22.01.2014 Views

Metatheory - University of Cambridge

Metatheory - University of Cambridge

Metatheory - University of Cambridge

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

6. Completeness 44<br />

6.2 An algorithmic approach<br />

I start with the more concrete approach to Lemma 6.2. This works by specifying<br />

an algorithm, SimpleSearch, which determines, for any arbitrary sentences,<br />

whether or not those sentences are jointly contrary. (Iam assuming that we are<br />

given only finitely many sentences. I shall revisit this point in §6.4, but shall<br />

not mention it much until then.) Moreover, SimpleSearch two very desirable<br />

properties. For any sentences, ∆, that we feed in:<br />

(a1) if ∆ are jointly contrary, then the algorithm outputs a TFL-pro<strong>of</strong> which<br />

starts with ∆ as assumptions and terminates in ‘⊥’ on just those assumptions;<br />

and<br />

(a2) if ∆ are not jointly contrary, then the algorithm yields a valuation which<br />

makes all <strong>of</strong> ∆ true together.<br />

Clearly, any algorithm with both <strong>of</strong> these properties is independently interesting.<br />

But the important thing, for our purposes, is that if we can prove that<br />

there is an algorithm with property (a2), then we will have proved Lemma 6.2<br />

(pause for a moment to check this!) and hence the Completeness Theorem. So,<br />

my aim is to specify an algorithm, and then prove that it has these properties.<br />

First steps towards an algorithm<br />

To say that ∆ ⊢ ⊥ is to say that there is a TFL-pro<strong>of</strong>, whose assumptions are<br />

all among ∆, and which terminates in ‘⊥’ without any additional assumptions.<br />

It obvious that, if ‘⊥’ appears anywhere in a TFL-pro<strong>of</strong>, then the TFLpro<strong>of</strong><br />

involves an application <strong>of</strong> the rule ⊥I. So our algorithm will have to look<br />

for situations in which we might be able to apply the rule ⊥I.<br />

Of course, to show that some sentences are jointly contrary, it is not enough<br />

simply to find a situation in which we can apply ⊥I. For if we only obtain ‘⊥’<br />

within the scope <strong>of</strong> additional assumptions, we will not have shown that our<br />

original sentences are jointly contrary. Fortunately, there are rules that allow us<br />

to take instances <strong>of</strong> ‘⊥’ that appear in the scope <strong>of</strong> additional assumptions, and<br />

derive an instance <strong>of</strong> ‘⊥’ that appears within the scope <strong>of</strong> fewer assumptions.<br />

As an example, consider the last line <strong>of</strong> this TFL-pro<strong>of</strong>:<br />

1 A ∨ B<br />

2 (¬A ∧ ¬B)<br />

3 ¬A ∧E 2<br />

4 ¬B ∧E 2<br />

5 A<br />

6 ⊥ ⊥I 5, 3<br />

7 B<br />

8 ⊥ ⊥I 7, 4<br />

9 ⊥ ∨E 1, 5–6, 7–8

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!