25.10.2013 Views

lexical and semantie relations

lexical and semantie relations

lexical and semantie relations

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

6 <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong><br />

Keywords: PARADIGMATIC, Y TAGMATIC, SEMANTIC RELATIO ,<br />

LEXICAL RELATION, SYNONYM, CONTRAST, ANTONYM,<br />

COMPLEMENTARY, CO TRARY, CONVER E, HYPONYM,<br />

HYPERO YM, MERONYM, HOLO YM, DICTIO ARY APPROACH,<br />

THESAURUS APPROACH, EMA TI FIELD, LEXICAL BLOCKI G<br />

6.1 Overview<br />

This chapter examine particular emantic relation among words.<br />

They are called semantic <strong>relations</strong> because they are <strong>relations</strong> between senses.<br />

Some ca es of semantic relation can al o be <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>relations</strong> in which it is<br />

not ju t the meaning that are related, but al o other a pect of the lexeme ,<br />

like morphological form or collocational pattern . After looking at the detail of<br />

synonymy, hyponymy, antonymy, <strong>and</strong> other relation, we evaluate two approache<br />

to the representation of semantic <strong>relations</strong> in the mental lexicon. In the fir t<br />

approach, the lexicon is theorized to be like a dictionary, which record sen e<br />

but not nece arily <strong>relations</strong> among them. The econd view the lexicon like a<br />

thesauru in which relation, but not meanings, are repre ented.<br />

6.2 Paradigmatic <strong>relations</strong>:<br />

synonymy, antonymy, hyponymy<br />

6.2.1 Paradigmatic vs. syntagmatic<br />

Relation among word can be divided roughly into two type :<br />

paradigmatic <strong>and</strong> yntagmatic. Syntagmatic <strong>relations</strong> are relation between<br />

words that go together in syntactic phra e - like ship 's <strong>and</strong> captain or dogs<br />

<strong>and</strong> barko Notice that syntagmatic <strong>and</strong> syntax are from the same Greek root,<br />

meaning 'touching together' - in other word, word in yntagmatic <strong>relations</strong><br />

"touch" each other in phra e . Because they go together in phra e, yntagmatically<br />

related word often belong to different word cla ses - e.g. dog (noun)<br />

+ bark (verb). Syntagmatic <strong>relations</strong> are studied more <strong>and</strong> more these day a<br />

108<br />

corpu research highlight the<br />

word rather than other . For i<br />

goes with certain modifier to i<br />

or sound asleep, <strong>and</strong> that it oec<br />

modifiers that indicate the am<br />

others, like very as/eep. Our fo<br />

tudy for <strong>lexical</strong> semantic : par<br />

i ues in the later chapters - ineJ<br />

adjective , in chapter ll.<br />

Word in paradigmatic rels<br />

orne characteristics in comme<br />

form a paradigm - that i ,a I<br />

paradigmatic relation i a morp<br />

verb: drink, drank, drunk. otie<br />

in common except their ten e..<br />

involve word senses that hare I<br />

for example, the et of ba ic co<br />

each refer to a different part of ti<br />

word, paradigmatically relatec<br />

For example, red, white, <strong>and</strong> any<br />

<strong>and</strong> grammatically occur in the<br />

(l) a redlwhite/greenlblue<br />

(2) a shade of redlwhite/g<br />

Lexical semanticist study parac<br />

relation among entence mean<br />

of what they might tell u abor<br />

ee in §6.3. They are also intere:<br />

Using related words allow u t<<br />

providing varied information an<br />

A few paradigmatic relation<br />

Synonymy i the relation of hal<br />

are ynonyms in many people':<br />

for example, house is a hypor<br />

building. Co-hyponymy ( orne<br />

of en e that make up a et, bt<br />

heart/club/spade/diamond. Tha<br />

type - in this case, playing card<br />

which two words are opposite<br />

the e <strong>relations</strong> in more depth in<br />

While people of ten talk abou<br />

accurate to talk about senses or II<br />

being synonyms or antonym, i


ans<br />

C RELATION,<br />

M,<br />

l,<br />

PROACH ,<br />

ILOCKJNG<br />

n among words.<br />

i between en es.<br />

n in which it i<br />

i of the lexemes,<br />

g at the detai I of<br />

:etwo approache<br />

icon. In the fir t<br />

:h records sense<br />

he lexicon like a<br />

l.<br />

into two type :<br />

ilations between<br />

captain or dogs<br />

me Greek roots,<br />

gmatic <strong>relations</strong><br />

ses, syntagmate.g.<br />

dog (noun)<br />

re these day as<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 109<br />

corpu re earch highlight the way in which word tend to occur with certain<br />

words rather than other. For in tance, we can notice that the adjective asleep<br />

goe with certain modifier to indicate 'ab olute tate of sleep,' as in fast asleep<br />

or sound asleep, <strong>and</strong> that it occasionally goe with orne other general-purpose<br />

modifier that indicate the arne meaning, like completelyasleep, but le with<br />

others, like very asleep. Our focus in thi chapter i the more traditional area of<br />

tudy for <strong>lexical</strong> emantic : paradigmatic relation. We'll see orne yntagmatic<br />

is ue in the later chapter - including the issue of which modi fiers go with which<br />

adjectives, in chapter Il.<br />

Words in paradigmatíc <strong>relations</strong> belong to the ame word cla s <strong>and</strong> hare<br />

orne characteri tie in common. The word in uch <strong>relations</strong> can be aid to<br />

form a paradigm - that i , a et of example that how a pattern. One kind of<br />

paradigmatic relation i amorphological paradigrn, uch as the tense forms of a<br />

verb: drink, drank; drunk. Notice that the ve rb in this paradigm have eve ry thing<br />

in common except their ten e. We are interested in emantic paradigms, which<br />

involve word sen e that hare many emantic propertie , but differ in orne. So,<br />

for example, the et of ba ic color adjective form a paradigm who e members<br />

each refer to a different part of the color spectrurn. Unlike syntagmatically related<br />

words, paradigmatically related word are u ually ub titutable for each other.<br />

For exarnple, red, white, <strong>and</strong> any other member of the color paradigm can en ibly<br />

<strong>and</strong> grammatically occur in the ame phrases, as in (l) <strong>and</strong> (2).<br />

(l) a red/white/green/blue house<br />

(2) a hade of red/white/green/blue<br />

Lexical emantici t tudy paradigmatic relation becau e of their roles in logical<br />

relation arno ng entence meanings, uch a entailment (see §2.2), <strong>and</strong> because<br />

of what they might tell us about how the mental lexicon is organized, as we'lI<br />

ee in §6.3. They are alointeresting for their u e in creating coherent discourse.<br />

U ing related word allow u to describe the ame things in different way, thu<br />

providing varied information <strong>and</strong> avoiding repetition in di cour e.<br />

A few paradigmatic <strong>relations</strong> receive the mo t attention in <strong>lexical</strong> emantics.<br />

Synonymy i the relation of having (nearly) the ame meaning. Couch <strong>and</strong> sofa<br />

are ynonym in many people' dialect. Hyponymy i the 'type-of' relation;<br />

for example, house i a hyponym of building becau e a house i a type of<br />

building. Co-hyponymy (ometime called <strong>lexical</strong> contrast) involves a group<br />

of ense that make up a et, but which contra t with one another, for example<br />

heart/club/spade/diamond. That i , they are different varietie within a single<br />

type - in thi ca e, playing card uit. Antonymy i a peci al ca e of contra t in<br />

which two word are oppo ite, for example black/white. We examine each of<br />

these relation in more depth in the following sub ection .<br />

While people of ten talk about word being ynonyms or antonyrn , it i more<br />

accurate to talk about senses or <strong>lexical</strong> units (form + en e-in-u e - see § 1.2.4) as<br />

being ynonym or antonym, ince a ingle word may have different ynonym


110 LEXICAL MEA ING<br />

or antonym for different en es. For instance, when using the 'ternperature'<br />

en se of hot, it oppo ite i cold. but when u ing the' picy' en e of hot, its<br />

opposite is mild. For thi rea on, ernantic relation are ometimes called sense<br />

<strong>relations</strong>.<br />

6.2.2 Synonymy<br />

The term synonym come from Greek roots syn 'alike' <strong>and</strong> onym<br />

'name.' It refer to word that mean the ame as each other, o the equal sign =<br />

is used to signal synonymy. Becau e it i rare for two word to have exactly the<br />

same rneaning/u e, discussions of ynonymy frequently concern word that are<br />

not perfect synonym , but that differ only slightly. The substitutability test is<br />

u ed to determine whether two words are synonym . Word are ub titutable if<br />

there is no change in the mean ing of a sentence when one word is ubstituted<br />

for the other. So, for example, if the truth of (3) entails the truth of (4), <strong>and</strong> vice<br />

ver a, then we have evidence that person <strong>and</strong> human are synonyrn<br />

(3) A per on is st<strong>and</strong>ing beside me.<br />

(4) A human is t<strong>and</strong>ing be ide me.<br />

If we want to te t whether man is a ynonyrn for per on, then we can compare<br />

(5) <strong>and</strong> (3).<br />

(5) A man is t<strong>and</strong>ing be ide me.<br />

In thi case, ince we can conclude that ometime it would be true that a person<br />

is st<strong>and</strong>ing beside me at the ame time when it is fal e that a man is t<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

be ide me - since there things that can be referred to as person that can not be<br />

called man - namely, women, girls, <strong>and</strong> boy . Hence man <strong>and</strong> person are not<br />

ynonyms.<br />

Absolute vs. sense synonyms<br />

Words are said to be absolute syn ony ms if they are substitutable in any po sible<br />

context with no changes in denotation or other a pect of meaning (including<br />

connotation - see §2.2.2). U ing that criterion, it i ea y to see that very few<br />

word are ab olute ynonym . Take for example funny = peculiar <strong>and</strong> funny =<br />

comical. Where peculiar is substitutable for funny, as in (6), comical probably i<br />

not ub titutable <strong>and</strong> vice ver a, a in (7).<br />

(6) My turnrny feels a bit funny (= peculiar, 1comical) whenever l eat fish.<br />

(7) Anna told a hilariously funny (l peculiar, = comical) joke.<br />

Funny has different ynonym in different context beca u e it is polysemou ,<strong>and</strong><br />

its various en e match up semantically with different set of words. Since they<br />

do not share all their en se .funny <strong>and</strong> pecu/iar are not ab olute ynonym , <strong>and</strong><br />

neither are funny <strong>and</strong> comical. In tead, they are sense synonyms, in that they<br />

each have one sen e that mean the ame as one of the other word' en e .<br />

For each of the followingpa<br />

ynonyms by giving a enter<br />

Describe why they are not 1<br />

a. safe, ecure<br />

b. fake. false<br />

C. big, large<br />

d. (a tough one!) Ol<br />

The exi tence of large the:<br />

are very close in meaning. :<br />

to find pair that are perfectl<br />

may feel that funny <strong>and</strong> co,<br />

funny joke is a slightly diff<br />

(1973:12-13) has gone of.<br />

where two expres ion canr<br />

be deceiving our elve ." Tt<br />

technical names for thing<br />

furze = gorse = whin, whic<br />

American example i groutu<br />

leave it to you to decide wh,<br />

myself in claiming that the (<br />

Near-synonyms<br />

Far more common is for wo<br />

[ake ~ false in Puzzle 6-1.<br />

ynonyms (in a particular<br />

contexts, but not every conte)<br />

ub titution te t in (8), but fa<br />

have a sense that roughly me:<br />

are not shared by both word<br />

(8) Ian obtainedlacquir<br />

(9) a. Jan obtained permi<br />

b. Ian acquired a Briti!<br />

So far, we have seen that<br />

being poly emou in differer<br />

ynonym ) or by not having<br />

onyms that are denotationally<br />

way - for exarnple, by belo<br />

different connotations. So, w


ng the 'ternperature'<br />

icy' en e of hot, its<br />

metime called sense<br />

yn 'alike' <strong>and</strong> onym<br />

o the equal ign =<br />

I to have exactly the<br />

mcern words that are<br />

bstitutability test i<br />

Is are ubstitutable if<br />

_ word i ubstituted<br />

truth of (4), <strong>and</strong> vice<br />

nonym .<br />

hen we can compare<br />

be true that a person<br />

at a man ist<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

erson that can not be<br />

I <strong>and</strong> person are not<br />

table in any pos ible<br />

meaning (including<br />

lo ee that very few<br />

eculiar <strong>and</strong>ftll1ny =<br />

comical probably is<br />

whenever l eat fish.<br />

)joke.<br />

ti poly emou ,<strong>and</strong><br />

of word. Since they<br />

rlnre ynonyms, <strong>and</strong><br />

onyms in that they<br />

.worďs sense .<br />

Puzzle 6-1<br />

For each of the following pairs, demonsrrate that the two words are not absolute<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 111<br />

synonyms by giving a sentence in which they are not sub titutable for each other.<br />

Describe why they are not substitutable (i.e. how their ense differ).<br />

a. safe. secure<br />

b. fake, false<br />

c. big. large<br />

d. (a tough one!) somebody, someone<br />

The exi tence of large thesauru eprove that Engli h ha plenty of words that<br />

are very clo e in meaning. But if we look closely at those words, it is very rare<br />

to find pair that are perfectly ynonymou • even for just one of their senses. You<br />

may feel that funny <strong>and</strong> comical never mean exactly the ame thing, o that a<br />

[unny joke i a slightly different kind of joke than a comica/ joke. Roy Harris<br />

(1973:12-13) ha gone o far as to claim that "If we believe there are instances<br />

where two expre ion cannot be differentiated in re pect of meaning, we must<br />

be deceiving our elve ." The rare c<strong>and</strong>idate for perfect ynonymy tend to be<br />

technical names for things like plants, animals, <strong>and</strong> chemicais. An example i<br />

[ur;« = gorse = whin, which all name the ame European evergreen plant. An<br />

American example i groundhog = woodchuck, which name the same animal. l<br />

leave it to you to decide whether you think, as Harri would, that I'm deceiving<br />

my elf in claiming that these are perfectly ynonymous.<br />

Near-synonyms <strong>and</strong> variants<br />

Far more common i for word' en e to overi ap <strong>and</strong> be near-synonyms, like<br />

fake ~ ja/se in Puzzle 6-1. (We can use ~ to ignal near- ynonymy.) earsynonyms<br />

(in a particular en e) can of ten substitute for each other in some<br />

coruexts, but not every context. An example is obtain <strong>and</strong> acquire, which pas the<br />

ubstitution te t in (8), but fail it in (9). This is because obtain <strong>and</strong> acquire both<br />

have a sense that roughly means 'get,' but there are ubtleties to those senses that<br />

are not shared by both words.<br />

(8) Ian obtainedlacquired three diplomas.<br />

(9) a.<br />

b.<br />

Ian obtained permi. sion to l<strong>and</strong>. [?acquired]<br />

[an acquired a British accent. I#oblained]<br />

So far. we have seen that o-called ynonym may differ from one another by<br />

being poly emou in different ways (i.e. en se ynonym that are not absolute<br />

ynonyms) or by not having the exact arne denotation (near- ynonyms). Synonyms<br />

that are denotationally identical may still be different in non-denotational<br />

way - for exarnple, by belonging to different diaJect , regi ters. or by having<br />

different con notation . So, we could ay that the synonym for toilet facilities


112 LEXICAL MEA ING<br />

are not strictly substitutable because the sentences in (lO) would not be equally<br />

appropriate in all ocia1 contexts.<br />

(10) a.<br />

b.<br />

c.<br />

Where is the john?<br />

Where i the lavatory?<br />

Where is the powder room?<br />

John, la vato ry, <strong>and</strong> powder room are sense synonyms because they denote the<br />

same things, but because they differ in register <strong>and</strong> connotation, they are variants<br />

of one another. Synonyms can be variants with respect to any number of nondenotational<br />

properties, including connotation, register, dialect, <strong>and</strong> affect. The<br />

American sense of bathroom (which can refer to a room with a toilet but no ba th)<br />

<strong>and</strong> British 100 (which refer to a room with a toilet) are ense near-synonyms,<br />

but dialectal variants.<br />

Why so many synonyms?<br />

The moral of the synonym story is that it is very rare for two words to mean<br />

exactly the ame thing. As Cruse (1986:270) has noted, "languages abhor ab olute<br />

synonyms just as nature abhors a vacuum." English has many near-synonyms<br />

because it has readily borrowed words from other languages <strong>and</strong> because English<br />

productively makes new open-class word through the morphological processes<br />

of derivation <strong>and</strong> compounding (§1.3.4) <strong>and</strong> conversion (§5.3.2).<br />

In some case , those new or borrowed word tart out a perfect ynonym<br />

for existing words in the language, but over time one of two things generally<br />

happens. In some cases one of the ynonym "wins" <strong>and</strong> the other drop out of<br />

use. For example, the Greek-derived Eucharist began to replace the Old English<br />

husi toward the end of the Middle Age, <strong>and</strong> now husl is obsolete. In other ca e ,<br />

the words' senses diverge. A famous example is what happened when Norman<br />

French words for certain live tock animals were borrowed into Engli h in the<br />

Middle Ages. Before that point, Engli h speakers had words for these animals<br />

<strong>and</strong> used them also to describe meat from those animals; so they ate ox or sheep or<br />

pig fiesh. After the French words for livestock became available, Engli h peakers<br />

came to use the French livestock word (which became anglicized a beef, mutton,<br />

pork) to refer to meat, while the native English words were retained for denoting<br />

the animal. Other animal words were not affected by French borrowings, either<br />

because the French word was not popularized in English (in the case of lamb)<br />

or because the word was added to the language later (in the ca e of turkey).<br />

Synonyms are also found in ca e where one word i reserved for technical<br />

registers while the other sounds more folksy or poetic. For example, the Latinate<br />

uterus is a more "medical" sounding word than womb, which is more likely to<br />

be used in poetry.<br />

Languages react to ynonyms in this way for a number of reason . First, it i<br />

not economical or helpful to have many word for the ame thing - it takes more<br />

effort to learn <strong>and</strong> remember two word form when one i sufficient. When we go<br />

through the effort of having two words, we usually work under the a sumption<br />

of a principIe of contrast - ti<br />

different meanings. This mean<br />

the same thing as another WOl<br />

di fference - in denotation, conn<br />

Clark <strong>and</strong> Clark (1979) give ex<br />

noun into verbs results in a nl<br />

for fo cook <strong>and</strong> to che! in (ll):<br />

(Il) a.<br />

b.<br />

Phil cooked up a fea I<br />

Phil chef'd up a feast.<br />

To cook is an established verb,<br />

denotes the ame activity a lo<br />

a little different than cook. For<br />

more professionalism or panacJ<br />

In um mary, while language<br />

words that are very close in n<br />

can be seen as enriching, rathei<br />

is aid to be particularly syna<br />

more expressive than language<br />

in meaning can be conveyed a<br />

paralinguistic (e.g. intonational<br />

6.2.3 Hyponymy <strong>and</strong> h~<br />

Another type of pan<br />

or are contained in, other mee<br />

extension (§2.3. J) of one word ii<br />

the extension of cheddar ia'<br />

i cheddar is al o cheese, but ev<br />

( ince it could be gouda or mo<br />

cheddar is a type of cheese, a:<br />

meaning of cheddar.<br />

Properties of inch<br />

The inclusion relation is asynu<br />

is not a type of cheddar, o we I<br />

relation: cheddar is a hyponyn<br />

dar. The e terms come from the<br />

over,' <strong>and</strong> this under/over inu<br />

a "family trees," as illustrated<br />

ification, or taxonomy, of foc<br />

peaking, we use the terms hy!<br />

<strong>relations</strong> between words like c<br />

cheddar itself, or the nation of (


not be equally<br />

hey denote the<br />

~yare variants<br />

umber of nonmd<br />

affect. The<br />

let but no bath)<br />

iear- ynonyms,<br />

word to mean<br />

abhor absolute<br />

near- ynonyms<br />

ecau e English<br />

gical processes<br />

fect ynonyms<br />

ung generally<br />

tel'drops out of<br />

:heOld English<br />

. In other ca es,<br />

when Norman<br />

Engli h in the<br />

r these animal<br />

e ox or sheep or<br />

ngli h speakers<br />

as beef, mutton,<br />

led for denoting<br />

rrowings, either<br />

e case of lamb)<br />

:a e of turkey).<br />

:d for technical<br />

ile, the Latinate<br />

; more likely to<br />

ans. First, it is<br />

~- it takes more<br />

nt, When we go<br />

the as umption<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> l 13<br />

of a principie of contrast - that different lingui tic form are associated with<br />

different meanings. This means that if we come across a word that seem to mean<br />

the same thing a another word we already know, we expect it to have orne<br />

difference - in denotarion, connotation, or social meaning - from the other word.<br />

Clark <strong>and</strong> Clark (1979) give examples of when the common proce of making<br />

nouns into verbs result in a new lexerne that contra ts with the extant verb, a<br />

for to cook <strong>and</strong> to chef in (l l):<br />

(Il) a. Phil cooked up a feast.<br />

b. Phil cheťd up a feast.<br />

Tocook is an e tabli hed verb, but if we read a new ve rb to ch~fthat ostensibly<br />

denotes the same activity as to cook, then we presurne it mu t mean something<br />

a little different than cook. For instance, one might interpret (l lb) as connoting<br />

more professionalism or panache on Phil's part than (lIa) does.<br />

In summary, while language resist synonyrny, they can nevertheless tolerate<br />

words that are very close in meaning. Having words that overi ap in meaning<br />

can be seen as enriching, rather than duplicating, our vocabulary. While English<br />

is aid to be particularly synonyrn-rich, this should not be taken to say it is<br />

more expressive than languages with fewer synonyms, since subtie differences<br />

in mean ing can be conveyed a well through other yntactic, rnorphological, <strong>and</strong><br />

paralinguistic (e.g. intonational, gestural) means.<br />

6.2.3 Hyponymy <strong>and</strong> hyperonymy: inclusion <strong>relations</strong><br />

Another type of paradigmatic relation involves meanings that contain,<br />

or are contained in, other meanings - or, to put it a different way, when the<br />

extension (§2.3. l) of one word is a subset of the extension of another. For example,<br />

the extension of cheddar i a ubset of the extension of chee e; everything that<br />

ischeddar is also cheese, but everything that is chee e is not necessarily cheddar<br />

(since it could be gouda or rnozzarella or feta instead). We could say then that<br />

cheddar is a type of cheese, <strong>and</strong> that the meaning 'cheese' is included in the<br />

meaning of cheddar.<br />

Properties of inclusion <strong>relations</strong><br />

The inclusion relation i asymmetrical; cheddar i a type of cheese, but cheese<br />

i not a type of cheddar, o we need different names for the two directions in the<br />

relation: cheddar i a hyponym of cheese, <strong>and</strong> cheese is a hyperonym of cheddar.<br />

These terms come from the Greek-derived prefixes hypo- 'under' <strong>and</strong> hyper-<br />

'over,' <strong>and</strong> this under/over imagery is useful in picturing hyponyrn paradigms<br />

a "family trees" as illustrated in figure 6.1 which shows the y ternatic classification,<br />

or taxonomy, of foods (with particular attention to chee e). Strictly<br />

speaking we u e the terms hyponytn <strong>and</strong> hyperonym. when speaking about the<br />

<strong>relations</strong> between word like cheese <strong>and</strong> cheddar. lf we talk about cheese or<br />

cheddar itself, or the notion of CHE E S E or CHE O o AR (rather than the words for


114 LEXICAL MEA l G<br />

food<br />

I =--=<br />

meat dairy product fruit vegetable<br />

~<br />

chee e bul/el' yogurt<br />

Cheddar feta Edam Gouda<br />

Figure 6.1 A partial taxonomy of food, particularlv chee e<br />

grain<br />

them), we refer to superordinate <strong>and</strong> subordinate categorie . So, we can ay<br />

that the word cheese i a hyperonym of the word cheddar <strong>and</strong> that the category<br />

CHEESE i uperordinatetothecategorYCHEDDAR. Wecanabbreviatethi with<br />

< <strong>and</strong> >: cheddar < cheese <strong>and</strong> cheese> cheddar. The ymbol alway points<br />

toward the smaller category. Figure 6.1 show that while one word may have<br />

several hyponym , each hyponym has only one immediate (i.e. on the next level<br />

up) hyperonym.<br />

A well as being asymmetrical the inclusion relation i. often aid to be transitive,<br />

which is to say that if X < Y <strong>and</strong> Y < Z, then X < Z. For example, cheddar<br />

is a type of cheese <strong>and</strong> chee e i a type of food, therefore cheddar i a type of<br />

food too. But this is where defining hyponymy get tricky, ince not all 'type-of'<br />

<strong>relations</strong> are tran itive, as (12) shows:<br />

(12) a.<br />

b.<br />

c.<br />

a peci men cup (as used for urine samples) is a type of cup<br />

a cup i a type of drinking ves el<br />

#!! a peci men cup i a type of drinking ves el<br />

The intransitivity of specimen cup < cup < drinking vessei tem from the fact<br />

that the 'type-of' <strong>relations</strong> in (12a) <strong>and</strong> (l2b) are not the ame. The relation<br />

in (l2a) involves proper inclusion; that is, the meaning cup is included in the<br />

meaning specimen cup - a cup i a container with a wide, round opening <strong>and</strong><br />

a low profile that can hold liquid , <strong>and</strong> a peci men cup i a particular kind of<br />

low container with a wide/round opening. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, (12b) i not proper<br />

inclusion - the meaning of cup doe not include the meaning of drinking vesse/instead<br />

a cup is an example of omething that can be u ed as a drinking ve sel.<br />

Cru e (1986) calls the proper-inclusion type of hyponymy taxonymy ( ince<br />

these are the <strong>relations</strong> found in cla ic taxonomies), while the ca e in (12b) can<br />

be called functionaJ hyponymy, ince we can say 'is used a ' rather than 'i a<br />

type of' in de cribing the relation. Beside functional hyponymy, there are other<br />

types of hyponymy that many would not con ider to be 'true' hyponymy. A<br />

Cruse (2000b) note , all queen are women, but iť a bit funny to aya queen<br />

is a type of woman (but le funny to say a queen is a type of monarch). In<br />

other words, we'd probably not li t queen in the same taxonomy in which we<br />

have the term woman, so queen < woman i not a taxonymic relation, while<br />

queen < monarch i . We can think of taxonyms as prototypical hyponyms,<br />

ince they are reliably tran i<br />

is a type of Y'<br />

The inclusion/taxonym relation<br />

ynonymy in light of the e tem<br />

Tran itive or intransitive? l yo<br />

near- ynonyms?<br />

Folk vs. scientift<br />

An important thing to notice<br />

valuable to u on an everyda<br />

hyperonym for cheese. In eve<br />

i a type of food bul in lhe '<br />

i a much-needed lexeme th.<br />

chee e belongs to <strong>and</strong> the Ol<br />

taxonorny that goe traight<br />

while in more specialist con<br />

with more fine-grained level<br />

ation , we are happy to say<br />

need to specify dog < cani<br />

tel' how many level a taxo:<br />

apply.<br />

Even among the smaller rn<br />

alient - i.e. more readily u I<br />

cheese example, notice that if<br />

to caJl it a cheese s<strong>and</strong>wich r;<br />

of cheddar, you would proba'<br />

have more specific informati<br />

caJl it cheese rather than CI/(<br />

general names in the e ituai<br />

a dairy-product s<strong>and</strong>wich. T<br />

that we generally attend to c<br />

Rosch (1978) <strong>and</strong> other h<br />

gui tie <strong>and</strong> cognitive term . li<br />

we notice <strong>and</strong> can easily dií<br />

tie level, the names for basi<br />

one morpheme rather than<br />

of the recognized propertie<br />

table 6.1.


e/able grain<br />

. So, we can say<br />

that the category<br />

breviate this with<br />

101always points<br />

word may have<br />

on the next level<br />

aid to be transi-<br />

:xample, cheddar<br />

ddar is a type of<br />

:not all 'type-of"<br />

p<br />

m from the fact<br />

ne. The relation<br />

included in the<br />

Ind opening <strong>and</strong><br />

uticular kind of<br />

2b) i not proper<br />

trinking vesseI -<br />

drinking ve el.<br />

rxonymy ( ince<br />

a e in (12b) can<br />

rather than 'is a<br />

" there are other<br />

hyponymy. A<br />

r to aya queen<br />

of monarch). In<br />

ny in which we<br />

relation, while<br />

ica! hyponym ,<br />

<strong>lexical</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> I 15<br />

ince they are reliably transitive <strong>and</strong> are easiest lo de eribe in the terms 'X<br />

is a type of Y. '<br />

Puzzle 6-2<br />

The inclu ion/taxonym relation is asymmetrical <strong>and</strong> transitive. Reconsider<br />

ynonymy in light of the e terms. Is ynonymy symmetrical or a ymmetrical?<br />

Tran itive or intransitive? Is your an wef the same for perfect ynonym <strong>and</strong><br />

near- ynonym ?<br />

Folk vs. scientific taxonomies <strong>and</strong> the basie level<br />

An important thing to notice about taxonomies is that the level are not equally<br />

valuable to u on an everyday basis. Dairy product i somewhat artificial as a<br />

hyperonym for cheese. In everyday language we would probably ay that cheese<br />

is a type of food, but in the language of supermarket manager, dairy product<br />

i a much-need ed lexeme that allow. for a contra t between the category that<br />

chee e belong to <strong>and</strong> the one that potatoes belong to. The everyday kind of<br />

taxonomy that goe traight from cheese to food is called a folk taxonomy,<br />

while in more speeialist context, we might need more elaborate taxonornies<br />

with more fine-grained level of cIas ification. For instance, in everyday ituations,<br />

we are happy to ay a dog is a type of animal, but a zoologi t might<br />

need to specify dog < canine < mammal < vertebrate < animal. o matter<br />

how many levels a laxonomy has, though, the same principie generally<br />

apply.<br />

Even among the smaller number of level in folk taxonomy one level i more<br />

alient - i.e. more readily used <strong>and</strong> noticed - than the others. Sticking with the<br />

cheese example, notice that if you make a s<strong>and</strong>wich out of cheddar, you are likely<br />

to cali it a cheese <strong>and</strong>wicli rather than a cheddar s<strong>and</strong>wich. lf you saw a picture<br />

of cheddar, you would probably say it wa a picture of cheese. Even though you<br />

have more pecific information about the nature of the ehee e. you are likely to<br />

cali it cheese rather than cheddar in many situations. We would not u e more<br />

general name in the e ituations either; you would not ay CI food s<strong>and</strong>wich or<br />

Q dairy-product s<strong>and</strong>wich. There i a level between too peeifie <strong>and</strong> too general<br />

that we generally attend to, called the basie level.<br />

Ro ch (1978) <strong>and</strong> other have noted that the basie level is pecial, both in linguistic<br />

<strong>and</strong> cognitive terms. In cognitive term ,the ba ie level i the level at whieh<br />

we notice <strong>and</strong> can ea ily differentiate between type of thing. At the lingui -<br />

tic level, the name for basie level items tend to be more ba ic them elves -<br />

one morpheme rather than more - <strong>and</strong> are the term we learn fir t. Some<br />

of the recognized properties of basie level item /term are ummarized in<br />

table 6.1.


116 LEXICAL MEANING<br />

Table 6.1 Properties of the basic-level category CHEESE <strong>and</strong> the basic-Ievel<br />

word cheese<br />

TypicaI properties of basíc-level categories<br />

Similarity of food (superordinate): different shapes<br />

shape cheeses (ba ic level): similar hapes<br />

cheddar ( ubordinate): shape that are indistinguishable from<br />

one another<br />

Similarity of<br />

motor<br />

movements<br />

food: meat, cheese, ice cream, nut (erc.) are prepared <strong>and</strong> eaten<br />

with different motions<br />

cheeses: prepared <strong>and</strong> eaten with similar motions<br />

cheddar : prepared <strong>and</strong> eaten with identical motions<br />

Typical properties of basic-level words<br />

Most frequently food: used when referring to mixed collections of food (e.g. the<br />

used contents of a grocery bag), but rarely used to refer to cheese<br />

speei fieally<br />

cheese: oeeurs about 5 times per million words in English<br />

cheddar: oecurs less than 1 time per mill ion words in English<br />

(Dahl 1979)<br />

Most readily<br />

used<br />

Morphologieally<br />

simple<br />

Earliest learned<br />

If shown a pieture of some cheddar, most people say it's cheese,<br />

rather than iťs food or it's cheddar.<br />

superordinate: dairy product = 2 morphemes<br />

basie-level: cheese = I<br />

subordinate: we of ten use eompounds like cheddar cheese<br />

(2 morpheme ) or goat's chee e (3 morphemes)<br />

Children learn to name cheese before hyperonyrns jbozŕ or dairy<br />

product or hyponym cheddar.feta, etc.<br />

Thus we can conclude that while we describe things at many different taxonornic<br />

levels, alllevels are not created equal. The basie levej is perceptually more<br />

salient, <strong>and</strong> therefore the most unmarked (i.e. morphologically implest <strong>and</strong> mo t<br />

broad ly used) level, lingui tically speaking.<br />

Hyponymy <strong>and</strong> word classes<br />

So far, all of our examples of hyponymy have been nou ns, <strong>and</strong> this is typical<br />

in discussions of hyponymy, raising the question of whether inclusion <strong>relations</strong><br />

exist in other word cias es. Certainly, it i more natural to u e noun in X is a<br />

type of Y statements, a shown in (13).<br />

(13) a.<br />

b.<br />

c.<br />

Cheddar is a type of cheese. [nouns]<br />

? To march is a type of to walk. [verbs]<br />

? Nauseated is a type of iiI. [adjectives)<br />

Cru e (1986) propo e that<br />

Xing is a way of Ying insn<br />

copular ("linkjng") verb be<br />

(14) a.<br />

b.<br />

Marching i a wa<br />

Being nau eated<br />

But while we can identif<br />

taxonornies do not tend to<br />

example, it is hard to thin<br />

inc1usion chain marching <<br />

a hyperonym for ili could b<br />

state of health, but notice I<br />

paradigmatic relation to ili<br />

cross word-class boundarie<br />

type of incJusion relation<br />

Is hyponymy éI<br />

While incJusion <strong>relations</strong> ar<br />

tics, it is not clear that ucl<br />

say that the relation betwee<br />

of the relation between com<br />

word s are in a hyponym re<br />

related by inclusion relatio<br />

meaning is only part of the<br />

ub titutable) synonyms ut<br />

<strong>and</strong> dialect as well a deno<br />

to the e non-denotational ii<br />

even though kitty <strong>and</strong> anii<br />

cat is a type of animal JUI<br />

pronouncement of X being<br />

something called kitty is jl<br />

thi rea on, it can be said<br />

both a semantic (i.e. denot<br />

since it involves similarity I<br />

hyponymy is just a semanti<br />

6.2.4 Incompatibilit<br />

The relation di<br />

lapping categories. Incom<br />

can not denote the same thi<br />

patible, a there are no fíov<br />

link flower <strong>and</strong> equatiom<br />

that constitute semantic par


le basic-level<br />

guishable from<br />

.epared <strong>and</strong> eaten<br />

of food (e.g. the<br />

) refer to cheese<br />

.in English<br />

ord in English<br />

le say it 's cheese,<br />

idar cheese<br />

les)<br />

rmsfood or dairy<br />

y different taxoereeptually<br />

more<br />

imple t <strong>and</strong> most<br />

Id thi i typical<br />

eiu ion <strong>relations</strong><br />

: noun in X is a<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 117<br />

Cruse (1986) proposes that we test for hyponymy in verbs using the test sentence<br />

Xing is a way of Ying instead. We could extend thi to adjectives by using the<br />

copular ("linking") verb being, as in (14b).<br />

(14) a. Marching is a way of walking.<br />

b. Being nauseated is a way of being ill.<br />

But while we can identify hyponyrn <strong>relations</strong> for verbs <strong>and</strong> adjective , their<br />

taxonornie do not tend to have as many level as noun taxonomies have. For<br />

example, it is hard to think of more verbs that could go on either end of the<br />

inelusion chain marching < walking < moving <strong>and</strong> even harder to think of what<br />

a hyperonyrn for iII could be. You might sugge t that it would be something like<br />

state of health, but notice that state of health is a noun phrase, so not really in<br />

paradigrnatic relation to iII. Lyon (1977) refers to <strong>relations</strong> like these, which<br />

cross word-class boundaries, as quasi-hyponymy. In chapter 10 we look at other<br />

types of inclusion <strong>relations</strong> for verbs.<br />

Is hyponymy a <strong>lexical</strong> relation?<br />

While inelu ion <strong>relations</strong> are definitely relevant to the discussion of <strong>lexical</strong> semantics,<br />

it i not clear that such <strong>relations</strong> are specifieally <strong>lexical</strong> in nature. This is to<br />

say that the relation between the word s cheese <strong>and</strong> cheddar i a direct reflection<br />

of the relation between concepts (<strong>and</strong> the objeets) CHE ESE <strong>and</strong> CH EDDA R. The<br />

words are in a hyponym relation imply because the things that they denote are<br />

related by inclu ion <strong>relations</strong>. Cornpare thi to ynonyrny, for which denotative<br />

meaning i only part of the story - we noted that word are not "good' (i.e. fully<br />

ubstitutable) synonyrn unless they rnatch on is ue like con notation, register,<br />

<strong>and</strong> dialect as well as denotative meaning. Hyponyrn relation are le s sensitive<br />

to these non-denotational is ue . It i true to ay that a kitty is a type of animal,<br />

even though kitty <strong>and</strong> animal differ in register. We might prefer to ay that a<br />

cat is a type of animal, ju t because it is odd to u e a non-st<strong>and</strong>ard word in a<br />

pronouncernent of X being a type of Y, but that doe not change the fact that<br />

something cali ed ki/ty is just as much an animal as sornething cali ed cat. For<br />

this rea on, it can be said that synonymy (<strong>and</strong>, as we shall see, antonyrny) is<br />

both a semantic (i.e, denotational en se) relation <strong>and</strong> a <strong>lexical</strong> (word) relation,<br />

sinee it involve imilarity on both denotational <strong>and</strong> non-denotational levels, but<br />

hyponymy is just a ernantic relation.<br />

6.2.4 Incompatibility, antonymy, <strong>and</strong> contrast<br />

The <strong>relations</strong> di eu sed so far hold between words that denote overlapping<br />

categorie . Incompatibility is the logical relation between words that<br />

cannot denote the same thing. So, for example, fiower <strong>and</strong> equation are incompatible,<br />

as there are no flowers that are al o equation - in fact, there is little that<br />

links flowers <strong>and</strong> equations. More interesting to us are cases of incornpatibility<br />

that con titute sernantic paradigrns. Of these, the most di cussed iantonymy, the


118<br />

person<br />

adult ~ child<br />

mÔoman bo/"iirl<br />

Figure 6.2 Age/sex taxonomy for person categories<br />

relation of oppo itenes which hold between pair of word , uch a black/white,<br />

old/young, <strong>and</strong> down/up. (We use a la h "I " to ignal incompatibility.) When<br />

the paradigm involve more than two words, it i called a contrast set or a set<br />

of co-hyponyms - that is, words that have the same hyperonym. We pay more<br />

attention here to antonymy, since it ha particularly interesting properties.<br />

Binarity<br />

Antonymy i the only relation that is particularly binary- i.e. it holds between<br />

pairs of words. Any word sense can have more than one synonym (e.g. fur;e =<br />

gorse = whirú or hyponym (cheese> t cheddarígruyeretfeta, etc.l), but we tend<br />

to think of word a having only one antonym in any particular en e. In orne<br />

cases, this is becau e there are only two co-hyponym in a et, <strong>and</strong> o by default<br />

the contrast set is a pair. This is the ca e in the taxonomy in figure 6.2. In this<br />

case, adult/child, man/woman, <strong>and</strong> boy/girl can be con idered to be antonym pair<br />

becau e they are contrast ets of two. Pair of antonym can also ari e through<br />

morphological derivation. Engli h for example, ha several negating prefixes<br />

that can be used to create antonym, uch a asymmetrical, infrequent, unhappy,<br />

non-partisan, <strong>and</strong> dissatisfied.<br />

In addition to these kind of "natural' binarity, antonyrn pairs ari e in ca e in<br />

which a larger contra t et exi t . For instance black/white belong to the larger et<br />

of achrornatic colors black/grey/white, <strong>and</strong> happy/sad al o contrast with ang ry,<br />

afraid, <strong>and</strong> surprised. Nevertheles , we oppo e black/white <strong>and</strong> happy/sad a<br />

if there were no other possibilitie . It seern that when people want to contra t<br />

things, they like to have ju t one other item to contra t it with. Thi raise the<br />

que tion of why we consider black the oppo ite of white instead of gre)', <strong>and</strong> why<br />

sad is the oppo ite of happy rather than ang ry. You rnight an wer that black is<br />

the opposite of white because it i more different from white than grey i , but that<br />

an wer doe not work o well for the happy/sad/ang ry problem since sad <strong>and</strong><br />

angry are both very different from happy.<br />

Minimal difference<br />

The solution, on the contrary, is not how different the word are but how similar<br />

they are. For instance, hot/cold make a better antonym pair than hot/cool becau e<br />

the senses of hot <strong>and</strong> cold are more irnilar to each other than the en e of hot<br />

<strong>and</strong> coal are. Antonymy i a relation between two lexerne that hare all relevant<br />

properties except for one that causes them to be incompatible. Thi is to ay that<br />

the rneanings of antonym<br />

thi definition better than h<br />

are both perception of ter<br />

scale. They are different i<br />

cale. HOl <strong>and</strong> coal are bo<br />

temperature scale they are<br />

componential analy i in C<br />

than hot <strong>and</strong> cold are.<br />

(15) hol<br />

+ ternperature<br />

+ high<br />

[<br />

+ extreme<br />

Sirnilarly, white <strong>and</strong> black a<br />

extrernes in the range of a<<br />

op po ite extremitie of the<br />

white <strong>and</strong> black <strong>and</strong> not a<br />

contrasts with sad <strong>and</strong> ang/<br />

in cornmon with sad, ince<br />

with reversed facial expres<br />

the e facial expression an<br />

each other, they are imila<br />

which are much more diffe<br />

minimal difference allow<br />

when two member within I<br />

than to other member of th<br />

Types of antor<br />

There are several subtype I<br />

Contra ry antonym are<br />

a ertion of one entail the I<br />

entail the assertion of the Ol<br />

(16) a.<br />

b.<br />

Glady i tall. ~<br />

Gordon i not tall<br />

Not tall doe not entail shor,<br />

that a thing or per on could t<br />

in that they describe the t\<br />

CA more sophi ticated ven<br />

adjectives in chapter II.) E<br />

be measured (e.g. l centim<br />

of the cale include shon a<br />

mea urements that are neith


s black/white,<br />

.bility.) When<br />

st set or a set<br />

We pay more<br />

perties.<br />

iold between<br />

I (e.g./Llrze =<br />

), but we tend<br />

ense. In some<br />

loby default<br />

re 6.2. In this<br />

antonym pairs<br />

arise through<br />

ating prefi xes<br />

ent, unhappy,<br />

ise in cases in<br />

) the larger set<br />

t with angry,<br />

happy/sad as<br />

mt to contrast<br />

:hi raises the<br />

gre)', <strong>and</strong> why<br />

r that black is<br />

re)' i , but that<br />

since sad <strong>and</strong><br />

ut how similar<br />

t/cool because<br />

; en es of hot<br />

rre all relevant<br />

s i to say that<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> semantic <strong>relations</strong> 119<br />

the meanings of antonyms are minimally different (Clark 1970). Hotlcold fits<br />

this definition better than hot/cool, since hot <strong>and</strong> cold have in cornrnon that they<br />

are both perception of temperature, <strong>and</strong> both are extremes on the temperature<br />

scale. They are different in that they are on oppo ite ends of the temperature<br />

scale. Hot <strong>and</strong> cool are both temperatures, but differ in both which side of the<br />

temperarure cale they are on <strong>and</strong> whether or not they are extreme. A the basie<br />

componential analysi in (IS) how, hot <strong>and</strong> cool are less similar to each other<br />

than hot <strong>and</strong> cold are.<br />

(15) hot cold cool<br />

+ temperature]<br />

+ high<br />

[<br />

+ extreme<br />

+ temperature]<br />

- high<br />

[<br />

+ extreme<br />

+ temperature]<br />

- high<br />

[<br />

- extreme<br />

Similarly, white <strong>and</strong> black are antonyms because they are alike in that they denote<br />

extremes in the range of achromatic colors, but different in that they are at the<br />

opposite extremities of the color range, while grey is both a different color from<br />

white <strong>and</strong> black <strong>and</strong> not at an extreme point on the scale. And while happy<br />

contrasts with sad <strong>and</strong> angry <strong>and</strong> surprised <strong>and</strong> afraid, it seems to have the most<br />

in cornmon with sad, since (arnong other reasons) happy <strong>and</strong> sad reftect states<br />

with reversed facial expressions (smile/frown) <strong>and</strong> postu res (up/down). While<br />

these facial exp re ion <strong>and</strong> postures are different, since they are reversals of<br />

each other, they are similar (as opposed to expressions of anger <strong>and</strong> surprise,<br />

which are much more different expressions). In all these cases the principIe of<br />

rninimal difference allows for binary antonym pairs within a larger contrast set<br />

when two members within the et are perceived to be more similar to one another<br />

than to other members of the set.<br />

Types of antonyms<br />

There are several subtypes of antonyrn relation:<br />

Contrary antonyms are th ose, like short/tall <strong>and</strong> old/young, in which the<br />

assertion of one entails the negation of the other, but the negation of one does not<br />

entail the as ertion of the other. as illustrated in (16):<br />

(16) a. Gladys is tall. ~ Gladys is not short.<br />

b. Gordon is not tall. -+> Gordon is short.<br />

Not talf does not entaiI short because tall <strong>and</strong> short do not describe all the heights<br />

that a thing or person could be. We can say that these contraryantonym are seaIar<br />

in that they describe the two extremes of a cale, as illustrated in figure 6.3.<br />

(A more ophisticated ver ion of thi cale is presented in the di cussion of<br />

adjectives in chapter ll.) Each point on the line designates a height, which can<br />

be measured (e.g, l centimeter, 2 cm, 3 cm, ... ). The left <strong>and</strong> right extremes<br />

of the scale include short <strong>and</strong> tall height , but the middle area includes height<br />

mea urements that are neither tall nor short. So, Gordon is not tall does not entaii


120 LEXICAL MEA I G<br />

not tall<br />

----------~--------~<br />

~ _ ~<br />

short tall<br />

Figure 6.3 Height scale (preliminary version)<br />

Gordon is short becau e he could have an unremarkable height in lead. Thu tall<br />

<strong>and</strong> short con titute a contrary pair. Some author (e.g. Lyon 1977, Cru e 1986)<br />

re erve the name antonym for preci ely thi type of scalar (or gradable) contrary<br />

relation.<br />

Cornplementary (alo cali ed contradictory) antonym are tho e for which<br />

the assertion of one entails the negation of the other <strong>and</strong> vice versa, a in (17).<br />

(17) a.<br />

b.<br />

That integer i even. ~ That integer i not odd.<br />

That integer is not odd. ~ That integer i even.<br />

In other word, the en e of complementary antonym completely bi ect some<br />

domain: every integer is either odd or even; there is no midd1e ground.<br />

ot all adjectival antonyms fit o nicely into the e categories. So-called gradable<br />

complementaries, like dishonest/honest, lie between complementarity <strong>and</strong><br />

contrariety. They seem to contradict each other (X is not honest entaii X is<br />

dishonest, <strong>and</strong> vice versa), but a middle ground seem to exi t, ince we can<br />

a sert that ome person is neither honest nor dishonest. Even cla ic examples<br />

of complementarity, like dead/alive, sometimes take on gradable qualitie (e.g.<br />

he 's more dead than alive).<br />

Cont.rariety <strong>and</strong> complementarity are of ten discussed with reference to adjectives<br />

( ee also chapter ll), although we can find contrary <strong>and</strong> complementary<br />

antonym in other part of speech. For example, Love/hale (noun or verb) are<br />

contrarie ,wherea the verb stay/go are in a complementary relation.<br />

Converse antonym describe the same relation or activity from different perspectives,<br />

<strong>and</strong> follow pattern like: if X i p to Y, then Y i q to X. Sometime<br />

one need to make adju tments to thi te t pattern in order to form a grarnrnatical<br />

sentence, a the examples in (18) how. For example ince Bill (X) i a parent<br />

(P) to Madeline (Y), Madeline (Y) i a child (q) of Bill' (X). In other word,<br />

Bill <strong>and</strong> Madeline have. a <strong>relations</strong>hip, <strong>and</strong> Bilľs position in the <strong>relations</strong>hip is<br />

parent, <strong>and</strong> Madeline' i child.<br />

(18) a.<br />

b.<br />

c.<br />

Bill i Madeline's parent. ~ Madeline is Bilľs child.<br />

John gives to Oxfam. ~ Oxfam receives from John.<br />

Scotl<strong>and</strong> i above Engl<strong>and</strong>. ~ Engl<strong>and</strong> is below Scotl<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Reversíve oppo ite involve the undoing of some action: tie/untie, con truction/demolition.<br />

Conver e <strong>and</strong> rever ive antonym can be collected, along with<br />

other mi cellaneou example (e.g. come/go), in a general category of directional<br />

antonyms.<br />

Some word pairs that an<br />

categorie . For example, le<br />

but they are not different p<br />

that typically co-occur. (1<br />

semantics to the tudents<br />

Other pairs of word that<br />

minirnally different (they a<br />

in being alcoholic/non-alo<br />

the e to be proper antonyn<br />

entailment relation like c<br />

Some of these types of al<br />

ness are nece sarily binary<br />

or a relation with two per p<br />

more generally in larger cr<br />

ha to be adapted to allow<br />

(19):<br />

(19) a.<br />

b.<br />

That ace i a clul<br />

That ace i not a<br />

Determine whether the follo<br />

converse, or no ne of these. E<br />

a. fast/slow<br />

b. student/teacher<br />

c. clean/dirty<br />

d. female/male<br />

e. [eminine/masculu<br />

Is antonymy a<br />

Finally, there i the que ti<br />

emantic relation or al o a I<br />

of the word are relevant la<br />

to be particularly <strong>lexical</strong>, Il<br />

hould not make much diff<br />

But a k anyone what the or<br />

intuition is backed up by th<br />

but large <strong>and</strong> Little do not (<br />

for in tance, dead/alive ee<br />

seems "better" than rise/des.<br />

ju t meaning may come intr


stead. Thus tall<br />

17,Cruse 1986)<br />

dable) contrary<br />

ho e for which<br />

W, a in (17).<br />

ely bisect some<br />

ound.<br />

So-calied gradlementarity<br />

<strong>and</strong><br />

est entails X is<br />

t, since we can<br />

las ic examples<br />

e qualities (e.g.<br />

erence to adjeccomplementary<br />

un or verb) are<br />

ation.<br />

m different per-<br />

~X. Sometimes<br />

] a granunatical<br />

(X) is a parent<br />

In other words,<br />

! <strong>relations</strong>hip is<br />

untie, construc-<br />

.ted, along wi th<br />

y of directional<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 121<br />

Some word pair that are commonly considered opposites do not fit the above<br />

categories. For example, learn/teach seem to go together in a conver e-like way,<br />

but they are not different perspectives on the same action, but rather two actions<br />

that typically co-occur. (They certainly do not alway co-occur. Lynne taught<br />

semantics to the students does not entaii that the students leamed anything!)<br />

Other pairs of words that go together, such as gin/tonic can be argued to be<br />

minimally different (they are imilar in being part of the same drink, but different<br />

in being alcoholic/non-alcoholic). However, many semanticists do not consider<br />

these to be pro per antonyms SLnce they can not be described in terms of logical<br />

entailment <strong>relations</strong> like complementary, contrary, <strong>and</strong> converse <strong>relations</strong> can.<br />

Some of these types of antonyrny, including gradable contrariety <strong>and</strong> converseness,<br />

are nece arily binary relation , a they require either a cale with two ends<br />

or a relation with two perspectives. The notion of complementarity can be applied<br />

more generally in larger co-hyponym sets, though the test for complementarity<br />

has to be adapted to allow for more than one complementary possibility, a in<br />

(19):<br />

(19) a. That aee is a club. ---7 That aee is not a heart or a diamond or a spade.<br />

b. That aee is not a club. ---7 That aee is a heart or a diamond or a spade.<br />

Puzzle 6-3<br />

Determine whether the following antonym pairs are eomplementary, contrary,<br />

conver e, or none of these. Briefíy explain your answers.<br />

a. fast/slow<br />

b. student/teacher<br />

c. cleanldirty<br />

d. female!male<br />

e. feminine/masculine<br />

Is antonymy a <strong>lexical</strong> relation?<br />

Finally, there is the question of whether antonymy, like hyponymy is just a<br />

seman tie relation or al o a <strong>lexical</strong> relation, in which non-denotational properties<br />

of the words are relevant to the relation as well. Some opposite pairings do seem<br />

to be particularly <strong>lexical</strong>. If it were ju t the meaning that were relevant, then it<br />

hould not make much difference whether big or large i the antonym of little.<br />

But a k anyone what the opposite of little is, <strong>and</strong> they will tell you iť big. Thi<br />

intuition i backed up by the fact that big <strong>and</strong> little occur together of ten in texts,<br />

but large <strong>and</strong> little do not (Muehleisen ] 997). There are many similar examples;<br />

for instance, dead/alive seems "better" than deceased/alive <strong>and</strong> ascend/descend<br />

seems "better" than rise/descend. Since antonyms come in pairs, factors other than<br />

just meaning may come into play in determining the "be t" antonym for a word,


122 LEXICAL MEA ING<br />

for instance morphological or phonological sirnilarity (as for ascend/descenďy<br />

<strong>and</strong> register (deceased/alive).<br />

Because antonyms frequently co-occur in peech <strong>and</strong> wri ting, it is likely that we<br />

learn antonym pairs like big/little <strong>and</strong> large/small <strong>and</strong> these get reinforced to the<br />

extent that we prefer them to other possible oppo ites like large/little. In this case,<br />

we are not just relying on our knowledge of the words' meanings to recognize<br />

their oppositene s; we are also relying on our knowledge of which word go<br />

together in language use. Some lexicologi ts use the term opposite to refer to the<br />

semantic relation <strong>and</strong> an tonym pecifically for oppo ite that are al o <strong>lexical</strong>ly<br />

related. We are les likely to learn co-hyponyrn <strong>relations</strong> as <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>relations</strong>. Since<br />

whole large contrast sets do not co-occur in di course as often a opposite pairs<br />

do, there is less opportunity to learn them as et of related word. For instance,<br />

if l try to name the whole range of emotions, I get as far as happy/sad/ang ry, but<br />

then am less sure about which other items go on that list. (Which hould lincJude:<br />

afraid or [righteneďl Is surprised in thi contra t set?) However, some cases exi t,<br />

like the playing card suit <strong>and</strong> scientific contrast sets, uch as solid/liquid/gas <strong>and</strong><br />

the prismatic colors, red/orange/yellow/green/blue/indigo/violet.<br />

Further evidence that some opposites are also in a <strong>lexical</strong> antonym <strong>relations</strong>hip<br />

cornes from psycholinguistic experirnents. Pairs like high/low, happy/sad, <strong>and</strong><br />

black/white prime each other (§ 1.4.4), so that if you had just read happy, you<br />

would recognize the word sad much quicker than if you had not read happy.<br />

The same kind of test can show that a semantically opposite, but not <strong>lexical</strong>ly<br />

antonymous, word like depressed would not be recognized as fast as sad (Becker<br />

1980). People are also quicker <strong>and</strong> more con i tent in noticing the opposition<br />

between pairs like happy/sad than happy/depressed (Charles et al. 1994). Thi<br />

argues for a lexicological theory that repre ents the opposition of happy/sad in a<br />

more accessible way than happy/depressed, who e opposition we have to figure<br />

out on emantic grounds (see §6.3 below).<br />

6.2.5 Other paradigmatic <strong>relations</strong><br />

Synonymy, hyponymy, <strong>and</strong> antonymy/contrast are the most important<br />

<strong>relations</strong> for semantic theories, but they are not the only paradigmatic sernantic<br />

<strong>relations</strong> among words. We could name many more, like the relation between<br />

agents <strong>and</strong> the fields they work in (teacher-education, actor-theatrei, organizations<br />

<strong>and</strong> their heads (team-captain; club-president, committee-chairi, or the<br />

<strong>relations</strong> between animals <strong>and</strong> the sounds they make (cow-moo, cat-meow, pigoink).<br />

Since these <strong>relations</strong> apply to relatively narrow ranges of vocabulary <strong>and</strong><br />

have fewer logical implications, linguists have not bothered to give them -onym<br />

names.<br />

An additional relation that has been named i the part-whole or 'has-a' relation,<br />

meronymy. Like inclusion, this is an asymmetrical relation, so we say that<br />

finger is a meronym of h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong> is the holonym of finger. Also like<br />

hyponyrny, meronymy does not rely on the <strong>lexical</strong> forrns of the words - it is a<br />

direct reflex of the mea<br />

be identified, such as ,<br />

component (car> eng<br />

substanee (pipe> copp<br />

<strong>lexical</strong>/sernantic organi:<br />

meronyms <strong>and</strong> holonyn<br />

<strong>and</strong> their hyperonym . ~<br />

the same part-name of<br />

i always a part-name, b<br />

doors, jugs, suitca e .ai<br />

meronym relation can<br />

or as consistent a the o<br />

6.2.6 Summary<br />

Table 6.2 u<br />

Table 6.2 Properties of<br />

Syn<br />

semantic relation ml!<br />

binary X<br />

syrnrnetrical J<br />

transitive J<br />

<strong>lexical</strong> relation J<br />

6.3 Two appr<br />

Different cl<br />

emantic <strong>relations</strong> in th<br />

whether the theory viev<br />

like a thesaurus. Dictio<br />

componentially represei<br />

introduced in chapters 3<br />

Generative Lexicon the<br />

represented in the lexic<br />

an tonym of hoť) becau<br />

ponential semantic repn<br />

hold that semantic relatí<br />

senses) are linked to one<br />

antonym , <strong>and</strong> hyponyn<br />

tradition of Structurali I


d/descend)<br />

ely that we<br />

erced to the<br />

ln thi case,<br />

) recognize<br />

l word go<br />

refer to the<br />

;0 lexicaJly<br />

ion. Since<br />

po ite pair<br />

)r in tance,<br />

Vangry but<br />

dl include:<br />

ca es exist,<br />

uid/gas <strong>and</strong><br />

elation hip<br />

ry/sad, <strong>and</strong><br />

happy, you<br />

ead happy.<br />

ot <strong>lexical</strong>ly<br />

ad (Becker<br />

oppo ition<br />

1994). This<br />

'Py/sad in a<br />

ve to figure<br />

t important<br />

c emantic<br />

)fi between<br />

'e), organiair),<br />

or the<br />

neow.pigibulary<br />

<strong>and</strong><br />

bem -onym<br />

.a' relation,<br />

le say that<br />

,Alo like<br />

'ds - it is a<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 123<br />

direct reflex of the meaning of the words. Different ubtype of meronymy can<br />

be identified, such as whole> segment (month> day), whole> functional<br />

component (car> engine), collection> member (pride> lions, <strong>and</strong> whole><br />

substance (pipe> copper). Meronymy is generally not thought to be a central to<br />

<strong>lexical</strong>l emantic organization as the other -onym <strong>relations</strong>. The relation between<br />

meronyms <strong>and</strong> holonym i not a nece ary a the relation between hyponyms<br />

<strong>and</strong> their hyperonym . Many part are optional (a wingle bird is till a bird) <strong>and</strong><br />

the ame part-name of ten apply to many different whole - for instance, h<strong>and</strong>le<br />

is alway a part-name, but i not the part of any one particular kind of thing ince<br />

door ,jug, uitca es, <strong>and</strong> hammer all have (very different) h<strong>and</strong>les. Thu ,while<br />

meronym relation can be helpful in defining word, they are not a widespread<br />

or as con istent a the other 'onym <strong>relations</strong>.<br />

6.2.6 Summary<br />

Table 6.2 summarize the facts about the relation discussed above.<br />

Table 6.2 Properties of paradigmatic <strong>relations</strong><br />

Synonym Hyponym Antonym Co-hyponym Meronym<br />

semantic relation imilarity inclu ion oppo ition contra t part/whole<br />

binary X X J X X<br />

syrnmetrical J X J v' X<br />

transitive v' v' (taxonyrn) not applicable v' sometimes<br />

<strong>lexical</strong> relation v' X often sometime X<br />

6.3 Two approaches to <strong>relations</strong> <strong>and</strong> the lexicon<br />

Different chool of thought exi t regarding the role of paradigmatic<br />

semantic <strong>relations</strong> in the mental lexicon. These can be classified according to<br />

whether the theory views the men tal lexicon a more like a dictionary or more<br />

like a the auru . Dictionary approaches hold that the meaning of words are<br />

componentially repre ented in the mind - o the e include the main approache<br />

introduced in chapter 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 (e.g. Katz <strong>and</strong> Fodor 1963, Conceptual Semantic ,<br />

Generative Lexicon theory). In thi ca e, emantic relation do not need to be<br />

repre ented in the lexicon (i.e. nothing in the lexicon need to ay cold i the<br />

antonym of hot') becau e tho e relation are derivable from the word ' componential<br />

emantic repre entations. Thesaurus approaches, on the other h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

hold that semantic <strong>relations</strong> are represented in the lexicon, In thi ca e word (or<br />

enses) are linked to one another in order to indicate which words are synonyms,<br />

antonyms, <strong>and</strong> hyponyms of which other word . These mostly derive from the<br />

tradition of Structurali m that begin with Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de Sau ure (1959/1915).


124 LEXICAL MEANI G<br />

The mo t extreme the aurus- tyle approache hold that there are no definition for<br />

word in the lexicon, as the mean ing of a word can be derived from "the company<br />

it keeps" - i.e. which other word it is linked to. The following sub ection exemplify<br />

the e po itions in turn, though it mu t be pointed out that many lexicologi t<br />

take a middle ground, expecting that both definitional (dictionary) <strong>and</strong> relational<br />

(the aurus) information i needed for a complete emantic repre entation of a<br />

lexeme.<br />

6.3.1 Lexicon as dictionary<br />

In chapter3 we di eu ed the lexicon-a -dictionary metaphor in term<br />

of how componential theories, like dictionarie , break down the meaning of<br />

lexeme into smaller parts. This mean that the information needed for predicting<br />

synonym, hyponym or antonym relation among word i available in their<br />

componential definition . Thus mo t componential theo ri ts take the view that<br />

the <strong>relations</strong> themselves do not need to be explicitly mentioned in the words'<br />

<strong>lexical</strong> entrie. In other word, these theori t think that arepre entation like that<br />

in (20) is ufficient, so that the additional information in (21) is not nece sary.<br />

(20) man [HUMA, ADULT, MALE]<br />

(21) man HUMA, ADULT, MALE<br />

SEX ANTONYM = woman<br />

AGE A TONYM = boy<br />

E R- Y O YM = gentleman, guy, chap.fetlow<br />

HYPONYM (MARITAL TAT ) = bachelor<br />

HYI'ONYM (JOB) = {fireman, postman, h<strong>and</strong>yman ... }<br />

Approache that do not include the relational information in (21) require<br />

another mean of determining which lexeme are ynonyms, antonyms, <strong>and</strong><br />

hyponyms. This i done by pecifying rule that determine these relation, uch<br />

a tho e in (22):<br />

(22) a.<br />

b.<br />

c.<br />

X <strong>and</strong> Y are synonym iff [i.e, 'ir <strong>and</strong> only ir'] thcy hare all the same components<br />

X <strong>and</strong> Y are an tonym (<strong>and</strong>/or co-hyponyms) iff only one of their componenl di ffer ,<br />

X is the hyponym of Y iff it has all of the arne component a Y plu at lea t one more.<br />

Using the e rules, we can tell that lady (in the sense that denotes 'female<br />

adult ' generally) is a ynonym of woman, man i the oppo ite of woman, <strong>and</strong><br />

fireman i a hyponym of man, a hown in figure 6.4.<br />

Evaluating the dictionary approach<br />

The dictionary approach i attractive becau e it explain why particular word<br />

are related to one another - that is, because they have semantic components<br />

in common. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, becau e it only concem the word' emantic<br />

components, non-denotational propertie (like the ound of a word or it ocial<br />

register) cannot contribute to these relation . So, according to the information<br />

[<br />

sa me componen<br />

-7<br />

flwo<br />

synonyms<br />

lady<br />

HUMA HU<br />

ADULT AD<br />

FEMALE FE<br />

Figure 6.4 eOin<br />

in figure 6.4, lady i a go<br />

classical componential th<br />

<strong>and</strong> not for relation that<br />

There have been attem<br />

non-denotational issue I<br />

matic approach, in whicl<br />

hare all relevant propen<br />

except one. In the case c<br />

i their form, <strong>and</strong> in the (<br />

meaning. The tricky part<br />

relevant or not within a CI<br />

6.3.2 Lexicon as ti<br />

Theorie that<br />

entries (or en se ubentr<br />

to other <strong>lexical</strong> entrie (Ol<br />

high would somehow rep<br />

roots in Structurali t view<br />

thinkers - e.g. Co eriu a<br />

orne computationally in<br />

1996' WordNet, Fellbaun:<br />

forgo componential sen e<br />

words that constrain one I<br />

are in the antonym relatir<br />

end of whatever cale tt<br />

different, but related, to te<br />

Diagrammim<br />

One the aurus-type appn<br />

enne Lehrer (1974). Thi:<br />

in figure 6.5, in which ear<br />

fieJd - an organization of


definitions for<br />

"the company<br />

ections exernr<br />

lexicologiats<br />

<strong>and</strong> relational<br />

sentation of a<br />

rphor in terms<br />

meanings of<br />

for predicting<br />

lable in their<br />

the view that<br />

in the words'<br />

ation like that<br />

t necessary.<br />

(21) require<br />

itonyms, <strong>and</strong><br />

elation , such<br />

the ame component<br />

their components differs<br />

I Y, plus at least one more.<br />

iote 'female<br />

: woman, <strong>and</strong><br />

ticular words<br />

, components<br />

rd ' semantic<br />

1 Oľ it social<br />

~ information<br />

same components<br />

-7 synonyms<br />

ladyftwoman<br />

HUMAN HUMA<br />

[<br />

ADULT ADULT<br />

FEMALE FEMALE<br />

one different<br />

-7 antonyrn<br />

man<br />

HUMAN<br />

ADULT<br />

MALE<br />

Figure 6.4 Componential approach /0 seman/ic <strong>relations</strong><br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 125<br />

extra component<br />

-7 hyponym<br />

Ht:~~lQnJ<br />

ADULT<br />

MALE<br />

FIGHTS FJRES<br />

in figure 6.4, lady is as good an antonym for man as woman i . In other words, the<br />

cias ical cornponential theory only accounts for denotational <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> not for <strong>relations</strong> that involve other properties that words may have.<br />

There have been attempts to extend the dictionary approach o that it considers<br />

non-denotational issues as well. For exarnple, Murphy (2003) presents a pragmatic<br />

approach in wh.ich words are related if, within a particular context, they<br />

share all relevant propertie - including relevant non-denotational properties -<br />

except one. In the case of ynonymy, the property that the word s do not share<br />

is their form, <strong>and</strong> in the case of antonymy, it is typically an a pect of denotative<br />

meaning. The tricky part about this approach is deciding which properties are<br />

relevant or not within a context. (See Murphy 2003 for discus ion.)<br />

6.3.2 Lexicon as thesaurus ...------------------,<br />

Theories that treat the lexicon as thesaurus-Iike hold that <strong>lexical</strong><br />

entries (or sense subentries within them) are cross-referenced with or linked<br />

to other <strong>lexical</strong> entries (or sense subentrie ). Such models hold that the entry for<br />

high would somehow represent that it antonym is low. The e model have their<br />

roots in Structurali t view of emantic (following on from Saus ure <strong>and</strong> irnilar<br />

thinker - e.g. Co eriu <strong>and</strong> Geckeler 1981), but have also been carried on in<br />

some computationally in pired approache (e.g. Meaning-Text Theory, Mel'čuk<br />

1996; WordNet, Fellbaum 1998b). Some proponents ofthesauru models aim to<br />

forgo componential sense representations altogether in favor of large network of<br />

words that constrain one another's senses. In such models, because high <strong>and</strong> low<br />

are in the antonym relation, they are constrained to always denote the opposite<br />

ends of whatever scale they describe, <strong>and</strong> high will always refer to something<br />

different, but related, to tall, long, <strong>and</strong> big, since they are all types OfSIZE.<br />

Diagramming <strong>relations</strong> among words<br />

One thesaurus-type approach is Semantie Field Theory, promoted by Adrienne<br />

Lehrer (1974). This approach can be illustrated by a box diagram, as<br />

in figure 6.5 in which each word cuts out some "sernantic space" in a semantic<br />

field - an organization of related concepts.


126<br />

l'<br />

z<br />

o<br />

vi<br />

:J<br />

..J<br />

U<br />

~ 11<br />

(l)<br />

X -c<br />

..J<br />

<<br />

u<br />

~<br />

'"><br />

~ HORIZONTAL AXIS = CONTRAST<br />

move<br />

crawl walk run jurnp,<br />

211:::~<br />

...c:<br />

~ 0..0 •.... u<br />

::l •....•...• 0::1<br />

~ t; t: r-<br />

(l) 0::1 ~<br />

jog print hop jump-<br />

Figure 6.5 Field representation for selected verbs of human locomotion<br />

Figure 6.5 give a partial emantic field for English verb ofhuman locomotion,<br />

which hows all the relation that a box diagram can illustrate:<br />

The ub cripted numeral on the two in tances of jump indicate its<br />

poly emy. Jumpi has a general sen e 'to pri ng off the ground,' while<br />

jump-. indicates springing <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>ing with both feel, a opposed to<br />

one foot, as for hop. Jump, then, i an autohyponym, a poly emou<br />

word that ha a en e that i a hyponym of another of it en e .<br />

The horizontal axis represents contra t: if two lexeme on the ame<br />

level are separated by a line, th y contra t with each other <strong>and</strong>, transitively,<br />

with other word on that line. So, crawl, lValk,jog, run, <strong>and</strong><br />

jump i contrast as co-hyponym of rnove. Note that orne lexemes'<br />

boxes inhabit more than one leve!. Jog, for in tance, i a member<br />

of two co-hyponym et: crawl/walk/jog/run/jumpi <strong>and</strong> jog/sprint<br />

(hyponym of run). In other word ,jog i ometime u ed to contrast<br />

with run (a in 1don 'l run, l just jog) <strong>and</strong> ometime u ed to de cribe a<br />

kind of running (a in When running ; alternate jogging <strong>and</strong> sprinting<br />

for an extra good workouťy.<br />

Viewing the vertical axi from the bottorn up, we ee hyponymy<br />

<strong>relations</strong>. So, march is a hyponym of walk <strong>and</strong> (transitively) of /110\ e.<br />

We've already seen thatjog i a pecial ca e, a it ha either run or<br />

move as its immediate hyperonym.<br />

Synonymy is indicated by two lexemes in the same box - as for stroll<br />

<strong>and</strong> amble. (They may not be perfect synonyrn , but we can pretend<br />

that they are for the sake of thi illu tration.)<br />

Overlap in meaning (partia1 ynonymy) is indicated where there i<br />

shading in tead of a horizontal line between two terrn , like saunter<br />

<strong>and</strong> stroll-amble. Thi mean that orne activitie are definitely saunle<br />

ring or ambling (but not both), but other (in the haded area) could<br />

be called by either name.<br />

Blank areas in box diagram how <strong>lexical</strong> gaps, which are potential<br />

sense that have not been <strong>lexical</strong>ized in a language. In thi diagram,<br />

there i a bOJ<br />

We can de (<br />

bipedal locc<br />

cover thi r<br />

Box diagram are al o l<br />

order to ee difference<br />

Devi e a box diagram fc<br />

red, purple yellow, blue<br />

To le t your diagram:<br />

From the br<br />

of' the abox<br />

A k your e'<br />

contra l wil<br />

Alternative to box<br />

network of en e witl<br />

1998b) or by creating<br />

entries have feature li!<br />

for tho e features are o<br />

Mel 'čuk 1996). These!<br />

"tran lated" into a netv<br />

of the "sernantic pace'<br />

u e of walk (e.g, to del<br />

other u e .<br />

Evaluating<br />

Proponents of the aun<br />

word ha to other at II<br />

no rneaning exist in a<br />

Box diagram how the<br />

out" for individual lexe<br />

at their boundarie .<br />

One type of eviden<br />

i the phenomenon kno<br />

meanings of finger <strong>and</strong><br />

can mean 'any digit of<br />

meaning i blocked whe<br />

my finger, you would r


union<br />

locomotion,<br />

, indicate it<br />

ound,' while<br />

; oppo ed to<br />

polyemou<br />

en e .<br />

on the ame<br />

er <strong>and</strong>, tranog,<br />

run, <strong>and</strong><br />

ne lexernes'<br />

a member<br />

d jog/sprint<br />

d to contra t<br />

to de cribe a<br />

IId sprint ing<br />

: hyponymy<br />

:ly)of move.<br />

.ither run or<br />

. a for stroll<br />

can pretend<br />

iere there i<br />

like aunter<br />

initely saun-<br />

Iarea) could<br />

are potential<br />

hi diagram,<br />

<strong>lexical</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 127<br />

there i a box above walk.jog, run, <strong>and</strong>jump that contra t with crawl.<br />

We can describe what that box symbolizes - the category of upright,<br />

bipedal locomotion - but there is no particular English lexeme that<br />

cover this meaning.<br />

Box diagram are also useful for comparing emantic field across language, in<br />

order to ee differences in <strong>lexical</strong>ization.<br />

Puzzle 6-4<br />

Devise a box diagram for the f llowing COLOR words.<br />

red,purple, yellow. bille, cala 1', lavender, scarlet, orange, green, crimson<br />

To test your diagram:<br />

From the bottom up, ask your elf whether the lower word name 'type<br />

of the above color .<br />

A k your elf whether all the color name on any horizontal level<br />

contrast with one another.<br />

Alternatives to box diagram include repre enting emantic <strong>relations</strong> a a<br />

network of sense with line linking related enses (e.g. Word et, Fellbaum<br />

1998b) or by creating attribute-value rnatrice (see §3.2.l) in which <strong>lexical</strong><br />

entries have features like A TO N Y M <strong>and</strong> s Y o Y M <strong>and</strong> the values speci fied<br />

for those features are other lexeme - a done in Meaning- Text Theory (MIT;<br />

Meľčuk 1996). The e are all fairly equivalent (e.g. the AVM in MIT could be<br />

"translated" into a network diagram). The box diagram, however, give a sen e<br />

of the" emantic pace' that the lexemes take up, o one can visualize certain<br />

use of walk (e.g. to denote 'power walking') a clo er to thejog boundary than<br />

other u e .<br />

Evaluating the thesaurus approach<br />

Proponents of thesauru -style <strong>lexical</strong> model hold that the relation that one<br />

word ha to others at lea t part1y determine the word' sen e. In other word,<br />

no meaning exi t in a vacuum, in tead meanings are created through relation .<br />

Box diagram how the e relation within the ernantic field. Space are "car ved<br />

out" for individual lexeme , <strong>and</strong> one can imagine the "ten ion" between word<br />

at their boundarie .<br />

One type of evidence for the idea that <strong>lexical</strong> meaning depend on relation<br />

i the phenomenon known as <strong>lexical</strong> blocking, which can be exemplified by the<br />

meaning of finger <strong>and</strong> thumb, hown in the box diagram in figure 6.6. Finger<br />

can mean 'any digit of the h<strong>and</strong>', as in 1 have ten fingers. But that 'any digiť<br />

meaning i blocked when one refer to a ingle finger. So, if omeone say 1 broke<br />

my finger, you would probably feel mi led if you di covered that the finger in


128 LEXICAL MEANING<br />

finger<br />

(l have ten fingers)<br />

(l broke my finger) thumb<br />

BLO( KING<br />

index pinkie<br />

finger middle ril/g<br />

finger finger little<br />

pointer finger<br />

Figure 6.6 Lexical blocking<br />

question was their thumb. In that case, you would have expected them to say l<br />

broke my thumb. The existence of thumb as a po sible contrast term for finger<br />

bJocks the interpretation of ingular finger to mean 'thurnb. ' Thus we see that the<br />

semantic relation betweenfinger <strong>and</strong> thumb affect how they are interpreted.<br />

While the aurus-style theorists have sometimes taken the extreme view that<br />

<strong>relations</strong> are all that is needed for meaning, no successful model of the lexicon<br />

has been able to rely on <strong>relations</strong> only <strong>and</strong> completely leave out any kind of<br />

definitional rneaning. Figure 6.5 show us that walking <strong>and</strong> jumping are different<br />

kinds of moving, but it does not tell us how to walk or jurnp. Similarly, if you<br />

looked at a box diagram of locomotion term for a language you didn't know, you<br />

would be able to say which were the more general terms <strong>and</strong> which contrasted,<br />

but you probably would not be able to translate the word into Engli h. Thi lack<br />

of definitional information has pro ved difficult for computational model that use<br />

thesaurus-style links among words, Mo t uch model (like WordNet <strong>and</strong> MIT)<br />

include definitions as well as <strong>relations</strong>.<br />

This raise the question: if thesaurus-style models require definition , then<br />

why not just use a dictionary-style model, which has to have definitions anyway<br />

<strong>and</strong> which can account for <strong>relations</strong> by rules (as in (22) above)? The main<br />

argument in fa vor of representing <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> in the lexicon is that not all<br />

sense <strong>relations</strong> are completely predictable. In this ca e, their relation need to be<br />

represented in the lexicon, the repository of unpredictable facts about language.<br />

Recall the examples of antonymy like big/little, but not large/little, which seem<br />

to indicate that words' seman tie properties are not sufficient to determine which<br />

of a range of synonyms will be its antonym. If thaťs the case <strong>and</strong> the e <strong>relations</strong><br />

are arbitrary to orne degree, then they are fact about the language that must<br />

be recorded in the lexicon. Proponents of the dictionary view argue in reply that<br />

if you look closely enough, you can find emantic difference that predict, for<br />

example, that big/little is a better antonym pair than large/little because big <strong>and</strong><br />

little are more minimally different than large <strong>and</strong> little (recalI your solution to<br />

Puzzle 6-1c). But theori t with a thesaurus point-of-view might till reply that<br />

these words have developed slight variations in meaning preci ely in order to<br />

accommodate the existing <strong>relations</strong> between them within their <strong>semantie</strong> field.<br />

6.4 Summary<br />

This chapter i<br />

hyponymy, <strong>and</strong> antonym:<br />

defining them. It al o de:<br />

of tbe e <strong>relations</strong>. Dictior<br />

of the words' emantic (<br />

accounts explicitly repres<br />

of how the men tal lexicc<br />

these extremes, since die<br />

non-seman tie propertie<br />

relation , <strong>and</strong> thesaurus-:<br />

on their own. We return t<br />

<strong>relations</strong> for verbs in § 1O<br />

antonym type in chapter '<br />

6.5 Further rea<br />

Textbooks by<br />

lots of detail <strong>and</strong> example<br />

des discussion of the type<br />

sion of history of the dicti:<br />

tie <strong>relations</strong> in other tiel<br />

cien ce. Sources on the d:<br />

but you can also explore 1<br />

6.6 Answers to<br />

6-1<br />

Your answers will vary,bu<br />

a. The car is safe~<br />

tend to mean di<br />

will come to yo<br />

won't be hit by<br />

locked up <strong>and</strong> p<br />

b. She was wearin<br />

substitute for re<br />

costurne.<br />

c. A big/large 1110\<br />

large star i phy


;)<br />

lem to say l<br />

m for finger<br />

: ee that the<br />

erpreted.<br />

le view that<br />

: the lexicon<br />

any kind of<br />

are different<br />

Jarly, if you<br />

't know, you<br />

l contra ted,<br />

ih. This lack<br />

dels that use<br />

.t <strong>and</strong> MIT)<br />

iitions, then<br />

ion anyway<br />

? The main<br />

that not all<br />

IS need to be<br />

ut language.<br />

which seem<br />

nnine which<br />

ese <strong>relations</strong><br />

ge that must<br />

in reply that<br />

. predict, for<br />

ause big <strong>and</strong><br />

r solution to<br />

.iIIreply that<br />

I in order to<br />

mtic field.<br />

6.4 Summary <strong>and</strong> conclusion<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 129<br />

This chapter introduced three major <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> - synonymy,<br />

hyponymy, <strong>and</strong> antonymy/contra t - their propertie , ubtypes, <strong>and</strong> problem in<br />

defining them. It al o described <strong>and</strong> evaluated two approache to the treatment<br />

of these <strong>relations</strong>. Dictionary-sty le accounts airn to predict <strong>relations</strong> on the basis<br />

of the words' semantic propertie in the mental lexicon, while the aurus-style<br />

accounts expJicitly represent those <strong>relations</strong> in the lexicon. An accurate account<br />

of how the menta! lexicon works is probably to be found somewhere between<br />

these extremes, since dictionary-style approaches cannot explain the effects of<br />

non-sernantic properties (e.g. morphological form) on the "goodness" of these<br />

<strong>relations</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the auru s-style approache are not sufficient models of meaning<br />

on their own. We return to <strong>semantie</strong> relation issues when we examine inclusion<br />

<strong>relations</strong> for verbs in § 10.6 <strong>and</strong> the connections between adjective meaning <strong>and</strong><br />

antonym type in ehapter J l.<br />

6.5 Further reading<br />

Textbook by Lyon (1977, 1995) <strong>and</strong> Cruse (1986, 2000b) provide<br />

lots of detail <strong>and</strong> examples of the relation discussed here. Murphy (2003) includes<br />

discussion of the type <strong>and</strong> ubtype of <strong>relations</strong>, as well as extended di cussion<br />

of history of the dictionary/thesaurus debate <strong>and</strong> of the importance of <strong>semantie</strong><br />

<strong>relations</strong> in other fields, including philo ophy, psychology, <strong>and</strong> computer<br />

science. Sources on the different the auru -style approaches are given in §6.3.2,<br />

but you can a! o explore WordNet on the web at http://wordnet.princeton.edu/.<br />

6.6 Answers to puzzles<br />

6-1<br />

Your answers will vary, but here are some examples:<br />

a. The car is safe/secure. While both of these are acceptable sentences, they<br />

tend to mean different things. The car is saje mean either that no harm<br />

will come to you if you drive it - or that the car i in a afe place (e.g. it<br />

won't be hit by a falling tree). The car is secure probably mean that it is<br />

locked up <strong>and</strong> protected against thieves.<br />

b. She was wearing fake/false teeth. False teeth are dentures, used as a<br />

ubstitute for real teeth, but you might u e fake teeth for a vampire<br />

costume.<br />

c. A big/large movie star signed autographs, A big tar is very famou, but a<br />

large tar is phy ically impo ing.


130<br />

d. I want lo be a somebody/(#someone). While the e two word are u ually<br />

6-2<br />

substitutable, somebody (<strong>and</strong> not someone) ha a noun u 'e that means<br />

'a ignificant per on.'<br />

Perfect sen e synonymy is ymmetricaJ <strong>and</strong> transitive. It is ymmetrical since if<br />

sofa = couch, then coucli = sofa, <strong>and</strong> tran itive in that if s/eep = slumber <strong>and</strong><br />

slumber = snooze, then it hould follow that sleep = snooze. However, becau e there<br />

are few perfect synonym , there i of ten ome" emantic lippage" among the<br />

near- ynonym that one can find in a thesauru , which re ult in non-tran itivity<strong>and</strong><br />

sometime even non- ymmetry. It ha been hown that if you look up a word in a<br />

thesauru , then look up the ynonyms of its ynonym (<strong>and</strong> so on), the ynonym<br />

path between any word <strong>and</strong> its antonym i typically ix teps or fewer, a is the ca e<br />

for authentic/unauthentic in The New Collins Thesaurus (reported in Church et al.<br />

1994):<br />

authentic -7 believable -7 probable -7 ostensible -7 pretended -7 spurious=«<br />

unauthentic<br />

6-3<br />

a. contrary:<br />

slow.<br />

thing can have a 'medium' peed a well as beingfasl or<br />

b. converse: if Max i Alice's teacher, then Alice i Max's student.<br />

c.<br />

d.<br />

e.<br />

6-4<br />

contrary or complementary: ometimes dean is used to mean ab olutely<br />

clean - in which ca e one peck of dirt render omething dirty, But when<br />

we are talking about, ay, the rate of omeone hou ekeeping, we often<br />

treat it as contrary - o that one could ay that orneone' hou e i neither<br />

clean nor dirty - it could be better or worse.<br />

usually a sumed to be c mplementary: if omeone told you that the<br />

univer ity has 10,000 tudent, half of them fernale, you would a urne<br />

that the other half i male. While tate between malene <strong>and</strong> femalene s<br />

are medicaUy po ible, we tend lo ignore that pos ibility in our everyday<br />

u e of the word .<br />

contrary: while male <strong>and</strong>female indicate a per on' phy iological ex,<br />

feminine <strong>and</strong> masculine de cribe behavior or appearance - <strong>and</strong> ome<br />

people are neither feminine nor masculine in tho e re pect .<br />

A common mi take in thi exerci c is lo put orange under or above red <strong>and</strong> yellow,<br />

ince orange i 'made of red <strong>and</strong> yellow. Thi 'made-of relation may be relevant to<br />

paint that are orange <strong>and</strong> red, but not to the meaning of the word orange <strong>and</strong> red,<br />

which are in an overlapping, but contrasting, relation. The diagram hould look<br />

something like figu re 6.7.<br />

All of the contra ting terms overiap, since color boundaries are very fuzzy -<br />

something turquoi e, for in tance, could be called either green or blue. Ideally, the<br />

diagram hould be three-dimen ionalothat purple <strong>and</strong> red join up <strong>and</strong> overlap as<br />

well.<br />

crimson<br />

red<br />

scarlet<br />

Figure 6.7 wil<br />

6.7 Exercises<br />

Ad O pt-a-word<br />

A. Explore the iss<br />

synonyms fou<br />

synonymous?<br />

synonymy is d<br />

why the thesa<br />

B. Design a box (<br />

of its senses)<br />

word class (e.<br />

within the fiek<br />

more appropr<br />

l. Show whethe<br />

whether or no<br />

a. quick, fa t<br />

b. ick. iII<br />

c. near, clo. e<br />

2. Devi. e box dl<br />

ju tify your d<br />

Take into aee<br />

sen e that re<br />

a. tool, bar<br />

b. bun, roll,<br />

3. The followins<br />

whether thi: .<br />

sense of tart


ire usually<br />

tmean<br />

ince if<br />

. <strong>and</strong><br />

cau e there<br />

: the<br />

iitiviry <strong>and</strong><br />

ord in a<br />

ionym<br />

i the ca e<br />

rch et al.<br />

purious -><br />

S/ or<br />

h olutely<br />

. But when<br />

we often<br />

: i neither<br />

tthe<br />

assume<br />

'emalene s<br />

everyday<br />

:al ex<br />

orne<br />

lyellow,<br />

elevant to<br />

<strong>and</strong> red,<br />

look<br />

~ylily,<br />

the<br />

erlap a<br />

crim on carlet<br />

B.<br />

Lexical<strong>and</strong> <strong>semantie</strong> <strong>relations</strong> 131<br />

color<br />

red I orange yellow I green blue purple<br />

Figure 6.7 Lexica/ fie/d for cotor terminology<br />

6.7 Exercises<br />

Adept-a-word<br />

A. Explore the issue of synonymy by comparing your word to up to three<br />

synonyms found in a thesaurus. To what extent are the words really<br />

synonymous? Demonstrate using the substitutability test. Consider how<br />

synonymy is defined <strong>and</strong>, if the words are not absolutely synonymous,<br />

why the thesaurus proposed them as synonyms.<br />

I<br />

lavender<br />

Design a box diagram for a semantic field that your word (i.e. at least one<br />

of its senses) is in. Limit yourself to about twelve words, all in the same<br />

word class (e.g. noun, verb), if possible. Discuss the semantic <strong>relations</strong><br />

within the field <strong>and</strong> critique the box diagram method. Are such diagrams<br />

more appropriate to some kinds of words than others?<br />

l. Show whether the following word are sense ynonym by dem on trati ng<br />

whether or not they are ub titutable in all context.<br />

a. quick. fa t<br />

b. ick, iII<br />

c. near clo e<br />

2. Devise box diagram that contain the word. in the following lists. Briefly<br />

ju tify your deci ion ba ed on your own under t<strong>and</strong>ings of these words.<br />

Take int a count whether any word are polysemous. but only con ider<br />

enses that relate to the r u a ITUREorBAKED oo o n fields.<br />

a. tool, bar tool, chair, armchair, chaise longue, seat, ofa<br />

b. bun. roll. bread. cake, muffin, . cone. bage1<br />

3. The following words have more than one antonyrn. FOľ each, di cus<br />

whether thi is becau e the word i polysernou . For in tance, doe the<br />

en e of s/ar/ that is an antonym to finish differ from the ense of starr that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!