17.06.2014 Views

printer-friendly version (PDF) - Reflex Sympathetic Dystrophy ...

printer-friendly version (PDF) - Reflex Sympathetic Dystrophy ...

printer-friendly version (PDF) - Reflex Sympathetic Dystrophy ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

COMMENTARY | GIORDANO<br />

Comprehending the complexity of …<br />

suffering involves both scientific and<br />

humanistic inquiry and is fundamental<br />

to the provision of technically right<br />

and morally good care.<br />

what sterile and does not depict the potentiality of effects<br />

elicited by a particular type of pain. However, if framed as<br />

domains within the spectrum of pain, these classifications<br />

impart insight to mechanism(s), manifestation(s), and broader<br />

existential meaning.<br />

Maldynia: The Illness of Pain as Suffering<br />

I PROPOSE THAT MALDYNIA be reconsidered to be the multidimensional<br />

constellation of symptoms and signs that represent the syndrome<br />

of persistent pain as phenomenal illness. Thus, by its nature,<br />

maldynia (irrespective of initiating cause and/or constituent<br />

mechanisms) produces, and results from, functional and perhaps<br />

structurally maladaptive changes in the nervous system that<br />

evoke, and are reciprocally affected by, alterations in cognition,<br />

emotion, and behavior. In this way, maldynia is both the conscious<br />

state of pain and a consciousness of pain as a condition of<br />

the internal domain of the lived body and existential disattunement<br />

of the life world. 3 This definition compels a more thorough<br />

consideration of the philosophical and pragmatic basis of pain<br />

medicine, for if maldynia is the illness of pain experienced as suffering,<br />

then the ethical obligations of the pain practitioner are<br />

soundly-based upon an objective knowledge and subjective affirmation<br />

that a patient’s pain and suffering are genuine. 4<br />

Moskovitz describes CRPS as the quintessential maldynic<br />

syndrome. This is well illustrated by Galer and Covington, who<br />

note how multiple biological and psychosocial factors contribute<br />

to, and are affected by, CRPS. The authors take steps to<br />

reveal CRPS not as an unsolvable mystery or specious myth,<br />

but as a complicated clinical problem that is explicable and<br />

treatable. But complicated problems are rarely resolved through<br />

simple means, and the diagnosis and treatment of CRPS<br />

require an insightful, innovative approach that is wholly focal to<br />

the varying pathologic bases and unique, needs of each patient.<br />

The cornerstone of this approach is accurate diagnosis, (4, 5)<br />

and Sherry addresses the differential diagnosis of persistent<br />

musculoskeletal pain in adolescents as an example of how precise,<br />

timely assessment is essential to establishing and implementing<br />

what should be done to most effectively treat a particular<br />

patient with a specific pain disorder. Diagnosis is built<br />

from generalized and specifically contextual knowledge, and<br />

Getson examines thermography as a novel technology and technique,<br />

that, when utilized within an expanded objective and<br />

subjective diagnostic framework, may afford improved evaluative<br />

acumen, thereby determining the appropriate type and ultimate<br />

trajectory of subsequent care. Manning, Webster, and<br />

Fakata, as well as Prager each discuss this care, and their work<br />

emphasizes the importance and viability of rational pharmacology<br />

and new technologies, in an approach that reflects understanding<br />

of the contributory neuropathic mechanism(s), as well<br />

as the relational importance of how these mechanisms are<br />

expressed in the patient.<br />

I maintain that this latter point is particularly critical to<br />

treatment. While there is considerable similarity in the underlying<br />

neural mechanisms of CRPS, their manifestations can be<br />

widely different, based upon the compound predispositions of<br />

each person. The clinician must take this into account when<br />

considering the prudential question of what should be done to<br />

best meet the medical needs of a given patient at a particular<br />

point in the disease-illness continuum (4, 6, 7). Such “customization”<br />

of care allows for evaluation and therapeutics based<br />

upon multiple levels and domains of evidence and is instrumental<br />

in providing the right treatment(s) for the right reason(s) (8,<br />

9). Instead of being inappropriately wedded to a singularly disease-based,<br />

curative model, this approach embraces a larger,<br />

more integrative paradigm, (10) that I feel acknowledges and<br />

communicates to the patient that while cure may not be possible,<br />

effective, ethical care is both achievable and obligatory.<br />

Toward a Neurophilosophy of Pain<br />

GIVEN THE NOTION THAT:<br />

[1] maldynia induces functional and structural changes in<br />

the neurological axis from periphery to brain;<br />

[2] distinct regions in the brain are responsible for the conditions<br />

and awareness of discriminable consciousness (e.g.,<br />

the cingulate gyrus, parietal, prefrontal, and operculoinsular<br />

cortex); and<br />

[3] maldynia-induced changes in these brain regions are capable<br />

of evoking alteration of the sensed internal state that is consciousness,<br />

it becomes clear that maldynia (i.e., pain as suf-<br />

2 There is considerable discussion in the neural sciences (i.e., neurobiology,<br />

cognitive psychology, [neuro]philosophy) regarding the nature or existence<br />

of the “self.” To gain insight into recent perspectives of some of the leading<br />

scholars in this discourse, see: Blackmore S. Conversations on Consciousness:<br />

What the Best Minds Think About the Brain, Free Will, and What It<br />

Means to Be Human. Cambridge (UK), Oxford University Press, 2005.<br />

3 I base this upon the model of levels of conscious processing, first detailed<br />

in psychological terms by Ray Jackendoff (Consciousness and the Computational<br />

Mind, Cambridge, MIT Press, 1990); and expanded by Jesse Prinz<br />

(Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and Their Perceptual Basis, Cambridge, MIT<br />

Press, 2004) to include neural substrates. I feel that this model fits well<br />

within a complexity-based paradigm, and bridges neural mechanisms with<br />

phenomenal experience(s). For further discussion of the phenomenological<br />

approach to illness and pain, see: Gadamer HG. The Enigma of Health. Stanford,<br />

Stanford University Press, 1996; Husserl E. Ideas: General Introduction<br />

to a Pure Phenomenology. NY, Collier, 1962; Svenaeus F. The Hermeneutics of<br />

Medicine and the Phenomenology of Health. Dordrecht, Kluwer, 2000; and<br />

Zaner R. The Problem of Embodiment: Some Contributions to a Phenomenology<br />

of the Body. The Hague, Nijhoff, 1964.<br />

4 Suffering is an extensive topic of study. One of the leading scholars in this<br />

field is Eric Cassell. For an overview of his work specific to a discussion of<br />

suffering and the ethical obligations in caring for those who suffer, see: Cassell<br />

E. The Healer’s Art, NY, Lippincott, 1976, and, Cassell E. The Nature of<br />

Suffering, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1991.<br />

10 | T H E PA I N P R A C T I T I O N E R | S P R I N G 2 0 0 6

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!