29.08.2013 Views

FUNCTIONALISM AND ITS CRITICS - Intercollegiate Studies Institute

FUNCTIONALISM AND ITS CRITICS - Intercollegiate Studies Institute

FUNCTIONALISM AND ITS CRITICS - Intercollegiate Studies Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> :<br />

An Analysis of the Writings of Gabriel Almond<br />

alcott Parsons began his first major sociological study with a<br />

T rhetorical question. " Who, " he asked, "now reads Spencer? "<br />

His implicit answer was, hardly anyone, and he agreed with Crane<br />

Brinton that Spencer was " Dead by suicide or at the hands of<br />

person or persons unknown. " Today many sociologists are begin- ning to ask the same question about Parsons himself. Parsons never<br />

achieved Spencer's eminence in the intellectual community and that<br />

community 's rejection of his work has not been as thoroughgoing.<br />

However, it is true that, after a period in the 1950 's during which<br />

the Parsonian brand of functional analysis seemed to be carrying<br />

all before it, his decline has been precipitous.<br />

There are some signs that a similar development may be about<br />

to take place in political science, for here, too, primarily in comparative<br />

politics, the late 1950 ' s and the early 1960 ' s was the era<br />

of a type of systems analysis loosely derived from Parsons. The<br />

series of volumes sponsored by the Committee on Comparative Politics<br />

of the Social Science Research Council and the Little Brown<br />

comparative politics series testify to the widespread acceptance of<br />

at least elements of this conceptual framework by political scientists.<br />

Of late, however, criticism has been mounting, induced, in part, by<br />

methodological considerations and in part by the changing political<br />

climate in the United States and the world.<br />

To comparativists, at least, functional analysis and the name<br />

of Gabriel Almond are almost synonomous. While others have<br />

labored mightily and fruitfully in the same vineyard, the publication<br />

of Almond and Coleman 's, The Politics of the Developing Areas in<br />

1960 was something of a landmark, and Almond and Powell's Comparative<br />

Politics (1966) has served, more recently, as the paradigm<br />

of a functional approach.'<br />

Almond actually yields pride of place for the introduction of<br />

systems analysis into political science to David Easton. For it was,<br />

as he notes, the publication of Easton' s, The Political System which<br />

1 Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (New York, 1937), p. 3.<br />

2 Gabriel Almond and James S. Coleman (eds.), The Politics of the Developing<br />

Areas (Princeton, 1960), and Gabriel Almond and G. Bingham Powell,<br />

Comparative Politics: A Developmental Approach ( Boston, 1966). Hereafter<br />

referred to respectively as Developing Areas and Comparative Politics.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 237<br />

led him to experience "one of those moments of intellectual liberation;<br />

when a concept comes along that gives one ' s thoughts an<br />

ordered structure."' Almond's earlier work had lacked a systematic<br />

theoretical focus, and had been largely descriptive or concerned with<br />

the development of what Merton would call theories of the middle<br />

range.'<br />

After his conversion to a functional approach, however, Almond<br />

moved in a somewhat different direction from that of Easton or<br />

Parsons. While the latter tended to concentrate on conceptual<br />

rigor, Almond remained far more concerned with developing constructs<br />

which were tied as closely as possible to concrete problems.<br />

Specification of the meaning of theoretical terms or examining all of<br />

the implications of theoretical constructs seemed less important to<br />

him than developing some ordering of the material of politics, and<br />

he continued to borrow concepts freely from other intellectual traditions<br />

than functionalism. It is for this reason, perhaps, that his influence<br />

among students of comparative politics has been far greater<br />

than that of Easton. Most of those scholars studying the politics of<br />

developing areas have felt that it was far easier to apply Almond<br />

than to work with Parsons ' or Easton ' s more elaborate frameworks.<br />

Almond has denied that even his work of the period (roughly<br />

1956-1969) can easily be subsumed under the rubric of functionalism,<br />

and this is certainly true.' Even at the height of his " functional<br />

period, " if we may so label it, he remained fairly ecclectic.<br />

More recently this ecclecticism has become even more pronounced.<br />

Functionalism is a mansion with many rooms, and has meant<br />

somewhat different things to different theorists. Certainly Almond ' s<br />

functionalism is, as we shall see, of a far more restricted kind than<br />

that of Radcliffe-Brown or Parson.' Thus many of the criticisms<br />

which have been directed against them are not applicable to him.<br />

' Gabriel Almond,<br />

"<br />

Political Development: Analytic and Normative Perspectives,<br />

" Comparative Political <strong>Studies</strong>, I (January, 1969), p. 449.<br />

4<br />

These had included: The American People and Foreign Policy ( New<br />

York, 1950), and The Appeals of Communism ( Princeton, 1954). The term<br />

middle range theory is from Robert K. Merton,<br />

Structure ( New York, 1949), pp. 3-16.<br />

5<br />

In a personal communication.<br />

Social Theory and Social<br />

°For a discussion of the variety of approaches subsumed under the rubric<br />

of functionalism, and the variety of interpretations of its essential nature, see<br />

Francesca M. Cancian, "Varieties of Functional Analysis, " International En-


238 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

On the other hand, it is the elaboration of a theoretical framework<br />

broadly functional in orientation which has distinguished Almond ' s<br />

work in the past sixteen years, and the issues raised by the approach<br />

shall serve as the focus for organizing this essay review. Even where<br />

Almond is elaborating a concept like political culture or developing<br />

a theory of political evolution, or talking about the capabilities of<br />

political systems, concepts and theories which are compatible with<br />

a number of approaches, the fact that he thinks of a political system<br />

in functional terms gives his approach a particular cast. The same,<br />

of course, is true of Talcott Parsons. The latter ' s emphasis on cultural<br />

variables is derived from a non-functionalist (Weber) and his<br />

developmental theory (from which Almond ' s seems to be derived)<br />

probably has more in common with that of Spencer than he would<br />

care to admit. Yet the fact that he is a functionalist leads. him to, rely<br />

implicitly on biological analogies of a certain kind which are not<br />

intrinsic to an evolutionary theory of social and political development.<br />

I shall attempt to summarize Almond ' s ideas as they have developed,<br />

bringing out what seem to me some of the underlying, but<br />

often unstated assumptions. At relevant points I shall point out<br />

ambiguities, contradictions and lacunae. It must be said at the outset<br />

that Almond ' s writing, because of his ecclecticism, and lack of concern<br />

with theoretical completeness, abounds in these. I shall, however,<br />

ignore minor details and stick to major issues. After all, the<br />

key question is whether a functional approach, presented in as reasonable<br />

a form as possible, is likely to be of more value in the study<br />

of politics than alternate conceptual frameworks. If this seems likely<br />

to be the case, theoretical elegance is not essential at this stage, although<br />

the possibility of improvement is.' Conceptual frameworks<br />

are not proven or disproven, they are only more or less useful. A<br />

cyclopedia of the Social Sciences (New York, 1968) 6, pp. 29-43, and N. J.<br />

Demerath III and Richard A. Peterson (eds.), System Change and Conflict<br />

(New York, 1967). A short history of functionalism will be found in Don<br />

Martindale, The Nature and Types of Sociological Theory ( Boston, 1960),<br />

pp. 441-500. A variety of functional approaches in political science are .<br />

described in articles by Robert T. Holt and William Flanigan and Edwin<br />

Fogelman in Don Martindale (ed.), Functionalism in the Social Sciences<br />

( Philadelphia, 1965), pp. 84-110 and pp. 111-126.<br />

7 Abraham Kaplan, The Conduct of Inquiry (San Francisco, 1964), pp.<br />

77-78, points out that complete conceptual clarity is not the sine qua non of<br />

scientific advance, and that such clarity is attained only after the maturation<br />

of new approaches to the study of nature, man and society.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

framework which lacks precision but which seems to open possibilities<br />

for fruitful work is much preferred to one which is quite rigorous<br />

but whose focus is so narrow that it can only deal with relatively unimportant<br />

matters.<br />

I shall reserve an overall evaluation of the strengths and weaknesses<br />

of Almond ' s approach for the concluding section of the essay.<br />

At that time I will consider some of the major criticisms which have<br />

been directed against it and against functionalism in general.<br />

I. SYSTEM, STRUCTURE <strong>AND</strong> FUNCTION<br />

Almond ' s first major attempt to develop a functional framework<br />

for the study of politics is to be found in his introduction to The<br />

Politics of the Developing Areas, although some of his ideas had<br />

already appeared in article form. Pointing out that such traditional<br />

concepts as the " state " were of little utility in comparing the politics<br />

of western and non-western societies, he suggested substituting such<br />

concepts as the " political system, " which he defined as :<br />

that system of interactions to be found in all independent societies<br />

which performs the functions of integration and adaptation (both<br />

internally and viz-a-viz other societies) by means of the employment<br />

or threat of employment, of more or less legitimate force s<br />

The " political system " is essentially an analytic system and is<br />

not to be identified with any empirical "structure " or " structures, "<br />

although Almond is not entirely clear on this. He does not, at this<br />

point, define what he means by a " structure, " nor does he define a<br />

system. However, he does list those features which characterize a<br />

political system. There are : (I) comprehensiveness, (2) interdependence,<br />

and (3) the existence of boundaries.'<br />

By comprehensiveness, Almond means that the political system<br />

includes all those inputs and outputs which affect in some way the<br />

use or threat of use of legitimate coercion, whether these derive<br />

'Developing Areas, p. 7.<br />

e lbid., pp. 7-9. In Comparative Politics, Almond defines a structure as:<br />

" particular sets of roles which are related to each other." He prefers it to the<br />

term institution, with which he regards it as practically synonomous, because<br />

he wishes to emphasize " the actual behavior of individuals. " Comparative<br />

Politics, p. 21.<br />

239


240 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

from formal governmental institutions or caste groups or whether<br />

they involve petitions, demonstrations or judicial decisions. By interdependence<br />

Almond means that significant changes in any part of<br />

the system will produce. chances in other parts :<br />

" a change in one<br />

subset of interactions produces change in all other subsets. . . . io<br />

By the existence of a boundary Almond means that there are points<br />

where other systems begin and the political system ends. Complaints<br />

about policy, for example, are not part of the political system, until<br />

they become demands upon public authorities for some form of<br />

action or are interpreted as such.<br />

According to Almond, the superiority of functionalism to other<br />

approaches to politics lies in the fact that it enables us to develop a<br />

set of categories for the comparison not only of contemporary industrial<br />

societies, but also of industrial societies with "developing"<br />

societies and of contemporary societies with historical social orders.<br />

Traditionally students of comparative politics have limited their<br />

work to the comparison of such institutions as interest groups, political<br />

parties, legislatures, courts, etc. These efforts can be reasonably<br />

successful, Almond argues, if one is concerned only with the politics<br />

of contemporary European societies which share something of a<br />

common political and social heritage. However, he notes, when one<br />

turns to comparisons between, say, England and Indonesia, traditional<br />

analytic categories break down. One can point out, of course,<br />

that England or the United States are characterized by many formally<br />

organized large membership associations, and that in Indonesia<br />

such associations are poorly organized and inadequately financed,<br />

and have highly fluctuating memberships. However, such structural<br />

comparisons deal only with the comparative anatomy of the three<br />

polities, and within a European frame of reference at that. They tell<br />

us little of the "physiology" of the systems in question, let alone<br />

their dynamics.<br />

On the other hand, Almond contends, if we assume that certain<br />

functions must be performed in all societies if they are to , survive,<br />

and we compare how these functions are actually performed in each<br />

society, we can enrich our understanding of all of them by facilitating<br />

meaningful comparative analysis. Further, he suggests, we escape<br />

both the ethnocentrism that has blinded us to the richness of<br />

lo Developing Areas, p. 8.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

political life in societies whose formal structure differs from ours,<br />

and the kind of moralizing which assumes that societies lacking certain<br />

Western institutions are somehow at a lower stage of development.<br />

In the end we will develop a better perspective on our own<br />

and other advanced societies, because we will come to realize that,<br />

while the same functions must be performed in all societies, they<br />

can be performed ,by a variety of different structures which are<br />

related to each other in quite different ways than is the case of our<br />

own or other European systems. Finally, in so far as this approach<br />

orders our empirical material more systematically, and leads to the<br />

discovery of new data, it should help us develop theories and lawlike<br />

statements about the political process. '1<br />

Any conceptual scheme, even if only classificatory, has embedded<br />

within it some general model the relationships which its<br />

creator hopes to clarify. The model Almond chose was derived from<br />

the work of David Easton." Easton conceived of the political system<br />

essentially as a mechanism for converting demands from the society<br />

(inputs) into policies which involved the "authoritative allocation<br />

of values " (outputs) and further supports for the system through a<br />

feedback loop. Although the discerning reader can probably detect<br />

at least a tension between this model and some of Almond 's definitions,<br />

his efforts in The Politics of the Developing Areas were largely<br />

directed to explicating in some detail what kinds of activities this<br />

conversion process entailed. Before demands could become politically<br />

relevant they had to be articulated in some way, and since, theoretically,<br />

the number of demands was infinite, they had to be aggregated<br />

into a relatively smaller number of policy alternatives before processing<br />

could take place. If values were to be allocated in an authoritative<br />

manner, the system had to include mechanisms for rule making,<br />

rule application, and rule adjudication. Finally, mechanisms had<br />

to be created for recruiting individuals into political roles, and for<br />

communicating both demands and policy decisions. "<br />

The study of how these conversion mechanisms perform their<br />

1l<br />

lbid., pp. 9-17. In this summary I have made explicit a few points which<br />

are only implicit in Almond ' s discussion.<br />

12<br />

" "<br />

An Approach to the Analysis of Political Systems,<br />

David Easton,<br />

World Politics IX ( April, 1957), pp. 383 if. Easton developed his ideas more<br />

fully in: A Framework for Political Analysis (New York, 1965) and A Systems<br />

Analysis of Political Life ( New York, 1965).<br />

13<br />

Developing Areas, pp. 15-19.<br />

241


242 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

functions in various political systems constitutes the meat of comparative<br />

politics for Almond, and the essay attempts to demonstrate<br />

the utility of an approach with this focus in organizing political<br />

data, as well as its fruitfulness in the development of law-like<br />

statements of a " probabilistic " kind. For example, Almond argues<br />

that if various interest groups in a society make " raw " demands<br />

upon governmental institutions, rather than allowing these demands<br />

to be aggregated by political parties, such demands will be more<br />

difficult to process and the result may well be political instability. 14<br />

Almond is convinced that the most important differences between<br />

political systems pertain to whether they are " traditional " or<br />

" modern. " Traditional societies with traditional political systems<br />

are those characterized by particularistic, ascriptive and functionally<br />

diffuse norms and structures, while modern societies tend to be<br />

characterized by universalistic, achievement, and functionally specific<br />

norms and structures. The classification is one derived from contemporary<br />

sociological analysis and Almond is careful to point out<br />

that the concepts refer to " ideal types. " No society is completely<br />

modern or completely traditional. All societies contain a mixture of<br />

modern and traditional elements. Modern societies are more highly<br />

differentiated than traditional ones, such that specialized structures<br />

have been created for the performance of particular functions.<br />

Nevertheless, even in advanced societies all political structures are<br />

multifunctional, and the analysis of the relation between function<br />

and structure is always a highly complex matter. 76<br />

Nevertheless, it is already clear that Almond ' s standard for<br />

analyzing societies is derived from advanced industrial European<br />

communities such as England and the United States. Further, the<br />

metaphor is already an organic one. The structures to be<br />

found in " advanced " societies are implicit in traditional societies,<br />

which modernize, in part, by a process of differentiation. Latent<br />

in the conception is an evolutionary theory of social change<br />

which becomes explicit in his later work; and at least one problem<br />

is also discernible here: Almond tells us that his list of functions<br />

is derived from the classic separation of powers doctrines of European<br />

and American political theorists. " Logically this fact is of<br />

' Ibid., p. 35.<br />

"Ibid., pp. 24-25.<br />

"Comparative Politics, pp. 10-12.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

little relevance to its adequacy as a means of classifying and studying<br />

political systems. However, as we shall later see, the source of<br />

its derivation is not without importance, for Almond is not completely<br />

free of that ethnocentric bias from which he had hoped to<br />

escape.<br />

The Politics of the Developing Areas was a preliminary attempt<br />

to apply a structural-functional framework to the analysis of political<br />

systems. In it Almond was not particularly concerned with the<br />

nature or direction of social change, at least explicitly, but merely<br />

with fashioning a tool which would permit effective comparisons In<br />

Comparative Politics he added a number of dimensions to his<br />

analysis, including a theory of evolution and a set of concepts designed<br />

to enable political scientists to evaluate political systems.<br />

Both of these dimensions will be described later. For the moment,<br />

however, we are concerned with his efforts to increase the precision<br />

and depth of his conceptual framework.<br />

Almond begins Comparative Politics with a discussion of some<br />

of the criticisms which have been leveled against a functional approach-for<br />

example, that it implies an equilibrium or harmony of<br />

parts and that it has a conservative bias. He rightly points out that<br />

his use as a functional approach does not assume that system equilibrium<br />

is natural and certainly does not assume harmony among<br />

system parts. He admits that his previous writing had lacked an approach<br />

to political change, but promises to rectify this in the present<br />

volume. 14<br />

His definition of the political system has changed somewhat.<br />

The political system now consists of ". . . all those interactions<br />

which affect the use or threat of legitimate physical coercion. " It is<br />

the potential use of legitimate force, indeed, which gives the political<br />

system its coherence. 18 He still considers himself a functionalist, however,<br />

and promises to :<br />

. . . consider the activities or functions of political systems from<br />

three points of view. The first of these we have already referred tothe<br />

conversion functions of interest articulation, interest aggregation<br />

political communication, rule making, rule application, and rule<br />

adjudication. The second consideration is the operation of the politi-<br />

"Ibid., pp. 12-13.<br />

18 1bid., pp. 17-18.<br />

243


244 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE .REVIEWER<br />

cal system as an " individual " in its environment. We refer to this<br />

aspect of the functioning of a political system as its capabilities.<br />

Finally, we will need to consider the way in which political systems<br />

maintain themselves or adapt themselves to pressures for change<br />

over the long run. We speak here of system maintenance and adaptation<br />

functions-political recruitment and political socialization. 19<br />

After invoking the names of Malinowski, Radcliffe-Brown, Parsons,<br />

Merton and Levy, he actually begins his discussion of functions with<br />

the analysis of system capabilities.<br />

Now all of this is very confusing, and it might be wise to pause<br />

and take stock at this point. Functionalism has meant many things<br />

to many people. Au Fond, however, and especially in the authors<br />

whom Almond cites, it is a conceptual scheme which involves the<br />

analysis of social institutions in terms of the functions they perform<br />

in some larger system, and/or the analysis of the functions which<br />

must be performed in any system if it is to persist. 20 An activity is<br />

not synonomous with a function, and while Almond ' s analysis of<br />

system capabilities derives from a functional analysis, a description<br />

of the capabilities of a system or an institution has nothing to do<br />

with functionalism as a system of thought. Given Robert Merton ' s<br />

explicit treatment of this kind of error many years ago, it is surprising<br />

that a scholar as sophisticated as Almond should repeat it at<br />

this late date. 21<br />

Almond faces other problems. One can define the political<br />

system in functional terms or coercion terms, but, as Meehan points<br />

out, one cannot easily do both, at least without developing the argument<br />

in much greater detail. The monopoly of legitimate force is a<br />

system attribute not a system function, and the admitted effort to<br />

combine Weber and Parsons in one definition leads only to confusion.<br />

22<br />

"Ibid., p. 14.<br />

20<br />

See the references in footnote 6.<br />

21 " "<br />

Robert Merton, Manifest and Latent Functions, in Social Theory and<br />

Social Structure, op. cit., pp. 21-82.<br />

22<br />

Eugene J. Meehan, Contemporary Political Thought: A Critical Study<br />

( Homewood, Illinois, 1967), pp. 175-81. Almond is obviously trying to give<br />

both Parsons and Weber their due. For a critical appraisal of functionalism<br />

from a Weberian perspective see Randall Collins, " A Comparative Approach<br />

to Political Sociology, " in Reinhard Bendix (ed.), State and Society ( Boston,<br />

1968), pp. 42-69.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 245<br />

Our confusion is compounded by the fact that Almond has<br />

dropped integration and adaptation as overall functions of the political<br />

system. In one sense the loss is not very great, for he never did<br />

define the terms. They seem to have been taken over from the work<br />

of Parsons, although Parsons tended to see adaptation as a function<br />

of the economic system, and thought that integration was the function<br />

of the legal system, among others. 23<br />

The inconsistencies in Almond ' s discussion of the political system<br />

are fairly distressing. However they are not really terribly important<br />

in terms of his analysis, for it is quite clear as we examine Comparative<br />

Politics, that Almond ' s functionalism is still derived from an<br />

Eastonian model. The political system is conceived of as a mechanism<br />

for processing demands from the larger society. Almond ' s strategy<br />

for comparing political systems, then, is still in terms of the variables<br />

first developed in The Politics of Developing Areas, with some additions.<br />

As already noted, interest articulation, interest aggregation,<br />

rule making, rule application and communication are considered<br />

" conversion functions. " Political recruitment, as classified along<br />

with political socialization as fulfilling intra political " system maintenance<br />

" and " adaptation " functions, and the content of demands<br />

and supports which flow into the political system, are specified, as<br />

are system outputs. Demands include those for the allocation of<br />

goods and services; for the regulation of behavior, for participation<br />

and communication. Supports include material supports, obedience<br />

to laws and regulations, participatory supports such as voting, and<br />

attention paid to communications. Finally, outputs include extractions,<br />

regulations, allocations or distribution of goods and services,<br />

and symbolic outputs. Clearly, Almond ' s scheme for evaluating<br />

system capabilities derives from this list. 24<br />

There are a number of issues we might raise. It is not easy to<br />

see, for example, why communication is called a conversion function.<br />

Communication would seem, on the face of it, to play a<br />

quite different role in any political system than, say, interest aggregation.<br />

Further, Almond still fails to indicate clearly what he<br />

means by adaptation and system maintenance and how and why<br />

political recruitment and political socialization fulfill these functions<br />

23<br />

Talcott Parsons, Politics and Social Structure (New York, 1969), pp.<br />

398-99.<br />

24 Comparative Politics, pp. 25-27 and seq.


246 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

for the political system. These, however, are relatively minor difficulties<br />

which can probably be worked through and I shall not pursue<br />

them.<br />

Even more explicitly" than in The Politics of the Developing<br />

Areas, Almond seems convinced, in his later work, that the major<br />

differences between political systems have to do with where they<br />

fall on a continuum from primitive to modern. The structural factors<br />

which seem to be of key importance for determining the nature<br />

of demands, conversion processes and outputs are: (1) the degree to<br />

which political roles, structures and subsystems are specialized or<br />

differentiated, and (2) the relative autonomy or subordination of<br />

these roles with respect to each other. 25 Modern systems are those<br />

with a relatively high level of institutional and subsystem differentiation,<br />

as well as relative subsystem autonomy, and despite Almond ' s<br />

efforts to avoid ethnocentrism, it is quite clear that his model of<br />

advanced states is drawn from the British and American political<br />

systems.<br />

Almond ' s analysis of political culture, defined as " the pattern<br />

of individual attitudes and orientations toward politics among the<br />

members of a political system, " demonstrates this derivation quite<br />

clearly. 26 The basic distinction developed is that 'between " secularized<br />

" and non-secularized political cultures. The former are characterized<br />

by "pragmatic, empirical orientations, " and a " movement<br />

from diffuseness to specificity " of orientations. Individuals who' are<br />

part of a secular political culture deal with others in terms of universalistic<br />

criteria as against considerations arising from diffuse<br />

societal relationships such as those of tribe caste or family. 27 They<br />

are aware that institutions have specific functions and orient themselves<br />

to institutions in these terms. 28<br />

Further, secularized, i.e., modern, political cultures are characterized<br />

by bargaining and accommodative patterns of political<br />

action which are relatively open, in that values are subject to change<br />

in the basis of new experience. Modern states in which " rigid "<br />

ideological politics continue to play a substantial role are those in<br />

which, for some reason, " the bargaining attitudes associated with<br />

2 51bid., p. 306.<br />

26 1bid., p. 50.<br />

27 1bid., p. 58.<br />

28 1bid.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 247<br />

full secularization " have failed to develop. 29 The image is of the<br />

United States and England in the 1950 ' s, and I would suppose<br />

that Almond would be forced to say that both of those societies have<br />

regressed somewhat in recent years. 3o<br />

Most of Comparative Politics is taken up with elaborating the<br />

basic elements of Almond ' s conceptual scheme and demonstrating<br />

its utility. He applies his categories to a number of historical and<br />

contemporary societies to indicate the fruitfulness of his framework<br />

for ordering existing data and discovering new relationships. The<br />

richness of the offering is hard to convey in a short review but one<br />

comes away with the impression from this and other works of the<br />

same genre that whatever the weaknesses of the approach, its utility<br />

for some purposes has been demonstrated. Comparisons can more<br />

easily be made between England and Indonesia or 'between England<br />

and France, which take into account the richness of political life in<br />

all of these societies; and the traditional modern distinction seems<br />

to order a good many relationships which had been ignored by political<br />

scientists in the past.<br />

The volume does contain at least one general (although incomplete)<br />

theory: an analysis of the nature of political development.<br />

Almond follows Talcott Parsons in approaching social change from a<br />

broadly evolutionary view, and it is to this theory and its consequences<br />

that we shall now turn. 3'<br />

29<br />

1bid., 58-59. pp.<br />

'°Almond seems to have accepted and built upon " the end of ideology, "<br />

which became so prominent in the 1950 ' s. For debate on the subject, see<br />

Richard H. Cox, Ideology, Politics and Political Theory ( Belmont, California,<br />

1969). See also Joseph La Palombara, " Decline of Ideology: A Dissent and<br />

Interpretation, " The American Political Science Review LX (March, 1966),<br />

pp. 5-16, and the reply by Lipset in the same issue. The concept of modernization<br />

is derived essentially from German sociology of the late nineteenth<br />

century and especially Weber. Rinehard Bendix, Embattled Reason (New<br />

York, 1970), pp. 250-315 gives a good review of its sources as well as a<br />

critique, and Samuel Huntington,<br />

" The Change to Change: Modernization,<br />

Development, and Politics, " Comparative Politics 3 (April, 1971), pp. 283-<br />

332, provides some interesting insights in a review of the contemporary literature<br />

on development. I will have more to say on the concepts of political culture<br />

and modernization later.<br />

3 "Talcott Parsons, " Evolutionary Universals in Society, " American Sociological<br />

Review 29 (June, 1964), pp. 339-357, and Societies: Evolutionary<br />

and Comparative Perspectives ( New York, 1966).


248 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

II. POLITICAL <strong>AND</strong> SOCIAL CHANGE :<br />

A FUNCTIONAL APPROACH<br />

Almond' s 'Comparative Politics offers two theories of political<br />

development which, for want of better terms, may be called his<br />

general and special theories. The general theory implicitly draws<br />

upon biological analogies. Societies begin as one celled (primitive)<br />

creatures, and gradually differentiate. They develop specialized roles<br />

and structures (cells and organs), such as judiciaries, specialized<br />

organs of communication, etc., for dealing with particular problems.<br />

As they do so their capacity to deal with their environment increases,<br />

although problems of coordination become more pressing,<br />

entailing the creation of a more complex 'bureaucratic (nervous?)<br />

system. 32<br />

Almond suggests on a number of occasions that relative<br />

subsystem autonomy is an important aspect of development, the<br />

argument being that such autonomy allows for the more efficient<br />

performance by particular structures of their functions." The implication<br />

is sometimes that modern pluralistic societies on the English<br />

or American model are more advanced than one party regimes. 34<br />

Almond, however, is not completely convinced, for in his comparisons<br />

of the Soviet with other modern regimes he speaks of the<br />

high capabilities of the former, in terms which will be described<br />

later. 35<br />

Democratic pluralistic regimes are more advanced than one<br />

party regimes or traditional regimes in still another way. Culturally,<br />

a major feature of development is secularization, defined as " the<br />

process whereby men become increasingly rational, analytical, and<br />

empirical in their political action." 3fi " We may illustrate this concept,<br />

" Almond notes:<br />

by comparing a political leader in a modern democracy with a<br />

political leader in a traditional or primitive African political system.<br />

A modem democratic political leader when running for office, for<br />

instance, will gather substantial amounts of information about the<br />

"Comparative Politics, pp. 299-332.<br />

33<br />

Ibid., pp. 311-312, for example.<br />

34 1bid. Almond uses the term totalitarian to describe one party regimes<br />

such as the Soviet.<br />

35<br />

Ibid., p. 278.<br />

"Ibid., p. 24.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

constituency which he hopes will elect him and the issues of public<br />

policy with which that constituency will be concerned. He has to<br />

make estimates of the distribution and intensity of demands of one<br />

kind or another; he needs to use creative imagination in order to<br />

identify a possible combination of demands which may lead to his<br />

receiving a majority of the votes in his constituency. A village chief<br />

in a tribal society operates largely within a given set of goals which<br />

have grown up and been hallowed by custom. The secularization of<br />

culture is the process whereby traditional orientations and attitudes<br />

give way to more dynamic decision-making processes involving the<br />

gathering of information, the evaluation of information, the laying<br />

out of alternative courses of action, the selection of a course from<br />

among these possible courses, and the means whereby which one<br />

tests whether or not a given course of action is producing the consequences<br />

which were intended. 37<br />

Part of this description of tribal societies seems something of a<br />

caricature, for we seem to find as much bargaining and weighing of<br />

alternatives in these societies as in our own. 3S Almond, however, is<br />

suggesting something more. Pluralistic societies are more advanced<br />

than others because the ends of these societies are not given. Rather,<br />

their values are constantly being revised in the light of new experience.<br />

His pragmatism-and it is the very American naturalistic<br />

pragmatism of a John Dewey-is clear. Evolution is the replacement<br />

of unscientific (traditional or ideological) choices of ends by a<br />

rational experimental model in which both means and ends are<br />

constantly changing, as our knowledge increases and the adaptive<br />

problems of the society change.<br />

Evolutionary advance may be defined in any number of ways<br />

For example, one can argue, that the application of the scientific<br />

method to social affairs, including the sphere of moral action, is<br />

more " advanced " because it is more rational or more humane or<br />

more adaptive. Almond clearly thinks that all three statements are<br />

true. His implicit theory of evolutionary change (it is never quite<br />

explicit), as against a description of evolutionary stages has to do<br />

with power. He seems to be saying that those societies become<br />

dominant whose capabilities (power) are greater, either, one sup-<br />

37 1bid., p. 25.<br />

38 See, for example, Marc J. Swartz and associates (eds.), Political Anthrolology<br />

(Chicago, 1966) and Marc J. Swartz (ed.), Local Level Politics<br />

(Chicago, 1968).<br />

249


250 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

poses, because they become models for other societies or incorporate<br />

them. 39 Rationality, differentiation and openness enhance capability<br />

and the dominance of certain kinds of political orders over other<br />

kinds. Unfortunately the evidence on this issue is far from clear.<br />

Democratic societies have been rather short lived historically, and<br />

we have little real empirical reason to believe that an "experimental<br />

democratic " model is more efficient in this sense than others.<br />

Indeed, Almond never comes to grips with the criticisms of<br />

scholars like Nisbet or Bendix. The diffusion of a scientific industrial<br />

culture may be the result of a unique breakthrough in Europe. 4o<br />

After all, before the modern period, a good many more highly<br />

differentiated societies rose to prominence only to collapse. Moreover,<br />

the fact that the scientific revolution and the power derived<br />

from it were associated with liberal pluralism initially says nothing<br />

about the future, and Almond does not offer any good theoretical<br />

reasons for assuming that the pluralist model is more adaptive in the<br />

contemporary world than other political models. Indeed, one can<br />

argue, on a number of grounds, that contemporary scientific culture<br />

may well be superseded by something else. In the introduction to his<br />

collected essays, Almond perceives in the contemporary world :<br />

a reaction against the cognitive overemphasis of the Enlightenment<br />

and associated modernizing processes, and a search for philosophical<br />

and moral meaning and order consistent with science and technology<br />

but not subordinated to it. 41<br />

One need not add, perhaps, that current problems of population,<br />

and pollution and the destructiveness of modern weapons raise<br />

serious doubts as to the ultimate adaptiveness of scientific industrial<br />

culture. Indeed, there are some very cogent reasons to believe that<br />

the agricultural productivity so necessary to current levels of existence,<br />

and which depends so heavily on fossil sources, will not be<br />

able to be sustained very long even at present population levels. 42 In<br />

39<br />

Almond never says this, but, so far as I can determine, it is the most<br />

reasonable assumption to be drawn from his analysis.<br />

40 "<br />

Bendix, "<br />

Tradition and Modernity Reconsidered, op. cit. Robert Nisbet,<br />

Social Change and History ( New York, 1969).<br />

41<br />

Gabriel Almond, Political Development: Essays in Heuristic Theory<br />

(Boston, 1970), p. 27.<br />

42<br />

Hugh Nicol, The Limits of Man: An Inquiry into the Scientific Bases<br />

of Human Population ( London, 1970).


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 251<br />

short, it is conceivable that the scientific revolution has had very nonadaptive<br />

consequences.<br />

Whatever the ultimate merits of Almond ' s scheme (although<br />

I have raised objections to it, these are by no means insurmountable),<br />

it does serve admirably to organize a good deal of material<br />

about historical societies which had hitherto been dealt with in a<br />

very ad hoc fashion. It must be added that Almond, in Comparative<br />

Politics, has transcended his earlier rather simple distinction between<br />

modern and traditional societies and has developed a far more complex<br />

and satisfying scheme, partly derived from Eisenstadt. 43 His<br />

classification runs from primitive bands through patrimonial systems<br />

and centralized bureaucratic empires, to various types of<br />

modern systems, including secularized city states, pre-mobilized<br />

modern systems and mobilized modern systems. 44<br />

Almond ' s specific theory of evolution seems to apply primarily<br />

to the modern period and, more specifically, to Europe and the developing<br />

countries: It has a peculiar teleological quality to it, for<br />

it assumes the mobilized modern state as the inevitable outcome of<br />

development, and deals with the countries studied in terms of the<br />

problems they faced in trying to achieve this end. In Almond ' s terminology,<br />

European states, since about the sixteenth century, have<br />

been faced with a series of problems, viz, state building, nation building,<br />

participation, and distribution. State building pertains to the<br />

creation of institutions which enable the political system to regulate<br />

behavior and extract a larger volume of resources from the society.<br />

Nation building is a process of evolving allegiance to the larger<br />

community at the expense of parochial attachments to tribes, vil -<br />

lages or regions. Problems of participation and distribution arise<br />

as more and more members of the community demand a voice in<br />

determining the decisions that affect them and what they consider a<br />

more equitable division of the values of the society. 45<br />

Almond suggests that the relative peacefulness of British development<br />

in the modern period stems from the fact that these problems<br />

emerged one at a time. A viable state and nation had been created,<br />

for example, before other problems emerged. Other European<br />

nations faced many of the problems at the same time. As a re-<br />

43<br />

S. N. Eisenstatd, The Political Systems of Empires ( New York, 1963).<br />

44<br />

See the table in Comparative Politics, p. 217.<br />

45<br />

1bid., pp. 34-41.


252<br />

THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

suit the load upon the system was too great, resulting in distorted<br />

development and authoritarian rule. Most of the developing countries<br />

today are faced with the need to solve all of these problems at<br />

the same time. 46<br />

The specific developmental model does not seem to derive from<br />

the more general, except for state building which, of course, has<br />

to do with differentiation. While it is extremely useful in ordering<br />

certain kinds of material, it raises certain questions. The general<br />

theory deals with society as an organism, differentiating and coordinating;<br />

the specific theory seems to treat the community as an<br />

individual involved in a problem solving. A good many critics of<br />

functionalism argue that societies are always composed of individuals<br />

and groups with divergent interests, and that such groups are always<br />

in conflict. The organismic model ignores, or, at least, plays down<br />

this fact. 47 In so far as the special theory treats the nation state as an<br />

individual engaged in problem solving, it has the same effect. The<br />

effect is compounded by a tendency to set up the modern " stable "<br />

democratic state as the norm, and to examine development in so far<br />

as it has led to this goal or deviated from it. Given this emphasis,<br />

social justice questions are ignored. The end of the political community,<br />

after all, argues 'Christian Bay, is not stable anything, but a<br />

richer and more meaningful life for all its members. "<br />

Almond has not been insensitive to some of these criticisms. His<br />

most recent work takes into account conflict approaches to the study<br />

of politics and both Comparative Politics and other writings have<br />

attempted to deal with broader issues of sound justice. Indeed,<br />

Almond regards political scientists as sober trustees of the enlighten-<br />

"Ibid., pp. 322 if.<br />

47 See, for example, Collins, op. Cit. and Ralf Dahrendorf, " Out of Utopia:<br />

Toward a Reconstruction of Sociological Analysis," in Demerath and Peterson,<br />

op. cit., pp. 465-480.<br />

48 See, for example, Christian Bay, " Politics and Pseudopolitics: A Critical<br />

Evaluation of Some Behavioral Literature, " in Jack L. Walker, " A Critique of<br />

the Elitist Theory of Democracy, "<br />

in Charles A. McCoy and John Playford<br />

(eds.), Apolitical Politicals: A Critique of Behavioralistn (New York, 1967),<br />

pp. 12-37 and pp. 199-219 respectively. On the stable democracy theme Almond<br />

is lumped together with a number of other political scientists who start<br />

with fairly different assumptions under the general label of "behavioralist. "<br />

These latter include people like Heinz Eulau, Robert Dahl and Nelson Polsby.<br />

One should add that critics of " behavioralism " are generally less harsh with<br />

Almond than they are with scholars like Dahl.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 253<br />

ment. Their job is to bring intelligence to , bear on social issues. While<br />

he never states his position in full detail, he clearly feels that the ends<br />

we choose and the means to choose to attain given ends can both be<br />

improved by a better understanding of reality. The political scientist<br />

cannot and should not avoid dealing with the moral dimensions of<br />

politics. We may, then, turn to Almond ' s attempts to evaluate political<br />

systems. We shall first describe and discuss the implications of<br />

his concept of the civic culture and democratic stability. From there<br />

we will turn to his analyses of the capabilities of regimes, and finally<br />

we shall discuss his attempt to create an index for scoring regimes<br />

according to explicit social justice criteria.<br />

III. EVALUATIONS <strong>AND</strong> VALUES<br />

It is perhaps a commentary on the attitudes prevalent among<br />

American academics during the 1950 ' s, that Almond ' s major concern<br />

at that point should have been the conditions of democratic<br />

stability. The Civic Culture reflected these concerns. Anglo-American<br />

institutions were regarded as reasonably satisfactory; certainly satisfactory<br />

enough to serve as a normative model. The aim of the<br />

volume, then, was to understand the bases of their democratic<br />

stability from a political culture perspective. The study served other<br />

purposes, i.e., it enabled Almond to refine his concept of political<br />

culture. However, it is his conception of democracy, a conception<br />

which falls into the camp of what some of his critics have called<br />

" neo-elitist " democratic theory, that has roused the most controversy,<br />

and we shall emphasize the problems the theory raises in our<br />

discussion of the book.<br />

In The Civic Culture the evolutionary model which was to be<br />

made explicit later in Almond ' s work is already foreshadowed.<br />

Political culture is described in terms of the orientation of citizens<br />

toward the political system. The scholar should study orientations<br />

toward the system as a general object, toward political roles or structures<br />

involved in political inputs or outputs, and toward the self<br />

as a political actor. The character of these orientations varies with<br />

the society ' s level of political development, and Almond develops a<br />

typology of three basic kinds of political culture: " parochial " political<br />

cultures, " subject " political cultures and " participant " political<br />

cultures.<br />

Parochial political cultures characterize primitive or traditional<br />

societies with limited political role differentiation. Members of such


254<br />

THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

societies have few if any orientations toward the political system.<br />

Subject political cultures are found in more advanced-although<br />

still (usually) traditional-societies. Members of the community exhibit<br />

"a high frequency of orientations toward a differentiated<br />

political system, but orientations toward specifically input objects<br />

and toward the self as an active participant approach zero. " 4 °<br />

The third major type of political culture, the participant political<br />

culture, is one in which the members of the society tend to be<br />

explicitly oriented to "the system as a whole and to both the political<br />

and administrative structures and processes. " 50 Such a culture is<br />

obviously more congruent with modern democratic states.<br />

These are ideal type constructs and Almond carefully points<br />

out that most actual political cultures are a mix of these orientations.<br />

One of these mixes, The Civic Culture, is most congruent with existing<br />

stable democratic regimes and is the culture which, in somewhat<br />

different ways, is characteristic of both England and the United<br />

States.<br />

The civic culture, Almond notes, is not the "rationalityactivist<br />

" model described in American civics textbooks. That model<br />

implies that all citizens must participate actively and rationally at<br />

all times in the political process. On the contrary, Almond argues,<br />

not only do citizens in successful democracies fail to behave in this<br />

way, but they cannot. Indeed any approach to full participation in<br />

such a political order would lead to stasis, instability and perhaps<br />

eventual collapse of the democratic polity. 61<br />

British and American politics do not conform to the rationality<br />

activist model because citizens also accept passive subject roles viz a<br />

viz authority, and maintain parochial ties to families and other nonpolitical<br />

groupings. Participation in politics does not have great<br />

salience save at certain critical junctures. It is kept in its place.<br />

Actually, the civic culture and stable democracy depend for<br />

their continued success on an uneasy balance between the myth of<br />

p. 17.<br />

5<br />

49 Gabriel Almond and Sidney Verba, The Civic Culture ( Boston, 1965),<br />

°Ibid., p. 18.<br />

51<br />

The substance of this argument and the next few paragraphs will be<br />

found on pp. 337-368 of The Civic Culture. Almond, of course, is largely<br />

continuing the analyses of people like Robert Dahl, Bernard Berelson and<br />

V. O. Key. See Bernard Berelson et al, Voting ( Chicago, 1954), Robert Dahl,<br />

Who Governs (New Haven, 1961), and V. O. Key, Public Opinion and<br />

American Democracy ( New York, 1961).


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 255<br />

the rational activist citizen, the non-salience of politics, and the<br />

willingness of most citizens to behave as subjects most of the time.<br />

The rationalist activist myth is necessary so that citizens will act at<br />

enough times on sufficient issues to keep elites in line and so that<br />

elites will expect such action. If special groups of citizens act only<br />

at certain times and on issues which are salient to them, the polity<br />

can respond to their demands, thus re-enforcing their allegiance.<br />

The balance, however, does face certain dangers. If issues of<br />

considerable salience to substantial segments of the population<br />

emerge and cannot be dealt with in a reasonable time, serious<br />

problems can develop. Citizen activity can increase to a point where<br />

elites, caught up in all sorts of cross pressures, will be unable to act<br />

at all, and citizens whose demands are not met could develop a<br />

sense of impotence and alienation, with serious consequences for<br />

the system. Further, in so far as socialization into the civic culture<br />

stems less from early childhood experiences (although these are important)<br />

than from experience with the political process itself, the<br />

impact of a crisis like this on later generations could be fairly substantial.<br />

Assuming the argument to be correct, its further implications<br />

are rather disturbing. Mass activism would probably result in either<br />

a longish period of political stasis punctuated by considerable violence,<br />

or some sort of dictatorship. In the latter eventuality voluntary<br />

participation might be replaced by directed participation, but<br />

the great mass of the population would, in fact, be merely subjects.<br />

Of course, some of the issues which brought about the crisis could<br />

be resolved and political activity would then fall back to. normal<br />

levels.<br />

I ' ve extended and extrapolated from Almond ' s argument somewhat<br />

for a particular purpose. It seems to me that it offers some<br />

interesting insights into the current malaise of American democracy,<br />

especially among upper middle class youth, although among other<br />

groups as well.<br />

Both the Vietnam war and the race issue have generated a<br />

series of conflicts involving upper middle class youth (and their<br />

parents) allied in some cases with blacks, versus various middle class,<br />

and working class " ethnics. " Despite all the current student rhetoric<br />

about power elites it seems quite clear that upper middle class reformers<br />

have failed to, achieve their aims not because of " elite "<br />

opposition (after all they and their parents constitute a substantial


256 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

part of the social establishment, at least, if there is an etsablishment)<br />

but because a segment of the political and social elite has joined<br />

with the working class and lower middle class white majority in opposition.<br />

Having been brought up on a " rationality activist " model,<br />

upper middle class youth expect the system to respond relatively<br />

rapidly to the essential rightness of their cause, as they perceive it.<br />

When the system fails to respond in textbook fashion they become<br />

alienated. Their alienation is heightened when they discover that<br />

supposedly " liberal " politicians who profess sympathy are unable<br />

or unwilling to sponsor the policies upon which they theoretically<br />

agree. What they often fail to realize is that these political figures are<br />

more fully committed to the political system as it actually functions<br />

than are activist youth and/or their hands are partially tied by an<br />

electoral constituency which is more conservative than they themselves<br />

are.<br />

In part upper middle class youth and their parents have been<br />

able to achieve more than they might have in terms of numbers,<br />

because they have succeeded in mobilizing positions of the black<br />

community, and because their working class and lower middle class<br />

opponents tend to behave more like " parochials " and "subjects."<br />

Of course, upper middle-class liberals also dominate the prestige<br />

papers and magazines as well as national television and the universities.<br />

They have achieved less than they might have because their<br />

opponents have been activated at least sporadically by real or<br />

imagined threats W . what they consider vital interests: Urban<br />

planning is a case in point. The problems faced by New York City<br />

today, while they have many sources, are less a result of the mayor ' s<br />

unwillingness to act than they are of the fact that almost all groups<br />

feel that their interests should be served and are increasingly willing<br />

to engage in direct action to secure them. Urban planning has been<br />

far easier in England in part . (but only in part) because the average<br />

citizen is still willing to accept elite decisions rather passively.6 2<br />

It seems to me, then, that Almond ' s theory is of considerable<br />

utility in explaining some of our current difficulties, and that he<br />

could have predicted them with the relevant information. His<br />

analysis, therefore, should commend itself to us. It has, however,<br />

come under serious attack from those who argue that because it<br />

52<br />

The argument is developed somewhat more fully in Stanley Rothman,<br />

European Society and Politics (Indianapolis, 1970), pp. 580-582.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 257<br />

undermines the " rationality activist model" it has conservative implications<br />

and. thus is unacceptable. 53 It is a little difficult to understand<br />

what the attackers propose. At least some of their arguments<br />

sound quite similar to those the Church offered when deciding to<br />

silence Galileo because his theories were felt to undermine the basis<br />

of Christian morality. After all, if the kind of democratic polity described<br />

by Almond is the best we can realistically expect to create,<br />

then rejecting it because it does not conform to our wishes, is a<br />

little like suggesting we repeal the law of gravity because it does<br />

not permit men to walk on water. 54 Whatever the relation between<br />

facts and values, no reasonable person will. continue to strive to<br />

achieve a state of affairs which cannot be realized, especially if<br />

Almond ' s theory is correct, and the attempt seems likely to lead to<br />

greater evils than now exist.<br />

Faced with Almond ' s analyses, then, a scholar with a serious<br />

commitment to attaining as democratic a polity as possible, has but<br />

two options. He may offer an alternative theory which is at least<br />

as good as Almond ' s in terms of its explanatory power, and which<br />

permits us to believe that full "rational" political participation can<br />

be achieved by means of structural changes in the society. Alternately,<br />

he may accept Almond ' s analysis and yet deny its implication,<br />

by showing that so-called disruptive behavior promotes values which<br />

are more important than " democratic stability." He may not,<br />

without emulating the Church in one of its most ludicrous moments,<br />

reject the analysis for its " moral " or political implications."<br />

Bay and Walker, in the analyses I have been summarizing, attempt<br />

both tasks. With regard to the first, however, they do little<br />

but assert that the average man has potentially more competence<br />

than Almond gives him credit for. Unfortunately their argument<br />

remains on the level of assertion, and does not quite hit the mark<br />

53 See Walker, and Bay, op. cit., among many others.<br />

54<br />

As Marx noted in attacking the German idealists. His point was that<br />

there was little to be gained in attacking the existing system and calling for<br />

socialism, unless one could develop a conceptual scheme and a theory which<br />

demonstrated that a superior type of social order such as socialism could replace<br />

existing social arrangements.<br />

J5 See the insightful essay by Charles Taylor, " Neutrality in Political Science,"<br />

in Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (eds.), Philosophy, Politics and<br />

Society, third series (Oxford, 1967), pp. 25-57. Walker cites this article, but<br />

it seems to me that he does not really understand its implications.


258<br />

THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

at that. Almond ' s analysis, after all, was derived from structural<br />

considerations rather than personal competence arguments.<br />

The second part of their criticism seems to me to be on firmer<br />

ground. In The Civic Culture Almond seemingly focused on the<br />

achievement of stable democracy to the exclusion of other concerns.<br />

66 His critics suggest, as a counter argument, that a certain<br />

amount of disorder may serve humane ends. Now, this may very<br />

well be true. However, the issues are rather more complicated. Very<br />

few political scientists today would seriously suggest that a political<br />

system characterized by violence and disorder is an end to be sought<br />

in itself. The vast majority would recognize that some kind of order<br />

is necessary if any goals are to be attained. A given kind of political<br />

order may benefit dominant groups. Continued disorder can only<br />

benefit the stronger and the more aggressive, if it benefits anyone.<br />

Walker and Bay would certainly seem to accept the above proposition.<br />

Their argument is that a certain amount of instability can<br />

be tolerated if it results in greater social justice. I suspect that Almond<br />

would not disagree with their position. The differences, if any,<br />

would have to do with the relationship between instability, social<br />

justice and a reasonably democratic order. In short, the issues between<br />

the revisionist democratic theorists and their post-revisionist<br />

critics are essentially empirical. I will not, here, attempt to join in<br />

the argument, except to point out that the analyses of the revisionists,<br />

including Almond, have to be dealt with directly. They cannot<br />

simply be dismissed. 5 7<br />

Actually, Almond himself has recently attempted to develop<br />

measures which might allow theorists to begin to talk in more meaningful<br />

terms about just the issues we have been discussing. In Comparative<br />

Politics he discussed in a preliminary manner the problem<br />

56 '<br />

Two points should be made in Almond s defense. One cannot say everything<br />

in one book, and The Civic Culture was about the cultural conditions<br />

supportive of democratic regimes. Secondly, nothing in Almond ' s analysis<br />

denies that stable democracy can be associated with the repression of some<br />

minority groups.<br />

6 7 These points are made from a somewhat different perspective by Peter<br />

Y. Medding,<br />

"<br />

Elitist Democracy: An Unsuccessful Critique of a Misunderstood<br />

Theory," Journal of Politics 31 (August, 1969), pp. 641-654. I shall<br />

return to some of the points made here in the conclusion of the essay. I shall<br />

also have some critical remarks of another kind to make about Almond ' s<br />

approach to the study of political culture at that time.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

of evaluating political systems. His aim was to develop measures<br />

which would enable us to specify the consequences of policies and<br />

hence to make more intelligent choices:<br />

The capacity for greater precision . . . enables us to make our<br />

comparative analysis more relevant to debates over the ethics and<br />

benefits of different types of political systems. 5R<br />

When we introduce the capabilities level of analysis, we enhance<br />

not only our capacity for scientific prediction and explanation, but<br />

also our capacity to talk about policies as they may affect political<br />

change in desired directions. 59<br />

Almond ' s first concern at this point was with measures of sys -<br />

tem effectiveness. Such measures, he felt, could give us some notion<br />

of the capacity of the system to survive and grow. A measure of<br />

system capacities is certainly a necessary preliminary to evaluating<br />

any political system in social justice terms, if we assume that ought<br />

usually implies can. For example, one ' s ethical evaluation of a<br />

society which exposed weak or deformed children would certainly<br />

depend very much upon one ' s estimate of its food resources and<br />

level of technology.<br />

Almond concentrates on three system capacities: the extractive,<br />

regulative, and symbolic. 40 Extractive capacity has to do with the<br />

range of system performance in drawing material and human resources<br />

from the domestic and international environment. 61 Regulative<br />

capacity has to do with the system's capacity to exere&se control<br />

over individuals and groups. Symbolic capacity is not defined with<br />

complete clarity, but seems to be a measure of the system ' s ability<br />

to secure the support of its members through the "judicious creation<br />

and exploitation of the set of powerful and popular symbols." 6 2<br />

Two measures of system capacity discussed by Almond are more<br />

closely related to issues of social justice, those of " distributive "<br />

and "responsive " capacity. The first has to do with the "activity<br />

of the political system as a distributor of benefits among individuals<br />

or groups. Capacity here is measured by<br />

5 8 Comparative Politics, p, 192.<br />

69 Ibid., p. 194.<br />

"Ibid., pp. 190-212.<br />

sl lbid., p. 195.<br />

"Ibid., p. 200.<br />

259


260 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

... the quantity and importance of the objects distributed, the areas<br />

of human life they touch, the particular sections of the population<br />

receiving various benefits, and the relationship between individual<br />

needs and governmental distribution to meet those needs."<br />

To determine the responsive capacity of a regime one must know<br />

what groups are making demands, how these are processed and<br />

what kinds of reactions occur to such demands. 64<br />

In a later essay Almond expanded his attempts at evaluation<br />

somewhat further, and added a system of ethical scores primarily<br />

for purposes of "loosening up the imagination. "61 A justice score<br />

would<br />

consist of a set of per capita rates of regulatory acts over a period<br />

of time, emanating from a particular political system, weighted for<br />

the salience of the areas regulated and the severity of the regulation,<br />

and corrected for opportunities available to the subjects of regulation<br />

to participate in the determination of the content, scope and<br />

intensity of the regulatory rules, and for the procedural protections<br />

in their enforcement. G °<br />

He added suggestions for a liberty score and offered the possibility<br />

of adaptability and other scores.<br />

It is probably unfair to evaluate these efforts at setting up<br />

empirical measures for evaluating polities, given the tentativeness<br />

with which they have been offered. Thus far, however, attempts<br />

to translate them into meaningful research strategies would not<br />

seem too likely to meet with success. One can perhaps develop some<br />

measures of regulatory and extractive capacity, but categories like<br />

responsiveness raise all sorts of issues as to what constitute decisions<br />

and non-decisions, which seem to raise problems of considerable dif -<br />

ficulty, to put it mildly. 87<br />

The ethical scoring system seems even more dubious. Frankly,<br />

I find it hard even to conceive how a justice score might be opera-<br />

63 Ibid., p. 198.<br />

"Ibid., p. 203.<br />

65" Political Development ...," op. cit., p. 467.<br />

86 Ibid.<br />

G7 See Peter Bachrach and Morton S. Baratz, " Decisions and Non-Decisions:<br />

An Analytic Framework, " American Political Science Review 57 ( December,<br />

1963), pp. 632-642, and a critique of their argument by Richard M. Merelman,<br />

" On the Neo-Elitist Critique of Community Power, " American Political<br />

Science Review 62 (June, 1968), pp. 451-460.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

tionalized. For example, would one measure opportunities available<br />

for participation in terms of felt needs or perceptions, or would one<br />

attempt to create some absolute scale? Nevertheless, continued attempts<br />

in this direction would not be without value, even if they<br />

contributed only slightly to our ability to talk about such issues in<br />

more precise terms.<br />

IV. TOWARD A PLURALISTIC APPROACH TO<br />

THE STUDY OF POLITICS<br />

Even as he began to work in a more detailed manner with<br />

problems of evaluation, Almond ' s thinking was undergoing some<br />

shifts as regards empirical analyses. In a series of essays he began<br />

to move away self-consciously from as heavy a reliance on a functional<br />

model as characterized Comparative Politics, and to seek to<br />

combine such a model with other approaches. " The criticisms<br />

leveled against functionalism in his most recent writing parallel those<br />

of some of his critics. Functionalism focuses too much upon equilibrium.<br />

Its picture of society is too mechanistic or organismic. It is<br />

too deterministic, ignoring such phenomena as political leadership. It<br />

assumes reciprocal relationship among elements of a system which<br />

may indeed not exist. It is too abstract, because its more general<br />

statements are not tied closely to research into the ways in which<br />

groups actually make decisions. It ignores or has ignored such<br />

matters as the changing international environment by not being<br />

sufficiently aware of the openness of political and social systems, and<br />

it ignores the effects of particular policies adopted by elites at critical<br />

periods.<br />

Almond also admits that functionalism has remained somewhat<br />

ethnocentric in its outlook, and accepts the criticisms of Hempel<br />

us"<br />

Determinancy Choice, Stability-Change: Some Thoughts on a Contemporary<br />

Polemic in Political Theory, " Government and Opposition 5 ( Winter<br />

1969-1970), pp. 22-40; Gabriel A. Almond, "State Building in Britain, France<br />

and Prussia, "<br />

(Draft paper prepared for the Summer Workshop in State<br />

Building in Western Europe; Stanford, California, mimeographed, n.d., 42<br />

pp.) ; " Approaches to Developmental Causation, " ( First draft of an introduction<br />

to Gabriel Almond and Scott Flanagan (eds.), Developmental Episodes,<br />

mimeographed, n.d., 71 pp.). Professor Almond was kind enough to send me<br />

copies of both papers prior to publication. The latter paper will be published<br />

this year.<br />

261


262 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

and others that functionalism does not involve casual explanation. 89<br />

Rather, he now argues, its major purpose is hueristic. It is designed<br />

to throw light on relationships which scholars might otherwise have<br />

ignored or misread.<br />

Almond ' s response to his self-criticism is to seek " the historical<br />

cure "<br />

and to attempt to use the functional model in combination<br />

with other models to examine particular developmental episodes in<br />

a variety of countries. The attempt is to combine analytic efforts<br />

with in depth studies of particular historical events.<br />

His conclusion is that any political analysis must draw upon<br />

four major approaches to the study of politics, which complement<br />

each other: the functional, social mobilization, decision making and<br />

leadership models. Any political analysis must also take into account<br />

both the domestic and international environment. Thus the study<br />

of a given system involves an analysis of system-environmental<br />

properties, structural functional properties, decision coalition properties<br />

and leadership properties.<br />

The analysis of change will involve the examination of coalition<br />

and policy outcomes and linkages between these and the system<br />

which is emerging. Part of the job of comparative political history is<br />

to write alternative scenarios in an attempt to clarify the impact of<br />

particular choices. For example, to clarify the development of English<br />

history in the nineteenth century the analyst might ask what<br />

would have happened if Whigs and Tories in 1831 had organized<br />

a coalition based on a policy of repression, or the Social Democratic<br />

Party in 1918 had moved toward the left rather than toward<br />

the " discredited military-bureaucratic establishment. "<br />

Almond is hopeful that the analyses of a series of case studies<br />

will help scholars integrate these various approaches into a more<br />

sophisticated general theory. The nature of this theory is not as<br />

yet clear. For example, Almond seems less taken with an evolutionary<br />

approach, but has not discarded it. He also seems more willing<br />

to accept the possibility of considerable indeterminancy in political<br />

change involving, for example, " accidents, " such as the appearance<br />

of a particular charismatic leader. However, it is far from<br />

certain how this would affect his attempts at conceptualization.<br />

69<br />

The classic critique is that of Carl G. Hempel,<br />

" The Logic of Func-<br />

tional Analysis, " in Llewellyn Gross (ed.), Symposium on Sociological Theory<br />

( Evanston, 1959).


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 263<br />

Conceivably it might lead him to argue that it is impossible to develop<br />

a general science of politics.<br />

V. <strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

The functional approach to the study of society has been around<br />

for some time, and the literature on it has grown to fairly enormous<br />

proportions. Most of the arguments as to its utility have been fairly<br />

well rehearsed and need not be repeated here. It should be noted<br />

that many of the technical objections raised against the functionalism<br />

of Radcliff-Brown, Malinowski or even Parsons are not really applicable<br />

to Almond, although some critics behave as if they were.<br />

Hempel, for example, quite correctly pointed out that " explaining"<br />

the emergence or persistence of an institution by the functions<br />

it performs in the larger society is not an explanation at all, for it<br />

assumes that the same function cannot be fulfilled by some other<br />

institutions, or indeed has to be fulfilled at all. 70 Hempel and others<br />

have also noted that many functional analyses implicitly assume<br />

some ideal model of a functioning society, and have suggested that<br />

this is a dubious procedure. One can easily identify a well functioning<br />

car, or, perhaps, a healthy organism, but given the difficulty of<br />

setting overall goals for a society, what appears to be functional<br />

from one perspective might well be disastrous from another.<br />

At least some functionalists have seemed to feel that every institution<br />

must have some relevance to the functioning of a given<br />

social system, and have attempted to explain institutions in ways<br />

which seemed to justify them. Critics have rightly pointed out that<br />

such analyses assume what has to be proven. They also point out<br />

that such analyses often take the overall values and structure of a<br />

society as given. It may be legitimate to demonstrate that Europeans<br />

have too lightly dismissed institutions which played an important<br />

integrative role in various " primitive " societies as archaic and irrational.<br />

It is another matter to inhibit reform in one ' s own society<br />

by making a similar suggestion.<br />

Other critics have suggested that since all societies consist of<br />

individuals and groups competing for relatively scarce resources,<br />

social arrangements which are functional for dominant sectors,<br />

may, in fact, injure other sectors of the population. It is, perhaps,<br />

70 See Hempel, op. cit.


264 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

because of criticisms such as these that functional theorists began<br />

to experiment with such terms as " eufunction" and " dysfunction, "<br />

in order to permit more critical analyses."<br />

Whatever the merits of the above criticisms and the efforts to<br />

meet them, they are not relevant to Almond ' s work. From the beginning<br />

he has limited his use of functional analyses to certain key<br />

elements. Essentially all Almond has argued is that in all societies<br />

mechanisms must be created for the authoritative allocation of<br />

values, and that the job of political scientists is to study the various<br />

ways in which this has been and is being done. He has also maintained<br />

that we can do so more effectively by using a systems approach<br />

and emphasizing process rather than formal institutions.<br />

Almond has always stated that given political functions can be<br />

performed in a variety of different ways by different institutions.<br />

He has never, therefore, attempted to explain the existence of a<br />

given structure by the function it performs. If one wishes to understand<br />

why the Soviet political system aggregates interests in one<br />

way and the American in another, one must engage in historical<br />

causal analyses. One may fault Almond his list of functions, or may<br />

argue that functional analysis does not exhaust the kinds of questions<br />

of interest to political scientists, but he cannot be accused<br />

either of using teleological explanations or of being a conservative<br />

on these grounds alone. 72 One can also argue, as does Hempel, that<br />

listing functional requisites is simply to explicate the obvious. Perhaps<br />

so, but in the social sciences at least, the systematic discussion<br />

of the obvious may yield at least some advances in our understanding.<br />

Functionalists have also been accused of having adopted a conservative<br />

stance because of their equilibrium assumptions. In his<br />

later writing Almond sometimes apologizes for having done so<br />

earlier, but from what he has written there is no evidence that this<br />

is so. His approach does have a static quality in another sense, however,<br />

and I shall return to that question later.<br />

"Robert Merton seems to have introduced the term dysfunction. Eufunc<br />

Lion was coined by Marion Levy, Jr. For a recent short statement, see the<br />

latter ' s essay in The International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, op. cit.,<br />

pp . 21-28.<br />

72 A. James Gregor raises many of these objections to functionalism in political<br />

science. See his " Political Science and the Uses of Functional Analysis, "<br />

The American Political Science Review 62 (June, 1968), pp. 425-439. However<br />

correct he may be in describing Easton ' s work, his analysis is not applicable<br />

to Almond.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 265<br />

I should add that one cannot really accuse Almond of having<br />

become a new scholastic, a charge which has been leveled against<br />

Talcott Parsons with some justification. 7 3 He does share some of<br />

the jargon of the functional school . of sociology, but he has tried<br />

to stick closely to the data and his category building enterprises have<br />

never really gotten out of hand. The negative side of this virtue is<br />

a lack of conceptual precision in some areas. However, I, for one,<br />

feel that, on balance, the positive aspects of his strategy outweigh<br />

its weaknesses.<br />

Finally, I am not impressed by the arguments of those scholars,<br />

such as LaPalombara, who maintain that attempts to develop an<br />

overall framework for studying political systems are premature<br />

and inhibit effective work. 14 All of us approach the study of society<br />

with some conceptual scheme or other. The benefits of attempts to<br />

make these explicit seem to me to outweigh the possible losses. It is<br />

undoubtedly true that system building of the functional kind has<br />

encouraged at least some scholars, including occasionally Almond<br />

himself, to apply conceptual schemes mechanically rather than<br />

creatively and to ignore the kinds of reality which could not fit into<br />

preconceived boxes. They have also used conceptualization as an<br />

excuse for not doing research. Frankly, I doubt that such students<br />

would be more creative if the functional model did not exist. The<br />

capacity of academics to substitute conceptual schemes or rhetoric<br />

for research is boundless.<br />

LaPalombara ' s critique is, however, useful. During the early<br />

1960's the movement in the direction of overarching intellectual<br />

schemes probably went too far, and rewards in the profession seemed<br />

to be directly proportional to the number of neologisms an author<br />

used. Further careful empirical and historical analysis tended to<br />

be downplayed as mere description. Nevertheless, when used with<br />

sensitivity and as a tentative guideline, the functional _approach has<br />

been fruitful. It certainly has enriched the study of politics in any<br />

number of ways. We forget now that for many years discussions of<br />

the Communist Party of the Soviet Union revolved about the question<br />

as to whether it should or should not be called a party, or<br />

73 See Barrington Moore, Jr., "The New Scholasticism and the Study of<br />

Politics, " in Demerath and Peterson, op. cit., pp. 333-338.<br />

7 4 Joseph LaPalombara, " Macrotheories and Microapplications in Comparative<br />

Politics: A Widening Chasm, " in Comparative Politics 1 ( October, 1968),<br />

p p. 52-78.


266<br />

THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

whether Soviet law was really law. How immensely liberating it<br />

was to forget these questions and start asking ourselves what functions<br />

such institutions performed in Soviet society. In a way functional<br />

assumptions have become so much a part of the intellectual<br />

climate, that we have forgotten what things were like before. 76<br />

Perhaps some of the disillusion with functional analysis has to<br />

do with the kinds of claims which were initially made for it. Many<br />

of those scholars drawn to the approach, including Almond, seemed<br />

to percieve of it initially as a full blown theory which was full of<br />

law like propositions only waiting to be explicated. However, if we<br />

make more modest claims for the approach and see it as Almond<br />

now does, i.e., as a conceptional scheme whose value is primarily<br />

heuristic, it takes on a different perspective. It has not brought<br />

about a revolution in the study of politics which has all but opened<br />

the way to tremendous advances in our understanding. It has not<br />

relieved us of the difficult and frustrating job of careful research<br />

into highly complicated relationships. And it is not even a guide<br />

to study of all the political questions in which we may be interested.<br />

Almond, then, is merely suggesting we adopt a certain research<br />

strategy. To be sure, as already indicated, certain assumptions about<br />

reality are implicit. For example, it is assumed that the reciprocal<br />

relations among parts of the political system are such that significant<br />

changes in some of them will produce changes in others. However,<br />

this statement does not have the status of a " law. " The actual<br />

extent of inter-relatedness must be determined by empirical investigation,<br />

and should it eventually prove to be the case that the postulated<br />

relationships are less interesting than others, a new strategy will<br />

have to be developed. Initially Almond ' s claims were bolder. Stated<br />

more modestly they seem reasonable. 7G<br />

There are, of course, a good many problems with Almond ' s<br />

framework even in his own terms. The political system is conceived<br />

of as an analytic system, one of several subsystems of the larger<br />

society. In postulating inter-connectedness among parts of the system,<br />

Almond does not deny, or at least does not have to deny,<br />

that at the boundaries at least, the relations between elements in<br />

the political system and elements in other subsystems may be of<br />

76 0ne of the first books to approach the Soviet Union from this perspec-<br />

tive was Frederick 'C. Barghoorn ' s, Politics in the USSR ( Boston, 1966).<br />

76<br />

The subtitle of his latest book is: Essays in Heuristic Theory.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

greater significant than relations among parts of the political system<br />

itself. We should like, then, some clarification as to the relationship<br />

between the political system and other subsystems in the society.<br />

Almond, however, has little or nothing to say about this problem.<br />

For one thing he has not developed a functional model of the<br />

whole society. Thus, while he argues that the political system performs<br />

certain functions, he never tells us what other functions must<br />

be performed in a society, and how the performance of such functions<br />

is to be conceptualized.<br />

Furthermore, Almond never tells us clearly what a boundary is,<br />

although he talks freely about boundaries. in reading his analysis<br />

we can develop some vague ideas After all, the political system is<br />

involved in processing demands, and we have some vague notions<br />

as to which structures are involved in such processing and which are<br />

not. Unfortunately, these vague notions are never clarified, and, as<br />

a result, a good deal of fudging occurs, some of it of considerable<br />

importance. The political system floats uneasily in an environment<br />

whose relation to it remains unclear, and, indeed, at times it seems<br />

to expand until it becomes practically co-equal with the society as<br />

a whole. "<br />

One of the major reasons for this, I think, has to do , with Al -<br />

mond 's conceputalization of the functions of the political system.<br />

The Eastonian model has very serious limitations. For example, if<br />

followed rigorously, it would prevent really adequate comparisons<br />

between the Soviet Union under Stalin, China under Mao, Cuba<br />

under Castro, and countries such as the United States or England.<br />

Indeed, it would make comparisons difficult between most modern<br />

states and bureaucratic empires (such as the Ottoman).<br />

In the case of mobilization regimes the effort of the political elite<br />

has not been simply to process demands, but to achieve certain<br />

goals based on ideological preconceptions, and, in fact, to change<br />

the demand structure of society. And, as Eisenstadt points out, one<br />

of the characteristics of bureaucratic empires was the availability<br />

of resources which the elite could use for ends of its own choosing. 78<br />

Almond attempts to deal with such questions by arguing that de-<br />

"See, for example, his discussion of France in Comparative Politics, op. cit.,<br />

pp. 263-66.<br />

"<br />

"<br />

"Cf. Stanley Rothman, One Party Regimes: A Comparative Analysis,<br />

Social Research 34 (Winter, 1967), pp. 675-702 and Eisenstadt, The Political<br />

Systems of Empires, op. cit.<br />

267


268 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

mands can come from within the political system itself. 79 The statement<br />

is, however, incompatible with the model. The political system<br />

cannot be at one and the same time a mechanism for processing<br />

societal demands and the source of such demands.<br />

It is, of course, quite clear that Almond ' s as well as Easton ' s<br />

conception of the functions of a polity are derived from classical<br />

liberalism. The view of Locke and others was essentially that society<br />

consisted of individuals and groups pursuing their own interests and<br />

that the role of the state was to mediate among these groups, and<br />

to perform certain common functions upon which all agreed. One<br />

may feel that this kind of society is essentially the good society, and<br />

the direction in which all political orders should move. However,<br />

such feelings are not a substitute for a conceptual framework which<br />

will enable us to understand how societies have functioned in the<br />

past and do function now. 80<br />

I am not suggesting that the " conversion " model is entirely<br />

wrong or lacks utility. Indeed, in so far as it has encouraged us to<br />

examine the structure of demands. in, say, Soviet society, it has<br />

served as a useful corrective to the totalitarian model so popular in<br />

the 1950 ' s. I would suggest, however, that it is a partial and<br />

ethnocentric model, and that Parson ' s definition of the functions<br />

of the political system is superior, although not without problems.<br />

In Parsonian terms the political system would be defined as that<br />

subsystem of the society through which its members define its goals,<br />

and, in the broadest sense, mobilize resources to achieve these<br />

goals.' Such goals, of course, include the authoritative allocation<br />

of values within the society.<br />

Parsons has been. criticized for. failing to specify whose goals<br />

he is talking about, and, in general, for ignoring power assymetries<br />

in society as well as the key role of dominant elites. S2 However, if<br />

he is at fault in this regard, his definition is not. The existence of<br />

political systems in all known present and historical societies is to<br />

79<br />

Comparative Politics, p. 25.<br />

80<br />

Joseph LaPalombara has made a similar point in Joseph LaPalombara<br />

(ed.), Bureaucracy and Political Development ( Princeton, 1963), p. 10.<br />

81<br />

Talcott Parsons, Politics and Social Structure (New York, 1969), pp.<br />

317-351.<br />

82<br />

See the very insightful discussion and critique by Anthony Giddings,<br />

" Power in the Recent Writings of Talcott Parsons," Sociology 2 (September,<br />

1968), pp. 257-272. and W. G. Runciman, Social Science and Political Theory<br />

(Cambridge, 1969, 2nd edition), p. 117.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong><br />

be explained by the fact that men require mechanisms of some kind<br />

to define common goals, including mere survival, as well as to mo -<br />

bilize resources for their attainment. The key role played by the<br />

political system in any society makes it a focal point of conflict, and<br />

a mechanism by which dominant elites can insure their dominance<br />

and engage in various forms of self-aggrandizement. In the study<br />

of any given society the actual relationship between the role of<br />

demands emanating from other groups within the society and elite<br />

preferences and perceptions is an open question to be settled by<br />

research.<br />

Almond ' s liberal perspectives also weaken his discussion of political<br />

culture. It may be that secular, rational, pragmatic cuture is<br />

the high point of evolution, as it manifests (should we say manifested?)<br />

itself in England and the United States. However one<br />

must deal with some serious questions before such an assertion can<br />

be accepted. American " pragmatism " has always operated within<br />

a framework of certain widely shared values themselves derived<br />

from the Liberal tradition. The " pragmatism " of the British, while<br />

superficially the same, has other roots. Both traditions seem to be<br />

breaking down, and I suspect that Almond would have been more<br />

sensitive to this fact had he not been caught up in certain assumptions<br />

of his own.<br />

His problems with the concept of political culture as an analytic<br />

tool have, however, deeper roots which are related to his entire<br />

methodology, and the methodology of much of the contemporary<br />

behavioral school. Responding to criticisms that functional theory<br />

was static, that it ignored conflict, and that the relationship between<br />

macro-theory and actual empirical analysis was not clearly articulated,<br />

Almond has modified his approach. An evolutionary theory<br />

was added to the repertoire of functionalism and, more recently,<br />

efforts have been made to include coalition and leadership analysis.<br />

However, the model still remains static in many ways. Scholars are<br />

to search for relevant variables to describe a given society at a given<br />

point and then to look for the forces which produce change. As yet,<br />

however, one has little sense that Almond has begun to think about<br />

the weight of particular variables in producing a given change or<br />

has developed a. method for adequately describing a society at a<br />

given period of time. As a result, superficial resemblances are often<br />

assumed to represent basic similarities, and concepts like political<br />

culture become reified. Let me offer an example of what I mean and<br />

269


270 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

then attempt to suggest a strategy. by which efforts may be made to<br />

deal with the problem.<br />

In Comparative Politics, Almond contrasts the political style of<br />

the United States, England and the Philippines, on the one hand,<br />

with countries such as France on the other. The latter he argues, is<br />

characterized by an " absolute, value oriented " style. The former<br />

on the other hand are more pragmatic. He goes on to note:<br />

The pragmatic-bargaining style characterizes aggregation in such<br />

systems as those of the United States, Great Britain and the Philippines.<br />

In these countries a wide variety of interests are often combined<br />

into a limited number of alternative policies. This aggregation<br />

is sometimes guided by more general ideological perspectives,<br />

but the accommodation of diverse interests is its more notable char-<br />

acteristic. . . The presence of this style greatly facilitates system<br />

responsiveness. 83<br />

My knowledge of the Philippines is not very detailed. I would<br />

guess that the style of politics described by Almond is based on quite<br />

different values than that of the United States or England, and has<br />

more to do with the clientelist politics so characteristic of Latin<br />

American as well as a number of Asian societies. 84 Placed in the<br />

total context of the society, the style of interest aggregation in the<br />

Philippines, therefore, would seem likely to have a quite different<br />

meaning than superficially similar styles in the U. S. and Great<br />

Britain. It has, for example, been associated with extremely low<br />

rates of economic growth and quite high levels of corruption. The<br />

latter phenomenon, at least, is not characteristic of English<br />

politics. 86<br />

Further, while Almond ' s model helps us understand some aspects<br />

of the American malaise today, it seems clear that other forces<br />

have been at work too, associated with changing family patterns,<br />

and the decline of Protestant sensibilities of a certain kind. Relating<br />

the particular pattern of American political culture dynamically<br />

to other variables in the 1950 ' s might not have enabled Almond<br />

83<br />

Comparative Politics, p. 108.<br />

84 "<br />

See John Duncan Powell, Peasant Society and Clientelist Politics,"<br />

American Political Science Review 64 (June, 1970), pp. 411-425.<br />

86<br />

Almond is certainly aware that similar styles do not have the same<br />

meanings in all three countries, but I feel that he is unable adequately to<br />

conceptualize the differences (see Ibid., pp. 57-58).<br />

1


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 27 1<br />

to be completely clear about what would happen in the 1960 ' s.<br />

It would perhaps have inspired somewhat greater caution in making<br />

statements about political cultures which implied that their character<br />

was relatively fixed.<br />

Almond ' s efforts to conceptualize societies at given periods of<br />

time do seem to resemble a series of static snapshots. One finds a<br />

certain kind of balance at point A. One then searches for exogenous<br />

and indigenous forces which have led or might lead to change. The<br />

strategy is not without merit. It does have limitations.<br />

This kind of approach, however, is not intrinsic to functional<br />

analysis per se.. On the contrary, a scholar can just as easily begin<br />

with the assumption that all modern societies, at least, represent at<br />

any given time an uneasy balance of forces. He would then<br />

actively search out potential tensions and sources of conflict and<br />

would recognize that any full description of the structures which<br />

characterize the political system necessarily involve an analysis of<br />

the balance of forces which led to their emergence, and the ways<br />

in which they seem to be changing. S6 The problems involved in<br />

dealing with political systems in this fashion are very complex, but,<br />

then, political systems are very complex. Political scientists might,<br />

in this respect, take a leaf from the work of contemporary psychoanalysts.<br />

The full description of the balance of forces which constitute<br />

a personality, involves the recognition that they are in a state<br />

of dynamic tension, and that they are a composite of an individual ' s<br />

entire life history. The same neurotic symptoms may represent a<br />

quite different combination of elements." Analyses of this type<br />

may often be erroneous, but those making them are less likely to be<br />

surprised by change, and are certainly less likely to be taken in by<br />

superficial resemblances in the responses to relatively short and<br />

highly structured questionnaires.<br />

The efforts which have been made by those of the functional<br />

school to develop an evolutionary theory of political development<br />

face a great many difficulties. They are not insuperable, but in so<br />

far as their analyses are decidely teleological they will have to be<br />

recast before they can be regarded as more than suggestive. Just<br />

as significantly, they will somehow have to be broadened to take<br />

"The point is made quite well in Walter Buckley, Sociology and Modern<br />

Systems Theory ( Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 1967).<br />

87 Otto Fenichel, The Psychoanalytic Theory of Neurosis ( New York, 1945).


272 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

into account man ' s relation to his total environment, and a theory<br />

of motivation which satisfies our knowledge of man ' s biological<br />

nature as well as his capacity to create culture. 88 If the events of<br />

the past several years have reminded us of anything it is that any<br />

such theory must take into account the non-rational elements of<br />

human behavior. Almond regards himself as a " sober " trustee of the<br />

enlightenment, but he is still a trustee, as are most political scientists.<br />

The model is still of rational men seeking to satisfy interests. Their<br />

conceptions of this interest may be determined, in part, by cultural<br />

givens, but within that framework, their means and ends are more<br />

or less rationally chosen. Despite the fact that psychoanalysis is all<br />

but an American institution, there has been little effort to integrate<br />

its insights into our work, since Lasswell ' s rather abortive efforts. 89<br />

These last remarks have been critical, and it is much easier to<br />

criticize than to innovate, at least if one sets reasonably rigorous<br />

empirical standards by which one ' s innovations shall be judged. The<br />

criticisms, however, are offered not to demolish functionalism as an<br />

approach, but to suggest possible ways in which its fruitfulness for<br />

the study of politics may be increased. Again, the functional approach<br />

has not involved a revolution in the study of politics and<br />

it has not led us much closer to solving the riddle of the sphinx. It<br />

has enabled us to develop increased sophistication. In short, Almond<br />

and those who have worked with him have important achievements<br />

to their credit.<br />

Much of the content of political science has remained and will<br />

remain unchanged by the development of functional perspectives.<br />

The need for historical analysis remains as important as ever, as do<br />

detailed descriptions of particular institutions. More importantly, and<br />

this may have more to do with the historical sources of functionalism,<br />

than the framework itself, certain very important questions<br />

do not seem amenable to a functional approach.<br />

88<br />

Two recent and very stimulating attempts to do just this are those of<br />

Weston LaBarre, The Ghost Dance (New York, 1970), chs. 1 and 2, and<br />

Peter A. Corning,<br />

" The Biological Bases of Behavior and Some Implications<br />

for Political Science, " World Politics 23 (April, 1971), pp. 321-370.<br />

88 The reasons for this are complicated and have as much to do with the<br />

nature of classical psychoanalysis as with political science. Recently signs have<br />

developed of a new attempt to build bridges between psychoanalytic theory,<br />

history and other social sciences. See, for example, the very insightful book<br />

by Fred Weinstein and Gerald M. Platt, The Wish to Be Free ( Berkeley,<br />

1969), La Barre, op. cit., also incorporates a psychoanalytic perspective.


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 273<br />

It may be true, for example, that all modern societies are and<br />

will be characterized by structures that fulfill the functions commonly<br />

assigned to bureaucracies, whatever one may call them.<br />

Nevertheless, there are still differences between modern societies<br />

which are important, and these differences are not adequately conceptualized<br />

by terms like " subsystem autonomy. " The Soviet<br />

Union may be a modern political system and a one party regime.<br />

It is also a socialist society. There can be but little question that<br />

the nature of the economic system has important consequences for<br />

political institutions, and that the politics of equally modern neocapitalist<br />

and socialist societies will take different forms. The study<br />

of these problems has been relatively neglected in recent years. They<br />

remain crucial to our understanding of comparative politics, as<br />

well as to our ability to confront some of the problems with which<br />

we shall be faced in the fairly near future.<br />

One final issue remains to be discussed. In recent years a widespread<br />

attack has been raised against functionalism in sociology and<br />

the whole behavioral tradition in political science (of which functionalism<br />

is usually considered part) which goes well beyond some<br />

of the criticisms I have already elaborated. 90 A good deal of the<br />

criticism is highly rhetorical and does not readily lend itself to systematic<br />

analysis. However, in much of it behavioralism and functionalism<br />

are accused of being conservative because they draw their<br />

image of man and his behavior from a highly corrupt contemporary<br />

society. Assuming contemporary behavior is natural, they refuse to<br />

use the facts for a leap of utopian speculation which would permit<br />

th emergence of new forms of social organization which are freer,<br />

more spontaneous and less characterized by " repressive " authority.<br />

90 The literature is becoming fairly substantial in sociology and political<br />

science. In the latter field the criticism of functionalism is generally part of a<br />

general criticism of the " behavioral " approach. Some representative works<br />

include: Alvin Gouldner, The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology ( New<br />

York, 1970): Henry Kariel (ed.), Frontiers of Democratic Theory ( New<br />

York, 1970), Marvin Surkin and Alan Wolfe (eds.), An End to Political<br />

Science (New York, 1970), Philip Green and Sanford Levinson (eds.), Power<br />

and Community: Dissenting Essays in Political Science (New York, 1970),<br />

and the McCoy and Playford volume already cited. See also Henry Kariel,<br />

" Expanding the Political Present, " The American Political Science Review 63<br />

( September, 1969), pp. 768-776, and Sheldon Wolin, " Political Theory as a<br />

Vocation," The American Political Science Review 63 December, 1969), pp.<br />

1062-1082.


274 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

Insofar as the (behavioralist) eliminates alternative realities<br />

by embracing as "real" the very institutions which the social sciences<br />

properly subject to continuous criticism, it is anti-empirical as well<br />

as elitist. When it fails to acknowledge the problematic-not to say<br />

grotesque character of the present, it is unable to specify how men<br />

are kept underdeveloped by the dominant order of commitments;<br />

government by a plurality of elites, a functional division of labor<br />

. . . the system of fixed social and biological roles within hierarchical<br />

organizations. ... 91<br />

... the issue is ... between those who would restrict the "reach"<br />

of theory by dwelling on facts which are selected by what are assumed<br />

to be the functional requisites of the existing paradigm and<br />

those who believe that because facts are richer than theories, it is<br />

the tasks of the theoretical imagination to restate new possibilities. e2<br />

In so far as behavioralists or functionalists have taken as natural<br />

what is twentieth century American and European political behavior,<br />

Kariel, Wolin and others certainly have a point, if we ignore<br />

their hyperbole. Beyond this I am more skeptical. It may be that<br />

developing a theory of human political behavior by drawing on its<br />

past and present manifestations produces a conservative bias. It still<br />

seems to be infinitely preferable to deriving such theory from the<br />

future unless one owns a good ouija board.<br />

Functionalists, after all, can argue that on the basis of their own<br />

assumptions they could have predicted and can explain why the<br />

French had to recreate a legal profession after 1789 and why the<br />

Russians had to recreate a legal system or a bureaucracy which re -<br />

sembles very closely the bureaucracy of other industrial societies.<br />

They could also have predicted the need for organizing industry<br />

and education in ways not too different from other communities.<br />

And they would predict that the Chinese, despite Mao 's efforts, will<br />

continue to face the same requirements. 93<br />

Finally, they could have<br />

predicted that the failure to recognize the need for some structure<br />

of authority in any society and public checks upon it would most<br />

likely result in its concentration in the hands of a self-perpetuating<br />

91 Kariel, op. cit., p. 769.<br />

"Wolin, op. cit., p. 1082.<br />

"Stanley Rothman, European Society and Politics, op. cit., chapters 3, 4,<br />

7, 20, 21, 22. On China after the cultural revolution, see John W. Lewis<br />

(ed.), The City in Communist China (Stanford, 1971).


<strong>FUNCTIONALISM</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>ITS</strong> <strong>CRITICS</strong> 275<br />

elite. 94<br />

Such predictions and explanations, deriving as they do from<br />

functional and structural imperatives, seem rather more reasonable<br />

than the simplistic notions of betrayal by which some utopians, at<br />

least, attempt to explain the failure of all past efforts to usher in<br />

the millenium.<br />

If one, then, is to convince reasonable men that transcendence<br />

is more than merely possible, one must develop a conceptual framework<br />

and theories which stand the test of all empirical theories. The<br />

creators of such frameworks and theories will have to demonstrate<br />

that they enable us to organize data about the present and past<br />

roughly as efficiently as alternate models, and that they are more<br />

fruitful with regard to new discoveries. Marx certainly realized<br />

this. Most of his adult life was dedicated to the attempt to construct<br />

a model of man and history which would demonstrate, on<br />

just these grounds, the probability of a future society which<br />

would maximize human freedom. Those who would make use of<br />

the philosophic " existential " Marx, while ignoring or rejecting the<br />

mature theory would have received little sympathy from him. Very<br />

few radical theorists have attempted anything like a comparable<br />

task, and the efforts of those who have tried, such as Marcuse, Bay,<br />

Gouldner or Moore seem less than convincing. 95<br />

At least some of the new set of radical critics would refuse to<br />

accept this task. The argument seems to be as follows: All social<br />

science begins with value assumptions, in Gouldner's terms " background<br />

" and " domain " assumptions. We, then, are free to choose<br />

our own and proceed from there. The only requirement is that we<br />

must be aware of the assumptions from which we start. 99<br />

I would assert the contrary. Unless we assume that disagreements<br />

about political-moral questions stem from constitutional<br />

94<br />

Stanley Rothman, "One Party Regimes ..., op. cit.<br />

95<br />

Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civilization ( Boston, 1955), One Dimensional<br />

Man ( Boston, 1964), Christian Bay, The Structure of Freedom (New York,<br />

1965), and other works cited above; Gouldner, op. cit., and Barrington Moore,<br />

Jr., Social Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy (Boston, 1966). For<br />

critiques, see Alasdair MacIntyre, Herbert Marcuse ( New York, 1970), Stanley<br />

Rothman, "Barrington Moore and the Dialectics of Revolution: An Essay<br />

Review, " The American Political Science Review 64 (March, 1970), pp.<br />

" "<br />

Objectivity, Commentary 50 (December, 1970),<br />

61-82. Stanley Rothman,<br />

pp. 95-97 represents a critique of Gouldner, and R. S. Peters, The Concept<br />

of Motivation (London, 1958) offers a short but devastating critique of<br />

Abraham Maslow, upon whom Bay builds much of his theorizing.<br />

"Gouldner, op. cit.


276 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER<br />

differences, they can only derive from differing beliefs about the<br />

natural order of things and their relation to human needs. Most<br />

of us derive these beliefs initially from our culture, or from childhood<br />

experiences. However, confessing that one starts from certain<br />

assumptions, does not release one from the obligation constantly to<br />

re-examine them in the light of new evidence. To refuse is to<br />

abdicate moral responsibility. Children do this, but as adults we<br />

should put away childish things.<br />

As Charles Taylor notes, in an article which should be read carefully<br />

by every political scientist:<br />

" " " . . . good doesn't mean conducive to the fulfillment of human<br />

wants, needs or purposes " ; but its use is unintelligible outside of any<br />

relationship to wants, needs and purposes. . . For if we abstract<br />

from this relation, then we cannot tell whether a man is using<br />

"good" to make a judgment, or simply to express some feeling; and<br />

it is an essential part of the meaning of the term that such a distinction<br />

can be made . . . " good " is used in evaluating, commending,<br />

persuading and so on by a race of human beings who are such that<br />

through their needs, desires, and so on, they are not indifferent to<br />

the outcomes of the world process.<br />

In setting out a given framework, a theorist is also setting out the<br />

gamut of possible politics and policies. But a political framework<br />

cannot fail to contain some, even implicit conception of human<br />

needs, wants and purposes. The context of this conception will de-<br />

termine the value-slope of the gamut... .<br />

In this sense we can say that a given explanatory framework<br />

secretes a notion of good, and a set of valuations, which cannot be<br />

done away with-though they can be overridden-unless we do<br />

away with the framework. 97<br />

To say that most ethical disagreements about politics stem from<br />

different conceptions of the world, is not to make the task of securing<br />

agreement easier. The assumptions underlying various frameworks<br />

and theories are difficult to deal with, and prejudice dies<br />

hard especially when compounded by self-interest. It is to say that<br />

morally responsible men must always subject their own and other<br />

frameworks to the kinds of empirical tests I have suggested.<br />

Smith College<br />

97<br />

Taylor, op. cit., pp. 54-55, 5<br />

STANLEY ROTHMAN

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!