22.08.2013 Views

Legal Committee - World Model United Nations

Legal Committee - World Model United Nations

Legal Committee - World Model United Nations

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

for debate, which leaves them open to broad interpretations.<br />

Examining each brings to light some relevant problems.<br />

Possessing just cause is the first and perhaps the most<br />

important condition of jus ad bellum, yet what acts constitute<br />

a “just cause” is unclear. Just cause may result from any act<br />

of aggression, social, economic, or political, which includes<br />

violation of territory, a blow against national honor, or a<br />

trade embargo. Just war theorists must therefore provide a<br />

structure to account for what is meant by just cause. One<br />

accepted belief is that an initiation of physical violence is<br />

wrong and may be justly resisted, which would classify selfdefense<br />

against physical aggression as the sufficient reason<br />

for just cause. 9 Yet, even this principle can be broadened<br />

as self-defense may extend to be construed as preventing<br />

anticipated acts of aggression, as well as assisting others<br />

against an oppressive government or from another external<br />

threat, otherwise known as interventionism. Debate and<br />

critique exists about whether preemptive strikes are based<br />

on conjecture rather than a real threat, and some argue that<br />

all they may do is further destabilize peace and cause more<br />

hostility.<br />

The next principle of just war is that it should always be a<br />

last resort. This means that all other forms of solution must<br />

have been attempted prior to the declaration of war and<br />

have been deemed ineffective and useless. As war normally<br />

causes significant damage for most economies, theorists have<br />

“Possessing just<br />

cause...should always<br />

be a last resport...<br />

proper authority...<br />

possession of right...<br />

reasonable success...<br />

the desired end should<br />

be proportional to the<br />

means used.”<br />

advised that war should not be lightly accepted. 10 However,<br />

for those whose military power is apparently great, war may<br />

present the easiest option for resolving a problem.<br />

The notion of proper authority may not seem to be an issue<br />

for those who believe it to obviously lie in the sovereign<br />

power of the state. However, the concept of sovereignty<br />

raises several issues for consideration: if a government is<br />

not just, the more its claim to justifiable political sovereignty<br />

diminishes. Therefore, we need to consider what is proper<br />

authority and what is meant by sovereignty and what is the<br />

proper relationship between a people and its government.<br />

Can tyrants truly claim to be sovereign powers? If they<br />

cannot, this may throw into question the right of a tyrant<br />

to declare war, a cost absorbed by the people more than the<br />

regime.<br />

Another principle of just war theory is the possession of right,<br />

meaning that a nation waging a just war should be doing so<br />

for the cause of justice and not for reasons of self-interest<br />

or aggrandizement. 11 The “right intention” contains several<br />

problems. If a nation’s only way to secure a general peace<br />

is to annex a belligerent neighbor’s territory, then political<br />

aggrandizement becomes inevitably tied to the “right<br />

intention” of maintaining peace for the majority. In realistic<br />

perspective, a nation will only wage war if the proper interest<br />

coincides with its personal economic or other interests.<br />

The next principle is that of reasonable success. This is another<br />

necessary condition for waging just war but is insufficient<br />

by itself. Given just cause and right intention, the just war<br />

theory asserts that there must be a reasonable probability<br />

of success. 12 The principle of reasonable success rides on<br />

predicting and attempting to calculate the costs and benefits<br />

of a campaign. However, this seemingly concrete concept<br />

of weighing benefits poses moral and practical questions<br />

concerning whether one should go to the aid of a people or<br />

declare war if there is no conceivable chance of success or<br />

whether it is right to comply with aggression because the<br />

costs of not complying are too prohibitive. Historically, many<br />

nations have overcome the probability of defeat: Winston<br />

Churchill offered the British nation some of the finest of war’s<br />

rhetoric when it was threatened with defeat and invasion by<br />

Nazi Germany in 1940. 13 However, the reasonable success<br />

principle reinforces the idea that human life and economic<br />

resources should not be wasted in what would clearly be an<br />

uneven match. For a nation threatened by invasion, other<br />

forms of retaliation or defense may be available, such as civil<br />

disobedience or even forming alliances with other small<br />

nations to equalize the odds.<br />

Harvard <strong>World</strong>MUN 2012 <strong>Legal</strong> 55

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!