01.01.2014 Views

1 Harvard University Political Theory Colloquium For 11 March 2010 ...

1 Harvard University Political Theory Colloquium For 11 March 2010 ...

1 Harvard University Political Theory Colloquium For 11 March 2010 ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.


 31
<br />

























































<br />

Ferrari accepts the standard cognitive reading that akrasia in the Protagoras is ‘a kind of<br />

ignorance’, while advancing his own stimulating understanding of the kind of ignorance<br />

involved as a second-order ‘ignorance of their own ignorance’ (<strong>11</strong>5).<br />

5 Philip Pettit and Michael Smith have argued in their account of failures of practical<br />

reason, among which they classify akrasia, that what matters is that desire and<br />

deliberation are in the right relation to each other. The point is not that reason is<br />

constantly exercising active control over desire (Pettit and Smith 1993), but that right<br />

relation is maintained through the ongoing exercise of what they call the ‘executive<br />

virtues’ which include temperance. These virtues maintain a balance rather than<br />

assuming directive control (1993:76-77). I find this account to resonate with that of Plato<br />

despite the fact that they take their own inspiration for it from Aristotle.<br />

6 Here Aristotle’s opposition between akrasia and enkrateia is helpful, as is his insistence<br />

that the phronimos would not exhibit either, but would rather exercise the self-control of<br />

full virtue. But Aristotle went wrong in his initial account of Plato’s Socrates in NE VII,<br />

misunderstanding the significance of the executive function of knowledge for him (even<br />

though at <strong>11</strong>47b he endorses Socrates’ conclusion after all). We may wonder whether<br />

Aristotle goes wrong in his accounts of Socrates and Plato deliberately, for his own<br />

purposes; I have documented such a case in his presentation of purported Socratic<br />

eironeia in Lane 2006, as has Garnsey 2007 in his diagnosis of Aristotle’s presentation of<br />

purported Platonic communism.<br />

7 Two further features of this view commend it to a comparison. The first is that it<br />

identifies rationality with psychic health (136). The other is that it rejects a sharp line<br />

between theoretical and practical reason, a line which Plato, notably, never drew: ‘from

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!