛQ = {λn : n = m!, m ∈ N}<br />

We remark that the restriction n = m! ensures that, for every λn ′, λn ′′ ∈ ΛQ, n ′ ≤ n ′′<br />

implies λn ′ ⊆ λn ′′, <strong>and</strong> so ⊆ is a total order on ΛQ.<br />

Before we define ΛR, we need to construct another family of sets: we call<br />

Θ = Pfin([0, 1] \ Q)<br />

In other words, Θ is the family of finite sets of irrational numbers between 0 <strong>and</strong> 1.<br />

Now, for all λn ∈ ΛQ <strong>and</strong> θ ∈ Θ, we set<br />

<br />

p + a<br />

λn,θ = λn ∪ :<br />

n<br />

p<br />

n ∈ λn<br />

<br />

\ {n}, a ∈ θ<br />

36

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!