28.03.2014 Views

isbn9789526046266

isbn9789526046266

isbn9789526046266

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

it – intuitive and self-evident. An example of a p-prim in naïve physics is the notion of ‘bouncing’: as a<br />

smaller object comes into impingement with a large or otherwise immobile other object, the smaller object<br />

will recoil (diSessa, 1993). ‘Bouncing’ is a common-sense equivalent of a physical law: it helps explain<br />

other phenomena but does not itself, as a primitive, require explanation. 6<br />

Knowledge-as-elements perspectives emphasize context-dependence. There is no overarching theorylike<br />

structure that allows for generalization. As the learner forms a new idea, it becomes an element in<br />

the learner’s conceptual ecology, associated with a particular context. It is possible for a learner to hold<br />

several contradictory understandings of a phenomenon, each particular to a different context. Instead of<br />

having a single consistent theory for the many physical phenomena governed by F = ma, for instance, one<br />

may have entirely distinct p-prims for bouncing and throwing, and even for throwing objects of a certain<br />

shape.<br />

Marton (1993) provides a nice summary of diSessa’s view of learning:<br />

This view of characterizing what it takes to learn physics contradicts other characterizations<br />

in which the transition between naive and scientific physics has been seen in Kuhnian terms<br />

as the replacement of one world view with another. [. . . ] The picture presented by diSessa is<br />

more evolutionary than revolutionary: Scientific physics evolves from naive physics more by<br />

organization than by reorganization, more by structuring than restructuring. (p. 228)<br />

According to knowledge-as-elements perspectives, it is context-specificity that makes misconceptions<br />

resilient to change; instruction intended to correct a misconception may simply add a parallel understanding<br />

rather than replace the old. However, some proponents of knowledge-as-elements maintain (from an<br />

explicitly constructivist position) that rather than being a problem, misconceptions are a useful or even<br />

necessary basis for further learning (e.g., Smith et al., 1994). Although Smith et al. agree with knowledgeas-theory<br />

perspectives that states of cognitive conflict are “certainly desirable and conducive to conceptual<br />

change” (p. 22), they oppose the idea of confronting misconceptions and trying to replace them with<br />

correct understandings. The challenge of learning from such a knowledge-as-elements perspective is not to<br />

replace the learner’s naïve misconception-ridden understanding with another – there is no well-organized,<br />

general structure to replace! – or even to replace individual misconceptions. Instead, the goal is to help the<br />

learner to organize their knowledge elements, to find borders for the rules they have constructed so as not<br />

to over- or under-generalize, to select the most productive ideas and refine them, and to observe similarities<br />

across contexts. The elements of naïve knowledge – misconceptions included – are the raw materials for<br />

such processes, which, if learning is successful, evolve into a theory-like scientific understanding.<br />

Recent developments have seen knowledge-as-theory and knowledge-as-elements move somewhat<br />

closer to each other, with researchers suggesting that both evolutionary and revolutionary changes are<br />

important during learning and that both families of conceptual change theory can inspire improvements<br />

in pedagogy (see, e.g., Özdemir and Clark, 2007; Hammer, 1996).<br />

6.6 Situated learning theory sees learning as communal participation<br />

This section introduces another theory that is a relative or form of constructivism, depending on<br />

interpretation. The theory of situated learning conceives of learning as an intrinsically contextualized<br />

process of social participation in a community (Lave and Wenger, 1991). Although it is not always<br />

phrased in such terms, situated learning theory is based on a social constructivist epistemology in which<br />

knowledge exists within a community rather than within individuals.<br />

Ben-Ari (2004, pp. 86–87) primes us on the lexicon of situated learning, as defined by Lave and<br />

Wenger:<br />

The learner is considered to be a participant within a community of practice (CoP). Learning<br />

occurs by a process of apprenticeship called legitimate peripheral participation (LPP): (a)<br />

the learner participates in a community of practice, (b) the learner’s presence is legitimate<br />

6 Although they were concerned with societal phenomena rather than physical ones, and their approach was less theoretical,<br />

Run-D.M.C. (1984) might as well have been rapping about p-prims as they cautioned would-be inquirers: “Don’t ask me,<br />

because I don’t know why, but it’s like that, and that’s the way it is.”<br />

83

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!